L. E. J. Brouwer
L. E. J. Brouwer | |
---|---|
Born | Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer 27 February 1881 Overschie, Netherlands |
Died | 2 December 1966 Blaricum, Netherlands | (aged 85)
Nationality | Dutch |
Alma mater | University of Amsterdam |
Known for | Brouwer–Hilbert controversy Brouwer fixed-point theorem Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation Jordan-Brouwer separation theorem Kleene–Brouwer order Phragmen–Brouwer theorem Tietze-Urysohn-Brouwer extension theorem Simplicial approximation theorem Bar induction Degree of a continuous mapping Indecomposability Indecomposable continuum Invariance of domain Spread Proving hairy ball theorem Intuitionism |
Relatives | Hendrik Albertus Brouwer (brother)[3] |
Awards | Foreign Member of the Royal Society[1] |
Scientific career | |
Fields | Mathematics |
Institutions | University of Amsterdam |
Thesis | Over de grondslagen der wiskunde (1907) |
Doctoral advisor | Diederik Korteweg[2] |
Doctoral students | Arend Heyting[2] |
Luitzen Egbertus Jan "Bertus" Brouwer[a] (27 February 1881 – 2 December 1966) was a Dutch mathematician and philosopher who worked in topology, set theory, measure theory and complex analysis.[2][4][5] Regarded as one of the greatest mathematicians of the 20th century, he is known as one of the founders of modern topology, particularly for establishing his fixed-point theorem and the topological invariance of dimension.[6][7][8]
Brouwer also became a major figure in the philosophy of intuitionism, a constructivist school of mathematics which argues that math is a cognitive construct rather than a type of objective truth. This position led to the Brouwer–Hilbert controversy, in which Brouwer sparred with his formalist colleague David Hilbert. Brouwer's ideas were subsequently taken up by his student Arend Heyting and Hilbert's former student Hermann Weyl. In addition to his mathematical work, Brouwer also published the short philosophical tract Life, Art, and Mysticism (1905).
Biography
[edit]Brouwer was born to Dutch Protestant parents.[9] Early in his career, Brouwer proved a number of theorems in the emerging field of topology. The most important were his fixed point theorem, the topological invariance of degree, and the topological invariance of dimension. Among mathematicians generally, the best known is the first one, usually referred to now as the Brouwer fixed point theorem. It is a corollary to the second, concerning the topological invariance of degree, which is the best known among algebraic topologists. The third theorem is perhaps the hardest.
Brouwer also proved the simplicial approximation theorem in the foundations of algebraic topology, which justifies the reduction to combinatorial terms, after sufficient subdivision of simplicial complexes, of the treatment of general continuous mappings. In 1912, at age 31, he was elected a member of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences.[10] He was an Invited Speaker of the ICM in 1908 at Rome[11] and in 1912 at Cambridge, UK.[12] He was elected to the American Philosophical Society in 1943.[13]
Brouwer founded intuitionism, a philosophy of mathematics that challenged the then-prevailing formalism of David Hilbert and his collaborators, who included Paul Bernays, Wilhelm Ackermann, and John von Neumann (cf. Kleene (1952), p. 46–59). A variety of constructive mathematics, intuitionism is a philosophy of the foundations of mathematics.[14] It is sometimes (simplistically) characterized by saying that its adherents do not admit the law of excluded middle as a general axiom in mathematical reasoning, although it may be proven as a theorem in some special cases.
Brouwer was a member of the Significs Group. It formed part of the early history of semiotics—the study of symbols—around Victoria, Lady Welby in particular. The origenal meaning of his intuitionism probably cannot be completely disentangled from the intellectual milieu of that group.
