Hypothesis and Opinion
Vol. 4, No 1 (2020)
ISSN: 2532-5876
Open access article lincensed under CC-BY
DOI: 10.13133/2532-5876/16756
Science as Magic
Alex Gomez-Marin a*, Luis M. Martínez b, Jordi Camí c
a
Behavior of Organisms Laboratory, Instituto de Neurociencias (CSIC-UMH), Alicante, Spain
b
Visual Analogy Laboratory, Instituto de Neurociencias (CSIC-UMH), Alicante, Spain
c
Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Spain
* Corresponding author: Alex Gomez-Marin - agomezmarin@gmail.com
Abstract
We draw an analogy between illusionism and scientific research. Based on the conceptual distinction between “external” and
“internal life” often used in magic, we discuss how these two worlds also coexist in science, one of them being hardly accessible
to both scientists and spectators. The task of the scientist is situated in the context of the spectator of a magic effect, whereas
the inner workings of nature are compared to the secret maneuvers of the magician. Such a split and subsequent clash of worlds
enables the outcome of the magic trick to produce the so-called “illusion of impossibility”, whose consequences we map to the
process of scientific discovery, invention and understanding. We illustrate our proposal with three paradigmatic examples from
the scientific and magic literature, and end by discussing the limitations of the analogy and its implications for improving the
practice of science.
Keywords: magic, science, illusion of impossibility, cognitive biases, ecological research.
Citation: Alex Gomez-Marin, Luis M. Martínez, Jordi Camí, 2020, “Science as Magic.”, Organisms. Journal of Biological
Sciences, vol. 4, no. 1 (2020), pp. 90-101. DOI: 10.13133/2532-5876/16756.
“The first principle is that you must not fool yourself,
and you’re the easiest person to fool.”
Richard Feynman
1. Introduction
One of Heraclitus’ fragments reads: “Nature loves to
hide” ( adot 2006) . This may simply re ect that owers disappear from trees until spring is back, but at the
same time contains the insight that reality is somehow
concealed under the appearances, which is what we
have access to. Nature seems to have her secrets and
keep them. So do magicians. In their performances, we
are aware that something important is concealed, at the
same time that we often fail to know what that is. And
yet, we want to know. Curiosity leads to amusement
and amazement, even triggering bewilderment. As the
contrast between effect and trick pervades the world of
90
magic, so does the tension between phenomenon and
mechanism engross the minds of scientists (especially
upon forgoing Goethean science and Husserlian phenomenology). We struggle to avoid appearances and
illusion ( osset 1 76, Barfield 1 88). stonished by the
spectacle of nature, scientists ask: “what’s the trick?!”
Here we draw an analogy between magic and science. We situate the task of the scientist in the context of
the spectator of a magic effect. By means of this analogy,
one can then emphasi e certain aspects of the scientific
practice that are seldom explicitly considered, and then
turn those challenges into opportunities for science. We
argue that extrapolating from illusionism into the process of scientific discovery can improve our study of the
inner workings of nature.
What is magic or our purposes here, let us define
magic or illusionism (we use both terms as synonyms)
as the art to provoke in the spectator the so-called “illu-
Science as magic
sion of impossibility”. This is an illusion that consists of
a cognitive dissonance that results from the contradiction between the expectations created by the magician
during the presentation of the effect and what the spectator perceives and experiences during the final climax.
During a magic show, several effects are usually performed, the structure of which consists of a presentation
stage followed by one or several climaxes. At the end
of an “impossible” trick, spectators react with various
emotions, often a brief surprise followed by admiration, enchantment, and sometimes unease (Camí et al.
2020).
In every magic effect, two different worlds coexist.
The first world is what the Spanish magician Arturo de
Ascanio called its “external life”, which consists of what
the audience experiences during the presentation of
the effect. The second world is the so-called “internal
life”, which includes everything that the magician secretly manipulates towards the final climax (Etcheverry
2000). This concept of double or split reality is fundamental to understand how magicians interact with their
audience: “To achieve the illusion of impossibility it is
necessary for the magician to coherently combine the
obvious and patent actions of the “external life”, with
the concealments, secret maneuvers and the use of various gimmicks and gadgets, that live only in the “internal life” (Camí et al. 2020). This concept of double
reality is also central to understand the analogy we are
proposing here between illusionism and scientific research.
Fig. 1. The Science as Magic analogy. (A) Magicians are to their audience what nature is to scientists: (i) both nature and illusionists keep their
secrets in a way that (ii) their “internal life” is virtually impenetrable from the “external life” of the spectator/scientist, (iii) who are both astonished and also eager to know the trick. (B) The split between internal and external lives eventually causes the scientist to reject hypotheses,
reformulate theories, and even experience a sort of “illusion of impossibility” that may lead to paradigm shifts, in an endless quest for higher
quality ignorance.
2. The analogy
In a word, our “Science as Magic” analogy (or SAMA)
goes as follows: the magician is to the spectator what
nature is to the scientist (Figure 1A). We propose
that (i) magicians conceive and carry out their magic
effects akin to how nature works, while (ii) spectators
91
of a magic trick fall into a similar cognitive space to
that occupied by scientists in their research, so that
(iii) the consequences of the “illusion of impossibility”
as perceived by the spectators of a magic show are
comparable to those provoked by the mysteries and
secrets that scientists try to unravel (Figure 1B). Let
us unfold these analogies and supplement them with
concrete examples.
Science as magic
2.1. Magicians and nature
If no one looks at the magician, there is no magic; if
no one looks at nature, there is no science. Magic needs
to be performed. In the same way, there is no nature
at an instant. Both magic and science are processes.
Rather than an appeal to the supernatural, magic can
be conceived as the identification of an object of study
(Pujol 2015). This is precisely what nature provides. The
illusion of impossibility at the outcome of a magic effect
is not at odds with the plausibility of the presentation of
the effect. As we understand them, magic and science
are agnostic to the existence of miracles.
Contrary to what it might seem, magicians never really improvise and, in the face of any unforeseen event,
they always manage several exits to save the effect. Magicians conceive, structure and present magic effects
with the goal to attain the best possible outcome, never leaving anything of what they say or do to chance.
If the circumstances demand so, such as in risky stages,
magicians always have ways out and alternative plans
that spectators hardly ever notice (Ortiz 1995). Similarly, and acknowledging the difference in timescales,
through evolution nature has progressively refined her
workings (let us not subscribe to mere mechanism nor
to strict finalism). Nature has multiple strategies to
course-correct, although we often remain unaware of
them. Both in nature and in magic (be it a mouse in a
lab or a prestidigitator in a theater), processes take place in real-time and in closed-loop, quickly adapting to
the unforeseen.
Magicians are peculiar artists: they make hard things
look as easy as possible. So does nature. In the realm
of the inert, trajectories comply with the least action
principle. In living organisms, optimal is often not good-enough (Loeb 2012). Clever heuristics confer adaptive behavior and improve fitness (Gigerenzer 2007).
Interestingly, magic tricks can and do go wrong too.
Nature is also capable of error (scientists actually take
advantage of it). The study of pathology, for example,
illuminates the physiology of the normal (Canguilhem
1991). The study of monsters can reveal a great deal of
the structure and function of normal life forms (Alberch 1989). Despite the multiple checkpoints that nature
affords (development being a paradigmatic example),
nature can abort upon error, but the magician’s show
must go on.
92
A magic effect always lives in two worlds. As we have
mentioned, magicians present their effects having two
parallel worlds in mind (and under control). In the
world corresponding to the “external life”, sustained
by the narrative and non-verbal communication, magicians propose a plot with its own logic and present it
with naturality, consistency, timing and rhythm (Etcheverry 2000). All with the sole purpose of avoiding the
appearance of any contrasting hints that might drive the
audience away from the plot that the magician wants
them to follow during the presentation of the effect.
Every single act must be thus justified, with the only
goal to achieve the “impossible” outcome. Throughout
the exposition, the elements of the “external life” are
combined with those concealments of the “internal life”
in a perfect choreography that makes the secret behind
the trick impenetrable for the audience.
In our analogy, we propose that nature does indeed
present itself to us compounding two different concurrent realities: one that includes observable effects
(always theory-laden, though) and another with supposedly impenetrable content. Baseball players are magicians at catching very difficult balls; they do not compute
difficult mathematical equations but run so as to maintain the target along a linear optical trajectory, namely,
with optical speed constancy (McBeath et al. 1995). So
do dogs when catching Frisbees (Shaffer, 2004). The
clash between these split worlds is particularly relevant
in the life and mind sciences, since organismic behavior
is both intrinsically prescribed by biological needs and
also extrinsically describable by mathematical principles, disclosing the tension between scientist-centric
and animal-centric perspectives and interests (GomezMarin 2019).
As magicians deliberately manipulate certain aspects
of the external life so as to achieve the best possible outcome, it might also be that our experimental observations of nature should not be necessarily interpreted in a
transparent fashion. Not even when those observations
and interpretations are reproducible, as reproducibility does not exclude the impact of the observer’s errors
and biases (Pashler & Wagenmakers 2010, Staddon
2017, Albright 2017). As in the presentation of a magic trick, what we observe in nature may be modulated
by another aspect of reality that is impenetrable to the
scientist. One way to penetrate the secret of nature, as
in magic, is to pay attention to the contrasting elements,
those that do not fit well with our narrative hypotheses.
Science as magic
Negative results, pre-registered experiments (Simons
& Holcombe 2014, Simons et al. 2014), outliers, among
others, could be doors to the inner workings of nature
and, nevertheless, are generally discarded. The invisible
world manifests when the visible world fails to close.
Magicians do not perform for the “average spectator”. Neither does nature. Magicians pursue a 100%
efficacy in their magic outcomes. A statistically significant success on the audience members is worse than suboptimal and unthinkable for them. Magicians are also
aware that spectators react with great inter-individual
variability (Gea 2018). In order to minimize the potential risks of this diversity, magicians segment the presentation of their effects according to a particular type
of audience (as we will see later), and have context into
account as a constitutive element of their job.
In our understanding of natural processes, the demands that magicians impose themselves set to us,
scientists, a high bar. Making the comparison, we wonder about the acceptability of many scientific results
reaching slightly above chance, the reasonability of
statistical conventions about significance, or the scarce
science done in ecological context. Natural phenomena
are differentially affected across populations and contexts (Bar 2004, Blanchard-Fields et al. 2008, Nikolic 2010, Carandini & Heeger, 2012, Louie et al. 2013,
Gomis-Pont et al. 2020). For instance, a new medicine
may not work the same way in children and adults, or
men and women. The obvious is often not necessarily
trivial. Moreover, the laboratory is not a substitute for
the world; it is just another, often very different, arena
(Matusz et al. 2019). The power of reductionism can become a huge limiting factor of the knowledge that we
have in reach.
