Skolem arithmetic

This is the current revision of this page, as edited by Tc14Hd (talk | contribs) at 10:02, 13 July 2024 (Idea of decidability: Changed capitalization). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this version.

(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

In mathematical logic, Skolem arithmetic is the first-order theory of the natural numbers with multiplication, named in honor of Thoralf Skolem. The signature of Skolem arithmetic contains only the multiplication operation and equality, omitting the addition operation entirely.

Skolem arithmetic is weaker than Peano arithmetic, which includes both addition and multiplication operations.[1] Unlike Peano arithmetic, Skolem arithmetic is a decidable theory. This means it is possible to effectively determine, for any sentence in the language of Skolem arithmetic, whether that sentence is provable from the axioms of Skolem arithmetic. The asymptotic running-time computational complexity of this decision problem is triply exponential.[2]

Axioms

edit

We define the following abbreviations.

  • a | b := ∃n.(an = b)
  • One(e) := ∀n.(ne = n)
  • Prime(p) := ¬One(p) ∧ ∀a.(a | p → (One(a) ∨ a = p))
  • PrimePower(p, P) := Prime(p) ∧ p | P ∧ ∀q.(Prime(q) ∧ ¬(q = p) → ¬(q | P))
  • InvAdicAbs(p, n, P) := PrimePower(p, P) ∧ P | n ∧ ∀Q.((PrimePower(p, Q) ∧ Q | n) → Q | P) [P is the largest power of p dividing n]
  • AdicAbsDiffn(p, a, b) := Prime(p) ∧ p | ab ∧ ∃P.∃Q.(InvAdicAbs(p, a, P) ∧ InvAdicAbs(p, b, Q) ∧ Q = pnP) for each integer n > 0. [The largest power of p dividing b is pn times the largest power of p dividing a]

The axioms of Skolem arithmetic are:[3]

  1. a.∀b.(ab = ba)
  2. a.∀b.∀c.((ab)c = a(bc))
  3. e.One(e)
  4. a.∀b.(One(ab) → One(a) ∨ One(b))
  5. a.∀b.∀c.(ac = bca = b)
  6. a.∀b.(an = bna = b) for each integer n > 0
  7. x.∃a.∃r.(x = arn ∧ ∀b.∀s.(x = bsna | b)) for each integer n > 0
  8. a.∃p.(Prime(p) ∧ ¬(p | a)) [Infinitude of primes]
  9. p.∀P.∀Q.((PrimePower(p, P) ∧ PrimePower(p, Q)) → (P | QQ | P))
  10. p.∀n.(Prime(p) → ∃P.InvAdicAbs(p,n,P))
  11. n.∀m.(n = m ↔ ∀p.(Prime(p) → ∃P.(InvAdicAbs(p, n, P) ∧ InvAdicAbs(p, m, P)))) [Unique factorization]
  12. p.∀n.∀m.(Prime(p) → ∃P.∃Q.(InvAdicAbs(p, n, P) ∧ InvAdicAbs(p, m, Q) ∧ InvAdicAbs(p, nm, PQ))) [p-adic absolute value is multiplicative]
  13. a.∀b.(∀p.(Prime(p) → ∃P.∃Q.(InvAdicAbs(p, a, P) ∧ InvAdicAbs(p, b, Q) ∧ P | Q)) → a | b) [If the p-adic valuation of a is less than that of b for every prime p, then a | b]
  14. a.∀b.∃c.∀p(Prime(p) → (((p | a → ∃P.(InvAdicAbs(p, b, P) ∧ InvAdicAbs(p, c, P))) ∧ ((p | b) → (p | a)))) [Deleting from the prime factorization of b all primes not dividing a]
  15. a.∃b.∀p.(Prime(p) → (∃P.(InvAdicAbs(p, a, P) ∧ InvAdicAbs(p, b, pP))) ∧ (p | bp | a))) [Increasing each exponent in the prime factorization of a by 1]
  16. a.∀b.∃c.∀p.(Prime(p) → ((AdicAbsDiffn(p, a, b) → InvAdicAbs(p, c, p)) ∧ (p | c → AdicAbsDiffn(p, a, b))) for each integer n > 0 [Product of those primes p such that the largest power of p dividing b is pn times the largest power of p dividing a]

