Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
The Shared Destiny of the Radically Other: a reading
of The Wizard of Oz
William Pawlett and Meena Dhanda
University of Wolverhampton
It’s the one who doesn’t lack me who is the Other. That is radical
Otherness. (Baudrillard 1999b: 132).
Everything which is symbolically exchanged constitutes a mortal
danger for the dominant order (Baudrillard 1993: 188, n. 7).
[R]ather than seeking out the identity beneath the mask, one should
seek out the mask beneath the identity – the face which haunts us and
deflects us from our identity (Baudrillard 1999b: 137).
The Wizard of Oz has long been one of my favourite films.1 An early
childhood memory is of watching it on Christmas day, its vivid images of
good and evil, innocence and wickedness, merging with the spirit of
Christmas such that the film seemed to partake of the sacredness of the
nativity. If Jesus was there to help Dorothy she would be able to destroy the
Wicked Witch of the West easily, but in this alien world the absurd rag-bag
of friends must help each other and accomplish this feat for themselves. Their
task is, of course, completely impossible. They have no magic, they each lack
knowledge of Oz, and are all outsiders without clear status. Further, each
lacks the instinct or desire to kill and, perhaps worst of all, each possesses
ridiculous weaknesses – tin man keeps seizing up, scarecrow can barely walk,
the lion from whom we might expect ferocity is actually permanently
1
As this is a jointly authored paper it is sometimes necessary to specify which of us is
designated by the ‘I’. In this case it is W.P.
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
113
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
terrified. Dorothy is lost and is prone to tears, and Toto is a tiny, pathetic
excuse for a dog. Even to the most optimistic child the odds against this
strange group’s success must seem utterly overwhelming. So, in a sense, the
narrative presents the well-worn theme of triumph over adversity, ‘don’t give
up, it will be alright in the end’ – but how the friends triumph is very peculiar
and very suggestive. In exploring this narrative we draw upon Baudrillard’s
notions of symbolic exchange, destiny and radical otherness. Symbolic
exchange occurs between these characters, in their first meetings, in the risks
and sacrifices they make to help each other even as they accept that they may
never get what they desire. Symbolic exchange emerges in their pact, much
stronger than their individual desires, and in their shared destiny to kill the
witch – without even trying. Symbolic exchange, for Baudrillard, is an act
within a relation of giving, receiving and reciprocation, its meaning(s) are
located within the relation, are singular and cannot be abstracted from the
relation (Baudrillard 1993: 133). Symbolic exchange cannot be the property
or attribute of any individual or character, nor can it be accumulated or
deployed, it is always relational. Symbolic exchange takes place in the space
established between the characters, a singular space that consists of both
great distance – they are not of the same race, species or even universe – they
are, in a sense, radically Other and yet a space also of great intimacy. This is
not a space of ‘respect’, not one of embracing ‘difference’ or ‘diversity’, it is,
we argue, a space of the unfolding of destiny. Each of the characters retains
what Baudrillard terms ‘singularity’ or radical otherness, both for themselves
and for their friends (Baudrillard 1993b: 111-174). Further they are not
restored, normalised or ‘corrected’ by the Wizard’s ‘gift’ of their hearts’
desires. Throughout the quest and beyond, their pact endures producing
shared metamorphoses or becomings.
In exploring Baudrillard’s notion of radical otherness through a
journey into Oz we are certainly not making claims about the ‘truth’ or
identity of the film.. Just as Baudrillard wasn’t looking for the ‘real’ America
but its ‘otherness’ (Baudrillard 1988: 5), what is at stake is the otherness of
the film, not the directors’ or the studio’s intentions, not the cultural
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
114
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
particularities of audience reception, not the film’s position in the history of
popular cinema, but something else. We seek neither the universal nor the
particular; rather we offer a singular reading of the film’s narrative, images,
songs and dances.
The film certainly visualises strangeness; it confronts us with the
remarkable, fantastical; once we see Oz we never forget it. Yet in suspending
reality and rationality the film does not lapse into the merely irrational or
senseless. This gives the film a curious relation to Baudrillard’s work since
symbolic exchange is presented as that which prevents, ruins or makes
volatile and ambivalent any binary opposition, such as those of real/unreal,
rational/irrational, human/animal (Baudrillard 1993: 133; Pawlett 2007: 559). The notion of symbolic exchange is used in two distinct ways by
Baudrillard. Firstly it is presented as the organising principle of pre-industrial
societies where everything must be given and returned (what Baudrillard,
drawing upon Mauss (1990) calls the ‘symbolic order’). Secondly concerning
modernity, where symbolic exchanges are dismantled, foreclosed or diverted
into commodification and simulation by the capitalist system, symbolic
exchange is described as the only genuinely revolutionary principle, the only
effective defiance of the system. Symbolic exchanges cannot be ascribed a
value, they cannot be designated or reduced to commodity signs. Moreover
symbolic exchanges threaten the capitalist system of power and control by
corroding or annulling the binary oppositions and ordered exchanges upon
which the system depends. Symbolic exchange ruins the systemic opposition
between self and other, good and evil, male and female, human and animal,
real and imaginary, even, according to Baudrillard, living and dead
(Baudrillard 1993: 134). Indeed it is the desperate attempt to safeguard these
oppositions, which are constitutive of ‘reality’ itself that leads the system into
simulation: the synthetic and ‘panic-stricken’ generation of ‘reality’ from preexisting bytes, codes and models. The system is so desperate to maintain
these binaries it now allows passage from one pole to the other,
on
condition that the two poles are treated as ‘real’. The system even offers
simulatory promotions of the repressed term of the opposition in order to
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
115
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
prevent genuine change: this is how the feminist movement was neutralised,
according to Baudrillard (Baudrillard 1990; see also Grace 2000).
