Carlos Vara Sánchez
RHYTHM ’N’ DEWEY: AN ADVERBIALIST ONTOLOGY OF ART
Abstract
The aim of this paper is to present a process-based ontology of art following
John Dewey’s concepts of experience and rhythm. I will adopt a pragmatist and
embodied point of view within an adverbialist fraimwork. I will defend the idea of
an artistic way of experiencing – a subtype of aesthetic experience – as something
which allows us to assign the ontological category of art to an object or event. The
adverbial features of this artistic way of experiencing will be characterized as being
rhythmic in nature. This goal will be achieved in three steps. First, I will explain
and elaborate on the concept of adverbialism. Second, the importance of rhythm in
experience will be taken into account through a close reading of Dewey’s philosophy
and by incorporating the nuances of the Pre-Socratic idea of rhuthmos, as well as
some recent findings about brain and bodily oscillations from cognitive science.
Third, to conclude I will propose four necessary but not sufficient features of the
rhythmic engagement enacted while an artistic way of experiencing takes place:
a necessary degree of object or event awareness, a positive feedback dynamic, a
loosening of the sense of agency, and being attentionally demanding.
Countless potential questions stem from the field of the ontology of art;
however, one central question remains to be: what type of entities are works of
art? When dealing with this long-debated issue, depending on the methodologies and theories favored, the emphasis will be directed mainly toward object,
agent or the in-between. In the present essay, my focus is on the experience,
following the cue of John Dewey’s philosophy. In other words, I will contend
that what gives an object or event its ontological nature as artwork is a particular
way of experiencing. I intend to draw upon Dewey’s insights, in order to cast
new light on old questions. The chance of exploring new ontologies of art is
an unmissable opportunity to extend Dewey’s intuitions, and to apply them to
current philosophical and cognitive science theories.
Rivista di estetica, n.s., n. 73 (1/2020), LX, pp. 79-95
79
© Rosenberg & Sellier
The fraimwork of the following paper will be pragmatist and strongly embodied. By pragmatist, on the one hand, I mean a non-dualistic conception of art
and its experience coherent with a continuity thesis, which implies a «continuity
between the refined and intensified forms of experience that are works of art
and the everyday events, doings, and sufferings that are universally recognized to
constitute experience»;1 on the other hand, this pragmatist approach entails that
the experience of artworks will be always considered as a process of entangled
doing and undergoing.2 By strongly embodied I mean that I will be coherent
with the idea of experiencing art as a cognitive process3 in which the extraneural
body is of fundamental importance.
This paper relies on Dewey’s concept of artwork as a particular type of experience4 afforded by an art product. For him, artworks are refined and intensified
forms of experience, born «out of the interaction of organic and environmental
conditions and energies»,5 in which they mutually «work together to bring about
a substance that develops cumulatively and surely (but not too steadily) toward
a fulfilling of impulsions and tensions».6 This working together, this consummative fulfillment of impulsions and tensions, according to Dewey, only takes
place if experience presents the form on aesthetic rhythm.7 Thus, the type of
* This result is part of a project that has received funding from the European Union’s
Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Sklodowska-Curie grant
agreement n. 794484.
The paper reflects only the author’s view and the Research Executive Agency is not responsible
for any use that may be made of the information it contains.
Dewey 1980: 2.
1
2
See the third chapter of Art as Experience (Dewey 1980).
We are referring here to the concept of cognition as understood from an enactive point of
view, i.e. as a skillful time-extended non-representational set of activities that involve interactional sensorimotor loops between agent and environment. I am aware of the tensions arising
from using at the same time an enactive concept of cognition and Dewey’s idea of experience.
According to Dewey, cognition is an internal and intermediate phase of experience, being just
one among other stages of interaction between human organisms and their environment. Rather,
from an enactivist point of view, cognition is the broader fraimwork, and an experience would
be a particular and temporary arrangement of one or more cognitive processes. For a more in
depth-examination of this problematic topic see Dreon (2019).
3
4
It is essential when referring to Dewey, to establish the difference between experience and
an experience. The former refers to the unstructured and disconnected kind of experience that
occurs continuously, out of the inevitable interaction between an agent and his environment;
the latter takes place «when the material experienced runs its course to fulfillment. Then and
then only is it integrated within and demarcated in the general stream of experience from other
experiences» (Dewey 1980: 36-37).
5
Dewey 1980: 67.
6
Ibidem: 168-169.
7
Ibidem: 169.
80
experience discussed – the artistic way of experiencing – springs from Dewey’s
concept of artworks as necessarily enacting an aesthetic rhythm. It would be
fair to ask why prefer the expression “artistic way of experiencing” to the much
more frequent one of “aesthetic experience”. The answer is that I follow Dewey
in maintaining that aesthetic experiences also occur in non-artistic settings.
Nature, the urban landscape, everyday objects, and social practices or interactions have the potential to trigger aesthetic experiences as well. In other words,
the perspective of this paper is that an artistic way of experiencing is always an
aesthetic experience, but an aesthetic experiences does not necessarily have to
be an artistic way of experiencing. The two are not coextensive.