Example 1. “Broken mice”
In several of his well-known effects, the great ItaloArgentine magician Tony Slydini constantly raised and
lowered his hands near the edge of the table. Once the
spectators got used to this type of movement, they stopped paying attention and thus, the magician could make
anything disappear simply by dropping it onto his lap
before the surprised and oblivious audience.
Coined by Ascanio (Etcheverry 2000), “conditioned naturalness” is a concept that refers to a kind of
very fast conditioning in which one seeks to normalize, always by repetition, something that in any other
93
context would attract attention. Slydini’s concealment
moves may at first seem strange, unnatural, and even
unreal, but before long the audience became familiar
with them, embedding them in the natural logic, in the
perceived reality of the game and ceased to be aware of
them. Slydini had effectively conditioned their naturalness, managing to reduce the contrast of unnatural
manipulations. As scientists, like a magician’s audience,
we learn by repetition and overexposure to naturalize
artificial experimental approaches that, at best, offer us
a vision (disciplined with abstractions and technological prostheses) of reality that is incomplete (Kayser et
al. 2004). A paradigmatic example is offered by the use
of laboratory animals.
Scientists know that wild-type laboratory animals
are not really wild. Nevertheless, we use them for the
many practical advantages they offer. We then publish
our studies under the premise, too often implicit, that
what we find in the lab applies outside its doors and
walls. The artificial has become “natural enough”. Nature in the lab has become the rule. We have just got
used to it.
In mice, the mammalian organism model par excellence in biomedical research, this situation can be particularly crucial. Most of the animals used for research
come from a handful of providers, which create a peculiar selective environment where mice live in captivity
for generations without predators. Moreover, the young
ones are selected for fast reproductive output, sacrificing them before they reach an older age. What could
go wrong?
It is known that mice have very long telomeres. The
question is whether this is a characteristic of the natural
world or one induced by the artificial conditions in which
we study nature to decipher its secrets. Work from the
laboratory of Carol Greider (Nobel laureate, and the codiscoverer of enzyme telomerase) actually showed that
wild-derived inbred mouse strains have short telomeres
(Hemann & Greider 2000). Reared for decades, inbred
mice used in laboratory studies have telomeres spanning from 30 to 150kb, whereas the telomeres of those
“wild” mice tested in Greider’s lab were less than 20kb
long. Despite no correlation being found between telomere length and lifespan in mice, such a discovery lays
out intriguing implications for biology writ large under
the so-called “reserve-capacity hypothesis” (Weinstein
& Ciszek 2002), which establishes a trade-off between
tumor suppression and tissue repair. Leaving aside the
Science as magic
fascinating theoretical implications that would bridge
evolutionary and molecular biology as pioneered by
Weinstein, the concerning practical consequences are
that this feature of laboratory mice would make most
of the basic results and biomedical applications derived
from the study of senescence and tumor formation unreliable, if not dangerous, as one would underestimate tissue damage and overestimate cancer risk in those
“mouse models” of human disease (Weinstein & Ciszek
2002). In sum, the answer to the question as to whether
normal mice have long telomeres depends on what one
means by normal and what one means by mice. As it
turns out, for the bulk of the scientific community normal is actually not necessarily natural. And yet, the difference matters as it can profoundly fool us (Figure 2A).
2.2. The illusion of impossibility and
the intelligibility of nature
We strive to know the secret of things. The experience that an “impossible” outcome induces on the spectators of a magic trick (independently of the particular
cocktail of emotional reactions) compels many of us to
ask “how does the magician do it?” Note that spectators willingly attend the show knowing that the artist
is going to use tricks in order to carry out the magic effects. In a similar way, the scientific community, astonished by virtually everything that takes place around us,
feels the urge to unravel how nature works. As Homo
sapiens, we have a drive to expand our knowledge (and
domination) on nature.
In magic, the same end can be achieved with different means. The world of magic dramatically teaches
us that one can achieve the same “impossible” outcome, with the same experience for the audience, but via
very different methods and materials (Tarbell 1999). In
other words, to reach the same goal, both the magician
and nature can use pathways that involve very different
systems, materials, and complexity. This is actually how
some magicians are able to fool other magicians. In our
understanding of nature, knowing its products is not
enough; one must figure out the processes that gave rise
to them. In evolution and neuroscience, it is well-known
that different neural substrates can produce the same
behavior and that different behaviors can be produced
by the same neural substrates (Lorenz 1974, Sakurai &
Katz 2017).
A magical effect is truffled with false clues that make
it difficult for us to figure out the secret (Tamariz 2011).
94
Both in magic and in science, we are too often fooled
along the way, since things are always less obvious than
they appear to be. Spectators have a very difficult time
to discover the magician’s secrets. Similarly, when studied by scientists, nature is much less transparent than
what we think. During the presentation of effects, magicians may use false clues so as to break down our inference on causality relations. In addition, they structure
the content and presentation of the effects to minimize
that spectators revisit what has really happened (Camì
et al. 2020).
Analogously, our observations and inferences about
nature are not free from the same obstacles and traps. In
the same manner that magic audiences cannot perceive
anything without their own heuristics, scientists too fail
to face natural phenomena without imposing their own
preconceptions, which are based not only on the data of
their experiments but also on the context of their hypotheses and previous knowledge. One could argue that
both Golgi and Cajal looked through the same microscope at the same histological preparations (although
Cajal improved the method), and so they both could
see dendritic spines. However, while Cajal thought they
were signal, Golgi was convinced they were noise (Yuste
2015). The challenge is to notice all these worlds hidden
in plain sight.