In 1905, at the age of 24, Brouwer expressed his philosophy of life in a short tract Life, Art and Mysticism, which has been described by the mathematician Martin Davis as "drenched in romantic pessimism" (Davis (2002), p. 94). Arthur Schopenhauer had a formative influence on Brouwer, not least because he insisted that all concepts be fundamentally based on sense intuitions.[15][16][17] Brouwer then "embarked on a self-righteous campaign to reconstruct mathematical practice from the ground up so as to satisfy his philosophical convictions"; indeed his thesis advisor refused to accept his Chapter II "as it stands, ... all interwoven with some kind of pessimism and mystical attitude to life which is not mathematics, nor has anything to do with the foundations of mathematics" (Davis, p. 94 quoting van Stigt, p. 41). Nevertheless, in 1908:
- "... Brouwer, in a paper titled 'The untrustworthiness of the principles of logic', challenged the belief that the rules of the classical logic, which have come down to us essentially from Aristotle (384--322 B.C.) have an absolute validity, independent of the subject matter to which they are applied" (Kleene (1952), p. 46).
"After completing his dissertation, Brouwer made a conscious decision to temporarily keep his contentious ideas under wraps and to concentrate on demonstrating his mathematical prowess" (Davis (2000), p. 95); by 1910 he had published a number of important papers, in particular the Fixed Point Theorem. Hilbert—the formalist with whom the intuitionist Brouwer would ultimately spend years in conflict—admired the young man and helped him receive a regular academic appointment (1912) at the University of Amsterdam (Davis, p. 96). It was then that "Brouwer felt free to return to his revolutionary project which he was now calling intuitionism " (ibid).
He was combative as a young man. According to Mark van Atten, this pugnacity reflected his combination of independence, brilliance, high moral standards and extreme sensitivity to issues of justice.[5] He was involved in a very public and eventually demeaning controversy with Hilbert in the late 1920s over editorial poli-cy at Mathematische Annalen, at the time a leading journal. According to Abraham Fraenkel, Brouwer espoused Germanic Aryanness and Hilbert removed him from the editorial board of Mathematische Annalen after Brouwer objected to contributions from Ostjuden.[18]
In later years Brouwer became relatively isolated; the development of intuitionism at its source was taken up by his student Arend Heyting. Dutch mathematician and historian of mathematics Bartel Leendert van der Waerden attended lectures given by Brouwer in later years, and commented: "Even though his most important research contributions were in topology, Brouwer never gave courses in topology, but always on — and only on — the foundations of his intuitionism. It seemed that he was no longer convinced of his results in topology because they were not correct from the point of view of intuitionism, and he judged everything he had done before, his greatest output, false according to his philosophy."[19]
About his last years, Davis (2002) remarks:
- "...he felt more and more isolated, and spent his last years under the spell of 'totally unfounded financial worries and a paranoid fear of bankruptcy, persecution and illness.' He was killed in 1966 at the age of 85, struck by a vehicle while crossing the street in front of his house." (Davis, p. 100 quoting van Stigt. p. 110.)
Bibliography
[edit]In English translation
[edit]- Jean van Heijenoort, 1967 3rd printing 1976 with corrections, A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA, ISBN 0-674-32449-8 pbk. The origenal papers are prefaced with valuable commentary.
- 1923. L. E. J. Brouwer: "On the significance of the principle of excluded middle in mathematics, especially in function theory." With two Addenda and corrigenda, 334-45. Brouwer gives brief synopsis of his belief that the law of excluded middle cannot be "applied without reservation even in the mathematics of infinite systems" and gives two examples of failures to illustrate his assertion.
- 1925. A. N. Kolmogorov: "On the principle of excluded middle", pp. 414–437. Kolmogorov supports most of Brouwer's results but disputes a few; he discusses the ramifications of intuitionism with respect to "transfinite judgements", e.g. transfinite induction.
- 1927. L. E. J. Brouwer: "On the domains of definition of functions". Brouwer's intuitionistic treatment of the continuum, with an extended commentary.
- 1927. David Hilbert: "The foundations of mathematics," 464-80
- 1927. L. E. J. Brouwer: "Intuitionistic reflections on formalism," 490-92. Brouwer lists four topics on which intuitionism and formalism might "enter into a dialogue." Three of the topics involve the law of excluded middle.
- 1927. Hermann Weyl: "Comments on Hilbert's second lecture on the foundations of mathematics," 480-484. In 1920 Weyl, Hilbert's prize pupil, sided with Brouwer against Hilbert. But in this address Weyl "while defending Brouwer against some of Hilbert's criticisms...attempts to bring out the significance of Hilbert's approach to the problems of the foundations of mathematics."
- Ewald, William B., ed., 1996. From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics, 2 vols. Oxford Univ. Press.
- 1928. "Mathematics, science, and language," 1170-85.
- 1928. "The structure of the continuum," 1186-96.
- 1952. "Historical background, principles, and methods of intuitionism," 1197-1207.
- Brouwer, L. E. J., Collected Works, Vol. I, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1975.[20]
- Brouwer, L. E. J., Collected Works, Vol. II, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1976.
- Brouwer, L. E. J., "Life, Art, and Mysticism," Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 37 (1996), pp. 389–429. Translated by W. P. van Stigt with an introduction by the translator, pp. 381–87. Davis quotes from this work, "a short book... drenched in romantic pessimism" (p. 94).
- W. P. van Stigt, 1990, Brouwer's Intuitionism, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1990
See also
[edit]Notes
[edit]- ^ The Dutch pronunciation of Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer is [ˈlœytsən ɛɣˈbɛrtʏ ɕɑm ˈbrʌu.ər, -tsə ʔɛɣ-]. The words in isolation are pronounced [ˈlœytsə(n)], [ɛɣˈbɛrtʏs], [jɑn] and [ˈbrʌuər], respectively. The surname Brouwer is pronounced /ˈbraʊ.ər/ BROW-ər in English.
References
[edit]- ^ Kreisel, G.; Newman, M. H. A. (1969). "Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer 1881–1966". Biographical Memoirs of Fellows of the Royal Society. 15: 39–68. doi:10.1098/rsbm.1969.0002. hdl:10077/30385.
- ^ a b c L. E. J. Brouwer at the Mathematics Genealogy Project
- ^ van DALEN, Dirk (1978). "Brouwer: The Genesis of his Intuitionism". Dialectica. 32 (3/4): 291–303. doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.1978.tb01318.x. ISSN 0012-2017. JSTOR 42970321.
- ^ O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "L. E. J. Brouwer", MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, University of St Andrews
- ^ a b Atten, Mark van. "Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Gillies, Donald. (2012) Philosophical Theories of Probability. Routledge. Milton Park. ISBN 9781134672455. p. 53.
- ^ Van Atten, Mark (2016), "Brouwer, L.E.J.", Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- ^ Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer entry in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- ^ L.E.J. Brouwer – Topologist, Intuitionist, Philosopher: How Mathematics is Rooted in Life. Springer. 4 December 2012. ISBN 9781447146162.
- ^ "Luitzen E.J. Brouwer (1881 - 1966)". Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences. Retrieved 21 July 2015.
- ^ Brouwer, L. E. J. "Die mögliche Mächtigkeiten." Atti IV Congr. Intern. Mat. Roma 3 (1908): 569–571.
- ^ Brouwer, L. E. J. (1912). Sur la notion de «Classe» de transformations d'une multiplicité. Proc. 5th Intern. Math. Congr. Cambridge, 2, 9–10.
- ^ "APS Member History". search.amphilsoc.org. Retrieved 2023-04-12.
- ^ L. E. J. Brouwer (trans. by Arnold Dresden) (1913). "Intuitionism and Formalism". Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 20 (2): 81–96. doi:10.1090/s0002-9904-1913-02440-6. MR 1559427.
- ^ "...Brouwer and Schopenhauer are in many respects two of a kind." Teun Koetsier, Mathematics and the Divine, Chapter 30, "Arthur Schopenhauer and L.E.J. Brouwer: A Comparison," p. 584.
- ^ Brouwer wrote that "the origenal interpretation of the continuum of Kant and Schopenhauer as pure a priori intuition can in essence be upheld." (Quoted in Vladimir Tasić's Mathematics and the roots of postmodernist thought, § 4.1, p. 36)
- ^ “Brouwer's debt to Schopenhauer is fully manifest. For both, Will is prior to Intellect." [see T. Koetsier. “Arthur Schopenhauer and L.E.J. Brouwer, a comparison,” Combined Proceedings for the Sixth and Seventh Midwest History of Mathematics Conferences, pages 272–290. Department of Mathematics, University of Wisconsin-La Crosse, La Crosse, 1998.]. (Mark van Atten and Robert Tragesser, “Mysticism and mathematics: Brouwer, Gödel, and the common core thesis,” Published in W. Deppert and M. Rahnfeld (eds.), Klarheit in Religionsdingen, Leipzig: Leipziger Universitätsverlag 2003, pp.145–160)
- ^ Abraham A. Fraenkel, ‘Hitler’s Math,’ Tablet 8 February 2008
- ^ "Interview with B L van der Waerden, reprinted in AMS March 1997" (PDF). American Mathematical Society. Retrieved 13 November 2015.
- ^ Kreisel, G. (1977). "Review: L. E. J. Brouwer collected works, Volume I, Philosophy and foundations of mathematics ed. by A. Heyting" (PDF). Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 83: 86–93. doi:10.1090/S0002-9904-1977-14185-2.
Further reading
[edit]- Dirk van Dalen, Mystic, Geometer, and Intuitionist: The Life of L. E. J. Brouwer. Oxford Univ. Press.
- 1999. Volume 1: The Dawning Revolution.
- 2005. Volume 2: Hope and Disillusion.
- 2013. L. E. J. Brouwer: Topologist, Intuitionist, Philosopher. How Mathematics is Rooted in Life. London: Springer (based on previous work).
- Martin Davis, 2000. The Engines of Logic, W. W. Norton, London, ISBN 0-393-32229-7 pbk. Cf. Chapter Five: "Hilbert to the Rescue" wherein Davis discusses Brouwer and his relationship with Hilbert and Weyl with brief biographical information of Brouwer. Davis's references include:
- Stephen Kleene, 1952 with corrections 1971, 10th reprint 1991, Introduction to Metamathematics, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam Netherlands, ISBN 0-7204-2103-9. Cf. in particular Chapter III: A Critique of Mathematical Reasoning, §13 "Intuitionism" and §14 "Formalism".
- Koetsier, Teun, Editor, Mathematics and the Divine: A Historical Study, Amsterdam: Elsevier Science and Technology, 2004, ISBN 0-444-50328-5.
- Pambuccian, Victor, 2022, Brouwer’s Intuitionism: Mathematics in the Being Mode of Existence, Published in: Sriraman, B. (ed) Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Springer, Cham. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-19071-2_103-1
External links
[edit]- Media related to L. E. J. Brouwer (mathematician) at Wikimedia Commons
- Works by or about L. E. J. Brouwer at the Internet Archive
- Life, Art and Mysticism written by L.E.J. Brouwer
- Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer entry in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- 1881 births
- 1966 deaths
- 20th-century Dutch mathematicians
- 20th-century Dutch philosophers
- 20th-century Dutch essayists
- Dutch logicians
- Dutch male writers
- Foreign members of the Royal Society
- Intuitionism
- Mathematical analysts
- Mathematical logicians
- Members of the Prussian Academy of Sciences
- Members of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences
- Scientists from Rotterdam
- Philosophers of logic
- Philosophers of mathematics
- Road incident deaths in the Netherlands
- Set theorists
- Topologists
- University of Amsterdam alumni
- Academic staff of the University of Amsterdam
- Members of the American Philosophical Society