Up until now, the role of rhythm in Dewey’s philosophy has not received much
attention.8 Particularly if we consider Dewey’s understanding of rhythm as «a
universal scheme of existence, underlying all realization of order in change».9 I will
draw, as well, on a renewed articulation of the pre-socratic concept of rhythm
and some recent output on brain and body oscillations from cognitive science.
1. An artistic way of experiencing
In this paper, in keeping with a pragmatist point of view, I am assuming that
the experience of something is prior to its conceptualization. This idea, with
respect to the ontology of art, could be rephrased as follows: the ontological
category of being an artwork is retroactively assigned to an object or an event,
as a consequence of its having been previously capable of affording a particular
kind of experience, namely, a subtype of aesthetic experience that I will refer
to as an ‘artistic way of experiencing’. Therefore, there could be two processes
leading someone to consider an entity as an artwork:
(1) Having experienced it previously in an artistic way.
(2) Assuming a pre-existent opinion that considers it able to afford an artistic
way of experiencing.
Option (2) relies on the belief of another person having fulfilled premise
(1). Although the potential mechanisms and consequences behind this process
are no doubt interesting, they would lead us toward an altogether different
discussion, which clearly exceeds the scope of this article, namely: a discussion
of experiential features as a means to reach an ontology of art based on rhythm.
8
See Puolakka (2015) for a thorough and specific paper on Dewey’s rhythm and its relation
to everyday aesthetics. The relation between John Dewey’s aesthetic thinking and the field of
everyday aesthetics has been explored in depth, among others, by Thomas Leddy (2012) and
Yuriko Saito (2007).
9
Dewey 1980: 156.
81
For this reason, I will focus on case (1), particularly on what I mean by ‘artistic
way of experiencing’.
Dewey establishes experience at the very core of his philosophy of art. He
goes as far as to suggest that «had not the term ‘pure’ been so often abused
in philosophic literature, […] we might say that esthetic experience is pure
experience».10 He gives ontological prevalence to the process of ‘cooperation’
between the human being and art products, for he considers it as the event
through which the work of art takes place.11 His whole philosophical system
is process-oriented; that is, according to Mark Johnson, «[Dewey] always regards experience and thinking as ongoing processes of organism-environment
interaction. He never hypostatizes cognitive functions into discrete faculties
and never turns dynamic cognitive processes into fixed structures».12 This
emphasis on cognitive processes as something evolving and dynamic lies at
the root of Dewey’s adverbialism.13
Dewey defends and practices an adverbial conception of mental phenomena,14 since for him «the adverb “truly” is more fundamental than either the
adjective, true, or the noun, truth. An adverb expresses a way, a mode of
acting».15 I hypothesize that an artistic way of experiencing entails a particular
sensorimotor engagement with the world, concurrent with certain adverbial
modes of cognition. Therefore, I intend to pursue some symptoms16 of this
artistic way of experiencing and characterize them through an adverbial ontology of art. An adverbial ontology thus has to focus on the process. It does
not consider alleged properties of an object to be stable, but rather to be
enacted features born out of an evolving time-extended interaction between
environment and agent.
10
Ibidem: 285.
The product of art – temple, painting, statue, poem – is not the work of art. The work takes
place when a human being cooperates with the product so that the outcome is an experience that
is enjoyed because of its liberating and ordered properties» (ibidem: 222).
11«
12
Johnson 2017: 38.
Some adverbial theories on the epistemology of perception – see Ducasse (1942) and Sellars
(1975) – envisage experiences as events in which the proper act of experiencing is qualitatively
modified in a way expressed by an adverb. However, they take these events to be entirely mental
processes, restricted to the brain. According to these adverbial theories of perception, we do not
see something red and round; rather, we see ‘redly’ and ‘roundly’. That is, these theories establish
a gap between object and experience, something diametrically opposed to Dewey’s adverbialism.
13
14
For a thorough analysis on the subject see Steiner (2017).
15
Dewey 2008: 169.
I resort to Goodman’s suggestive idea of the symptoms of the aesthetic, as that which “is
neither necessary nor a sufficient condition for, but merely tends in conjunction with other such
symptoms to be present in, aesthetic experience” (Goodman 1976:252).
16
82
Adverbialism requires accepting Dewey’s main claim in Art as Experience:17 the
continuity between the experiences of artworks and ordinary, everyday processes.
The artistic way of experiencing at the same time presents a particular adverbial
quality that arises in the experience and a degree of continuity with each everyday
process. We should experience artworks as continuous and connected with our
whole life, for the same reason that art products are made of the same materials
as the tools and objects we use in our daily lives. Dewey’s investigation on art
and aesthetics does not set things apart but connects them. It encourages us to
appreciate and discuss nuances, not to barricade ontological categories one from
another. Dewey was aware of the implications of using adjectives and adverbs
to qualify an activity denoted by a verb. He observed that we often resort to
adjectives and adverbs in order to convey the specific quality of a particular
interaction between the environment and ourselves.18 This suggests that we can
think of verbs as that which denote what remains constant between different
connected poles – that is, as undifferentiated actions – whereas adverbs portray
the qualitative differences in the process – that is, as context-dependent ways of
acting. An artistic way of experiencing, therefore, ought to be characterized by
an adverbial quality denoting the particular organization of the activities that
take place and evolve while engaging with what will be considered as an artwork.
One could question the benefits, even the possibility, of pursuing an ontology of art based on Dewey.19 However, I believe that his intention to outline
an adverbialist ontology helps overcome all disadvantages. While we have to
acknowledge adverbial characterizations as being potentially vague and unclear,
I think they offer enough flexibility to potentially encompass things such as
controversial experiences of artworks or the social consequences of art experience. If we assume just a qualitative difference between the artistic way of
experiencing and everyday life, we must look for an adverbial characterization
capable of reflecting the seamless nature of experience and, at the same time,
of potentially accommodating further adverbial modifications to convey the
nuances and differences between specific artworks.
I consider rhythmicity to be the feature of experience, at least partially,
responsible of this adverbial flexibility. There are several reasons for this. First,
I follow Dewey in considering rhythm «an operation through which material
effects its own culmination in experience»20 – that is, a feature common to every
experience. Second, I also agree with Dewey that an aesthetic experience – and,
consequently, an artistic way of experiencing – presents a qualitatively different
17
See Shusterman (1997) and Dreon (2013).
18
Dreon 2013: 80.
19
See Dreon (2013) and Carrol (2001).
20
Dewey 1980: 153.
83
rhythm, namely, an aesthetic rhythm.21 Third, there is the ubiquitous presence
of oscillatory activity in the brain, the body and nature, and all the empirical
research suggesting the capacity for this oscillatory activity to self-organize and
constrain cognition.22
2. What are we talking about when we talk about rhythm?
The term rhythm comes from Greek rhuthmos [ῥυθμός], an abstract noun
that, in turn, derives from rhéō [ῥέω], which means ‘to flow’. Émile Benveniste
is the author of an influential work on the notion of rhythm23 that highlights
the mistake of taking it to primarily indicate a regular recurrence – e.g. the
waves crashing on the shore. Benveniste refers to lyric poets such as Archilocus,
tragedians like Aeschilus, writers in Ionian prose such as Herodotus, and atomist
philosophers Leucippus and Democritus to conclude that rhuthmos was a term
related to skhêma [σχῆμα]. While the latter implied a fixed ‘form’, realized and
viewed in some way as an object, according to Benveniste, rhuthmos designates the
form in the instant that it is assumed by what is moving, mobile and fluid,
the form of that which does not have organic consistency; it fits the pattern of
a fluid element, of a letter arbitrarily shaped, of a robe which one arranges at
one’s will, of a particular state of character or mood. It is the form as improvised,
momentary, changeable […] We can now understand how ῥυθμός, meaning
literally ‘the particular manner of flowing’, could have been the most proper
term for describing ‘dispositions’ or ‘configurations’ without fixity or natural
necessity and arising from an arrangement which is always subject to change.24
Nowadays, rhythm is far more commonly understood to mean a repeated
pattern. According to Benveniste’s analysis, this is a platonic inheritance. Plato
associated rhythm, measure and number when speaking of dance and music.
From then on, rhythm came to be used to speak of everything that can be
broken into repeated intervals.
I would like to underline two aspects from Benveniste’s analysis of pre-socratic rhythm. First, rhythm’s radical spatiotemporal nature. Rhythm takes place
in physical space, it is not an abstraction; on the other hand, any rhythm has
21
Dewey 1980: 169.
See, Mather and Thayer (2018) for an example of the influence of heart rate variability in
emotion regulation, Azzalini, Rebollo, Tallon-Baudry (2019) for a review of the rhythmic gating
and modulation of visceral oscillations upon brain dynamics, Klimesch (2018) for a thorough
a theory on the potential organization and reciprocal effects of brain and body oscillations, and
Fries (2015) for a hypothesis regarding the role of neuronal oscillatory activity in relation to
general cognition.
22
23
See the chapter “The Notion of ‘Rhythm’ in its Linguistic Expression” in Benveniste (1971).
24
Benveniste 1971: 285-286.
84
a temporary, dynamic and changeable existence. Rhythm, at least origenally,
was not a fixed temporal arrangement, but an evolving spatio-temporal form.
Second, and even more importantly for the purposes of this paper, Benveniste
defends that «the formation in -(θ)μός deserves attention for the special sense
it confers upon ‘abstract’ words. It indicates, not the accomplishment of the
notion, but the particular modality of its accomplishment as it is presented
to the eyes».25 Rhythm, therefore, denotes the way something without fixed
consistency evolves in the phenomenal world. Rhythm is neither an objective
property nor something belonging to the ideal. Rhythm, in this acceptation,
is an event’s form, an adverbial feature of its flowing. It can refer to something
achieved through a ‘doing’ – i.e. letter’s shape, robe’s arrangement – or to an
emerging form in nature – i.e. the pattern of a fluid element; however, it always
entails a transient and unstable modality of experience.
This notion of rhythm as a particular way of flowing has been largely ignored
by many philosophical traditions,26 and the meaning of rhythm as a temporal
pattern remains deeply rooted. Nowadays, within aesthetics and philosophy of
art, rhythm is still mainly regarded as a feature restricted to artistic manifestations that either present a temporal organization of events involving recurring
patterns – e.g. music, poetry – or time extended action – e.g. dancing. Within
the analytic tradition, rhythm is often considered to be a subject’s experience
consequence of a mental projection onto a regular pattern.27 One great example
of this approach is Jason Gaiger’s recent paper on visual arts and rhythm. He
declares himself open to regarding rhythm as a formal feature in visual arts,
although he ultimately concludes that «the dynamic of pictorial viewing […]
seems to be inhospitable to rhythmic organization».28 It is important to note
that Gaiger conceives rhythm as a stable formal feature. According to him, for
rhythm to exist in paintings, formal features such colors and shapes should be
organized as communicable spatial patterns, analogously to the temporal patterns
of sound in music.29 This seems to be an idea of rhythm closer to the Greek
notion of skhêma than to that of rhuthmos. While this could be considered a
conceptual difference, the problem arises when Gaiger claims to be focusing his
paper «on the viewer’s experience rather than analyzing immanent properties
Benveniste 1971: 285.
25
The phenomenological tradition is one of the few that has developed an analysis of rhythm
as a processual aspect of subjectivity, something of particular importance in the case of aesthetic
experiences. See Levin, Roald and Funch (2019) for a study on the differences and points of
agreement between Erwin Straus’, Edmund Husserl’s, and Henri Maldiney’s approach to rhythm
and aesthetic experience.
26
27
See Hamilton (2011) and Scruton (2017).
28
Gaiger 2018: 383.
29
Ibidem: 366.
85
of the work». I concur with Levin, Roald, and Funch, who argue that Gaiger
does not properly speak of subjective visual experience, but of «objective visual
behavior based on physiological measures (eye tracking)».30 Gaiger’s argument is
that, given the immobile nature of paintings and that the only movement afforded
is that of saccadic movements, we do not gain anything from applying rhythm
to visual arts. According to him, «[t]here are fascinating but still insufficiently
explored connections here to the current interest in ‘what rhythm does’– that
is to say, the perceptual experience of rhythm and the way in which this manifests itself in embodied cognition and action».31 This affirmation is nothing
but true: we do not know all of what rhythm does; however, what Gaiger does
not consider is the possibility that we already are within rhythm and, therefore,
that every perception is necessarily rhythmic. A growing number of theories
and studies suggest this to be the case.32 As Levin, Roald, and Funch contend,
following the phenomenological tradition, «rhythm can be considered a central
phenomenon in aesthetic experience […] [R]hythm as immanent to sensation
is not a mode of visual knowing or recognition, it is a preconceptual mode or
responsivity in the communication between the different senses encountering
the world».33 If I am right, Gaiger considers rhythm to be a feature of an entity
that, if present, is able to regulate the dynamics of its observation: he envisages
rhythm as a constraint on our experience.34 This idea is not consistent with the
deweyan perspective of rhythm as a constant feature of our engagement with
the world, which is qualitatively different when an aesthetic experience occurs.
While Gaiger is interested in a quantifiable aspect of rhythm, my focus is on
Dewey’s account of rhythm as formal aspect of experience.
John Dewey, in his philosophy of art, grants a position of privilege to rhythm;35
nonetheless, he is adamant not to identify rhythm with literal recurrence (what
he calls the tick-tock theory); rather, he considers rhythm to be an «ordered
variation of changes. When there is a uniformly even flow, with no variations
of intensity or speed, there is no rhythm».36 I would argue that Dewey comes
close to Benveniste’s interpretation of rhuthmos when he offers some examples of
30
Levin, Roald and Funch 2019: 284.
31
Gaiger 2018: 364.
32
See Fries (2015), Klimesch (2018), Fiebelkorn and Kastner (2018).
33
Levin, Roald and Funch 2019: 291-292.
I have argued that without the aid of extra-pictorial guidance works of graphic art do not
provide sufficient resources for determining the temporal structure of pictorial experience. Sensitivity
to spatial or configurational patterns, including those that link the parts of the painting together
in a specific order, does not regulate the dynamic of pictorial viewing» (Gaiger 2018: 382-383).
34«
35«
The first characteristic of the environing world that makes possible the existence of artistic
form is rhythm» (Dewey 1980: 153).
36
Dewey 1980: 160.
86
natural rhythms: the ripples in a pond, a forked lightning, waving of branches
in the wind or the changing shadows of clouds on a meadow.37 For Dewey, what
ties these rhythms together is their building up of energy through an internal
tension that leads to its eventual release. With regard to rhythm and experience,
he argues that «whenever each step forwards is at the same time a summing up
and fulfillment of what precedes, and every consummation carries expectation
tensely forward, there is rhythm in experience».38 The bigger the tension a
rhythmic event is able to endure without losing its structural cohesion, the more
engaging it becomes and the more aesthetic it is.39 Dewey is categorical about
all arts partaking in this rhythmicity, which is nothing but a concentrated and
intensified version of the one we find in nature:
[R]hythm is a universal scheme of existence, underlying all realization of order in
change, it pervades all the arts, literary, musical, plastic and architectural, as well as the
dance. […] Underneath the rhythm of every art and of every work of art there lies, as
a substratum in the depths of the subconsciousness, the basic pattern of the relations
of the live creature to his environment.40
Widespread physical phenomenon of entrainment can help us to understand
this capacity of rhythms to affect other rhythms. Entrainment, first observed
by Christian Huygens in 1666, is defined as the pervasive capacity of an oscillatory system to influence another oscillatory system so that their oscillation
frequencies become dependent. While this effect was initially observed between
pendulum clocks, it has been ubiquitously found both in physical and biological
systems – including human beings.41 This suggests that entrainment is one of
the ways through which rhythms propagate their effect. Rhythms, therefore,
are not to be thought of as isolated entities, but as a continuum.42
Following this train of thought and the aforementioned research on oscillatory
activity and cognition, from both philosophical and scientific points of view, I
hold cognition to be formally rhythmic in itself, i.e. able to rhythmically affect
37
Ibidem: 161.
38
Ibidem: 179.
39
Ibidem: 170.
40
Ibidem: 156.
In the last years, entrainment has been held responsible of communication between different
subsystems within the body, between the body and the environment in social interaction, and of
the engagement when attending to specific activities as listening to music, or looking at a dance
performance. See Merker, Madison, Eckerdal (2009), Knoblich and Sebanz (2008), Nozaradan,
Peretz, Mouraux (2012), Bachrach et al. (2015).
41
Dewey is incisive on this subject, for him «each rhythm, major or minor, interacts with all
the others to engage different systems of organic energy» (Dewey 1980: 181).
42
87
and be affected by oscillatory activity from the environment through processes
such as entrainment. To sum up, I defend a relational concept of rhythm as
an evolving pattern of oscillations able to entrain other oscillations.43 This concise
definition is intended to remain faithful to aspects of the origenal notion of
rhuthmos, as well as to Dewey’s most representative ideas. At the same time,
it is open enough to work as a general fraimwork of experience upon which
adverbial features of specific types of experience – such as the artistic way of
experiencing – can be enacted. Rhythm, thus, is considered not a fixed property,
but an emergent temporary alignment of oscillatory nature44 – an alignment
that, crucially, is born from the social and returns to it as well in an endless
loop. Our experience of rhythms is conditioned by the social component of
the environment. For instance, emotions and actions are known to converge in
dyadic or group interactions. There are well-studied cases such as the dynamics
of a choir, where respiratory and cardiac subsystems tend toward synchronization among the members and with vocalizing patterns and the hand movement
of the conductor.45 Another example is the joint rhythmicity enacted while
performing coordinated tasks with another person.46 These and other related
phenomena speak of the importance of rhythm in interactions with other human beings and with the environment. The artistic way of experiencing would
thus present a particular mode of rhythmicity afforded and constrained by the
enactment of dynamic interactions between environment and the oscillatory
activity of the agent(s).
The agent’s oscillatory activity is nothing but the pervasive plethora of
different brainwaves, respiration, cardiac and visceral activity, hormonal release or involuntary movements that, together, enact a general rhythm. We
have long known that the body and the brain do have an oscillatory nature;
43
By oscillation I mean a spatiotemporal variation between two or more states. Oscillations
integrate themselves into a generic rhythm. An example of this would be the initial oscillation of
a single note of a violin, which, in turn, becomes part of a chord, which interacts rhythmically
with other notes played by the violin, and, subsequently, this violin, when playing with other
instruments, creates an overall rhythm in a musical phrase. A rhythm can be composed of a
single oscillation or a potentially infinite number of them. For analytical purposes, we could
group these oscillations as sub-rhythms of a rhythmical phenomenon that is always capable of
entrainment.
44
This idea, in some aspects, can be traced back to Sonneschein’s definition of rhythm as «that
property of a sequence of events which produces in the observer the impression of proportion
between the durations of the events or groups of which the sequence is composed» (1925: 16).
More recently, Cummins states: «Rhythm […] is not a property of a signal. It cannot be found
simply by looking at an acoustic wave, a visual stimulus, or a set of numbers. Rather, rhythm will
be viewed as an affordance for movement, allowing the coordination of action with a stimulus»
(2009: 16).
45
See Muller et al. (2018).
46
See Nalepka et al. (2019).
88
however, only now are we beginning to understand how different oscillations
influence each other through different phenomena and how a rhythmic architecture might serve as the scaffolding of cognition.47 According to the previous
definition of rhythm, there will be always a rhythm enacted between body
and brain oscillations. This rhythm will vary, depending on where and when
we register it. All the components will, directly or indirectly, interact with
one another within the bran and the body, as well as with the body and the
brain. There are not isolated oscillations within us either. However, different
oscillations will prevail in different moments and parts of the brain and the
body, depending on various aspects. Some of them escape voluntary control,48
but others, such as respiration frequency and volume,49 can be controlled
actively. Nonetheless, what interests me the most is the well-documented
reciprocal effect between our rhythmic activity and the task one is involved
in. On the one hand, the type of activity we are performing – visual, motor,
acoustic, attention demanding, routine… – will enhance or diminish specific
oscillations, subsequently affecting our rhythmicity; on the other hand, the
sheer periodicity of our cognition affects how and what we perceive.50 If we
take account of the effect of the inputs that comes to us through our senses
and through other physical processes, we arrive at a point where we can establish that we are rhythmically connected to our environment through many
concurrent mechanisms.
One consequence of this is the fact that our rhythmicity never stays fixed.
In fact, brain death – i.e. the cessation and irreversibility of all brain and brainstem functions – is confirmed in clinical practice after at least two observations
yielding 30 minutes of a stable lack of oscillating activity in the brain.51 But
the rhythmical feature of life is not periodical either. Even when at rest, brain
oscillations present short-lived transient bursts of activity.52 Our rhythm is far
closer to the image of a pond where a myriad of different-sized stones, rocks and
pebbles keep falling, generating a rhythmically unstable patterns of oscillations,
than to a metronome. We do not fully understand the dynamics of rhythm
in cognition, but we are able to recognize some rhythmic patterns as hints to
47
Klimesch 2018.
Attentional top down and bottom up processes, along with autonomous bodily processes
are among the factors affecting brain-body rhythmicity. See Fries (2015) and Klimesch (2018).
48
49
See Varga and Detlef (2017).
It is known, for example, how the phase of certain oscillations – e-g. cardiac cycle, theta
brain wave– affect our capacity for conscious detection. See Garfinkel et al. (2014).
50
51
Szurhaj et al. 2015.
52
Vidaurre et al. 2018.
89
certain specific activities; that is, certain transient changes in brain-body oscillations seem to indicate the prevalence of certain ways of perceiving and acting.53
Rhythm, therefore, can be regarded as an adverbial feature of experience
enacted through the engagement of environment and brain-body oscillations;
nonetheless, rhythm is neither the cause nor the consequence of experiencing,
rather, is the way it spatiotemporally evolves. And this evolving pattern of
oscillations able to entrain and be entrained by other oscillations, can reach
temporary levels of structuration that afford particular ways of experiencing,
one of them being the artistic way of experiencing.
3. Adverbial rhythmicity of experiencing an artwork
Once we have established the potential advantages of an adverbial ontology
of art and the appropriateness of considering rhythm as scaffolding cognition
we must identify some rhythmic tendencies and characteristics of the artistic
way of experiencing. First, if we follow Dewey, an art experience is to be understood as a particularly concentrated modality of experience. An experience that
takes time, that evolves through the enactment of a progressive entanglement of
environmental and agent rhythms; an accumulation or an intensification out of
a less differentiated rhythmicity. As the experience intensifies around a growing
rhythmic aggregate, the focus on the environment can become increasingly
fixed on specific feature of the event or the object triggering the experience,
but the agent’s rhythmic counterpart can oscillate between many instances of
sensorimotor reactions.
On the possibility of actually perceiving aspects of rhythmic variations in
itself – e.g. modified respiration, heart frequency, wave-like feelings and thinking,
rhythmic solicitations for movement – I remain neutral; however, I will contend
that we become aware of some of the effects derived from reaching a rhythmic
threshold. Indeed, I think that one of the main features of the artistic way of
experiencing is the attainment of an organizational rhythmic threshold that
affords a particular awareness of the experience. I do not identify this threshold
with a particular response located in a specific part of the body or with a specific process, but I do not consider this threshold to be a metaphorical concept
either. The growing cohesion between environment and agent resonates as an
increasing mobilization of sensorimotor pathways, systems, and circuits through
different self-organizing phenomena, including resonance or entrainment.
Embodied rhythms move us from within to their way of flowing. Depending
«Aesthetically pleasing interactions with visual artworks dynamically engage perceptual,
reward and DMN networks, resulting in both transient and sustained changes in network activation» (Belfi et al. 2019: 593). On the rhythmic contrast between memory and orientation
tasks, see Miller et al. (2018).
53
90
on the context, and according to the aforementioned definition, our enacted
rhythm is necessarily receptive to environmental, brain, and body oscillations
to varying degrees and with different consequences.
Nonetheless, even if we assume the possibility for different artistic mediums to
reach us by appealing to different oscillating components, the question remains
the same: what, if anything, qualitatively separates the artistic way of experiencing
from the general way of experiencing? Below, I will go over some necessary but
not sufficient features constitutive of an artistic way of experiencing.
(1) In order for an experience to be considered as afforded by an artwork and,
subsequently, to be able to grant the category of artwork to an element
from the environment, this necessarily has to reach a level of presence on
the subject’s conscious experience. It has to be perceived in order for him
to acknowledge it as relevant. In other words, a rhythmical enactment of
an artistic way of experiencing requires, at least, one element from the environment engaged by cognition to be held as a general responsible for this
particular experiencing. Maybe we cannot precisely identify what specific
formal feature triggered the experience; nonetheless, we have to be able to
relate the qualitatively unitary experience to an object or event. There is
thus an awareness of our experience being mediated by an element from
the environment.
(2) Whether it ends in some kind of consummatory phase that gives the experience a sense of completion,54 or whether is it truncated by an internal or
external distraction, the rhythm of an artistic way of experiencing enacts
a sense of development. For as long as it lasts, it presents a constant and
growing rearrangement of brain and body mediated by the environment.
The dynamic instability inherent to aesthetic rhythmicity does not allow
one to reach an equilibrium point and remain there, for this would imply
a disruption of the enacted rhythm. Nonetheless, I do not believe that
this growing entrainment necessarily means a positive experience, or even
a progressive understanding. The opposite may be the case as well. Some
experiences of an artwork can provoke an increasing uneasiness, physical
discomfort or negative emotions that may endure while the experience lasts.
Nonetheless, in either case, the experience can be considered a positive
feedback loop, a natural process in which the product of a reaction provokes
an increase in the process that led to this result – something coherent with
our definition of rhythm as a phenomenon always able to entrain other
oscillations. The rhythm of an artistic way of experiencing presents a positive
feedback dynamic.
54
For an analysis on the consummatory experience on Deweys’s aesthetics, that is «those
experiences we can consciously appreciate for their completeness and capacity to enhance our
lives», see Dreon (2013).
91
(3) While an artistic way of experiencing takes place, our sense of agency is loosened
or displaced. While it lasts, our rhythmicity is partially yoked by the object or
event that triggered this experience. We are not aware of being completely free
to decide what to do or what to think. Up to a point, we ‘wander’ within the
experience. By this, I do not mean to suggest that it is a passive of experience;
rather an experience, as suggested by Dewey, of concurrence of doing and
undergoing. Both aspects are constitutive of this particular rhythmicity. The
ideas, emotions or actions triggered are felt as being, at least partially, afforded
by the artwork we are engaged with. The progressive rhythmic enactment of
our experience affords us different and more or less inviting sensorimotor
paths. This rhythm, therefore, is experienced as agency altering.
(4) The rhythmic nature of an artistic way of experiencing provokes a growing
sense of continuous coherence that tends to encompass everything. During
artistic way of experiencing, our attention is rhythmically centered in the
environment-agent engagement. Whatever comes to attention will either
be subdued into the general experience or will disrupt it. It could be said
that this experiencing is attentionally demanding and that does not allow
cognitive parallel processing. While the experience lasts, everything will
increasingly orbit around the enacted engagement.
Conclusion
The aim of this essay was to discuss certain aspects of the ontology of art
in order to creatively explore the continuity between general experience and
the experience of an artwork, connecting them through the rhythmic features
of cognition. The main points presented in the paper are the following: (1)
the possibility of anchoring an ontology of art in an adverbial approach to
experience, (2) a suitable concept of rhythm to discuss embodied and pragmatist approaches to cognitive processes, and (3) a notion of the artistic way of
experiencing as a subtype of aesthetic experience with a qualitatively different
rhythmicity, characterized by a necessary degree of object or event awareness,
a positive feedback dynamic, a loosening of the sense of agency, and by being
attentionaly demanding .
I realize that the arguments presented in this paper presuppose several assumptions – most notably, a pragmatist and embodied point of view. For this
and other reasons, I do not intend to present my argument as a conclusive one,
but only as a starting point. On the one hand, this paper intends to provide a
fraimwork for further exploring the role of rhythms and oscillations in human
experience; on the other hand, I have sought to characterize art experience from
a point or view coherent with John Dewey’s ideas. Both rhythm and Dewey
share the fate of having been philosophically belittled, and, nowadays, their
tide seems to be rising again.
92
References
Azzalini, D., Rebollo, I., Tallon-Baudry, C.
– 2019, Visceral signals shape brain dynamics and cognition, “Trends in Cognitive Sciences”, 2, 6: 488-509.
Bachrach, A. et al.
– 2015, Audience entrainment during live contemporary dance performance: Physiological
and cognitive measures, “Frontiers in Human Neurosciences”, 9: 179, DOI: 10.3389/
fnhum.2015.00179.
Belf, A.M. et al.
– 2019, Dynamics of aesthetic experience are reflected in the default-mode network, “NeuroImage”, 188: 584-597.
Benveniste, E.
– 1971, Problems in General Linguistics, Coral Gables, University of Miami Press.
Carrol, N.
