Response
Addressing polarisation in science
Brian D Earp
ABSTRACT
Ploug and Holm argue that polarisation in
scientific communities can generate conflicts of
interest for individual researchers. Their
proposed solution to this problem is that
authors should self-report whether they are
polarised on conflict of interest disclosure
forms. I argue that this is unlikely to work. This
is because any author with the self-awareness
and integrity to identify herself as polarised
would be unlikely to conduct polarised research
to begin with. Instead, I suggest that it is the
role of (associate-level) editors of journals to
detect and report on polarisation. One
consequence of this view is that they need to
be sufficiently familiar with the field of research
they are evaluating to know whether
polarisation is at stake.
INTRODUCTION
In a recent issue of the Journal of Medical
Ethics, Ploug and Holm1 point out that
scientific communities can sometimes
become rather polarised.i This happens
when two different groups of (comparably
respectable) researchers argue for more or
less opposite positions on some hotbutton empirical issue or question of
public policy.
The examples they give are debates
over the merits of breast cancer screening
and the advisability of prescribing statins
to people at low risk of heart disease.
Other examples can be easily brought to
mind.ii It is important to note, however,
that—according to Ploug and Holm—
i
Note: This article is adapted from a blog post by
the author2 originally published at the Journal of
Medical Ethics blog. This post is available at the
following link: http://blogs.bmj.com/medicalethics/2015/04/30/how-can-journal-editors-fightbias-in-polarized-scientific-communities/.
ii
For instance, there is the ‘enhancement’ debate
in biomedical ethics, which pits so-called
bioconservatives against so-called bioliberals
(eg, ref. 3, p.12)—with each group taking
roughly opposite positions on the question of
using medical technologies for purposes other
than treatment.4 Another example, familiar to
me from my own research focus, is the debate
over the health benefits versus risks of male
circumcision.5–9 I will say a little more about
this debate in a subsequent footnote.
Correspondence to Brian D Earp, Uehiro Centre for
Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, Oxford OX1 1PT,
UK; brian.earp@gmail.com
mere disagreement is not the same as
polarisation. Instead, the latter can (only?)
be said to happen when researchers
POLARISATION AS A CONFLICT OF
INTEREST
Ploug and Holm’s suggestion is this: the
polarisation of a scientific community can
generate conflicts of interest for particular
researchers. Specifically:
[T]he threat is that a polarised group
may nourish an interest in advancing the
position and views of the group, and
that this interest may come to be a main
criterion and goal for the choice of
methods, the reporting of findings and
the provision of policy advice. This
interest may well be based on an honest
conviction that one is right and thus not
be in any way morally reprehensible, but
even honestly held convictions can
introduce potential biases in research
and reporting. ( p.356)
(1) begin to self-identify as proponents
of a particular position that needs to be
strongly defended beyond what is supported by the data, and
(2) begin to discount arguments and
data that would normally be taken as
important in a scientific debate. ( p. 356)
But there is something peculiar about
criterion number (1). On the one hand, it
is framed in terms of self-identification: ‘I
see myself as a proponent of a particular
position that needs to be strongly
defended’. That much makes sense—and
there probably isn’t anything wrong with
regarding oneself this way. But on the
other hand, it states that this act of
position-defending must go ‘beyond what
is supported by the data’.
The problem is: who would self-identify
as someone who makes inadequately supported arguments? As it seems to me, if
one realises that one’s arguments are
getting too one-sided (to the point of
being biased), then one would have a hard
time carrying on producing them without
making some suitable adjustment. At least,
one would without losing a degree of academic credibility—and no small measure
of self-respect. This point will become
important later on.
Now, we might chalk this up to
ambiguous phrasing. Perhaps the authors
mean that (in order for polarisation to
be diagnosed) researchers have to selfidentify as ‘proponents of a particular
position’, while the parts about going
‘beyond the data’ and ‘discounting’
important information are what an
objective third-party would attribute to
the researchers (even if it's not what they
would say about themselves). It is difficult to know for sure, based upon the
way the criteria are written.
But whatever the case, I am going to
suggest that this issue of self-identification poses a problem for Ploug and
Holm’s ultimate proposal – ie, for how
to combat polarisation. To see why this
is the case, I shall have to say a little bit
more about what they see as being the
matter with polarisation in the first
place.
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2015 Vol 0 No 0
That would be a serious problem.iii As
Ploug and Holm explain, it could ‘threaten
the objectivity of science, and may in turn
bias public debate and political decisionmaking’ ( p.356). Indeed, in many areas of
biomedicine (as well as in other scientific
fields), one often gets the feeling that a particular group of researchers—whether they
are direct collaborators or not—is ultimately more interested in scoring points for
their ‘side’ than in getting to the bottom of
a genuine dispute.