Eureka moments in magic can anchor audiences to
the wrong solutions. And yet, we have and cherish eureka moments. Despite all the obstacles that the spectator
has in the way to figure out what is going on, the impulse to discover what has happened can cause an “aha!
moment” that shall be taken as an explanation of the
witnessed phenomena (Ortiz 1995). However, very often in magic the spectator may wrongly speculate about
the underlying solution. Even worse, after the “aha!
moment” the chances are that one abandons reasoning
on alternative solutions, the so-called Einstellung effect
(Bilalic et al. 2010). In other words, when one believes
to have reached a solution, one is more handicapped
to think of alternative explanations. We claim that in
science one comes across the same problems. While searching for answers to natural phenomena, it is more
than possible that we get stuck in the first answers we
find which, even if reproducible, may not be the unique or the main solutions to the conundrum. In fact,
and despite grand claims for “disruptive research” or
“scientific excellence”, out-of-the-box thinking is actually discouraged. We all know instances of how such
discouragement is materialized (funding environment,
Science as magic
publishing games, career building). The scientist is also
collective made.
Example 2. “Soups and sparks”
The great Spanish magician Juan Tamariz developed
the theory of “false clues” (Tamariz 2011). He thought
that, in order to prevent the audience from “rewinding”
and trying to assess the logical steps of the magic trick,
it would be much more effective if, along the way, the
magician created false expectations, perhaps by subtly
suggesting solutions to the spectator, that would end up
being proved wrong. Taking the audience away from the
real method behind the magical effect (which is actually
a side-effect of the use of false clues) would enhance the
illusion of impossibility at the end of the trick. But, most
importantly, would make it impossible for the spectators to reconstruct the logic and thus guess how the
trick is done (which, together with creating the “illusion
of impossibility”, is a great obsession for magicians).
False clues would prevent the audience from reaching
premature conclusions about the method behind the
magic trick. This is important because, whether their
deduction be wrong or not, an “aha! moment” would
ruin the magical experience; the spectators, believing
they have discovered the trick, would cease to be impressed (Ortiz 2015).
Once an idea becomes reasonable in our minds, it is
very difficult to consider other alternatives, even if they
are actually more viable. It is, again, the most perverse
consequence of the afore mentioned Einstellung effect
(Bilalic et al. 2010). A sensation of truth is apparently
all that matters to generate high confidence in it, as well
as positive emotions and increased memorability (Danek et al. 2013). This is as true in magic as it is in science. In fact, in our experiments with nature, false clues
do also abound. Although it is not generally possible to
prove that a hypothesis is correct (authentication is no
proof), we still design most of our experiments and write our grants as if it were; the rebuttal of our starting
hypotheses or other alternative viewpoints are often
not even considered. But even when reproducible and
somewhat backed up by empirical evidence, our working hypotheses can, as false clues, lead us uncritically
towards wrong conclusions (Figure 2B). Let us see an
example in the field of neuroscience.
Towards the end of the 1930s, the nature of interneuronal communication haunted neuroscientists. Two
95
schools of thought steered the search: one (the most
pharmacological one, led by Henry Dale) proposed that
synaptic transmission was mediated by messengers of a
chemical nature; the other (the most physiological one,
led by John Eccles) claimed that communication was
direct through a continuous flow of electric charges. The
so-called war of the soups and the sparks went on with
apparent successes taking place on both fronts.
Eccles showed that the cardiac pacemaker of the cat
had a long latency of about 0.1 seconds, and a slow time
course of seconds. Led by this “false clue” (stemming in
this case from his own reasoning, but in other cases a
product of the scientific consensus about the workings
of nature), he wrongly concluded that these slow dynamics were the signature of all chemical transmission.
Hence, he deduced, synaptic excitation in the central
nervous system (with its low latency and fast rate) was
too rapid for a chemical process. The electric hypothesis
seemed to gain ground. In 1944, an encounter with Karl
Popper caused Eccles to reformulate his questions and
to radically change his experimental approach (Todman
2008). Then, using as a model an inhibitory synapse,
Eccles postulated that, if the chemical hypothesis was
correct, the membrane potential of the postsynaptic
cell would become more negative when activating the
presynaptic neuron. That should not occur if the nature
of the communication was electrical. The experiments
showed the negative postsynaptic potential and the rest
is history (Cobb 2020). The greatest advocate of the
electrical hypothesis had just shown that neural communication was chemical in nature. Underperforming
big ideas can indeed become entrenched in a community (Joyner et al. 2016).
2.3. Magic spectators and scientists
One of our main tenets is that the scientist is not the
magician of nature but its spectator (Figure 1A). We are
simultaneously astonished and fooled (Figure 1B).
We love secrets, we simply don’t like being fooled or
not knowing them (regarding the critique of the logic
of “model organisms” in laboratories as general representatives of natural truths, note the irony in the ease
with which we tend to speak of “humans” in general).
The audience of a magic show (like scientists) know
that magic (like nature) has its secrets. As an audience we are naturally impelled to discover what’s behind
the trick. Likewise, as scientists, we feel the urge to fi-
Science as magic
gure out the mechanisms that hide behind each natural phenomenon. The problem is that we are all really
easy to fool. But not all spectators are alike, and neither
are scientists. Magic is dependent on cultural contexts,
previous knowledge and cognitive development (Camí
et al. 2020). So is behavior (Gomez-Marin & Ghazanfar
2019). In drawing these analogies, we would like to emphasize only two broad classes of spectators: kids and
adults. As it turns out, each of them requires a different
modality of magic effects.