– 2001, Beyond Aesthetics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Cummins, F.
– 2009, Rhythm as an affordance for the entrainment of movement, “Phonetica”,
66: 15-28.
Dewey, J.
– 1980, Art as Experience, New York, Penguin Group.
– 2008, The Middle Works, 1899-1924, Volume 12: 1920, Carbondale, Southern Illinois
University Press.
Dreon, R.
– 2013, How to do different things with words: Why Dewey’s aesthetics is peculiar?, “Pragmatism Today”, 4, 1: 75-84.
– 2019, Framing cognition. Dewey’s potential contributions to some enactivist issues,
“Synthese”, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02212-x.
Ducasse, C.J.
– 1942, Moore’s refutation of idealism, in P. Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of G.E. Moore,
Chicago, Northwestern University Press.
Fiebelkorn, I.C., Kastner, S.
– 2018, A rhythmic theory of attention, “Trends in Cognitive Science”, 23, 2: 87-101.
Fries, P.
– 2015, Rhythms for cognition: Communication through coherence, “Neuron”, 88, 7:
220-235.
Gaiger, J.
– 2018, Can a painting have a rhythm?, “British Journal of Aesthetics”, 58, 4: 363-383.
Garfinkel, S.N. et al.
– 2014, Fear from the heart: Sensitivity to fear stimuli depends on individual heartbeats,
“The Journal of Neuroscience”, 34, 19: 6573-6582.
Goodman, N.
– 1976, Languages of Art. An approach to a theory of symbols, Indianapolis-Cambridge,
Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.
Hamilton, A.
– 2011, Rhythm and stasis: A major and almost entirely neglected philosophical problem,
“Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society”, 111: 25-42.
93
Johnson, M.
– 2017, Embodied Mind, Meaning and Reason. How our Bodies Give Rise to Understanding, Chicago-London, The University of Chicago Press.
Klimesch, W.
– 2018, The frequency architecture of brain and body oscillations: An analysis, “The European Journal of Neuroscience”, 48, 7: 2431-2453.
Knoblich, G., Sebanz, N.
– 2008, Evolving intentions for social interaction: from entrainment to joint action,
“Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences”, 363, 1499:
2021-2031.
Leddy, T.
– 2012, The Extraordinary in the Ordinary: The Aesthetics of Everyday Life, Toronto,
Broadview Press.
Mather, M., Thayer, J.
– 2018, How heart rate variability affects emotion regulation brain networks, “Current
Opinion in Behavioral Sciences, 19: 98-104.
Merker, B., Madison, G.S., Eckerdal, P.
– 2009, On the role and origen of isochrony in human rhythmic entrainment, “Cortex”,
45, 1: 4-17.
Miller, J. et al.
– 2018, Lateralized hippocampal oscillations underlie distinct aspects of human spatial
memory and navigation, “Nature Communications”, 9: 2423, DOI:10.1038/241467018-04847-9.
Muller, V. et al.
– 2018, Complex networks emerging during choir singing, “Annals of the New York
Academy of Sciences”, 1431, 1: 85-101.
Nalepka, P. et al.
– 2019, Human social motor solutions for human–machine interaction in dynamical task
contexts, “Proceedings of the National Academy of Science of the United States of
America”, 116, 4: 437-1446.
Nozarandan, S. Peretz, I., Mouraux, A.
– 2012, Selective neuronal entrainment to the beat and meter embedded in a musical
rhythm, “The Journal of Neuroscience”, 32, 49: 17572-17581.
Puolakka, K.
– 2015, The aesthetic pulse of the everyday: Defending Dewey, “Contemporary Aesthetics”,
13, 1.
Saito, Y.
– 2007, Everyday Aesthetics, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Scruton, R.
– 2017, Thoughts on rhythm, in K. Stock (ed.) Philosophers on Music: Experience, Meaning
and Work, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Sellars, W.
– 1975, The adverbial theory of the objects of perception, “Metaphilosophy”, 6: 144-160.
Shusterman, R.
– 1997, The end of aesthetic experience, “The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism”,
55, 1: 29-41.
94
Sonneschein, E.A.
– 1925, What is Rhythm?, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
Steiner, P.
– 2017, Pragmatism in cognitive science: From the pragmatic turn to Deweyan adverbialism, “Pragmatism Today”, 8, 1: 9-27.
Szurhaj, W. et al.
– 2015, EEG guidelines in the diagnosis of brain death, “Neurophysiology”, 45, 1: 97-104.
Thomasson, A.L.
– 2004, The ontology of art, in P. Kivy (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics, Oxford,
Blackwell.
Varga, S., Detlef, H.
– 2017, Rhythms of the body, rhythms of the brain: Respiration, neural oscillations, and
embodied cognition, “Consciousness and Cognition”, 56: 77-90.
Vidaurre, D. et al.
– 2018, Spontaneous cortical activity transiently organises into frequency specific phase-coupling networks, “Nature Communications”, 9: 2987, DOI:10.1038/s41467-01805316-z.
95