New Political Science, Volume 25, Number 3, September 2003
REVIEW ESSAY
Marketing Critical Theory
Joseph Heath, Communicative Action and Rational Choice, Cambridge: MIT Press,
2001, 363 ⫹ vi pp.
The idea of an encounter between critical theory and rational choice seems
improbable. While critical theorists have supported the integration of philosophy and social science, they have generally opposed the use of natural scientific,
behaviorist, or positivist explanations of human action,1 such as those found in
the comprehensive rational choice program. Critical theorists also rejected the
atomism of rational choice, its inability to account for central aspects of the social
world, and the market assumptions inherent in economic models of politics. Nor
did the rise of Analytical Marxism (G. A Cohen, John Roemer, Eric Olin Wright
and Jon Elster), which draws heavily on rational choice theory, meet with
enthusiasm.2 Critical theorists think this approach leaves out the crucial areas
such as (inter)subjectivity, freedom, self-transformation and critical reflection.
1
Max Horkheimer’s original research program for critical theory foresaw a fusion of
philosophy and social science. See “The Present Situation of Social Philosophy and the Tasks
of an Institute of Social Research,” in Between Philosophy and Social Science: Selected Early
Writings (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1993), pp. 1–14, and “Traditional and Critical Theory,” in
Critical Theory: Selected Essays (New York: Seabury, 1972), pp. 188–252. Raymond A. Morrow
with David A. Brown, Critical Theory and Methodology (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 1994).
Morrow and Brown note that Horkheimer’s early program “represented the first systematic
attempt to employ traditional empirical techniques (e.g. survey research) to the refinement
and testing of propositions derived from the Marxist tradition” (p. 15). For more recent
attempts to conceptualize this problem, see Jurgen Habermas, On the Logic of the Social
Sciences (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1988); “Reconstruction and Interpretation in the Social
Sciences,” in Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990),
pp. 21–42; Karl-Otto Apel, Understanding and Explanation: A Transcendental–Pragmatic
Perspective (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); Brian Fay, Political Theory and Social Practice
(London: George Allen & Unwin, 1975); Richard Bernstein, The Restructuring of Social and
Political Theory (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1978); and James Bohman,
New Philosophy of The Social Sciences: Problems of Indeterminacy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1993).
2
G. A. Cohen, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defense, expanded edn (Princeton:
Princeton University Pres, 2000); Self Ownership Freedom and Equality (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1995); John Roemer, A General Theory of Exploitation and Class
(Cambridge: Harvard University Pres, 1982); A Future for Socialism (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1994); Theories of Distributive Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1998); Jon Elster, Making Sense of Marx (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985);
Ulysses Unbound: Studies in Rationality, Precomittment and Constraint (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2000); Eric Olin Wright, Class, Crisis and the State (London: NLB, 1979); E.
O. Wright (ed.), Reconstructing Marxism: Essays on the Explanation and the Theory of History
(London: Verso 1992). More generally, see Marcus Roberts, Analytical Marxism: A Critique
(London: Verso, 1996). One discussion from a Habermasian point of view is found in Tony
Smith, The Role of Ethics in Social Theory: Essays from a Habermasian Perspective (Albany: SUNY
Press, 1991).
ISSN 0739-3148 print/ISSN 1469-9931 online/03/030435–15 2003 Caucus for a New Political Science
DOI: 10.1080/0739314032000110682
436 Brian Caterino
It may come as a surprise then that in recent years there has been a
discussion between rational choice and critical theories. Many rational choice
theorists have questioned the viability of the comprehensive version of rational
choice. Jon Elster, for example, distinguishes between the market and the forum,
thus indicating a difference between the logic of strategically organized action
and that of a deliberative rationality. The market model is an insufficient basis
for the analysis of politics. In contrast, Elster proposes a deliberative model of
politics.3 Internal critics of rational choice have also recognized the inability of
rational choice models to explain the binding forces that knit individuals
together in society. Kenneth Shepsle, founder of the neo-institutional approach
to rational choice theory, argues, “Rationality based theories worry hardly at all
about the sources of preferences and beliefs.”4 Such theories fail to uncover the
“glue,” the binding force of social/political relations. Against core models of
equilibrium, Shepsle proposes a model of structure-induced equilibrium in order
to explain the ways in which institutional rules of order rather than core games
can underlie equilibrium. Grasping such institutional rules and beliefs, however,
brings rational choice into contact with the interpretive social sciences. Generally
speaking, contemporary versions of rational choice attempt to distance themselves from the positivistic covering-law models of explanation of their predecessors.5
While also rejecting the aims of a comprehensive theory, a second group of
theorists, impressed by what they see as the precision of the microfoundational
models, see value in rational choice models for the critical diagnosis and
explanation of social life. They have sought a rapprochement or at least a
dialogue between the parties. James Johnson has called for a conversation
between critical theory and rational choice, considering them as complementary
approaches.6 Critical theorists such as John Dryzek have argued that rational
choice illuminates the pathologies of the market.7
Dryzek proposes a circumspect integration of rational choice theory; however, Elster’s concern with deliberative democracy points to some broader areas
3
Jon Elster, “The Market and the Forum,” in Jon Elster and Aanund Hylland (eds),
Foundations of Social Choice Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). For an
illustration of the exchange between rational choice, analytical Marxism, and critical theory
on the role of deliberation, see James Bohman and William Rehg (eds), Deliberative
Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997).
4
Kenneth A. Shepsle, “Studying Institutions: Some Lessons from the Rational Choice
Approach,” in Farr, Dryzek and Leonard (eds), Political Science in History: Research Programs
and Political Traditions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
5
Robert Bates, Avner Greif, Margaret Levi Jean-Laurent Rosenthal and Barry S.
Weingast, Analytic Narratives (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998).
6
James Johnson, “Habermas on Strategic and Communicative Action,” Political Theory
19 (1991), pp. 181–210; “Is Talk Really Cheap? Prompting Conversation Between Critical
Theory and Rational Choice,” American Political Science Review 87⬊1 (1993), pp. 74–86;
“Rational Choice as Reconstructive Theory,” in Kristen Renwick Monroe (ed.), The Economic
Approach to Politics (New York: HarperCollins, 1991), pp. 113–142.
7
John Dryzek, “How Far is it from Virginia and Rochester to Frankfurt? Public Choice
as Critical Theory?” British Journal of Political Science 22 (1992), pp. 397–417. More generally,
see Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy and Political Science (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1990). Also see Bryce Weber, “It’s a Very Long Way from Frankfurt to
Virginia and Rochester: On the Hierarchy Market Distinction,” paper presented at the
meeting of the British Columbia Political Science Association, May 5–6, 1995.
Marketing Critical Theory 437
of comparison—primarily that of the normative grounds of political and moral
theory. Habermas’s discourse ethics, for example, is an element of his longstanding attempt to rethink the normative grounds of critical social theory. Analytical
Marxists such as John Roemer have also turned their attention to normative
questions of distributive justice, and post-positivist rational choice theory has
come to define itself as a normative rather than a value free enterprise.8 Of
course, this common focus does not necessarily mean that convergence is on the
horizon. There is a distinct danger that, given the seeming incompatibility of the
two perspectives, an attempted synthesis will occlude central elements of critical
theory.
Joseph Heath’s Communicative Action and Rational Choice takes up these
normative issues from a position sympathetic to James Johnson’s approach—
though Heath places greater emphasis on philosophical grounds of normative
commitments. Heath develops a version of the complementarity thesis. He holds
that communicative action and strategic action can be linked as forms of
normative social action. In so doing, he poses a series of significant revisions
that, he argues, “weaken” the overly strong requirements of Habermas’s critical
theory (p. 310).
Heath is concerned with the links between questions of social action, such as
the problem of order, and normative theory (pp. 6–7, 16–17). He agrees with
Habermas that rational choice theory lacks the resources to solve questions of
order. Yet Heath is not satisfied with Habermas’s alternative approach to the
questions of social order—especially his analysis of the presuppositions of moral
discourse—and generally with those elements inherited from the continental
tradition. Heath believes that there is a central confusion in Habermas’s approach between a “discourse theoretical” approach and an “action theoretical”
approach to the question of order. Heath proposes that under the action
theoretical approach, strategic and communicative action can be seen as complementary approaches to social order. Lacking an action theory foundation, he
argues, the discourse theoretical approach cannot tell us why we should or
would take up the stance of communicative action. In spite of its insufficiencies,
rational choice theory as a form of action theory provides a better account of the
need for adopting a communicative stance than Habermas’s approach. In
analyzing the theory of communicative action from this angle, Heath has
produced a serious, detailed, and careful engagement with Habermas’s work.
The book is distinguished by its clear account of some of the main features of
game theory, including recent philosophical literature on the subject. Heath has
carefully followed many of the important debates that have followed in the
wake of the Theory of Communicative Action, and he is alert to the subtle
modifications in Habermas’s position. This is no mean task!
For all its virtues, however, Heath’s reading of the theory of communicative
action, and his attempt to “weaken” the normative grounds of critical theory,
8
A decent summary of some of these attempts is found in Vidhu Verma, Justice, Equality
and Community: An Essay in Marxist Political Theory (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2000). For
an example of the view of post-positivist rational choice, see Randall Calvert’s polemical
exchange “Lowi’s Critique of Political Science: A Response,” PS: Political Science and Politics
26⬊2 (1993). Calvert is responding to Theodore Lowi’s inaugural address to the APSA
published as “The State in Political Science: How We Become What We Study,” American
Political Science Review 86 (1992), pp. 1–7.
438 Brian Caterino
are unsuccessful. Heath’s attempt to replace discourse theory with action theory
is artificial. Discourse theory is already linked to action through mutual understanding. Heath’s amendments provide a reductionist version of “action theory,”
one that has a subjective character incompatible with Habermas’s basic understanding of mutual knowledge. It integrates rational choice by limiting the
formative power of communicative action.
At the heart of these problems is Heath’s tendency to devalue the hermeneutic/interpretive foundations of Habermas’s project. Heath narrows the scope of
problems that a critical theory can address, and weakens such a theory’s power
to transform through critical self-understanding. I can illustrate the scope of
interpretive problems by considering Heath’s approach to Habermas’s theory of
communicative action. Heath reads Habermas’s theory as if it could be adequately explained as a product of debates in Anglo-American philosophy. One
looks in vain for references to Gadamer, Heidegger, Hegel, Humboldt, and
others. While Heath’s account clarifies Habermas’s use of such important
thinkers as Dummett, Davidson, Austin, Searle and Brandom—although I find
Habermas’s own expositions more lucid9—Heath’s account is one-sided. Habermas’s engagement with Anglo-American theory is significant, but it is not
sufficient to capture central aspects of Habermas’s approach.10 As Christine
Lafont notes:
Despite the importance of Habermas’s appropriation of different views from the
Anglo-American philosophy of language, his conception of language is decisively
influenced by the basic premises developed in the German tradition (especially in
Humboldt’s and Gadamer’s view) These are premises that … cannot be regarded
as equally central for the Anglo-American tradition.11
In Humboldt’s work, Habermas discovers the origin of the idea (later elaborated
by Gadamer and others) that language is a medium of intersubjectivity achieved
though mutual understanding. A society is a web of symbolically mediated
interactions, which are bound together consensually. The idea of mutual understanding, however, is also linked to moral and ethical problems of self-interpretation and self-formation. As members of a linguistic community speakers are
shaped through the supra subjective character of linguistic community, but at
the same time speakers also shape language. This process of renewal, however,
is not simply a reproduction of meaning but always holds out the possibility of
calling into question existing meaning and hence creating new meanings.
9
In addition to Habermas’s remarks in Theory of Communicative Action, volume 1 (Boston:
Beacon Press, 1984; especially pp. 273–337), he revises and restates his position in the
following essays collected in On the Pragmatics of Communicative Action (Cambridge: MIT
Press, 1998): “Actions: Speech Acts, Linguistically Mediated Interaction and Life World,”
pp. 215–256, especially 226ff; “Toward a Critique of the Theory of Meaning,” pp. 277–300;
and “Some Further Clarifications of the Concept of Communicative Rationality,”
pp. 307–342.
10
Just to give one example out of many Habermas noted in an interview from 1984 that
his notion of universal pragmatics combines elements form both speech act theory and
phenomenological sociology’s analysis of the life world. “A Philosophical–Political Profile,”
in Peter Dews (ed.), Habermas: Autonomy and Solidarity: Interviews with Jürgen Habermas
(London: Verso, 1986), p. 151.
11
Lafont, The Linguistic Turn in Hermeneutic Philosophy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1999),
pp. 118–119. Another useful source is Maeve Cooke, Language and Reason: A Study of
Habermas’s Pragmatics (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997).
Marketing Critical Theory 439
Participants also have an independent ability to critically judge and transform
common sense. Speakers are at the same time members of a community and
self-interpreting subjects endowed with the capacity for individuality and autonomy. They have the capacity to take up a position on the world and transform
it.12
Since mutual understanding is both a medium of language and a medium of
social life, it is difficult to see the basis for Heath’s central distinction. With this
broad conception of mutual understanding, action and language are linked to
reproduce the world through mutual understanding. Habermas’s theory of
communicative action draws on a distinction between our access to the natural
world and our access to the social world. While the natural scientist has to
employ symbolic means to grasp the world, the social world requires a twostage interpretive process. Members of the social world are also other interpreters of the world and we have access to these interpretations only as fellow
participants in the social world. Habermas spells out the implications of the
double hermeneutic for morality. He argues that questions of truth take place
within an “objective world,” while norms are aspects of the social world. The
latter is a world of normatively regulated interaction. In the social world, unlike
the objective world, norms are directly related to our commitments to act.
Norms and values (no matter how unique the latter are) have to be worthy of
being recognized. While we can consider nature to be constituted independently
of our claims about it, this is not he case with the social world. We cannot grasp
the social world without seeing it as an order of validity that is made up of the
very activity of mutually understanding that world; it is not independent of the
assent of participants. Norms are connected to and dependent upon the continual renewal of the social world through mutual accountability. The latter
provides the binding character of social life. When a member of a social group
holds a norm to be valid, it is assumed that she is obliged to act accordingly.
There is, in Habermas’s words, a “mutual dependence of language and the social
world.”13
Heath’s action theoretical reformulation of Habermas is in large measure
directed against the special status accorded such mutual knowledge. He rejects
the idea that moral understanding is distinct from understanding of facts in the
objective world.
Habermas’s conception of mutual understanding is also crucial to his political thought. Though often seen as a liberal procedural theory of justice, communicative theory provides more than a simple defense of liberalism; it also draws
on the counter enlightenment critique of liberal individualism. Habermas fre12
Habermas’s relation to Humboldt is developed in “Communicative Rationality and
the Theories of Meaning and Action,” in On the Pragmatics of Communicative Action, op. cit.,
pp. 183–192. Language also has a world-disclosing character. It makes it possible for
something to appear in the world. The world exists before language, but it can only be
understood as something thought language. Habermas reads this world-disclosing,
however, in different way than Heidegger or post-structuralism. The world is not disclosed
as a given meaning but as a mode of understanding. Claims still have to prove themselves
independently through discourse.
13
“Discourse Ethics,” in Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Cambridge: MIT
Press, 1990), p. 61. Simone Chambers in Reasonable Democracy: Jurgen Habermas and the Politics
of Discourse (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996) also argues that Habermas’s theory is
a kind of “interpretive deontology” (p. 43ff) and employs “hermeutical reconstruction”
(p. 55). However, I think her reading is too Kantian.
440 Brian Caterino
quently employs a theoretical nexus developed from Hegel to Humboldt
through to Mead to build upon a notion of mutual recognition. This nexus links
Habermas’s critical theory to elements of the 19th century critique of possessive
individualism. The expressivist version of this critique saw humans as developers and exerters of powers, but recognized that processes of individuation and
the development of capacities and powers were social processes. Individuals
were dependent upon social conditions and institutions for the development of
their abilities. Certainly, the early Marx drew on this notion. This critique could
thus be more sensitive to the restrictions and deformations of the capitalist social
and economic system. Communicative theory does not, however, rehabilitate the
expressivist critique, which it considers inadequate; rather it clarifies the ambiguities inherent in 19th century notions of mutual recognition, which fluctuated
between a subject-centered model, used by expressivists, and an intersubjective
notion of recognition. The latter incorporates both elements of self-determination
and self-realization under the rubric of an expanded notion of communicative
freedom. With this expansion of the concept of mutual understanding, critical
theory is capable of addressing questions of both recognition and identity, as
well as the pathologies of communicative action (such as “colonization”).14
Thus while Habermas employs a procedural approach to justice, one which
seeks to illustrate the limits of a purely republican conception resting on
homogenous community, he also incorporates elements of republicanism, such
as its emphasis on popular sovereignty, into his theory of democracy. His
analysis of the presuppositions of the moral point of view can also be the basis
for a conception of democratic legitimacy which can include a more widespread
democratic participation in political institutions, and for a widespread democratization of social life.15
Revising Strategic and Communicative Action
Heath’s neglect of the hermeneutic roots of Habermas’s theory is more than an
interpretive flaw; it is a central element in his revision of Habermas’s normative
theory. Heath rejects many of the elements central to Habermas’s notion of
mutual understanding, beginning with his analysis of the presuppositions of
discourse.
One of the central tenets of hermeneutics is the idea that understanding
meaning never occurs in isolation but only against a background of other
14
As pointed out clearly in work of C. B. Macpherson and Charles Taylor. See C. B.
Macpherson, Democratic Theory: Essays in Retrieval (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973)
and Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), Chapter 1. Also
see Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1992). For Marx’s expressivism, see “The Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts,”
in Karl Marx: Selected Writings (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994), pp. 72ff, 86ff, among many
possible references, and “Excerpt-Notes of 1844,” in Selected Writings, p. 50ff. Of course Marx
uses a labor theory of constitution which has other well known problems.
15
Habermas’s relation to Rousseau is discussed in Between Facts and Norms: Contributions
to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996), especially
Appendix 1, “Popular Sovereignty as Procedure,” pp. 463–490. The concepts of communicative freedom, self-determination and self-realization are developed throughout Between
Facts and Norms. I would emphasize these more radical elements more than some
commentators and more than perhaps Habermas himself.
Marketing Critical Theory 441
meanings. We can only make sense of meaning within the system of language
as a whole. Habermas gives this mode of analysis a formalistic twist. He asks
what conditions we have to accept to make sense of the idea of reaching
understanding. Are there unavoidable conditions we must accept when we
“perform, understand, or respond to a speech act”?16 This approach, which
forms the core of universal pragmatics, is not identical to Kant’s analysis of the
transcendental conditions of experience. Where the latter seeks the conditions of
our possible experience of objects in the world, universal pragmatics begins with
subjects who are members of a community who possess the interpretive knowhow to come to accord about elements of the world. Universal pragmatics then
is a way of explicating or making explicit the interpretive achievements of
participants in social life. These conditions help us to make sense of the practice
of reaching understanding. What Habermas has in mind is a more formal
version of what Heidegger and Gadamer mean by anticipatory understanding.
We have to assume in advance that these elements are constitutive of a practice
that could not function without them, anticipate that certain conditions can or
ought to exist. In a similar manner, Habermas argues that his discourse ethics
explicates the basic conditions of the moral point of view. These basic conditions
include freedom of access, equal rights to participate, the truthfulness of participants, and the absence of coercion. Our moral norms are fair only if they are
decided by the force of reasoning that all can accept.
Heath is uncomfortable with Habermas’s modified transcendental argument—at least as it applies to morality. In his view, it does not provide a
plausible account of the reason subjects would engage in communicative action.
Heath rejects Habermas’s claim that basic norms of equality, freedom, and
reciprocity are built into the structure of discourse itself. Speech acts, he argues,
do not generate any “extra discursive” commitment (p. 307). We cannot, he
contends, draw any normative implications form the presuppositions of mutual
understanding.
Habermas argues that mutual accountability requires that participants be
able when required to provide justifications of the norms they hold valid with
reasons that can be intersubjectively accepted. Heath raises an objection to this
claim based on the status of imperatives, such as commands, exclamations, and
the like (“Get me coffee” or “I hate broccoli”). Such imperatives only require that
the single actor consider them valid. Their meaning is agent-relative not intersubjective. Yet even if this objection is true for a limited class of imperatives, this
does not seem to undermine Habermas’s basic starting point. For the objection
here only holds against one aspect of Habermas’s reconstruction of our moral
know-how, not against the necessity of its starting point. Even common sense
reflection indicates that any imperative can become a contested claim in the
proper context. An employee may not think that an employer has a right to
make him a glorified gofer, with good reasons, and turn the command into a
contested claim. Such moral imperatives are not agent-relative. We still have to
reconstruct our implicit knowledge of such norms using the model of moral
discourse.
Heath overextends this objection. He believes that it undercuts any notion of
a reconstruction that starts from the assumption of mutual understanding.
16
On the Pragmatics of Communicative Action, p. 22.
442 Brian Caterino
Norms entail no commitments to mutual accountability or discursive redemption since in their basic form they are agent-relative (pp. 47, 121ff).
In contrast, Heath argues that rational choice theory provides a better
account of why we enter into communicative action. He thinks we enter into
communicative action for strictly pragmatic reasons. When we discover that
instrumental action is either insufficient or not feasible, then “it seems reasonable to suppose that agents will enter into discourse just because normatively
regulated interaction works better than strategic action” (p. 310). Discourse best
fixes “the content of the normative system.”
This argument recommends that we take up a communicative perspective
because it is a more effective way to reach our goals. Adopting this perspective,
however, would involve the participant in a type of performative contradiction.
One cannot act strategically and communicatively at the same time. In order to
engage in communicative action, an actor has to relinquish strategic or purposive aims. If a social actor retained the possibility of defecting in the background,
as Heath seems to argue, then agreements would be untrustworthy.
The only way that Heath’s proposal makes sense is if we view it as consistent
with the analytic starting point of rational choice theory, and begin with the
premise that individuals are at the start either purposive or strategic actors. Then
we can decide at some point that consensual action is superior, and switch to
another perspective. Of course the classic objection to this approach asks how we
have developed the ability to employ a communicative perceptive and how we
explain its development beginning from purposive or strategic action. Heath
provides no adequate answer to this question, because we can only make sense
of our social world to each other as members of an already existing community.
The performative contradiction noted above though indicates that we are
already in such a community if we are able to take up a communicative stance.
He has to suppose the very capacity he wants to explain.
Heath hopes to meet this objection by collapsing the strong distinction
Habermas makes between strategic and communicative action. The strong
distinction between facts and norms is unwarranted. All discourse is normative,
but its normative features apply in the first instance to fact-oriented discourse
(p. 85).17
17
Heath relies on the work of philosopher Robert Brandom to formulate an alternative.
Brandom’s major work is Making it Explicit: Reasoning Representation and Discursive
Commitment (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1998); a shorter and more accessible
version of his work is Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism (Cambridge:
Harvard University press, 2001). Habermas reviews Brandom in “From Kant to Hegel: On
Robert Brandom’s Pragmatic Philosophy of Language,” European Journal of Philosophy 8
(2000), pp. 322–355. Brandom replies in the same issue. Like Habermas, Brandom looks to
the accountability of knowledge as its central feature. Ordinary social activity that is
relatively inexplicit must be capable of transformation into explicit claims about the world
when questions arise. However Brandom, whom Heath follows, restricts accountability to
facts or at least he reduces moral norms to facts. All forms of inquiry according to Brandom
are normative. While it is beyond the scope of this review to give a full discussion of
Brandom’s interesting proposal, it is fair to say the in the end Brandom’s attempt to make
the world of fact normative leads him toward idealism. The basic problem with his work
relevant to the review is the attempt to absorb norms into facts. Moral norms become rather
moral facts. This line of argument has difficulty grasping the types of self-relations that
Habermas claims are central for communicative action. Nor can it grasp all dimensions of
interpretive access to the world.
Marketing Critical Theory 443
He merges the world of morally regulated actions to a variant of the objective
world. Norms are facts that can be true or false. Heath thus defines the terms of
the critical theory–game theory encounter, not as distinctive theories of the
rationality of action but as competing conceptions of rational choice (p. 2). Critical
theory simply takes a broader interpretation of rational choices to include
communicative actions.
Heath argues that Habermas wrongly characterizes the nature of strategic
action.18 For Heath, critical theory employs the model of a singular (atomistic)
subject who has no connection with the interests of others. These conditions,
according to Heath, only hold true for decision-making theories that construct
models of the individual subject who decides upon a course of action in
isolation. In contrast, game theory models of strategic action involve social
action. Individuals respond to the choices of others and change their preferences
based on the choices of others (pp. 47–51). Heath contends that Habermas does
not take into account the social character of strategic action. Thus, he does not
clarify the typological distinction between actions oriented to success and
communicative action oriented to agreement. Heath argues that the only way to
show the difference between types of action is to show that game theory models
of action cannot generate the kind of obligations and commitments that Habermas attributes to communicative action. In doing so, however, he reformulates
Habermas’s basic distinctions as the relation between non-social (instrumental)
action and social (communicative) action.
An action that has a natural outcome as its goal is a success oriented action. An
action hat has another’s belief as its goal (and does not rely upon “natural”
meaning) is an understanding oriented action … It is precisely the introduction of
beliefs into the actor’s environment that introduces the distinction between these
two orientations; since beliefs cannot be handled using the tools associated with
nonsocial decision problems. (p. 80)
This reformulation is problematic. Heath reads Habermas’s critique as a
derivation of the expressivist critique of atomism. This is incorrect. As I indicated above, Habermas extends this critique with an updated conceptual framework. Habermas’s theory does not, as far as I can determine, consider strategic
action to be non-social action. With Max Weber, Habermas considers social
action to be any action in which actors are guided by the expectations of others.
Not all social action is communicative action, however, only that activity in
which “actors coordinate their action plans with one another by way of linguistic
processes of reaching understanding”19 can be termed communicative. In contrast, strategic action is a type of social action in which actors seek to influence
others to act in a certain way to further a desired goal. Strategically acting
individuals understand the meanings of others such as their beliefs, their values,
etc., but do not take their bearing from the question of the mutual understanding
among participants. In strategic action, actors take account of the expectations of
others; in communicative action, we are accountable to the expectations of others.
“As soon as we take the role of a strategic actor we relinquish, not the social
dimension of action, but some of the central dimensions of the role of the
18
19
A point also argued by Johnson.
“Some Further Clarifications,” p. 326.
444 Brian Caterino
participant engaged in an intersubjective process of reaching understanding
with others.” In strategic action, Habermas argues, “this potential for communicative rationality remains unexploited, even where the interactions are linguistically mediated.”20
The careful reader is going to see the connection between this argumentative
strategy and Heath’s criticism of Habermas’s speech act theory above. By
making the basic form of normative action agent-relative, Heath argues that
strategic action is a basic form of normative social action, along with communicative action.
Heath also rejects Habermas model of social acquisition of capacities for
individualization. He argues that norms can be better explained using a sociological model of the social learning of behavioral expectations. While Heath
accepts the accountability model for the establishment of facts, he takes a
sociological approach derived from Parsons. “Accountability structure of social
norms is to be explained … by the mechanism that must be in place in order to
ensure that agents acquire the correct fundamental choice position” (p. 151).
Here language is not a medium of mutual understanding but a form of
norm-governed action. Meaning is determined by its effects in transforming the
status of obligations social actors hold (p. 310). While Heath argues that such
commitments require that agents must subordinate their goals to norms, he does
so in way that undercuts the very nature of the agents’ necessary capacities as
participants.
Heath defines accountability sociologically as the capacity to verbally justify
actions and as the ability to be held to account for failure to comply with norms
(pp. 151–152). This analysis is applied to collective decision problems. Individuals can defect, dissent, or deviate from collective expectations.
The problems with this approach can be seen through a thought experiment.
A social scientist approaches a culture and has to understand when subjects are
carrying out an agreement and when they are not. In short, she has to know
when they dissent or defect, and when they comply. Heath’s sociological
perspective seems to take the standpoint of an observer, who can discern the
meaning of these activities independent of the participants’ perspective. He can
discern the social currency of a norm through observational analysis of socialization patterns. But how does the observer know what how to discern what is
“dissent” vs. “deviance” from the observers perspective? Both entail non-compliance. In fact, there is no observer-neutral description of choice dispositions
that can satisfy this requirement. In order to understand the difference between
dissent and deviance the social inquirer must adopt a participant’s perspective.
She must examine the reasons why an individual does or does not comply. The
social inquirer must suppose that the participants have the capacity to take a
position through reasons that can be validated. For even though we are all
bought up within a social world, we are not simply cultural dopes socialized to
accept the norms of our society. Participants are autonomous; they have the
ability to independently judge and take a position on social norms.
20
Ibid.
Marketing Critical Theory 445
Norms and Morality
Heath employs a restricted reading of Habermas’s moral theory. He treats
Habermas as a social contract theorist in the tradition of Rousseau and Kant
(pp. 211ff; more generally on the contractualism of his project, see pp. 34, 104).
Analogous to the problem of order, a theory of justice has to answer the
question: how do individual interests fuse into a general interest or general will?
Some of Habermas’s earlier formulations such as that found in Legitimation Crisis
might suggest this reading, but it is inconsistent with his most recent work.
Reading Habermas’s approach to morality as a strict deontological one, Heath
rejects Habermas’s concern with ethical questions as insistent with his basic idea
(pp. 236ff). Like many rational choice theorists who criticize the idea of popular
sovereignty, Heath finds it difficult to see how general interests can be discerned
under conditions of value plurality. Heath takes up a version of Thomas
McCarthy’s objection to Habermas’s conception of justice.21 McCarthy contrasts
Habermas’s attempt to find universal “generalizable interests” with Max Weber’s conception of essential value pluralism (warring gods). McCarthy argues
that ultimate value commitment requires incommensurable orientations. The
only plausible alternative is compromise. Where Habermas, however, thinks that
compromise has to include the interests of the participants and by implication
both their sense of justice and their self-respect, McCarthy argues that compromise can and must bypass the participants’ perspective and incorporate nonmoral elements. In a sense, McCarthy’s position implies, like Rousseau’s, that
the only viable basis for generalizable interests would be a homogeneous
community.
Heath takes up McCarthy’s objection by arguing that in cases of value
disagreement critical theory does not have to surrender to the clash of warring
gods. It can “fall back” to a solution provided by bargaining theory (p. 243).
While bargaining theory solutions do not assure agreement or establish socially
binding norms, they do, in Heath’s view, narrow the scope of disagreement
postulated by McCarthy. Thus, bargaining theory provides a guarantee that is
lacking in Habermas’s theory: the guarantee that individuals can roughly agree
about outcomes. Given this rough convergence, Heath argues, game theory can
help to shape and structure the expectations of the participants such that they
can “agree” that such strategically achieved balances are “fair” compromises.
Through regularized expectations, choice problems come to be accepted as fair.
Retranslating problems of political order into questions of choice solved by
regularized behavioral expectations does not, however, address the questions
raised by Weber’s challenge. For questions of distinctive value orientations are
entwined with questions of individual and cultural identity and recognition. The
latter are not resolved by stable outcomes, but by the creation of moral respect.
Individuals and groups are harmed when the organization of power limits their
communicative freedom to interpret the world and develop their unique powers. Without this power subjects are prone to communicative as well as political
colonialization. Morality also draws on the power of recognition. Moral norms
are part of the web of mutual understanding through which individuals are
21
Thomas McCarthy, “Practical Discourse: On the Relation of Morality to Politics,” in
Ideals and Illusions: On Reconstruction and Deconstruction in Critical Theory (Cambridge: MIT
Press, 1991), pp. 181–199.
446 Brian Caterino
bound to each other. Morality like identity requires recognition of others as part
of a common world. The issue that has to be addressed is one of discerning
universal aspects of recognition that do not rely on homogenous values or
community.
Habermas draws upon the liberal social contract tradition, especially its
procedural versions, but he also incorporates elements of republican political
theory. Read though the Hegel–Humboldt–Mead position more than the expressivist one, this critique holds that the identity of moral subjects is be formed
though mutual understanding and recognition.
Moral theory does not begin from the fiction of a state of nature or from
any type of analytical procedure that can derive political community from
self-interested individuals. It proceeds holistically from already socialized individuals who are already members of an ethical community and who have a
conflict over some aspect of the world.
The social contract could not provide a satisfactory response to this challenge
because an agreement motivated by interests can lead at best to an externally
imposed social regulation of conduct but not to a binding, let alone a universalistic, conception of the common good … The members of a moral community are
not trying to replace morality with a social regulation of behavior that is to
everyone’s advantage.22
In his more recent formulations, Habermas distinguishes different types of
the rationality of action, such as instrumental strategic and communicative
action, through the orientations of action (success-oriented or oriented to mutual
understanding), not as different forms of choice. This is significant in light of his
more recent work that develops a three-part conception of practical reason. More
in the spirit of Kant and Hegel, Habermas distinguishes between the pragmatic,
the ethical, and the moral as three ways of answering the question: what should
I do?23 Only the pragmatic is concerned with choice. Pragmatic action is a type
of success-oriented action that comes into play in situations where we want to
choose between courses of action in order to achieve a goal. Here we choose in
the light of fixed purposes or by assessing ends in light of existing preferences.24
Ethical and moral practical reason requires forms of action oriented to
mutual understanding. In the first case actions are concerned with questions of
identity, that is, questions of who I am or what kind of person I want to be. (For
example, someone might ask: should I become an academic an activist or can I
combine elements into the person I want to be?) Such ethical considerations
require self-interpretation. We take up our own life history through an interpretation that links our own descriptions of what we are to our strong evaluations
of what we want to be, in the course of a life project. According to Habermas,
this entails a process of hermeneutic self-clarification. The moral use of practical
reason requires reference to a broader web of social relations in which we
develop obligations to others. Conflicts of ideas and interests require us to
22
“A Genealogical Analysis of the Cognitive Content of Morality,” in The Inclusion of the
Other: Studies in Political Theory (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1998), p. 23.
23
Habermas, “On the Pragmatic, the Ethical and the Moral Employments of Practical
Reason,” in Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics (Cambridge: MIT Press),
pp. 1–18.
24
“On the pragmatic,” pp. 2–3.
Marketing Critical Theory 447
consider what kind of norms and maxims of action we can reasonably expect to
oblige us to others and others to us as participants in common worlds. Unlike
strategic actions, which may benefit all, questions of justice require a shift to the
participants’ perspective. We do not try to influence others to do what we wish,
or to reciprocally influence each other, but to come to an understanding with
them about the right thing to do.
Certainly the conditions of modernity, most notably the breakdown of
religious and metaphysical worldviews, assure that competing conceptions of
the good arise. These conditions, however, are not identical to the conditions
McCarthy or Weber cite. On the one hand, modern plurality assumes some
version of equal freedom for all and the right not just to choice but also to
individuality. On the other hand, it relativizes these value orientations. Under
these conditions value orientations are reflexively understood. None carries an
absolute certainty, yet they do belong to the same ethical universe.