Expressive power

edit

First-order logic with equality and multiplication of positive integers can express the relation  . Using this relation and equality, we can define the following relations on positive integers:

  • Divisibility:  
  • Greatest common divisor:  
  • Least common multiple:  
  • the constant  :  
  • Prime number:  
  • Number   is a product of   primes (for a fixed  ):  
  • Number   is a power of some prime:  
  • Number   is a product of exactly   prime powers:  

Idea of decidability

edit

The truth value of formulas of Skolem arithmetic can be reduced to the truth value of sequences of non-negative integers constituting their prime factor decomposition, with multiplication becoming point-wise addition of sequences. The decidability then follows from the Feferman–Vaught theorem that can be shown using quantifier elimination. Another way of stating this is that first-order theory of positive integers is isomorphic to the first-order theory of finite multisets of non-negative integers with the multiset sum operation, whose decidability reduces to the decidability of the theory of elements.

In more detail, according to the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, a positive integer   can be represented as a product of prime powers:

 

If a prime number   does not appear as a factor, we define its exponent   to be zero. Thus, only finitely many exponents are non-zero in the infinite sequence  . Denote such sequences of non-negative integers by  .

Now consider the decomposition of another positive number,

 

The multiplication   corresponds point-wise addition of the exponents:

 

Define the corresponding point-wise addition on sequences by:

 

Thus we have an isomorphism between the structure of positive integers with multiplication,   and of point-wise addition of the sequences of non-negative integers in which only finitely many elements are non-zero,  .

From Feferman–Vaught theorem for first-order logic, the truth value of a first-order logic formula over sequences and pointwise addition on them reduces, in an algorithmic way, to the truth value of formulas in the theory of elements of the sequence with addition, which, in this case, is Presburger arithmetic. Because Presburger arithmetic is decidable, Skolem arithmetic is also decidable.

Complexity

edit

Ferrante & Rackoff (1979, Chapter 5) establish, using Ehrenfeucht–Fraïssé games, a method to prove upper bounds on decision problem complexity of weak direct powers of theories. They apply this method to obtain triply exponential space complexity for  , and thus of Skolem arithmetic.

Grädel (1989, Section 5) proves that the satisfiability problem for the quantifier-free fragment of Skolem arithmetic belongs to the NP complexity class.

Decidable extensions

edit

Thanks to the above reduction using Feferman–Vaught theorem, we can obtain first-order theories whose open formulas define a larger set of relations if we strengthen the theory of multisets of prime factors. For example, consider the relation   that is true if and only if   and   have the equal number of distinct prime factors:

 

For example,   because both sides denote a number that has two distinct prime factors.

If we add the relation   to Skolem arithmetic, it remains decidable. This is because the theory of sets of indices remains decidable in the presence of the equinumerosity operator on sets, as shown by the Feferman–Vaught theorem.

Undecidable extensions

edit

An extension of Skolem arithmetic with the successor predicate,   can define the addition relation using Tarski's identity:[4][5]

 

and defining the relation   on positive integers by

 

Because it can express both multiplication and addition, the resulting theory is undecidable.

If we have an ordering predicate on natural numbers (less than,  ), we can express   by

 

so the extension with   is also undecidable.

See also

edit

References

edit

Bibliography

edit
  • Bès, Alexis (2001). "A Survey of Arithmetical Definability" (PDF). In Crabbé, Marcel; Point, Françoise; Michaux, Christian (eds.). A Tribute to Maurice Boffa. Brussels: Societé mathématique de Belgique. pp. 1–54.
  • Cegielski, Patrick (1981), "Théorie élémentaire de la multiplication des entiers naturels", in Berline, Chantal; McAloon, Kenneth; Ressayre, Jean-Pierre (eds.), Model Theory and Arithmetic, Berlin: Springer, pp. 44–89.
pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy