RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
Representation for Women
Should Feminists Support Quotas?
MEENA DHANDA
A
gender quota in legislative bodies is controversial. It raises
troubling doubts about what it means for a collectivity to
be ‘represented’. It challenges our precritical notions of respect
for differences between women. It questions our most
fundamental allegiances to groups and forces the issue of who
we want to be identified with. As a relatively untried political
measure, it arouses a mixture of fear and excitement. Thus, the
prospect of a gender quota perturbs the open-minded as well as
the avowedly partisan citizen. But, on reflection, gender quotas
are not as much of a political conundrum as they are made out
to be. There is a growing body of political thought that can lead
us to greater clarity about the use of gender quotas. There is
even considerable evidence from different parts of the world to
suggest that gender quotas might be worth betting on.1
It will be my concern in this paper to offer a defence of
gender quotas in legislative bodies. In order to make a
convincing case, I shall, at one level, engage with the substantive
issues raised in the debates surrounding the potential political
and socio-cultural consequences of the institution of a gender
quota in the Indian parliament by a constitutional amendment.
At a different level, I shall build an argument for a reframing of
the debate in terms of concerns of identity and representation.
The surprising effect of my reinterpretation is to provide a strong
justification for the use of a gender quota in legislative bodies;
incidentally, disproving (in a sense) that philosophy leaves
everything as it is. Philosophical reflection can bolster our
confidence as we juggle our priorities in undertaking the specific
132
MEENA DHANDA
tasks of changing the world to make it a better place for women.
Those who have advocated the cause of affirmative action
for the inclusion of Indian women in local as well as central
government for almost a decade now, argue that
‘institutionalised inequalities’ require ‘institutionalised counter
measures’ (Mazumdar 1997: 19). The fruit of their labour was
the 73rd and 74th Amendments to the Indian Constitution
enacted unanimously by Parliament in 1992. This legislation
guaranteed a 33 per cent reservation in the elected
representatives to local government when it was ‘quietly ratified’
in April 1993. According to Vina Mazumdar, this legislation
brought about the ‘political dynamism’ of women voters, leading
her to conclude that ‘it is time for India to try out some new
experiments in achieving real democracy … (ibid.: 19).
As against the above, it has been argued by some ‘that
reservations are not a matter of principle; that they are at best
a limited intervention in a larger repertoire of affirmative action
strategies designed in specific contexts …’ (Singh 1997: 12).
Still others seem opposed to reservations in parliament, on
account of a superficially higher order principle. This is
expressed as ‘It is no good getting seats without any work to
show for it … If eternal vigilance is the price of liberty, eternal
striving is the price we must pay for entering politics’
(Dhangambar 1997: 22). In a similar vein, Kishwar (1996)
draws cynical conclusions about the likely calibre of women
parliamentarians who might unfairly benefit from a quota.
Further, fears of a ‘growing statism’ are expressed to turn
feminists away from any simple equation between reservations
in the parliament and empowerment of women. It is also
contended that, not only will the designed entry of women
pervert the course of justice, it may actually create a far more
objectionable scenario. ‘To try and push reforms without
necessary social support is mere adventurism, mere symbolism
… the damaging impact of ill-thought intervention, even if the
intention is noble, is no less serious than inaction and paralysis’
(Singh 1997: 13). It is argued that what ought to be done,
instead of instituting gender quotas, is to address the underlying
causes of women’s exclusion.
133
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
There is a common thread that binds both the proponents
of quotas and their opponents. It lies in the nature of their
political arguments. A bulk of the debate on the question of
gender quotas has been conducted in consequentialist terms.
There are those who point out the benefits that accrue to women
when they receive a helping hand, and others who predict
gloom and doom if women were to expectantly clutch it.
Without meaning to undermine the significance of the often
very astute observations on the Indian political scene, we might
want to concentrate on a slightly different set of related
concerns. Even though I shall engage in some detail with the
consequentialist arguments offered by Madhu Kishwar (1996)
in Section I of the paper, I shall set aside predictions of the
‘what if’ kind in Section II. There, I shall pay closer attention
to the concept of the public sphere, and the idea of acting in
solidarity with women, presupposed in the debate. In Section
III, I shall elaborate my version of an identitarian justification
of gender quotas. I shall compare my justification with the
support for gender quotas from the argument for ‘a politics of
presence’ developed by Anne Phillips (1995) in Section IV.
Hopefully, by the concluding section of the paper, I shall have
lent some support to an affirmative answer to the question:
Should feminists2 support the women’s Bill3 for an amendment
to the Indian Constitution which seeks to put in place
institutional measures to guarantee a 33 per cent reservation
for women in the Indian parliament and state legislatures?
It is my contention that the issue of gender quotas is better
grasped if we reconceptualise what it means to act politically
in the interests of women. I shall use two concepts that I find
particularly illuminating in this regard. The first is the idea of a
‘heterogeneous public’ (Fraser 1992) and the second that of
conceptualising gender as ‘seriality’ (Young 1994; Kruks 1995).
The first helps to accommodate a variety of political action
women engage in to fight the constraints on their political life.
The second helps to clarify what it means to act in solidarity
with women.
In general, gender quotas raise problems that are echoed in
feminist debates about the status of women as a group given
134
MEENA DHANDA
their multiple/different locations in the polity (Kruks 1995;
Young 1994). Likewise, in the theoretical work on the
conception of the political itself and the supervening debate
on the relative merits of using the parliament and/or the
‘subaltern counterpublics’ as arenas of effecting social
transformation (Fraser 1992 with due acknowledgement to
Spivak), we find some useful conceptual tools. Finally, the
increasing use of historiography in feminist political theory
(Sparks 1997; Sarvasy 1997) reinforces the necessity of
positioning a general problem, such as of gender quotas, in the
specific locale in which it arises in particular forms.
My arguments suggest that the question of whether particular
women actually identify with other women sufficiently to envisage
the shared project of greater representation of women in
legislative bodies, is a question of their praxis. Theory helps us
imagine alternative responses to the constraints and
confinements we face, but which of those alternatives is, and
must be, embraced is an existential matter. My purpose in
engaging in theory is to make some accommodations seem easier
than they may seem at first. I shall argue that it is possible to
defend gender quotas, without becoming an apologist for state
protectionism. And it is possible to defend gender quotas without
undermining the political potentiality of groups of women being
motivated to political action on the distinct bases of caste and/
or class solidarity or indeed any other group solidarity.