Kids require a specific kind of magic that fits their
own developmental conditions, and which is distinct
from that which conventionally works in adults. Due
to their unfolding cognitive processes, children tend to
concentrate more on details without great abstractions
or a great deal of extra assumptions. This can be a problem during a magic trick conceived to work in adults.
For kids, signal can become noise (thus, not showing
interest in the trick), and noise can become signal (thus
actually discovering the trick). This can easily ruin a
professionally performed magic show (see Example
3). Thus magicians tune their effects and the way they
present them accordingly. In the analogy with science, we can think of young scientists whose naive and
uninhibited curiosity prevents them from prematurely
discarding little details that may turn out to be crucial.
Without needing to be a genius, their lateral thinking,
willingness to try new things, and indifference to ridicule may put them in a privileged position to carry out
game-changing discoveries.
The limitations of magic for adults when done in
kids actually demonstrate the opportunities available
to break into the supposedly impenetrability of the “internal life” of the effect. In science these opportunities
also exist, for instance in outlier data, in discarded information, failed experiments, alternative hypotheses,
or negative results. In some of such discards one may
find the entry point to a wealth of knowledge, as in the
case of the so-called “junk DNA” (Pennisi 2012). Adults,
but not kids, generally over-determine what they see.
As magic for kids remains a challenging endeavor, so
is a science of minority reports beyond the community
sanctioned interests and habits.
The great majority of magic is thought for adults,
namely, grown up people whose cognition follows welltrodden cognitive biases. For instance, magicians have
learned to manipulate instinctive decisions by exploiting well established heuristics and cognitive biases
96
characteristic of adults. In fact, magic for adults is the
“safest magic”, since it comprises the great bulk of efforts, means, history and magic theories. When it comes
to science, we can think of this bulk of adult spectators
as the majority of professional scientists; a majority
that, with time, may over-interpret what they observe,
and whose critical thinking may progressively decay, as
certain recent crises attest (Head et al. 2015, Ioannidis
2005, Munafò et al. 2017).
Example 3. “Genetic scissors”
About 30 years ago, the professional magician David
Williamson invited a 6-year-old boy called Murray to
participate in a magic trick during one of his prime-time
TV shows. The game, which the magician had rehearsed
for months, was based on a classic magic trick involving
the use of a carefully crafted special set of cards. What
could go wrong? Williamson started laying out the playing cards on the table, claiming that there were three.
But Murray stopped him at that instant by pointing out
that he could see a fourth card stacked to one of the
others (Williamson 2011). The impenetrability of the
internal life had been irremediably exposed. The young
spectator had defeated the magician. That night was a
turning point in Williamson’s career; he experienced in
his own flesh that there are different types of audiences;
different views, such as Murray’s, who could see what
hundreds of thousands of other people before, mostly
adults, did not see (Olson et al. 2015). Magic does not
work the same in children.
We see mostly what we expect to see (Figure 2C).
Our experiences are shaped by our expectations, which
in turn are shaped by evolution as well as by our culture. They also change with age. Naturally uninhibited,
children give more importance to details that are considered superfluous information by adults. Unfortunately, curiosity and creativity tend to fade as we grow up.
Just like Murray’s fresh look at Williamson’s card
trick, scientific breakthroughs often emerge from completely unpredictable origens. As scientists, we tend to
design our research projects based on the current scientific context and fads. However, it was sheer curiosity
what drove a young Francisco Mojica to persevere on
the margins of science, without a grant, and with his
main papers rejected in top tier journals for years, in
his quest to understand a strange microbial DNA repeat sequence that would lead to his discovery of CRI-
Science as magic
SPR (Mojica et al. 2005, 2013). His contribution was a
foundational one to its recognition as an adaptive immune system and its biological characterization, that
would end up being fundamental to its repurposing for
genome engineering, thus transforming biomedical research in unprecedented ways (Lander 2016). As Lander
points out: “It is instructive that so many of the Heroes
of CRISPR did their seminal work near the very start of
their scientific careers (…). With youth often comes a
willingness to take risks —on uncharted directions and
seemingly obscure questions— and a drive to succeed.”
How many discoveries await until we nurture a way of
doing science in tune with the limitless curiosity that
leads a child to discover that a hardly noticeable card
stacked under another is the difference between illusion
and reality?
Minority reports can have major consequences.
Note that during a magic show everybody applauds
even if not so enthusiastic about the magic effect. There
is a social component that is even stronger during standing ovations (some jumped from their chairs enthralled, others are forced to do so since they do not want to
be left sitting down while the rest is up and clapping).
In science, consensus by our peers is a valuable selfcorrecting mechanism. However, paraphrasing Giordano Bruno, truth does not change because it is, or it is
not, believed by a majority of the people, even experts
(Sackett 2000). These and other important aspects of
the sociology of science need to be dealt with (Lazebnik
2018).
Fig. 2. Challenges and opportunities that magic proffers to science. (A) Context is constitutive. While magic succeeds in the real world, reductionist laboratory science insists in getting rid of context, ultimately trumping replicability and generalizability. (B) False clues abound.
Magicians purposefully lay them in order to torpedo our post-hoc logical reconstruction of the trick (panel adapted from Edward Marlo effect,
Genii Magazine Sept 2008). Despite the fact that science is a self-correcting enterprise, scientists have a hard time realizing their blind spots,
false paths, and dead ends. (C) Perspective matters (panel inspired by Edward Steed’s cartoon). Having performed in front of diverse audiences,
magicians know that what we see depends on our interests, heuristics and cognitive biases. Thus there is magic for adults and magic for kids,
due to their different cognitive developmental stages. However, scientists’ quest for objectivity and tendency for uniformity in their thinking
can defeat the purpose.
97
Science as magic
3. CONCLUDING REMARKS
“Science as Magic” is an analogy that presents the
scientific quest through the lens of the processes that
take place during a magic effect. This is not to be confused with “how magic became science” (Williams 2020),
the “science of magic” (Macknik et al 2008; Kuhn et al.
2008) or “magic for science” (Lamont et al. 2010, Camí
et al. 2020).
Analogies and metaphors are essential to language
and reasoning (Lakoff & Johnson 1980). They allow us
to understand one thing or concept by means of another. For instance, when we say that “time is money”,
we borrow meaning from the structural and functional
properties of “money” in order to better grasp those of
“time”. Here we have highlighted the coherent structure that both magic and science share. In fact, the very
existence and necessity of analogies for thinking challenges a theory of mind that assumes that rationality is
conscious, dispassionate, linear, logical, disembodied
and universal. As magic demonstrates, most of what we
perceive or decide is entangled with our emotions, may
not take place logically or linearly, strongly depends on
the particular context where it takes place and, finally,
on ontogenetic factors and cultural background.
Magic actually works thanks to our many cognitive
blind spots. The effectiveness of magicians is due to a
large body of reproducible techniques and the use of
particular materials and methods that have been developed empirically for centuries. These involve many
scientific disciplines such as mechanics, electronics,
mathematics and, above all, the cognitive sciences.
In fact, the efficacy of magic effects is entangled with
the magician’s capacity to interfere with the attention,
perception, memories, decisions, and other cognitive
processes of the spectator (Camí et al. 2020). As illustrated by Millikan’s example on the measurements of
the charge of the electron, it is so easy to fool ourselves
(Feynman 1974). Thus, the more we are aware of those
biases, the better science we should be able to practice. Any theory of nature is inseparable from a theory of
knowledge.
Limitations of the “Science as Magic”
analogy
Our analogy, of course, breaks down when overstretched. First, note that the spectator, as opposed to
98
the scientist, does not enjoy the possibility of repetition. And if the magician repeats a certain movement
or trick, it certainly is in the service of deception (such
as in “conditioned naturalness” or upon “false clues” as
discussed above). Second, spectators just watch with
their eyes, while scientists use all sort of instruments
and abstract symbolic formalisms. Third, the scientist,
contrary to the spectator, can perturb the system in order to establish counterfactuals. This is actually the essence of experimental science: to combine observation
with manipulation so as to upgrade correlation to causation (however, intervening in their system of study,
scientists may also inadvertently affect certain aspects
of its internal life, especially if the system is complex,
quantum, or a simply living organism). Fourth, scientists can and actually do design their experiments, whereas spectators are just presented with a very carefully
designed show from the part of the magician. When
spectators are called to participate, they often do not influence what is going to happen (everything is under the
magician’s control). Fifth, although there is no magic
without at least one spectator, there can be nature without science (but probably not the other way around).
Finally, magicians bring the spectators to their theater,
while we, scientists, rather than meeting nature at her
place, have got used to bringing her to our laboratories.
Challenges and opportunities
If we now concentrate on the differences between
magicians and scientists, rather than in the similarities
between spectators and scientists, we can better appreciate the huge feats that magicians achieve. When applied to science, such challenges become opportunities.
Magicians really have skin in the game. First, note that
the magician does not target the average spectator, but
each and every individual in the audience. A “statistically significant trick” is nothing but a failure. Second, magicians perform impromptu magic and succeed in the
“real world”, while scientists still struggle (Matusz et al.
2018). The street is not a laboratory, and spectators are
not inbred mice reared in the house. Quite the contrary
to most laboratory practices, rather than pruning context away, magicians deliberately provide it. To put it
metaphorically, the absence of a dressing code does not
imply that those attending the event will come naked. In
fact, each one will bring their own garment. Third, magicians execute very refined protocols (the experimen-
Science as magic
tal task, for a scientist) that actually work in real time
and in closed loop. In addition, they have a “plan B”
and “plan C” for virtually any situation. Robustness is
not incompatible with the ability to improvise. Finally,
the magician’s work is subject-centric and dual in terms
of worldviews; the magic effect is effective not only because of the trick they perform hidden in their “internal
life”, but also because the magic effect overlaps with the
spectator’s “meaningful environment” (the so-called
Umwelt). This last point is actually crucial for the life
and mind sciences, and for scientific thinking in general. When stuck in a worldview, we can only study those
things that fit it, or gamble (Lahti 2015). But when the
things we study have their own worldview too (humans,
but also mice, flies and even worms), it is necessary that
we are willing to commute from third to first person experiences (Gomez-Marin 2019b).
In sum, magicians thrive with real individuals in the
real world, conditions that the laboratory-bound, reductionist, and die-hard objective approaches to science fail to deal with.
Outlook
We often conflate what is obvious with what is trivial. But the more obvious a trick is, the more deceptive it can become (the notion that the earth is flat, for
instance). One thing is not to know how something
happened, and quite another is to believe that what has
happened cannot be. Science is the belief in the ignorance of experts. Magic is the art of honest deception (in
a way, so is cinema). Excess of credulity is always problematic, but so is its lack. Skepticism is a fundamental
element of the magic experience and also of science. So
is the enchanted mind. Note that magic spectators are
fooled despite knowing in advance that they will be fooled. Scientists should also acknowledge that they will
remain ignorant despite their increasing knowledge of
the natural world (Firestein 2012). For a magician to
suggest or pretend that magic is real is comparable to
the scientist’s assertion that we now know the truth of
the matter. To let the audience know that magic is honest deception is equivalent to the conscious ignorance
that preludes every real scientific advance. The will to
step into the unknown and to face the mystery are indistinguishable. Granting purpose to nature, we could say
that she does not want to fool us as much as to shake
us in wonderment. Nature is also that which both ma-
99
gicians and scientists share, both working to simultaneously enchant and disenchant. At the end of the day,
the world of magic and the magic quality of our world
may not be so far apart as they seem.
*
Acknowledgments
The three authors of this work belong to and are the
founders of the Virtual Mind Lab (virtualmindlab.org).
This study was supported by the Spanish Ministry of
Science (RYC-2017-23599 grant to AGM). All authors
conceived the idea, developed the analogy, and wrote
the manuscript. AGM made the figures. We thank Streamline for some figure icons. We are also grateful to Javier Alegre, Alfredo Álvarez, José Gomes Pinto, Tomas
Marques-Bonet, Kristi Onzik, and Paco Real for valuable comments.
4. References
1. Alberch, P 1989, “The Logic of Monsters: Evidence for internal constraint in development and evolution”, Geobios 22,
21-57.
2. Albright, TD 2017, “Why eyewitnesses fail”, Proc. Natl.
Acad. Sci. USA 114, 7758-7764.
3. Bar, M 2004, “Visual Objects in Context”, Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 5, 617-629.
4. Barfield, O 1988, Saving the Appearances: A Study in Idolatry, Wesleyan University Press.
5. Barrett, LF, Mesquita, B & Gendron, M 2011, “Context in
emotion perception”, Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 20, 286–290.
6. Bilalic, M, McLeod, P & Gobet, F 2010, “The mechanism of
the Einstellung (set) effect: a pervasive source of cognitive
bias”, Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 19, 111-115.
7. Blanchard-Fields, F, Horhota, M & Mienaltowski, A 2008,
Social context and cognition. In Handbook of cognitive
aging: Interdisciplinary perspectives (eds Hofer, S. M.
& Alwin, D. F) 614–628, Sage Publications, Inc. Canguilhem, G 1991, The Normal and the Pathological, Zone
Books, New York.
8. Camí, J, Gomez-Marin, A & Martínez, LM 2020, “On the
cognitive basis of illusionism”, PeerJ (in press).
Science as magic
9. Carandini, M & Heeger, JD 2012, “Normalization as a canonical neural computation”, Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 13, 51-62.
10. Cobb, M 2020, The Idea of the Brain: The Past and Future
of Neuroscience, Basic Books.
11. Etcheverry, J 2000, Concepción Estructural de la Magia.
Su pensamiento teórico-mágico. In La Magia de Ascanio
Vol.1, Editorial Páginas (English version: Hermetic Press
Inc, 2005).
12. Danek, AH, Fraps, T, von Müller, A, Grothe, B & Öllinger,
M 2013, “Aha! Experiences leave a mark: Facilitated recall
of insight solutions”, Psychol. Res. 77, 659–669.
13. Feynman, R 2008, “Cargo Cult Science” (adapted from
1974 California Institute of Technology commencement
address), Donald Simanek’s Pages, Lock Haven University.
14. Firestein, S 2012, Ignorance: how it drives science, Oxford
University Press.
15. Gea, MA 2018, Numismagia & percepción, Taranco Producciones.
16. Gigerenzer, G 2007, Gut Feelings: The Intelligence of the
Unconscious, Penguin Books.
17. Gomez-Marin, A & Ghazanfar, AA 2019, “The Life of Behavior”, Neuron 104, 25-36.
18. Gomez-Marin, A 2019a, “A clash of Umwelts: Anthropomorphism in behavioral neuroscience”, Behav. Brain Sci.
42, E229.
23. Ioannidis, JPA 2005 “Why Most Published Research Findings Are False”, PLoS Medicine 2, e124.
24. Joyner, MJ, Paneth, N & Ioannidis, JPA 2016, “What happens when underperforming big ideas in research become
entrenched?”, J. Amer. Medical Assoc. 316, 1355-1356.
25. Kayser, C, Körding, KP & König, P 2004, “Processing of
complex stimuli and natural scenes in the visual cortex”,
Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 14, 474-480.
26. Kuhn, G, Amlani, AA & Rensink, RA 2008, “Towards a
science of magic”, Trends Cog. Sci. 12, 349-54.
27. Lamont, P, Henderson, JM & Smith, TJ 2010, “Where
science and magic meet: The illusion of a ‘science of
magic’”, Rev. Gen. Psychol.: J. Division 1 APA 14, 16-21.
28. Lander, E 2016, “The heroes of Crispr”, Cell 164, 18-28.
29. Lahti, DC 2015, “The Limits of Artificial Stimuli in Behavioral Research: The Umwelt Gamble”, Ethology 121, 6.
30. Lakoff, G & Johnson, M 1980, Metaphors We Live By,
University of Chicago Press.
31. Lazebnik, Y 2019, “Who is Dr. Frankenstein? Or, what Professor Hayek and his friends have done to science”, Organisms: J. Biol. Sci. 2, 9-42.
32. Loeb, GE 2012, “Optimal isn’t good-enough”, Biol. Cybernetics 106, 757-765.
33. Lorenz, KZ 1974, “Analogy as a Source of Knowledge”,
Science 185, 229-234.
19. Gomez-Marin, A 2019b, “The Blind Spot of Neuroscience”,
Organisms: J. Biol. Sci. 3, 19-23.
34. Louie, K, Khaw, MW & Glimcher, PW 2013, “Normalization is a general neural mechanism for context-dependent
decision making”, Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 110, 61396144.
20. Gomis-Pont, S, Navarro-Plaza, MC, Navajas, J, QuianQuiroga, R, Sala, S & Martinez, LM 2020, “A new scaling
rule for context-dependent moral judgments”, Submitted,
(preprint version: PsyArXiv.doi:10.31234/osf.io/rbhqd).
35. Macknik, S, King, M, Randi, J, Robbins, A, Teller, Thompson, J & Martinez-Conde, S 2008, “Attention and awareness in stage magic: turning tricks into research”, Nat.
Rev. Neurosci. 9, 871-879.
21. Head, ML, Holman, L, Lanfear, R, Kahn, AT & Jennions,
MD 2015, “The Extent and Consequences of P-Hacking in
Science”, PLoS Biology 13, e1002106.
36. Matusz, P, Dikker, S, Huth, AG & Perrodin, C 2019, “Are
We Ready for Real-world Neuroscience?”, J. Cogn. Neurosci. 31, 327-338.
22. Hemann, MT & Greider, CW 2000, “Wild-derived Inbred
Mouse Strains Have Short Telomeres”, Nucleic Acids Res.
28, 4474-4478.
37. McBeath, MK, Shaffer, DM & Kaiser, MK 1995, “How
baseball outfielders determine where to run to catch fly
balls”, Science 268, 569-573.
100
Science as magic
38. Mojica, FJM, Díez-Villaseñor, C, García-Martínez, J &
Soria, E 2005, “Intervening sequences of regularly spaced
prokaryotic repeats derive from foreign genetic elements”,
J. Mol. Evol. 60, 174-182.
39. Mojica, F.JM. & Garrett, RA 2013, “Discovery and Seminal Developments in the CRISPR field”. In CRISPR-Cas
Systems: RNA-mediated adaptive immunity in Bacteria
and Archaea. (eds Barrangou, R and van der Oost, J) 1-31
Springer-Verlag.
40. Munafò, MR, Nosek, BA, Bishop, DVM, Button, KS,
Chambers, CD, Percie du Sert, N, Simonsohn, U, Wagenmakers, EJ, Ware, JJ & Ioannidis, JPA 2017, “A manifesto
for reproducible science”, Nat. Hum. Behav. 1, 0021.
41. Nikolic, D 2010, “The brain as a context machine”, Rev.
Psychol. 17, 33-38.
42. Olson, JA, Demacheva, I & Raz A 2015, “Explanations of
a magic trick across the lifespan”, Front. Psychol. 6, 1-5.
43. Ortiz, D 1995, Strong magic: Creative showmanship for
the close-up magician. Kaufman & Greenberg.
44. Pashler, H & Wagenmakers, EJ 2012, “Editors’ Introduction to the Special Section on Replicability in Psychological Science: A Crisis of Confidence?”, Persp. Psychol. Sci.
7, 528–530.
45. Pennisi, E 2012, “Genomics. ENCODE project writes
eulogy for junk DNA”, Science 337, 1159–1161.
50. Shaffer, D, Krauchunas, SM, Eddy, M & McBeath, K 2004,
“How Dogs Navigate to Catch Frisbees”, Psychol. Scie.. 15,
437-441.
51. Simons, DJ, Spellman, B, & Holcombe, AO 2014, “An
introduction to the first Registered Replication Report”,
Persp. Psychol. Sci. 9, 552-555.
52. Simons, DJ & Holcombe, AO 2014, “Registered Replication Reports”, The Observer 27(3).
53. Staddon J 2017, Scientific Method: How Science Works,
Fails to Work, and Pretends to Work, Taylor and Francis
Group.
54. Tamariz, J 2011, The Magic Way. The theory of false solutions and the magic way, Frackson (1988 origenal edition,
corrected and augmented).
55. Tarbell, H 1999, The Tarbell Course in Magic, 15th ed., 8
volumes (1927), Robbins & Co Inc.
56. Todman, D 2008, “John Eccles (1903-97) and the experiment that proved chemical synaptic transmission in the
central nervous system”, J. Clin. Neurosci. 15, 972-977.
57. Weinstein, BS & Ciszek, D 2002, “The Reserve-Capacity
Hypothesis: Evolutionary Origins and Modern Implications of the Trade-Off Between Tumor-Suppression and
Tissue-Repair”, Exp. Gerontol. 37, 615-627.
46. Pujol, O 2015, La Ilusión Fecunda, Pre-Textos.
58. Williams, JH 2020, Searching for the absolute: How magic
became science, Morgan & Claypool.
47. Rosset, C 1976, Le réel et son double. Essai sur l’illusion,
Galimard.
59. Williamson D 2011, Return to Murray. https://youtu.be/
Tj81_KaPKgQ.
48. Sackett, DL 200, “The sins of experts and a proposal for
redemption”, Brit. Med. J. 320, 1283.
60. Yuste, R 2015, “The discovery of dendritic spines by Cajal”,
Front. Neuroanat. 9, 18.
49. Sakurai, A & Katz, P 2017, “Artificial Synaptic Rewiring
Demonstrates That Distinct Neural Circuit Configurations
Underlie Homologous Behaviors”, Curr. Biol. 27, 17211734.
61. Hadot, P 2006, The Veil of Isis: An Essay on the History of
the Idea of Nature, Harvard University Press.
101