Baudrillard is quite clear, though the capitalist system can be seen as
hyperreal – as increasingly characterised by simulation – it understands itself
as ‘real’ (Baudrillard 1994: 20-1). This is because the system stands or falls
with ‘reality’, power always ‘opts for the real’ as its force is utterly dependent
upon this faltering illusion.
In Oz, as in life, binary oppositions do not hold. In Oz everything has
its place and everything unfolds according to destiny. Destiny, for
Baudrillard, occurs only within the space of symbolic exchange, and it is
destiny which provides an alternative sense, not merely preventing a lapse
into the irrational but tearing binary structures to shreds. In Oz any event at
all, any apparent coincidence or accident works, magically, to fulfil the
shared destiny of the radical Others that find themselves together. For
Baudrillard, ‘[i]n this predestined world of the Other, everything comes from
elsewhere – happy or unhappy events, illnesses, even thoughts themselves …
[t]his is a universe of fatality not of psychology’ (Baudrillard 1993b: 141).
Baudrillard and Film: Illusion and Simulation
I like the cinema. Of all spectacles it’s even the only one I do like
(Baudrillard [1982] in Gane Ed. 1993:29).
Baudrillard did not claim to provide any particular way of theorising film
yet, clearly, he prized cinema as a site of illusion, myth, ‘the dream’ and the
play of the imaginary (Baudrillard 1987: 92).2
Nevertheless, Baudrillard
located cinema within his speculative classification of the orders of simulacra
(Baudrillard
1994:
43-60).
For
Baudrillard
contemporary
cinematic
production has, by and large, accelerated into simulation and hyperreality.
While delighting in early cinema, silent films and American films of the
1930s, Baudrillard asserts ‘the films coming out today are no longer so
2
As Le Dœuff suggests, philosophical argument itself relies on the imaginary for its
force. For an application of Le Dœuff’s perspective in a defence of film theory as
‘impure, perspectival and imaginative’ see Constable (2000).
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
116
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
interesting … [though] technically sophisticated … they fail to incorporate
any element of the make-believe [l’imaginaire or the imaginary] … cinema
has become hyper-realist,’ (Baudrillard in Gane Ed. 1993: 30).
For Baudrillard hyperreal culture performs a crucial post-ideological
function within the capitalist system, that of ‘saving the reality principle’
(Baudrillard 1994: 13). Cinema, for example, does not simply distract
audiences from the grim realities of work, exploitation and inequality, it
enables audiences to consume and enjoy these ‘realities’ as signs. In
consuming such signs, Baudrillard asserts, audiences are comforted with the
belief that something at least is real. Much contemporary cinema works very
hard to persuade us of its realistic nature and if the signs are ‘realistic’ that
must be because they seem to refer to a reality beyond the screen (Baudrillard
1987: 13). And if audiences can no longer be persuaded that ‘reality’ is a just
or ordered place, perhaps they can be persuaded that it is a horrifying and
disgusting place. Hyperreal cultural production, unbound from the moral
and ideological restrictions of earlier phases of capitalism, draws upon any
notion, any fear or horror to safeguard the faltering sense of ‘reality’ on
which it depends. As examples of hyperrealist cinema we might include
Quantum of Solace (2008) where the opening scenes of a car chase do not
merely signify speed, technology, danger but attempt to show more than any
‘real’ experience of a car chase could possibly encompass. Both cars are
shown from many different angles, capturing an accumulated ‘reality’ that no
human being, either driver or spectator could ever experience. There is little
tension because the scene does not feel ‘real’; it feels determined by technical
and special effects criteria, what Baudrillard calls simulation models. The
illusion or imagination of speed is replaced by the hyperrealisation or hypervisualisation of speed. It is not a case of being able to experience the chase
from the perspective of both drivers; rather ‘perspective’ is re-fashioned by
special effects technology. It is not a case of the audience being granted a
God’s eye view of the chase, but of a demand on the viewer to keep up,
forcing them to see more of ‘the real’ than there is to see. For this reason
Baudrillard often describes hyperreality as pornographic (Baudrillard 1990:
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
117
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
28-36, 1994: 28). The evoking of the ‘real’ of representation through
cinematic technique (that is the effect of ‘the real’ enabled by the oppositions
between signifier and signified and the sign and the referent) is no longer
what is at stake here. The scene works so hard to capture the real, far too
hard, and it fails dismally. In working so hard to maintain these ‘realities’ the
film exhausts them, draining away the real’s power of illusion, ‘[t]he
impossibility of rediscovering an absolute level of the real is of the same
order as the impossibility of establishing illusion’ (Baudrillard 1994: 19). For
Baudrillard, as for Nietzsche, without the power of illusion the real is
nothing, real and apparent are abolished simultaneously (Nietzsche 1990: 51
[1889]. Hyperreality, for Baudrillard, is an unexchangeable or residual
surplus, an accumulation of signs of the ‘real’ to an excess that could never
exist and cannot be broken down by the audience: a toxic oil slick polluting
cinematic illusion.