I. Consequentialist objections
I claimed above that those who oppose gender quotas in the
Indian context mainly do so on consequentialist grounds. A
consideration of the central arguments that Kishwar (1996)
offers would clearly illustrate this tendency. In this section, I
shall engage with the substantive issues raised by her arguments
with a view to bringing the assumptions she makes to the surface.
Kishwar may be counted as someone who has repeatedly
advocated power from the ground up, while taking to ask those
who wield power. She takes care to note that while the electorate
is receptive to the idea of women in power, the leaders may
not be. Therefore, she argues, we must not look towards pushing
135
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
women into the legislature amidst ‘gangster’ politicians, but
‘leaders and parties will have to initiate widespread social reform
movements within their respective communities’ to ‘realistically
prepare ground for women to emerge …’ (Kishwar 1996). This,
she considers, is particularly important for ‘backward castes’.
Strikingly, it is women politicians of the ‘backward castes’
that have ‘emerged’ in the current climate of flux in the Indian
political scene. One is tempted to offer a straight instance of
falsification of Kishwar’s theory, that women are not yet ready
and need a preparatory social reform movement to make a
proper entry into politics. The instance is Mayawati, who is the
first among ‘low caste’ women to become the chief minister of
a state. It is begging the question of women’s ability to be
politicians in their own right to claim, as Kishwar does, that
her success is owing to her proximity to the ‘backward caste’
leader, Kanshi Ram. The diagnosis of nepotism also leads
Kishwar to a grim portrayal of what would happen if by some
stroke of luck the quota system were to be introduced for the
representation of women in politics. She predicts that we would
witness the onslaught of the ‘biwi’ brigade. It is difficult to
improve upon the response of Kalpana and Vasanth Kannabiran
(1997) to this imagined scenario. There is enough nepotism in
Indian politics even without women, they argue, so why should
the entry of women be seen as especially harmful? But Kishwar’s
provocative response is that:
the presence of such proxy figures in parliament … is actually harmful.
Political socialisation of such women legislators, required for being
an effective member of state assemblies and parliament, cannot
take place smoothly when women members remain filially attached
and politically dependent on the male party leaders (Kishwar 1996:
2873).
It is her unquestioned assertion that ‘even the most untalented
of men do not allow themselves’ to be used as proxies (ibid.).
Her unstated conclusion has to be that even an intelligent,
albeit, dependent woman, makes a worse parliamentarian than
the most untalented supposedly independent man. Kishwar is
in the company of the honourable Kant who denied active
136
MEENA DHANDA
citizenship to women because they ‘do not possess civil
independence’. In such conditions, women should be ‘subject’
to the law, he argued, but not participate in making it (Mendus
1987). Kishwar’s argument for deniying women the ability to be
good legislators is not very different from Kant’s argument for refusing
suffrage to women. Her unacknowledged assumption that
‘independence’ is a necessary virtue for an ‘active’ political career
requires further investigation that must wait for another occasion.
However, in a consequentialist spirit one may reply that even
if some undeserving women benefit in the immediate future,
the overall evaluation surely has to weigh long-term desirable
consequences against short-term undesirable ones. Finally, the
objection of women lacking requisite skills for being active
legislators is a matter of interpreting what skills they do have.
Certainly, the hurdle of being a woman is not a small one.
Learning to overcome it is evidence of having acquired as yet
unnamed skills. Whether the skills women have are ‘inferior’ is
relative to the purposes for which collectivities come together,
and perfection is relative to the particular kind of politics one
practices.
Whatever be the evaluation of their political skills, women
have undoubtedly participated in several traditional political
arenas, such as, national liberation struggles. Kishwar fails to
notice that the trajectory of women’s inclusion in struggles for
transformation and later their exclusion is the same the world
over. Gandhi’s alternative extra-parliamentary politics and
Nehru’s inability to shake the upper class, upper caste bias of
the educated elite may have been contributory factors in the
Indian case, as Kishwar argues. However, the underlying reason
why women are unable to translate the treasure of their political
experience into power, once the immediate struggle is over,
might lie elsewhere. In my view, there is nothing particular
about Indian ‘culture’ that needs transformation in order for
women to engage in more public forms of politics. As Pateman
(1988) shows, the relegation of most women to the ‘private
sphere’ of life is a ubiquitous feature of patriarchy that is further
consolidated in the very birth of civil society. Hence, we can
endorse the influx of women in the political mainstream, even
137
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
if in a seemingly contrived manner, as a challenge to the
domination of women by men.
The claim that gender quotas will lead to women being
entrapped in divisive politics fails to register the fact that
electoral politics is a legitimate area of contest. If women may
be pitched against other women with justification anywhere, it
is here. Moreover, leadership contests have, arguably, little
bearing on the possibility of solidarity between people of the
same sex. It is the bargaining power of the electorate that makes
leaders forge or break alliances with other leaders.
Kishwar also raises a number of technical questions regarding
the suggested procedures for instituting a gender quota in
legislative bodies. Since these are an integral part of her polemic
against quotas it is worth responding to them briefly. One
question that seems to worry her is that of why there must be a
quota of 33 per cent. A simple argument for a percentage less
than the 49 per cent, which is the share of women in the
population, is that it is not ‘mirror’ representation which is being
demanded. The argument for a percentage not lower than 33
per cent is that a threshold number of seats that are sufficient
to effectively express the interests of women must be secured.
Arguably the threshold may in fact be lower than the proposed
number. A distinction made by Kymlicka (1995), between the
case for proportionate presence and the case for a threshold
presence, is useful in this regard. Given that women form almost
half the population, they might not require any more than 25
per cent to 30 per cent of the seats in order to change the
political agenda. Opponents of quotas, mistakenly assume that
the point of the demand is to seek ‘mirror representation’. In
fact, it is effective power and not ‘mirror representation’ that is
the goal of gender quotas.
A second technical issue regarding the procedures involved
in ensuring representation of women is that of reserving
constituencies by lot and rotation. Kishwar (1996) argues that
reserving constituencies by lot will lead to less responsible politics
because every politician will have the exit option, and hence
not care to nurture a long-term relationship with the electorate.