Moral questions arise as a new level of moral reflection on the conditions of
modern plurality. Moral questions do not ask about the relative worth of
differing conceptions of the good, but the conditions under which the vulnerable
processes of mutual recognition that underlie value orientations can be protected. When there is no substantive agreement about the good, participants
have access to another level of consideration, that is, consideration of the general
conditions of communicative forms of life in general. Habermas argues that the
line of analysis he derives from the Hegel–Humboldt–Mead nexus can ask just
these questions. This approach illustrates that “communicative actions involve
shared presuppositions and that communicative forms of life are interwoven
with relations of reciprocal recognition and to this extent both have a normative
content.”25
On this reading, moral consideration extends to persons not just as unique
individuals but also as members of a community. This type of moral universalism takes into account the general conditions of identity formation and is
sensitive to the question of difference. Because Habermas formulates the problem in this way, I do not think that his attempt to incorporate ethical and moral
questions under the horizon of mutual understanding is inconsistent. Rather we
can see that questions of recognition are central to both moral and ethical
understating. Such questions, however, cannot be approached from the standpoint of rational choice games. They require reference to the integrity (and the
vulnerability) of participants who form their identity though communicative
forms of life.
Rational Choice, Social Crisis and Diagnosis
Heath argues that the system of functionalism employed by Habermas in Theory
of Communicative Action fails as a method of diagnosing the problems of market
society. For Heath, functionalism is a circular explanation that presumes order
exists (through presumed functions) without showing how order is achieved. It
does not explain problems of social disorganization in which aspects of social
25
“Genealogical Analysis,” p. 40. Axel Honneth has also developed a version of mutual
recognition using primarily Mead and Hegel. See especially Honneth, The Struggle for
Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996).
448 Brian Caterino
life are instrumentalized but not successfully integrated. Rational choice provides a more “scientific” foundation for analysis of political/economic problems.
Marx, he argues, held a 19th century view of capitalism based on 19th macroeconomic analysis. After the marginalist revolution in the 20th century, however,
micro foundational analysis such as rational choice provides “small scale concrete analysis of interaction” that is “rigorously developed and empirically
verifiable.”26 Such concrete analysis he argues enhances the diagnostic power of
a critical theory. It can illustrate some of the pathologies of strategic action, e.g.
it shows the ways in which strategic action fails to solve problems of order. The
explanatory diagnostic function, however, also goes hand in hand with a
commitment to critique. Communicative action provides the basis for an emancipatory/utopian critique missing in rational choice theory.
I do not think we can reject Heath’s clams for this employment of rational
choice out of hand. However, his examples of fruitful research, such as William
Riker’s critique of populism, seem ill chosen. Riker’s analysis is a prime example
of what Ian Shapiro and Donald Green see as artificially problem-generated
research.27 If one begins with the false assumption that democracy can be
explained by strategic action, a methodological decision that excludes the
participant’s perspective at the start, then no doubt one will get the conclusion
that a populist version of democracy is impossible
Heath narrows the scope of diagnosing social ills in contemporary society. In
a correlate work, The Efficient Society, Heath argues that the market, that is,
capitalist markets, is an unassailable foundation of social organization. Those
who think that markets can be overthrown are wrongheaded. “There are,”
according to Heath, “no viable alternatives.” This includes market socialism,
which he views simply as capitalism under another name. In the post-socialist
world, Heath sides with the new end-of-ideology thinkers. He even compares
Habermas’s work to Francis Fukuyama’s, a claim I consider very dubious.28
Heath, in spite of his earlier claims, rejects the utopian project. We must do away
with the totalizing spirit of the French Revolution and content ourselves with
small reforms. Yet, these reforms are largely matters of game theoretical intuitional design. According to Heath:
The most exciting proposals for social reform currently being generated all come
from the field of economics known as “mechanical design.” Rather than simply
trying to legislate desirable social outcomes, the goal of the mechanism designer
is to develop a set of rules that will indirectly constrain the conduct of individuals
in such a way that it will be in their interest to promote the desirable outcome …29
Here Heath takes leave of the participants’ perspective and adopts the
standpoint of a detached scientist and social engineer who designs institutions
26
Heath, “Rational Choice as Critical Theory,” Philosophy and Social Criticism 22 (1996).
See Donald Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of
Applications in Political Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994).
28
Even a quick reading of Habermas’s essay “The Postnational Constellation and the
Future of Democracy,” whatever its limits, would have differentiated him from
contemporary end-of-ideology thinkers. In The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays
(Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001), pp. 53–112.
29
Joseph Heath, The Efficient Society: Why Canada Is as Close to Utopia as it Gets (New York:
Penguin, 2001), p. 306.
27
Marketing Critical Theory 449
that are best for every one. This is not the standpoint of the critical theorist who
must engage in mutual critique. Heath’s conception of change seems more like
social engineering than critique. He does not refer to the questions of the
freedom or the happiness of the participants.
Habermas’s theory explores the connections between mutual understanding
and social order. He also argues that his conception preserves a dimension of
critical understanding that was not well clarified in earlier critical theory,
including his own. Because he employs a notion of understanding social life that
is rooted in the participation of actors in social life, he can develop the idea of
mutual critique. In such a critique, the knowledge of the participant and that of
the inquirer are (in principle) on the same level. The critic has no privileged
position of knowledge prior to discourse with participants. The only critique of
society then that is valid is one that can be accepted and taken up by the
participants themselves. The diagnostic element of critical theory requires reference to our interpretive access to the world though mutual understanding. A
diagnosis of the times is not just an explanation in the sense that Heath and
rational choice theorists employ the term. It is more akin to an historical and
narrative account—one that because of its narrative structure can only grasped
from the standpoint of a participant.
BRIAN CATERINO
Rochester, NY