The most consistent or defining feature of the third order (simulation),
and the fourth order (virtualisation) is, for Baudrillard, that they are devoid
of the imaginary.3 The imaginary, a term Baudrillard adopts from Lacan
(1977: 75-81), refers to the power of the image to enchant and fascinate, to
stimulate the imagination and produce identifications within the self. For
Lacan the self is always alienated in these identifications. For Baudrillard the
era of the imaginary, of the signified and referent, and of alienation, is now
fundamentally over. It is important to emphasise that Baudrillard’s thought
3
We might suggest an example of the fourth order in the recent monster movie
Cloverfield (2008). This film tries, very hard, to convince us that it has grasped the
importance of new media. A group of attractive young New Yorkers are terrorised
by a monster that is never clearly seen but which leaves a trail of devastation and
horror that is recorded in ‘real-time’ by the characters’ mobile phones and video
cameras. The effect is close indeed to what Baudrillard termed ‘integral reality’ in
that the distance between an event (the monster’s attack) and its representation or
mediation disappears in ‘real-time’; ‘ ‘Integral Reality’ has no imaginary’ (Baudrillard
2005: 18). The ‘real-time’ footage is not, strictly speaking, hyperrealist because it
does not show more of the real (chaos and carnage) than there is to show, it actually
shows very little: grainy, shaky footage of concrete floors and walls, the grey sky line
and very little else. For example, what does the monster symbolise? What fears are
secreted within it? The monster is merely an inconvenience; it gets in the way of a
fuck between the lead characters. But at least the film preserves the fiction that there
is some ‘reality’ worth filming on your mobile phone when your friends’ gossip
about their sex-lives begin to bore: reality safe-guarded, the system defended!
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
118
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
does not privilege the imaginary per se, nor does he mourn it as a ‘lost
object’, a common mis-reading. The opposition of real and imaginary is
important for Baudrillard only insofar as symbolic exchange is able to erupt
through these terms, making each annul or dissolve the other in ceaseless
exchange (Baudrillard 1993: 133). The phase of simulation repudiates the
possibility of symbolic exchange far more effectively than can ‘real’
structures, because simulation abolishes a ‘real’ structure that might be
challenged. Nevertheless defiance, revolt and symbolic exchange will always
emerge in new forms (Baudrillard 1983: 14). For Baudrillard the media
reduces the power of the image to captivate and stupefy, the image is
‘degraded’; cinema is corrupted by television such that the two forms
‘implode’ and can barely be distinguished (Baudrillard 1987: 25). Further, in
the age of the internet the power of the image is further depleted, the image is
reduced to a flow of information, websites contain so many images, text,
links, streamed video, and pop-up adverts that the image is never given time
to arrest and enchant the viewer, indeed the viewer is now user of
information, not spectator of images. This condition, Baudrillard asserts, is
far worse than alienation; it is one of dispossession, exhaustion and
‘irradiation’ (Baudrillard 1993b:122).
The Wizard of Oz, as cinematic production, is perhaps a film of the
second order of simulacra, before the contamination of image and reality,
before the implosion of real and imaginary, of cinema and television in the
relay of coded or modelled signifiers of simulation (Baudrillard 1987: 30).
For Dorothy, and for the audiences she seduces, there is still a clear
distinction between the ‘real’ (the dust and poverty of Kansas) and the
imaginary (‘somewhere over the rainbow … where troubles melt like lemon
drops, way above the chimney tops, that’s where you’ll find me’). The
Technicolor world of Oz is not real, but nor is it hyperreal, it engages the
imaginary, it is Dorothy’s dream and ours, it provokes our identifications, it
speaks to our alienations.4 It is tempting to present The Wizard of Oz as an
4
There is a commonplace mis-reading of Baudrillard which assumes his argument to
be that all constructed images are hyperreal or simulatory. However Baudrillard’s
essay The Order of Simulacra (1993: 50-86) presents clear distinctions between
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
119
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
example of cinema before its acceleration into simulation and its loss of the
power of illusion. But the greatness of the film seems, as Rushdie (1992: 26)
argues, to have been the result of accident, coincidence or rather destiny, not
intention.
We’re off to see the Wizard!
The film begins with a great, whirling roar. Before Dorothy appears, before
Kansas appears, we hear the twister, the hurricane, the gale that is Dorothy –
Dorothy’s Otherness, her double, her destiny. Dorothy, we learn, is fleeing
Miss Gulch and naturally she seeks the protection of her family, Auntie Em
and Uncle Henry. But the opposition of Good and Evil, the polar structure of
many a lesser tale, is immediately shown to be out of kilter; Miss Gulch is
not unproblematically ‘evil’, she speaks with the backing of the Law, she has
a warrant from the local sheriff demanding that Toto is handed over to be
destroyed after allegedly biting her. Gulch is not evil, she is hyper-moral, she
is the force of Law applied without compassion (‘That dog is a menace to the
community’, Gulch says). Uncle Henry and Auntie Em can do nothing to
challenge this power structure as they are honest, law-abiding folks. In the
opening scenes, Auntie Em’s professed Christianity prevents her from
speaking her mind to Miss Gulch; here Christianity is utterly compromised,
reduced to the service of the Law. Adult beliefs and principles are revealed to
be impotent and contradictory; they cannot be relied upon in difficult times.
Moreover adult principles and laws can be perverted and misused to harm
those we love the most and, sure enough, Toto, scheduled for destruction, is
taken by Gulch. These are hard lessons indeed. The system leaves Dorothy
and Toto with no protection and no recourse, yet destiny intercedes and
orders with hyperreality as the major characteristic of the third order only. Applying
this scheme to the film, the fantastical land of Oz, though clearly constructed, is
imaginary or make-believe which are characteristics of the second order. The film’s
evocation of Kansas is achieved through elaborate theatrical staging, including hand
painting and the mechanical production of the twister effect, not the re-production
of digital code and so, in Baudrillard’s scheme, are again second order simulacra and
not hyperreal. For production details on the creation of Kansas and Oz see Scarfone
and Stillman (2004). The capacity of the film to engage us in our alienated identities
is developed in the sophisticated and convincing ‘queer’ reading offered by Davis
(2001).
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
120
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
Toto escapes and returns (‘Toto, you came back!’ Dorothy cries). The return
of the dead, the overcoming of death and the challenging of injustice – some
of the most powerful fantasies of the human condition are dramatised by the
opening scenes of the film.
The farm hands, Hunk, Hickory and Zeke, are ambivalent figures, as
are their counterparts in Oz. Hunk acts clever, advising Dorothy to avoid
Miss Gulch’s property on her way home, to use her brains: ‘Your head ain’t
made of straw’ he says to Dorothy. Yet one suspects that he is actually not
very smart, and, stupidly, he has just had his thumb hit by a hammer because
he was not paying attention. Zeke acts tough, telling Dorothy to ‘have a little
courage … next time walk up to her [Gulch] and spit in her eye – that’s what
I’d do’. Zeke talks big, yet almost straight away we learn that he is scared of
the pigs, nevertheless he does rescue Dorothy when she falls into their pen.
Finally, Hickory indulges in posturing, claiming ‘one day they’ll erect a statue
to me’. And in Oz he becomes a kind of statue, rusted solid, while Hunk and
Zeke are depicted as lacking precisely the qualities that they over-emphasised
in the early Kansas scene. The film, released in the last days of Sigmund
Freud’s life, clearly offers something like a dream-work in the Freudian sense.
The film version introduces the device of the dream, in the children’s story
Dorothy is literally blown into another, parallel world (Baum 1900: 13-4).5
The farm hands, Gulch and Professor Marvel are all transcribed into Oz, a
process that remains just below the level of Dorothy’s conscious awareness
during ‘the dream’, but is realised on her wakening. Further, Toto, in Kansas,
pulls away Professor Marvel’s sausage from the toasting fork just as he pulls
away the great humbug’s curtain in the palace of Oz, a gestural and dramatic
transcription, not merely one of character. While undoubtedly part of the
appeal of the film, these neat conversions do not account for the film’s
seductiveness. The realities of Kansas are not merely projected into Oz, they
are suspended, annulled, indeed almost forgotten, lost in the mythic and
5
As a mother and a philosopher, I see the imagery of Dorothy’s journey as a passage
through the birth canal. This resonates with another reading where Dorothy Gale
has been described as ‘a hero whose voyage(s) to Oz are births and re-births
symbolised over and over again…’ (Duncan 2008: 56). M.D.
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
121
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
imaginary world of Oz. In confronting the fighting trees, Dorothy says ‘I
keep forgetting I’m not in Kansas’ and after Tin man snuffs out the fire ball
thrown by the witch to burn the scarecrow, Dorothy feels that she has
known them both for a long time: ‘Still I wish I could remember’. Memory
seduces, pulls back or diverts, making the path to the Emerald city that much
harder for Dorothy than her fellow-travellers who do not once remember
their past.
The world of Oz is truly spectacular and the shift, early in the film,
from the eerie monochrome of Kansas to the saturated Technicolor of Oz
remains stunning. One of the most powerful moments of the film is when the
Munchkins’ song of jubilation at the demise of the Witch of the East rises to
a crescendo, and is then shattered by the absolute horror of the appearance
of a new, more potent evil – the Wicked Witch of the West. Rushdie
contends that Oz is a place without religion, a land without transcendent
values; the wizard may be feared but is certainly not worshipped: ‘[t]his
absence of higher values greatly increases the film’s charm’ (Rushdie
1992:12). We are not convinced by Rushdie’s argument. One of the most
stunning, dizzying moments of the film for me, a sociologist6, is that the land
of Oz possesses a distinct, quasi-feudal division of labour, and a definite
state, military and ceremonial structure. And Oz is clearly not a secular
society; it appears to have a priesthood as well as a judiciary. There is a
coroner whose role it is to establish that the Wicked Witch of the East ‘is not
merely dead, but is really most sincerely dead’. Further, the roles of Priest,
Mayor and Coroner, from the evidence of their marvellous costumes, seem to
be reversed or altered: the character in black priestly robes is the coroner, the
character addressed as Mayor wears country tweeds, a character in purple,
ecclesiastic robes and dog-collar speaks of legality, while it is left to another,
distinctly grey and ineffectual looking character, to raise the issues of
morality and spirituality. If these sources of authority are not revered as
such, the Munchkins do, quite clearly, bow their heads in reverence when
Glinda speaks the Wizard’s name. So far as ‘politics’ is concerned we are
6
W.P.
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
122
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
confronted by an incomprehensible yet manifest structure as we meet the
nominated ‘representatives’ of The Lullaby League and of The Lollipop
Guild. Oz, like Kansas, has a state religion, it is simply that state religion has
such limited power; it has lost the charge, ambivalence and volatility of the
sacred. Like Auntie Em’s Christianity the institutional religion of Oz is
powerless against the Wicked Witch of the West.
The Wicked Witch of the West seems not to mourn her sister, she
desires only the possession of the ruby slippers, magicked from her sister’s
feet to Dorothy’s by Glinda. The Wicked Witch of the West desires power, or
rather seeks to compensate for her lack of power (‘You have no power here,
be gone before someone drops a house on you too’, says Glinda to the
Witch). By possessing the ruby slippers – which it seems enabled her sister to
dominate Munchkinland, the Wicked Witch of the West will become more
powerful than both Glinda and the Wizard: ‘I’ll be the most powerful person
in Oz’, she shrieks. Destiny has brought Dorothy into the power struggles
over who rules Oz; it was by destiny not volition that her house landed on
the Witch of the East. Further, she is given no choice by Glinda as the ruby
slippers are ineluctably fastened on her feet, just like the unfortunate Karen
in Hans Christian Andersen’s The Red Shoes (2004 [1845]: 207-212).
Glinda, the Good Witch of the North, is, as Rushdie puts it, ‘soppy’
and saccharine. Yet as a magical force she is exterior to the state religion of
Munchkinland, just as is the Wicked Witch of the West. We disagree with
Rushdie’s position that ‘[i]n the moral universe of the film … only evil is
external’ (Rushdie 1992: 42). Rather ‘good and evil’, as binary opposition, is
severely shaken by the narrative, ripped by the twister and by Dorothy Gale
who is, in a sense, beyond good and evil.7 With her friends Dorothy
overcomes both the ‘hyper’ good/evil of Gulch/Wicked Witch of the West,
and also triumphs over the ‘good’ of the ‘great humbug’ himself the Wizard.
The film does not resolve or displace the good/evil opposition, as
Structuralist analysis might contend, thereby making evil more palatable, less
7
See Duncan (2008) for a convincing study of successive moves in the cultural
incorporation of Dorothy into ‘a needy adult’ in ‘dramatic contrast to Baum’s vital
and vigorous female child-hero’ (p. 60).
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
123
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
threatening, to young viewers. Rather, the film’s narrative shatters the
opposition; it exposes its simulatory nature and, in doing so, sets up the play
of symbolic relations between and beyond these poles, symbolic relations of
radical Otherness, or what Baudrillard termed ‘the dual principle’
(Baudrillard 1999: 90-102).
Like Baudrillard’s thought, the film challenges and subtly undermines
the notions of identity and non-contradiction, the operative forces of binary
disjunction. Only a short distance down the Yellow Brick Road, Dorothy
encounters Scarecrow, destiny brings them together.8 Dorothy has reached a
crossroads: there are three possible routes, all of them equally yellow. She
doesn’t know which way to go, she cannot decide, but she doesn’t need to
because, immediately, impossibly, fate intervenes as Scarecrow speaks to her.
It could be objected that the notion of radical otherness, as Baudrillard poses
it, is invalidated by the fact that Dorothy and her friends share a common
language – they all speak English and so are not radically Other at all. While
language barriers are not common in dreams (I frequently converse with
aliens9), a great strength of the film is its dramatisation of the suspension of
referential language. For example, scarecrow speaks to Dorothy (‘Pardon me,
but that way is a very nice way. That way is quite nice too’) but Dorothy
does not reply because, of course ‘Scarecrows don’t talk’. So scarecrow as
scarecrow (as an identity position in referential language) is inaudible to
Dorothy, it is only scarecrow as beyond ‘scarecrow’, as radical Other that is
audible.
SCARECROW: That’s the trouble. I can’t make up my mind. I’ve got no
brain, only straw.
DOROTHY: How can you talk if you haven’t got a brain?
SCARECROW: I don’t know. But some people without a brain do an
awful lot of talking, don’t they?
DOROTHY: Yes, I guess you’re right.
8
I’d like to express my gratitude to Marcus Doel, David Clarke, William Merrin and
Richard Smith for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper. W.P.
9
W.P.
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
124
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
No further confirmation is needed. The friendship is sealed when Scarecrow
falls down and Dorothy rushes to help him, exclaiming: ‘There goes some of
you! Aren’t you hurt?’ and Scarecrow replies: ‘No, I just pick it up and put it
right back’. Once the pact is forged they do not need to decide which way to
go, and they don’t, they simply dance together and go wherever the dance
may take them. This is an initiation, a mutual seduction that delivers them
from themselves and that opens them to destiny.
We might say that Dorothy rescues Scarecrow from remaining a
scarecrow. Similarly Tin man left alone cannot speak, because he is made of
tin and because his mouth has rusted. Like Scarecrow he speaks with the
force of impossibility, and the response of Dorothy and Scarecrow is to
accept impossibility. Lions, of course, do not speak, they roar, but this lion
roars in order not to speak. When his roaring fails to impress anyone he
speaks, and when he speaks he is not a lion but a friend. Friendship delivers
them
from
the
confinement
of
identity,
from
their
condition
of
‘discontinuity’, to borrow a term used by Baudrillard but taken from Bataille
(Bataille 1986: 15).
Fate brings Scarecrow and Dorothy to the Tin man. Tin man is
initiated through his dance and the three become friends. During his dance
Dorothy and Scarecrow are seen whispering to each other, evidently deciding
to ask Tin man to join them. Tin man and Scarecrow are presented with a
choice (unlike Dorothy who was not given a choice by Glinda) and must
make a decision. But the Tin man’s decision is, in a sense, made for him by
the Witch’s attack on the Scarecrow. Tin man stifles the fire-ball hurled by
the Witch to burn Scarecrow. The pact is forged:
SCARECROW: I’ll see you get safely to the Wizard now, whether I get a
brain or not!
TIN MAN: I’ll see you reach the Wizard, whether I get a heart or not!
DOROTHY: Oh, you’re the best friends anybody ever had … and its
funny but I feel as if I’ve known you all the time. But I couldn’t have,
could I?
Later, when fate brings the party to the Lion they are all terrified. Dorothy
finds the courage to slap Lion’s face only because he has threatened both
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
125
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
Scarecrow and Toto, accusing him of ‘picking on things weaker than you
are’. Only seconds after being threatened, Scarecrow and Tin man extend the
invitation to find the Wizard to the cowardly Lion. Lion is relieved and
delighted:
My life has been simply unbearable … It’s been in me so long. I’ve just
got to tell you how I feel.
[Sings] Yeah, it’s sad believe me missy, when you’re born to be a sissy,
without the vim and verve.
The friends deliver each other from identity and from ‘reality’; they are
opened to destiny and it is their shared destiny to shatter the power structure
of Oz.
Pay no attention to the man behind the curtain
[P]ower is in essence no longer present except to conceal that there is
no more power (Baudrillard 1994:26).
Even after the realisation of their individual desires, after the Wizard’s
conferring of tokens of ‘courage’, ‘brains’ and ‘heart’, their pact rooted in
radical Otherness, remains. On being given a medal to signify courage Lion is
still not ‘a lion’, he remains of the pact, begging Dorothy to stay with them,
and still proudly wearing a red ribbon in his hair. This Lion is still queer, still
soft and still friendly, he still would not ‘pass’ for a ‘real’ lion. Similarly, Tin
man has not become a ‘real’ tin man, this is fundamentally impossible
because there is no such ‘thing’. Nor is he made whole or complete in gaining
his testimonial. Indeed Tin man is even more prone to tears and rust now he
is able to acknowledge that he has feelings. And Scarecrow is still not ‘a
scarecrow’, nor has he become homo sapien (true, thinking man), after the
conferment of the diploma, he is still above all Dorothy’s friend. The friends
cannot be made complete, because in their singularity and radical Otherness,
they are already perfectly complete. The friends then cannot be reduced to
the proper identity position that language ascribes them: they remain
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
126
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
radically Other and it is not magic or fantasy that maintains them, it is their
symbolic pact – once forged it is never broken. Even after Dorothy awakes
from the ‘dream’ she will not submit to the rationalisation that it was all just
a dream. It was, Dorothy insists, a ‘truly live place’ – not merely real but
‘live’, and the live relations with her friends endure because they are still with
her, both figuratively and in the persons of Hunk (Scarecrow), Hickory (Tin
man) and Zeke (Lion).
In Oz Dorothy becomes radically Other. She is not a traveller, she is
not merely away from home; she is away from her universe. Her status in Oz
is not comparable to her status in Kansas; fate has made her a goddess. Her
transformed status, from ‘small and meek’ farm girl to avenging angel is
utterly incomprehensible to her; it cannot be assimilated to her identity or
subjectivity. It cannot be assimilated because as avenging angel she is also
small and meek, as she re-iterates to the wizard; she exists in a state of
ambivalence and radical Otherness, not of ‘identity’.
Dorothy accepts, without reservation, the friendship of Scarecrow, Tin
man and Lion and they immediately become ‘the queer party … so strange a
company’ (Baum 1900: 56, 67). Dorothy accepts them in their state of loss,
incompletion and unintelligibility: a scarecrow who can talk but barely walk,
who has no brain but is remarkably thoughtful and astute; a man of tin who
apparently was once flesh and blood, who has no heart but possesses
remarkable sensitivity; a talking lion with no courage who keeps fighting for
the sake of his friends.10 They are radically other, unencumbered by the
banal illusions of knowledge, and its concomitant of misunderstanding, or
even hyper-understanding, understanding oneself or the other only too
10
For an excellent study of the change in audience reception from ‘cowardly’ to
‘sissy’, of the ambivalent characterisation of the Lion affected by repeat viewings, see
(Davis 2001). Davis argues that ‘ultimately the Lion’s wish isn’t only about courage,
it’s about gender, and desire’ (2001: 5). Where we depart from the initial common
ground of affirming ambivalence in the characterisation of the Lion, is in focusing on
the way the Lion is engaged in a pact with Dorothy and her mates, a pact that
delivers each not only from their individual ‘lack’, but from the confines of
individuality itself.
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
127
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
well.11 Their pact is a deliverance. The queer party deliver each other from
the determinations and demands of self and identity and delivered of these
burdens they are able to embrace destiny.
After accidentally (or by destiny!) killing the Wicked Witch of the
West, the band returns to the Wizard. It is at this point that it is revealed that
there is no wizard: ‘pay no attention to the man behind the curtain’. Here the
film dramatises the last, desperate resort of power; just before it is
annihilated power says ‘ignore the evidence of your own eyes, just accept
what power wants you to do’. Power is already dead in this enunciation, but
power purports to be alive: it lives on after its death in a hyperreality.
What the exposed non-wizard offers the friends is not the imaginary
signified ‘thing’: the brain, the heart and courage, but rather a signifier, and
abstract token which merely stands for or signifies these qualities. These
token signs are efficacious because, of course, each of the friends already
demonstrated their desired attributes to a remarkable and admirable degree –
they simply did not ‘real-ise’ this. But as ‘non-wizard’ he does demonstrate
wisdom of sorts: once his ‘power’ is exposed as illusion, he goes on to show
how all power, and all identity positions and attributes are simulatory,
dependent upon signifiers. His wisdom here is an echo of the wisdom he had
shown in Kansas, when he helped Dorothy albeit through trickery, having
recognised her need for her family.
The non-wizard’s conferring of tokens might suggest a hyperrealisation
of the characters’ desires; they might be seen as the poisonous or potlatching
gifts of the consumer system (Baudrillard 1998: 46). However, their pact,
their mutual seduction, prevents the dangers implicit in the fulfilment of
desire (what Baudrillard termed ‘the despair of having everything’)12, from
being realised. Too much courage might endanger the Lion, too much
11
Acknowledgement of radical otherness, if such a thing can occur, would dissolve
the problem of understanding/misunderstanding, transforming the epistemological
stance into an ethical one. In responding to the Other the barrier of difference is
broken. For a discussion of the nature of acknowledgement in contrast with ‘respect’
see Dhanda (2008: 170-190).
12
Baudrillard’s essay ‘The Despair of Having Everything’ is available at
http://www.egs.edu/faculty/baudrillard.
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
128
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
thinking exhaust the Scarecrow, too much emotion shatter the Tin man.
However the band is not susceptible to these dangers because the conferring
of tokens does not result in any incremental change, rather it leads to
metamorphoses: each one transforms into an Other. Mere change
presupposes the logic of identity: an underlying discretely continuing entity,
which
changes.
Metamorphosis,
on
the
other
hand,
eschews
this
presupposition: whatever anything is, it can also become something else;
symbolic exchange makes this happen. .13 The gift giving relation is one of
symbolic exchange. The conferring of ‘gifts’ cannot potlatch or incur a debt
that wounds, humiliates or obligates, because the non-wizard gives nothing.
Further he does not give as wizard, he gives as exposed fraud, he gives as
nothing. Nor are the queer party indebted to each other because they gave
only of that which they did not know they possessed, their absence, alterity
or radical otherness, that in themselves which only the Other can perceive.
The pact of symbolic exchange is, indeed, a mortal danger for the
dominant order. Power is tied to the ‘real’, it cannot function without it but
symbolic exchange suspends the real and.reveals that ‘law and order
themselves might be nothing but simulation ‘ (Baudrillard 1994: 20,
emphasis in orig.). Their pact destroys the Wicked Witch of the West,
without resort to violence, and the ‘all powerful’ Oz becomes, once more, an
elderly man blown off course by a gale.
One can offload one’s will, one’s desire, on to someone else and, in
return, become free to take on responsibility for someone else’s life. A
symbolic circulation of affects and destinies is created, a cycle of
alterity – beyond alienation and all the individual psychology in which
we are trapped. There is in this symbolic circulation, in this sharing of
destinies, the essence of a subtler freedom than the individual liberty to
make up one’s mind (Baudrillard 1999: 85).
13
For a discussion of the important distinction between change and metamorphoses,
see Baudrillard (1999: 77-89)
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
129
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
Bibliography
Andersen, H. C. (2004) Fairy Tales, London: Penguin Classics.
Bataille, G (1986) Erotism: death and sensuality, San Francisco: Marion
Boyars.
Baudrillard, J. (1983) In the Shadow of the Silent Majorities, New York:
Semiotext(e).
Baudrillard, J. (1987) The Evil Demon of Images, Sydney: Power Institute.
Baudrillard, J. (1988) America, London: Verso
Baudrillard, J. (1990) Seduction, New York: St. Martins.
Baudrillard, J. (1993) Symbolic Exchange and Death, London: Sage.
Baudrillard, J. (1993b) The Transparency of Evil - Essays on Extreme
Phenomena, London: Verso.
Baudrillard, J. (1994) Simulacra and Simulation, Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press..
Baudrillard, J. (1998) Consumer Society – myths and structures, London:
Sage.
Baudrillard, J. (1999) Impossible Exchange, London: Verso.
Baudrillard, J. (1999b) ‘For Illusion isn’t the Opposite of Reality’ in
Photographies 1985-1998, Hatje Cantz: Neue Galerie Graz.
Baudrillard, J. (2005) The Intelligence of Evil, or The Lucidity Pact, London:
Verso
Baum, L. Frank (1900) The Wonderful Wizard of Oz, London: Penguin
Classics.
Cloverfield (2008) dir. Matt Reeves, Paramount Pictures.
Constable, C. (2000) ‘Beyond Theory in Crisis: Feminist Futures for Film
Theory’ in Women’s Philosophy Review, No.26, pp. 28-56.
Davis, R. (2001) ‘What WOZ: Lost Objects, Repeat Viewings, and the Sissy
Warrior’ in Film Quarterly, Vol. 55, No. 2 (Winter), pp.2-13.
Dhanda, M. (2008) The Negotiation of Personal Identity, Saarbrüken:VDM
Verlag Dr. Müller.
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
130
Film-Philosophy 14.2
2010
Duncan, S. (2008) ‘Lost Girl: Diminishing Dorothy of Oz’ in Studies in
Popular Culture, 31.1 (Fall) pp.55-67.
Gane, M. (ed.) (1993) Baudrillard Live, London: Routledge.
Grace, V. (2000) Baudrillard’s Challenge, London: Routledge.
Kellner, D. (1989) Jean Baudrillard: from Marxism to Postmodernism and
beyond, London: Sage.
Lacan, J. (1977) Ecrits – complete edition, New York: W.W. Norton.
Mauss, M. (1990) The Gift – the form and reason for exchange in archaic
societies, London: Routledge.
Nietzsche, F. (1990) [1889] Twilight of the Idols, London: Penguin.
Pawlett, W. (2007) Jean Baudrillard: Against Banality, London: Routledge.
Rushdie, S. (1992) The Wizard of Oz, London: BFI.
Scarfone, J & Stillman, W. (2004) The Wizardry of Oz, 2nd edition, New
York: Applause.
Filmography
The Wizard of Oz (1939) dir. Victor Fleming (also King Vidor and at least
two other directors contributed), MGM.
Quantum of Solace (2008) dir. Marc Forster, Columbia Pictures.
Film-Philosophy | ISSN: 1466-4615
131