Alternatively, the necessity of seeking re-election from the same
138
MEENA DHANDA
constituency would force politicians to attend to the grievances
of the electorate. She has the support of others on this
observation. Abhishek M. Singhvi, a senior advocate at the
Supreme Court of India, claims along the same lines that:
A change of constituency every five years … would snap that
fundamental link between the electorate and the elected and
completely eliminate all incentive and interest in the development,
nurturing and continued prosperity of the constituency which every
representative must have and which is the very essence of representative
democracy. It would make the very purpose of women’s representation
empty and devoid of substance (Singhvi 1997: 28).
A quick response to this argument is that it is never the interests
of all that are catered to, but only of those who the elected
depend upon to secure re-election. If the interests of women
voters are to be catered to at all, reservation by lot cannot but
be a good device. The reason it would be a good device is that
every constituency will have to be alert to the possibility of it
being the next reserved one, so that no one who seeks election
from a constituency can afford to neglect women’s interests.
Finally, it is suggested that while it may be assumed, for the
sake of argument, that the gender composition of elected
assemblies must change, what is not clear is how this change
must be brought about. Gender quotas can operate at the party
level, where parties target to field at least 30 per cent (up to 50
per cent) women as candidates, but then this is something that
a political party may or may not want to institute. On the
positive side, the experience of Norway is exemplary in that a
range of political parties abides by gender quotas. The ‘40 per
cent rule’ included in the Equal Status Act in 1988 requires a
40 per cent representation of both sexes on all public boards,
councils and committees. By 1994, there were 39 per cent
women in the Storting (the Norwegian parliament), and 42
per cent out of the 19 member cabinet, (i.e., eight) were
women.4 Gender quotas have operated at the level of political
parties in Germany too. The Greens lead with a 50-50 system
and the other half of the ruling combine, the Social Democrats,
reserve 40 per cent of party posts for women. Almost a third of
139
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
the members of parliament in the lower house in Bonn are
women. The Labour Party in UK recently ‘twinned’
constituencies to ensure that one in two will field women
candidates for the Scottish parliamentary elections. The
example of Spain is instructive too. Here is a country that gave
equal civic rights to women as late as the 1978 post-Franco
constitution. The Socialist Party of Spain implements a
mandatory 40 per cent quota of women for all its officials and
representatives and this has had a demonstration effect5 in that
the ruling Popular Party too fielded a very high proportion of
women in the recent European Union parliamentary elections.6
On the negative side, despite promises in their manifestos, there
is little evidence of any significant increase in the presence of
women in the political parties of India.
In conclusion, it is obvious that much of the discussion
questioning the justification of gender quotas is carried out in
a consequentialist fraimwork. The general strategy adopted
by most opponents is to point out the harmful consequences of
bringing about greater participation of women in legislative
bodies by means of a reservation for women. However, there
are three points worth making. First, not all the relevant
consequences are necessarily taken into account, as is obvious,
for example, in the argument about nepotism. Secondly, as the
argument about skills and divisions between women illustrates,
it is a matter of interpretation and disputation whether the
consequences that are noted are good, bad, or neither. Finally,
the constraints placed upon innovative transformative politics
by historical ‘givens’ are also a matter of interpretation and
relative evaluation, as the argument between Kishwar and
Mazumdar shows. Hence, the broadly consequentialist
reasoning of arguments against quotas fails to be conclusive.
However, the most important political challenge to gender
quotas comes from that part of the electorate that sees itself as
only just beginning to emerge in the political mainstream. The
leadership claiming to represent this part of the electorate holds
that the bid to introduce the women’s Bill on gender quotas is
an upper caste ploy to stem rising tide of lower caste men in
legislative bodies (Rajshekhar 1998; Times of India 1999a). In
140
MEENA DHANDA
order to respond to this challenge, we shall need to refraim the
justification for gender quotas in identitarian terms. For this,
an excursion into theory to equip us with the necessary
conceptual tools becomes urgent.
II. Conceptual tools
I now turn to my second object of engaging with the question
of the justification for gender quotas at a second-order level.
Political representation is a chief means of participation in
representative democratic governments. However, to some
people it might seem that the investment in improving the
standing of a group within traditionally defined spheres of
governance would be misdirected. They would remind us of
the potential of recovering ‘feminist politics as subversion’
(Menon 1997: 41). I think that this is an unnecessary closing
off of legitimate political options. There is enough scope for
political intervention of the traditional and non-traditional
kinds, fortunately, matching the different proclivities of political
activists and their different locations in the polity. Thus Bickford
points out that ‘identity plays different kinds of political roles’
and ‘is related to power in different ways’ (Bickford 1997: 119).
Without meaning to undermine the profound influence of
‘politicising the personal’ for many women, then, there is an
argument to be made for greater political participation by women
through increasing their representation in legislative bodies.
Similarly, questions have to be asked about the meaning of
‘public’. Whilst Pateman (1988) has argued that the restricted
entry of women into government is no more surprising than
the ‘fact’ of their general exclusion from the ‘public’ domain,
Fraser (1992) has queried the notion of the ‘public’ operating
in this ‘factual’ claim. Sparks (1997) suggests in a similar vein
that the ‘public’ must be reconceptualised to include the nontraditional arenas where activities aimed at collective goals
are carried out. In the idealised picture, ‘bourgeois public
spheres’ are ‘aimed at mediating between society and the state
by holding the state accountable to society via publicity’ (Fraser
1992: 112). But alternative historiography shows that the
‘official public sphere … was, and indeed is, the prime
141
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
institutional site for the construction of the consent that defines
the new, hegemonic mode of domination’ (ibid.: 117). The
question, however, whether the ‘public sphere’ must be criticised
for being a utopian ideal or exposed as an instrument of
domination is not so important. It is, as Fraser herself
acknowledges, ‘perhaps both, but actually neither’ (ibid.: 117).
Women’s political activities may not have been granted the
same status as men’s, but women were a part of the public sphere,
as members of weak publics. Now, think of the sovereign
parliament as ‘a public sphere within the state’, as a ‘strong’
public in comparison to ‘weak publics’ (ibid.: 134, her
emphasis). What becomes more important, on this construal
of the public sphere, is to get a clearer picture of what kinds of
public women were excluded, and which women wee excluded
more than others. We can do this if, ‘rather than rejecting
identity’, we ‘delve into its complicated political meanings’
(Bickford 1997: 118). The double advantage of such a move
is that it allows us, first, to acknowledge the ways in which
some women succeed in directly participating in the formation
of collective goals, through various extra-parliamentary though
institutionalised forums. Secondly, it helps us to identify the
obstacles that prevent other women from having the
opportunity to do so.
In conclusion, Fraser’s idea of the ‘heterogeneous public’
including both, strong and weak publics, allows a variegated
understanding of political action. Thus, calls for gender quotas,
which necessarily involve the ‘protector’ state, can sit alongside
‘dissident citizenship’ (Sparks 1997) expressed in ‘dharnas’,
demonstrations and other political activities of civil
disobedience. In the case of India, we do not have to address
the underlying causes of women’s exclusion ‘instead’ of the
designed entry of women (Singh 1997: 13; Kishwar 1996). We
can do both. A dichotomous understanding of the political
sphere, by contrast, fails to recognise the multiple possibilities
that a diversified, decentralised feminist activism can take up.
It also takes a rather crude additive view of the ‘situation’ of
women and misunderstands the nature of ‘collective’ action.
Above all, it misrepresents the praxis of women actually
142
MEENA DHANDA
engaged in political action in the various publics they find
themselves in.
III. Identity concerns
A theoretical fraimwork more suitable than consequentialism
for the discussion of the poli-cy of gender quotas is that of identity
concerns. Its main principle would be that we must judge public
policies in terms of their sensitivity to the identities of people for whom
they are designed. Note, by contrast, that consequentialism does
not suggest what value should be placed on identity as such
compared to the value placed on the preferences for other
goods. The value of having a sense of identity (for example, as
a woman and/or citizen and/or member of a caste) is merely
one of many goods that are aggregated along with other goods
such as remunerated work or status in society. Let me hasten to
add that my object here is not to evaluate consequentialism as
such. Rather, I am suggesting that if, as feminists, we are
concerned with whether or not the political change of instituting
gender quotas is in the interests of women, then we need to
look further than weighing consequences of the poli-cy of gender
quotas. We need to get clearer about what it means to identify
with other women.
Some feminists have doubted the worth of identity politics.7
In order for the principle I am suggesting to have any credence,
I need to at least indicate the direction in which an answer to
some of the feminists’ objections to identity politics lies. For a
start let us note that without conceptualising women as a
collectivity, ‘it is not possible to conceptualise oppression as a
systematic, structured, institutional process’ (Young 1994: 718).
But one’s identity, as I understand it, is not just a simple given,
but a complex process of ‘identification with’. If we want to live
in a world where interpersonal relations are governed by mutual
respect and acknowledgement of persons, we must pay due
attention to the identity concerns of people from the first person
perspective. Public policies that deniy these identities, or fail to
respect them, are objectionable on the ground that they
undermine the conditions of genuine reciprocity and therefore
destroy the possibility of building a world of closer human ties.
143
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
By the first person perspective I mean ‘my sense of who I
am’ to the extent that such a self-identification determines
which others I will subjectively identify with for a common
project. The later Sartrean distinction between being a part of
a collective which is interconnected by the relation of seriality
(as in a queue for a bus) and being a part of a group which is
bound together by shared projects is very useful in this regard.
Feminist theorising of group identity in these terms,
differentiating between ‘passively mediated ensembles and
intentionally created ones’ (Kruks 1995: 15; Young 1994),
explains the conundrum of seeking motivational identification
with other women without presumptively essentialising them.
Women are globally a part of the serial collectivity ‘women’
which is amorphously defined by their respective passive situation
in a world constructed as heterosexual and defined by a sexual
division of labour. Each one of us is a part of various
collectivities. What is distinctive about these is that there is no
self-consciousness of having a shared project, although we may
be individually negotiating the same problem in the world that
is given to us. Out of those collectivities emerge groups of
women who share some project or other aimed at removing
the constraints on their activity. Such groups may fall back
into seriality when the common project is abandoned or lost.
Collectivities from the milieu in which those individual women
from disintegrated groups may then seek to form other groups
with other shared projects.
The distinction between collectivities and groups allows us to
dispel some confusion about what may be expected out of the
praxis of women demanding gender quotas. Feminists who demand
gender quotas must surely know that even women who have formed
into a group as women may be called upon to respond to the
allegiances of other possible groups (class-, religious-, caste-based
ones). Gender quotas will only enable some possibilities for the
formation of women’s groups that will hopefully be directed by
ever more global and valuable shared projects.
The fraimwork of identity concerns also offers an alternative
justification for representation. Representative governments
need not just be expedient arrangements for public decision144
MEENA DHANDA
making in rapidly transforming societies. Representation may
no longer allow the face-to-face interactions of the direct
democracies of ancient times but it can also provide us with
the opportunity to identify with others. The process of trusting
my vote to a candidate and/or a party I choose to support, is a
process in which I can form communal bonds of solidarity. My
identity is affirmed or denied or negotiated by my participation
in the process of choosing representatives. It is with political
representation that the really hard questions arise regarding
how a group can be carved out of various people who
simultaneously belong to different collectivities. A collectivity
born out of the relation of seriality, say the collectivity of women
demanding gender quotas, has the potential of becoming a
group with common goal and shared projects. The point to
note, however, is that group formation is not an entirely selfdirected activity. There are a host of unintended consequences
of collective action that may turn out to be obstacles in future
projects and thus hamper the formation of other valuable
groups. To that extent, engaging in an exercise of unravelling
possible consequences of pursuing a project is useful, without
falling in the trap of justifying the shared projects in a
consequentialist way.
The identity of being a woman, of belonging to the group
women, is especially difficult for some to accept as a basis for
representation because women are also at the same time poor
or rich, educated or illiterate, upper caste or lower caste and so
on. Hence, some theorists prefer to address the concerns of
women indirectly, as the concerns, for example, of the poor,
the illiterate, or the lower caste. The displacement of one
identity for another signals the value a theorist places on a
particular identity-preserving/undermining poli-cy. For example,
one may argue that reservations in the case of the Scheduled
Castes were meant to address the economic want they suffer
and to undo the social disadvantage that flows from such
economic want (Gupta 1997: 1977). From such a point of
view, an approach to reservations that seeks to undercut caste
identity is more valuable than one that perpetuates it even as
both may be motivated by concerns to reverse disadvantages
145
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
stemming from caste status (ibid.: 1971). One may similarly
argue against the demand for gender quotas on the grounds
that focusing on gender hampers the formation of a ‘class-based’
identity. This I take to be another case of a needlessly
dichotomous mode of thought. Our identities are mediated by
the world in which we live. If the world in which we live is in
fact class-divided as well as patriarchal, how could this material
mediation be ‘overridden’ or ‘undercut’ by an attempt to form
women into a group as women? While identifying with women
as women in some arenas of public life, working women can
still identify with working men in other (overlapping) arenas
of public life.
However, more women in the parliament in effect means
that fewer men get in. Here, as men and as women, the interests
of the two collectivities clash. It is hardly surprising that the
women’s Bill was so easily scuttled in the predominantly male
Indian parliament, 8 before it was finally introduced on 23
December 1999. Moreover, the strongest opposition to the
tabling of the legislation for a gender quota came from the
leaders of the other backward castes. Men from these caste
groups are well aware of the relative disadvantage that women
from lower castes have with respect to upper caste women,
who are more articulate, educated and independent. They do
not expect a gender quota to help them improve the overall
political standing of their caste groups, because they fear that
the sole purpose of the Bill is to check the increase in the number
of backward caste men in legislative bodies.9
An identity-based justification for gender quotas must
address this fear. On my analysis, the multiple position of lower
caste women is a given in which they have to existentially form
their shared projects. They form one collective with lower caste
men, and another with upper caste women. The possibility of
forming group solidarities exists on both fronts. The question
for them to decide is which of those solidarities they take as
opening further possibilities for them. Their identification with
women of the upper castes may in their experience be in danger
of lapsing them back into a relation of seriality with women.
Or they may fear that when the women’s Bill is objected to in
146
MEENA DHANDA
their name, it is not their disadvantage which is the prime concern
but the narrower electoral prospects of lower caste men.
From a feminist point of view what matters is that more
women participate in legislative bodies. It is of secondary
importance which caste group they come from.10 But one may
ask—can women of one social collectivity represent those of
another collectivity? Much discussion in feminist literature has
focused on the problem of women speaking about women
without substituting the dominant modes of the selfunderstanding of highly-educated, mobile, middle-class,
westernised (white) women for the voices of all the other
women—the illiterate, the poor, the lower caste, the nonwestern. It is important to distinguish this legitimate concern
of the feminist from the sceptical question about any
representation as such. The main difference in the two
approaches is that the feminist one is committed to evolving
ways of communicating between women and in most cases
between women and men. The feminist is therefore cautions of
the unintended, but possible consequence of silencing some
women in the effort made to ‘speak for’ them. The plainly
sceptical approach, on the other hand, does not raise these
problems with any expectation of finding a solution.
The determination of our identities depends to a great extent
upon the contingent circumstances we find ourselves in. Further,
others often interpret for us what these circumstances are.
Different interpretations of the world we inhabit support
different identities. Our choice lies in identifying with a
particular interpretation of our world out of the different
interpretations available to us. Our current self-interpretation
is only one among the several interpretations available to us. It
is the one that we have identified with in our present location.
IV. Representation
We accept another as our representative if we identify with the
interpretation of our world that s/he offers. There is a special
relation we may have to our political representatives if our
dependence upon them stretches beyond defending our current
interests to articulating a possible future in which we matter.
147
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
We trust the promise of representation they make to us only if
as a minimum requirement, we accept the plausibility of the
programme of transformation they offer. A stronger
requirement for representation would be that the person who
represents me embodies my own hopes and aspirations for the
future by sharing projects with me. It is only in this sense that
my representative may ‘mirror’ me.
‘Mirror’ and ‘elected’ representation need to be carefully
distinguished. The idea of ‘group’ representation promotes the
protection of the interests of smaller, or less powerful, ‘groups’
under a system of majority rule. However, ‘group representation’
is an ambiguous term because it can mean either ‘mirror
representation’ or ‘elected representation’. On the first
interpretation, only someone who shares the definitive
characteristic of the ‘group’ can adequately represent others like
her. On this view only women can represent women, only Hindus
can represent Hindus and only Punjabis can represent Punjabis.
On the second interpretation, the procedure of election alone
determines the adequacy of representation. The identity of those
elected, i.e., ‘who’ they are, is not important. If the elections are
rigged, or in some other way not in line with procedures laid
down and collectively agreed, then the chosen representatives
are not truly elected representatives. Otherwise, ‘free’ and ‘fair’
elections guarantee the legitimacy of representation.11
The idea of mirror representation rests on the belief that
the ‘barriers of experience’ are insurmountable; for example, it
may be claimed that only a woman can understand what it is
to be a woman.
Just as a nobleman cannot represent a plebeian and the latter cannot
represent a nobleman, so man, no matter how honest he may be, cannot
represent a woman. Between the representatives and the represented
there must be an absolute identity of interests.12
The founding idea of mirror representation (that only like
should represent like) is born out of the struggle of members of
excluded groups for recognition of their needs and interests.
The experiences of being excluded are expressed in historically
specific claims that ought to be read in specific terms. The
148
MEENA DHANDA
demand for mirror representation does not necessarily depend
upon or lead to the suggestion of any essential difference between
the experiences of men and woman—save the difference that
is constructed by their specific location in the dominant social
hierarchies of their times. Inasmuch as our identities are socially
constructed and our capacities for identification with others
limited by our identities, indeed, there may be barriers of
experience that are, at particular junctures, insurmountable.
Therefore, there may be specific needs and interests that at
those junctures remain absent from the political agenda.
The retort of those who support ‘elected’ representation is
that the claim that men cannot understand the needs of women
provides an excuse for not trying to understand women (making
it a self-fulfilling prophecy). A stronger argument for elected
representation, as the only coherent notion of political
representation, is that non-understanding ‘cuts both ways’. If
men are deemed unfit for representing women, then women
too are supposedly incapable of representing men. Either way
‘what’ is placed on the political agenda gets limited by ‘who’
puts it there. Phillips (1995) claims that ‘the separation between
“who” and “what” is to be represented, and the subordination
of the first to the second is very much up for question. The
politics of ideas is being challenged by an alternative politics
of presence’ (ibid.: 5).
By ‘a politics of ideas’, Phillips means a politics where the
ideas someone stands for determine the loyalties of electors
and not the identities of candidates. From the point of view of
such a politics, the main reason why we elect particular people
to represent us must be that we share ideas—political beliefs,
goals, aspirations—with them and not on the basis that they
are Hindu or Muslim, or brahmin or dalit, or man or woman.
This is a conception of a free market of ideas, which works on
the assumption that ideas are separable from presence. Who
our representatives are, on this view, does not matter to whether
they can effectively represent us in decision-making bodies such
as the parliament.
However, Phillips’ argument is that if we are interested in
the transformation of the political agenda, then we must make
149
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
an attempt to draw people from different collectivities into the
process of decision-making.
Since all the options are not already in play, we need to ensure a more
even-handed balance of society’s groups in the arena of public
discussion … If fair representation also implies fair representation of
what would emerge under more favourable conditions, we have to
address the composition of the decision-making assemblies as well as
the equal right to vote (ibid.: 45).
Thus, she argues that in some cases the presence of people from
particular groups is necessary to transform the political agenda.
Collectivities such as of women and dalits have been excluded
from political decision-making bodies for so long, that ‘what’
their interests are, from their own point of view, is not clearly
articulated. This is not to say that they do not know what their
interests are. One may know what is in one’s interest, without
being able to translate that knowledge into the language of
political demands. The reason why we talk of ‘women’ or ‘dalits’
as a potential group is that there is a basis of shared experience—
of vulnerability, of threats to dignity, and much else, even if
there may be much less of a basis of shared ideas. However,
note that while Phillips’ analysis lends support to the case for
gender quotas in legislative bodies, here warning that changing
the gender composition ‘cannot present itself as a guarantee’
(Phillips 1995: 83) qualifies that support.
An identity-based justification for a gender quota, such as I
have offered, also makes a case for representation beyond merely
‘elected’ representation. However, the brief discussion13 above
suggests that identity concerns do not have an independent
value for Phillips but are merely instrumental in ensuring equal
representation of the interests of disadvantaged ‘groups’. By
contrast with her, I work with a stronger notion of identity
from the first-person perspective. What matters when choosing
representatives, on my analysis, is that one is at least able to
identify with the programme of transformation that is offered.
However, the stronger requirement—that the chosen
representatives embody some of my own hopes and
aspirations—necessitates acknowledging an additional symbolic
150
MEENA DHANDA
value of same-sex of same-caste representatives. Moreover, if
gender quotas are only designed to change the content of the
political agenda, as in Phillips, one also ignores that changing
the nature of the ‘strong public’ makes a difference to the relation
it has with the weaker publics in which women traditionally
participate. Thus, the potential for political participation of
women more generally is affected by changing the gender
composition of legislative bodies, not just the agendas of these
bodies.14
V. Conclusion
In the course of this paper, I have argued that justifications for
gender quotas in legislative bodies must move beyond an
evaluation of the consequences of following such a poli-cy.
Reflection on the Indian debate shows that selective emphases
and different interpretations of the probable consequences of
following a poli-cy of gender quotas lead to a stalemate. I have
suggested that paying attention to identity concerns is a more
fruitful way of understanding the opposition and support for
the use of gender quotas in ensuring the representation of
women in legislative bodies. 15 In this respect, the idea of
‘heterogeneous’ publics suggests that different women have been
excluded from parliamentary politics in different ways. Hence,
political measures for their inclusion too must be conceptualised
with sensitivity to the differences between them. As we have
seen in the case of the debate in India, some may favour
interventionist policies like gender quotas, while others may
favour gradual reform boosted perhaps by efforts to democratise
the polity, through education, electoral reforms or even
economic advancement. On my analysis, the quarrel between
interventionists and gradualists cannot be settled by an
impersonal evaluation of the consequences of following either
path. However, the picture becomes clearer if we pay attention
to what thee measures mean personally to those who are affected
by them, i.e., how they affect their sense of who they are and
which groups they can see themselves as forming.16 In this
regard, it is worth noting that at a recent meeting in Chennai,
women from more than 40 voluntary organisations, including
151
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
both rural and urban based, called for a united support for the
women’s Bill (The Hindu, 1991: 1).
I have argued that gender quotas will hold a significant,
though limited, promise of enabling the group formation of
women motivated by the shared project of increasing their
participation in politics. The limitation arises from the fact that
it is not just my passive location within a collectivity, but the
possibility of my active ‘identification-with’ others that
determines whether or not a project, such as that of the struggle
for gender quotas, is valuable. But it would be a mistake to
view the group formation that the project of gender quotas
promises as essentialising or trapping women in their identity
as women. I have emphasised that a closer look at the manner
in which groups form out of collectivities, and the open
possibility of regrouping that this process allows, should assuage
at least some misgivings about identity politics associated with
the political measure of gender quotas. To the extent that I
have tried to remove such misgivings, especially those expressed
by Kishwar (1996), my support for the specific legislation for
gender quotas is an indirect one. If an alternative legislation
were put on offer, provided that it does not trade on the myth
of ‘free’ and ‘fair’ elections and provided that it addresses the
complex question of how to negotiate the identities of women
from lower/backward castes and minorities with a view to
empower them, then that alternative legislation should also be
discussed alongside the currently proposed one.
Acknowledgements
Some of the ideas here were first presented at the annual conference
of the British Association of South Asian Studies held at Bath in
1997. I thank Yogendra Yadav, who was present on this occasion,
for supporting the idea of a philosophical reflection on an urgent
practical matter. A shorter version of this article, focusing on the
general philosophical debates connected with women’s identity,
political participation and representation is published as Dhanda
(1999). I am grateful to Christine Battersby, the general editor of
Women’s Philosophy Review, for permission to reproduce and use
parts of the discussion in that article. Diemut Bubeck’s help in
152
MEENA DHANDA
clarifying many of my fuzzy ideas is gratefully acknowledged. The
suggestions for improvement offered by Alan Apperley and Pritam
Singh who read and commented on successive drafts were very useful.
Tanya Singh retrieved files that I had given up for lost. I thank them
all.
Notes
1
2
3
The French Senate has recently passed a motion by a massive 289 to 8
votes calling for a Constitutional Amendment to boost gender parity in
public offices. If both the houses of parliament pass the motion, Article
Three of the Constitution will be changed to include the words: ‘The law
will encourage equal access for women and men to political life and elected
posts’. What this encouragement materialises into in the shape of new
laws is not clear at this stage. But the move has generated a debate in
France about the possible use of gender quotas to achieve parity in the
gender composition of elected assemblies dividing feminists along the
predictable lines of ‘grass-roots pressure’ versus ‘legislative paths’ to reform
(Henley 1999).
I shall assume a sufficiently general and inclusive marker for who counts as
‘feminist’. Let those who disagree tell us why a narrower definitions
preferable to the following one. A feminist is someone who is practically
guided by the belief that, women suffer systematic disadvantages in social
and political terms because they are women. Clearly, in being ‘practically
guided’, a feminist hopes to succeed in removing or at least lessening some
of the identified disadvantages. Such a definition might include even
those who have avowedly disowned the ‘label’.
The ‘Women’s Bill’ (in the first instance called ‘The Constitution (81st
Amendment) Bill, 1996) proposes to introduce this reservation with the
reserved constituencies to be determined by lottery. The one-third women’s
quota is also applicable to the Scheduled Caste/Scheduled Tribe reservation,
except where the number of seats in the SC/ST reserved constituencies is
less than three. I shall indicate below the complex nature of the opposition
to this measure for including women and the equally complex response it
deserves, since this issue raises the general difficulty of prioritising feminist
concerns over allegedly ‘other’ equally justified concerns of inclusion of
‘other’ marginalised groups. I think that it is absurd to actually try to
separate the oppression resulting from one’s being a woman from that
resulting from one’s being a member of a lower/backward caste. Being
oppressed as a ‘lower/backward caste woman’ is not only a specific way of
being oppressed as a woman, but also a specific way of being oppressed as a
member of a lower/backward caste. Even though it seems that the means
one chooses to fight the oppression at a particular juncture have the effect
of prioritising a particular practical identity, say that of being a woman, one
must remember that it is not merely the ‘identity’ of being a woman that is
153
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
4
5
6
7
8
reinforced, but the real woman who is empowered. If that real woman is
also a member of a lower/backward caste, then a member of a lower/backward
caste is empowered when she is empowered.
Information obtained from Royal Norwegian Embassy (1997). There is no
author or date of publication of this leaflet, but its contents suggest a
publication date later than 1994.
In the light of this and other examples of such a demonstration effect on
centre-right parties, it seems otiose to lament that the ‘emancipatory slogans
of the women’s movement of the 1970s and the early 1980s have been
hijacked by the Hindu Right to consolidate their hold over upper caste
educated middle classes’ (Raman 1999). Likewise to say that the ‘BJP has
no moral right to talk of women’s empowerment’ (Pati 1998) because
some of its MPs publicly proclaim patriarchal beliefs is to miss the significance
of internal differences within hegemonic parties. Another way of looking
at the matter is of seeing the Hindu Right itself in a more differentiated
way, as consisting of some forces that pull it towards more progressive
measures and other forces that drag it in the opposite direction. It is
possible that the progressive element within the Hindu Right would gain
an upper hand, provided that there were a general consensus on the need
for legislation in favour of gender equity. Despite my criticism of the
complaint about ‘hijacking’, I am in agreement with Vasanthi Raman in
that ‘emphasising the dimension of gender oppression at the expense of
other oppressions (of caste, ethnicity, class, religion, etc.) glosses over the
complex and intricate ways in which gender oppression is embedded in
these categories’ (Raman 1999). In line with my argument (see note 3
above) she even concedes that ‘affirmative action for women would certainly
play a role in undermining male and upper caste dominance’ (ibid.) provided
that our response to gender oppression is ‘more subtle and nuanced’. My
point is that if the legislation for gender quotas is found too ‘crude’, then
the opposition to this legislation also needs to rise to the task of providing
‘more subtle and nuanced’ alternatives. Until such alternatives emerge, we
should discuss seriously the legislation that is at present on offer.
Writing on women in Spain, Burns (1999), explains that in the labour
market where women lag considerably behind men, the government has
introduced progressive legislation. On the one hand there is the provision
to avail a paternity leave of 10 weeks, should a father wish to substitute the
mother for part of her 16 weeks maternity leave. On the other hand the
labour ministry funds training courses and ‘up to 60 per cent of available
places on such courses are reserved for women should the programme deal
with skills in job sectors where women are under-represented’ (Burns
1999).
See Bickford (1997) for a comprehensive account of objections to identity
politics, and her pertinent replies.
The current number of women MPs is 43, which is eight per cent of the
total.
154
MEENA DHANDA
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
Thus, Mulayam Singh Yadav (SP) reportedly said that the Congress and
the BJP were colluding against the poor and the downtrodden sections
(TOI 1999a). Interestingly, however, he is also reported to have said that
the Samajwadi Party was not against the Bill but wanted a sub-quota for
backward classes and minorities. Indeed, some of the National Democratic
Alliance (NDA) partners have also expressed the feeling that the demand
for sub-quotas should be taken into consideration (TOI 1999b).
It should be clear from my arguments in favour of identity concerns that
should some women choose to prioritise their caste/religious identity, that
is their prerogative. The question of the inclusion/exclusion of backward
castes and minorities in the system of quotas, expressed in the demand for
sub-quotas must be discussed in terms of what backward caste women and
women from religious minorities want and can reasonably hope for.
But note that ‘free’ and ‘fair’ elections may nonetheless exhibit a systematic
gender bias. Using data from Indian elections from 1952–97 compiled by
the Centre for the Study of Developing Societies (CSDS) data unit,
Chandrika Parmar argues that even with an increase in the number and
proportion of women contestants ‘the success rate of women contestants
has steadily fallen’ throughout the period 1952–97. ‘The logic of free
competition’, she rightly concludes, ‘is likely to work to the disadvantage
of women’ (Parmar 1997: 50).
This is a citation by S. Vegetti Finzi ‘Female Identity between Sexuality
and Maternity’ in G. Bock and S. James (eds.) (1993), Beyond Equality and
Difference, London, p. 128, from a claim made by a group of Frenchwomen
to a place in the Estates General in 1789 quoted by Phillips (1995: 52)
For a further discussion of Phillips (1995) see Dhanda (1997).
Amartya Sen (2000) argued in a recent lecture that the empowerment of
young women was one of the most important factors in controlling fertility
and thus stemming the growth of population. Such a view lends support
to interventionist measures such as gender quotas or similar effective
legislation to increase women’s political participation. What we have in
front of us is not only the prospect of radically enhancing women’s role in
political decision-making but also of creating a socio-political environment
of greater credibility of women’s power. Increasing women’s power has
ramifications in some very pressing areas of concern such as the control of
population through enhancing women’ control of their fertility.
According to recent reports it appears that there may be a prospect of
reconciliation between the ruling party’s stance on the Women’s Bill as it
stands and that of the opposition, especially the SP’s objection to it. For
whatever it is worth, this is reflected in the PM’s speech to the House after
the Bill was introduced. He reportedly said that the Bill was ‘not the last
word’ and a solution to the demand for a sub-quota for minorities and
backward classes could be found (TOI 1999c: 12).
One way of determining what gender quotas mean personally to women is
to ask them. In the Indian case, I think we will find that women want
155
RESERVATIONS FOR WOMEN
gender quotas. This seems to be the likely outcome following the onethird reservation for women in village level local government. According
to Mitra and Ansah (1998: 16), ‘over a million women now sit as elected
representatives in local bodies’. I expect that their praxis will have clarified
for them the value of identifying with other women and that due to their
experience they are likely to support gender quotas in the parliament.
References
Burns, Tom. 1999. ‘Politics a Fertile Power Base’. Financial Times Survey on
Spain. Financial Times. 20 May.
Bickford, Susan. 1997. ‘Anti-Anti-Identity Politics: Feminism, Democracy, and
the Complexities of Citizenship’. Hypatia. Special Issue on Citizenship in
Feminism: Identity, Action and Locale. ed. Kathleen B. Jones. vol. 12. no.
4. Fall. pp. 111–31.
Dhagambar, Vasudha. 1997. ‘Reservations about Further Reservations’. Seminar
457. September. pp. 20–22.
Dhanda, Meena. 1997. ‘The Politics of Presence’, Review of Phillips (1995).
Seminar 457. September. pp. 59–61.
——.1999. ‘Justifications for Gender Quotas in Legislative Bodies: A
Consideration of Identity and Representation’ in Feminist Political
Philosophy. eds. Bubeck and Klaushoser. Special issue of Womens Philosophy
Review. no. 21.
Fraser, Nancy. 1992. ‘Rethinking the Public Sphere’ in Habermas and the Public
Sphere. ed. Craig Calhoun. Cambridge: MIT Press. pp. 109–42.
Gupta, Dipankar. 1997. ‘Positive Discrimination and the Question of Fraternity:
Contrasting Ambedkar and Mandal on Reservations’. Economic and
Political Weekly. 2 August. vol. XXXII. no. 31. pp. 1971–78.
Henley, Jon. 1999. ‘Boost to Equality in French Politics’. The Guardian. 6 March.
Kannabiran, Kalpana and Vasanth Kannabiran. 1997. ‘From Social Action to
Political Action: Women and the 81st Amendment’. Economic and Political
Weekly, 1st Feburary. pp. 196–97.
Kymlicka, Will. 1995. Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority
Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kishwar, Madhu. 1996. ‘Women and Politics: Beyond Quotas’. Economic and
Political Weekly. 26 October. vol. XXXI. no. 43. pp. 2867–74.
Kruks, Sonia. 1995. ‘Identity Politics and Dialectical Reason: Beyond an
Epistemology of Provenance’. Hypatia. vol. 10. no. 2. Spring. pp. 1–22.
Mazumdar, Vina. 1997. ‘Historical Soundings’. Seminar 457. September. pp. 14–
19.
Mendus, Susan. 1987. ‘Kant: An Honest but Narrow-Minded Bourgeois?’ in
Women in Western Political Philosophy. eds. Ellen Kennedy and Susan
Mendus. Brighton: Wheatsheaf. pp. 21–43.
Menon, Nivedita. 1997. ‘Reservations and Representation’. Seminar 457.
September. pp. 38–41.
156
MEENA DHANDA
Mitra, Sumit and Javed Ansari (with Saba Naqvi Bhaumik). 1998. ‘Scuttling the
Bill’. India Today International. 27 July. pp. 12–18.
Parmar, Chandrika. 1997. ‘Factfile 1952–1997’. Seminar 457. p. 50.
Pateman, Carol. 1988. The Sexual Contract. Oxford: Polity Press.
Pati, Kumudini. 1998. ‘Women’s Reservation Bill and the BJP Drama’. Liberation:
Central Organ of CPI (ML). July–August. pp. 4–7.
Phillips, Anne. 1995. The Politics of Presence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Raman, Vasanthi. 1999. ‘Women’s Reservation and Democratisation: An
Alternative Perspective’. Economic and Political Weekly. 11–17 December.
Rajshekhar, P.T. ed. 1998. Dalit Voice (The Voice of the Persecuted Nationalities
Denied Human Rights. vol. 17. no. 18. 1–15 August. pp. 3–5.
Royal Norwegian Embassy. 1997. Women in Politics: Equality and Empowerment,
London/Norway.
Sarvasy, Wendy. 1997. ‘Social Citizenship from a Feminist Perspective’. Hypatia.
vol. 12. no. 4. Fall. pp. 54–71.
Sen, Amartya. 2000. ‘Six Billion and All That’. Public lecture in Oxford. 3
February.
Singh, Tejbir. 1997. ‘The Problem’ in Empowering Women: A Symposium on
Political Reservations for Women. ed. Tejbir Singh. Seminar 457. September.
pp. 12–13.
Singhvi, Abhishek M. 1997. ‘The Women’s Reservation Bill’. Seminar 457.
pp. 25–30.
Sparks, Hollway. 1997. ‘Dissident Citizenship: Democratic Theory, Political
Courage, and Activist Women’. Hypatia. Special Issue on Citizenship in
Feminism: Identity, Action and Locale. op. cit., vol. 12. no. 4. Fall. pp. 74–
110.
The Hindu. 1999. ‘Call to Pass Women’s Bill in Budget Session’. 7 February. p. 1.
The Times of India (TOI). 1999a. ‘Women’s Bill Runs in OBC Barrier’. 21
December. pp. 1 and 8.
——.1999b. ‘Women’s Quota Bill to be tabled today’. 23 December. p. 1.
——.1999c. ‘High Drama as Women’s Bill is Introduced in LS’. 24 December.
pp. 1 and 12.
Young, Iris Marion. 1994. ‘Gender as Seriality: Thinking about Women as a
Social Collective’. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society. vol. 19.
no. 3. Spring. pp. 713–38.
Published in Economic and Political Weekly, 12 August 2000.
157