One situation in which this can occur is
when there is a contentious moral or political question hanging in the balance
(although perhaps at some remove), such
that individual studies start to look like so
many chess pieces in an extra-scientific
debate (see generally, eg, refs. 10 and 11).iv
iii
As David Trafimow ( personal correspondence,
4 May 2015) has pointed out, however, ‘Few
researchers are completely objective [and] the
history of science is full of examples where
researchers with considerable—even extreme—
biases made important contributions. [So,]
although [ polarisation] has the potential to
cause harm, it also can confer benefits. [For
example,] researchers with a strong bias may
gain extra motivation to support their point of
view or disconfirm an opposing one, [and] this
[may in turn] lead to more creative ideas
and new insights. Furthermore…polarised
researchers may [ultimately turn out to] be
right. [But] even when they are wrong,
polarised researchers can greatly aid the
progress of science by proposing conundrums
for the other side to attempt to solve’.
iv
This sort of phenomenon can be seen in the
debate over male circumcision (if I may pursue
the example from footnote number ii). Since
circumcision is a religious ritual for some
groups—and one that is at least prima facie
harmful12–14—it might be seen as important
(for some researchers) to show that ‘health
benefits’ can be ascribed to it, since these could
be used to mount a ‘secular’ defense of the
practice.15–18 On the other hand, there are
moral and even human rights objections to
1
Response
Simple career interests can play a role
here too. For example, there may be a
perceived need to save face by defending
one’s own prior work, or that of one’s
friends or ideological allies. There are
many other factors as well. And these can
apply to any contested topic in science or
medicine.
So polarisation may very well contribute to bias in research. How do Ploug and
Holm propose to address it?
A SIMPLE SOLUTION?
Their basic suggestion is that researchers
should self-report polarisation as a ‘conflict of interest’ on the standard forms
they fill out when submitting their papers.
After reflecting on a few diagnostic questions, that is, they might end up writing
something like this (from p.357):
(1) This article reports research in a
polarised field.
(2) The research group I/we belong to
generally believe that the intervention
we have researched should/should not
be introduced in healthcare.
Is this a promising solution to the
problem of polarisation?
SOME DOUBTS
I argue that it is not. Imagine that you are a
researcher with enough self-awareness and
personal integrity to identify yourself as
‘polarised’ on a conflict of interest disclosure form (if in fact that is what you are).
How likely is it, in this scenario, that you
are also the sort of person who would
conduct polarised research—and write up
polarised articles—to begin with? I do not
think it could be very likely.
As I suggested earlier, once one realises
that one is getting dogmatic about pressing a particular viewpoint (so: failing to
engage seriously with the best arguments
from the other side, discounting important information, and so on), one cannot
go on submitting the same sorts of
papers, as though this realisation has had
no force. At least, one cannot if one has
even a modicum of academic integrity—
which is precisely what (self ) disclosure of
potential conflicts of interest requires.
circumcision,19–24 which are quite a bit easier
‘sell’ if one can demonstrate harm.25–27 This
ends up resulting in a strange—and contentious
—cocktail of religion, science and ethics in the
circumcision literature,9 28 29 with extremely
polarised camps making largely incompatible
empirical
claims
and
related
policy
suggestions.30 31
2
A ROLE FOR EDITORS?
So what about shifting the onus to
editors? Ploug and Holm touch on this
issue themselves when they write ‘Journal
editors have important roles to play here’
(p.357). Specifically, ‘[i]f editors are aware
that a field is polarised’, they should
factor this into their editorial process
regarding, for example, ‘choosing referees
or when scrutinising the quality of the
science or the policy recommendations’
(ibid.). But what if an editor is not aware
that a specific field is polarised, in the
sense defined by Ploug and Holm?
As Ploug and Holm point out, there are
‘many cases where [ journal editors] are
not themselves able to identify polarisation because they are in a similar position
to the average user of scientific evidence’
(p.357). This is where they suggest that
author self-reporting could be a helpful (if
admittedly partial) solution. If I am right,
however, and this is not likely to be a feasible strategy, then what alternative is there
for these problematic cases?
I would like to make the following suggestion. Any associate-level (handling)
editor who is charged with making a publication recommendation about a particular manuscript, should know at least
enough about the field in question to
judge whether it is polarised (in the Ploug
and Holm sense) and—if it is—on which
side of the fence the manuscript falls.
They do not need to be experts in
every field. But if they do not know
enough about the relevant subject matter
to assess if something as ‘big picture’ as
polarisation is an issue, then I do not see
how they could be qualified to make the
other sorts of important editorial decisions that are involved in, say, selecting
appropriate peer reviewers for the manuscript, or making an informed recommendation about whether to publish the paper
on the basis of the peer reviews.
Here is what this means in practical
terms. If a journal editor is not sure about
whether a given field (or manuscript)
show signs of being polarised, then she
should probably take the time to do some
background reading in the relevant area
of research. If she cannot, however—or if
she doesn’t have the time, etc—then she
should consider recusing herself from the
review process (for that paper) and
sending it to a different editor who knows
more about the field. Of course, it would
be important to make sure that this alternative editor was not herself a polarized
participant in the same scientific debate.
On the other hand, if the original
editor can assess polarisation—and sees
that the manuscript sits at one extreme
pole—then she can choose from among
the following options:
A. encourage the author(s) to resubmit
the manuscript in a less polarised
form (ie, by taking more seriously the
best arguments and data from the
other side and responding to them in
a charitable fashion),
B. invite a commentary or response paper
( prior to publication) from a respectable researcher on the ‘other side’,
C. publish the paper as it is, but with an
editorial statement alerting the reader
to the polarised nature of the research
and/or its author(s) (perhaps with a
list of references to credible opposing
arguments) or
D. some combination of the above.
These kinds of measures, in my view,
would have a decent chance of mitigating
some of the bias that may come with
polarisation, without relying on individual
researchers to self-characterise as making
polarised arguments.
CONCLUSION
In conclusion, it should not be the responsibility of authors to ‘out’ themselves (on a
conflict of interest disclosure form) as
being polarised: ie, as making inadequately
supported arguments. After all, anyone
with the integrity to do this would not be
making such arguments in the first place!
Instead, journal editors who are directly
handling manuscripts (ie, at the associate
level) should make sure that they know at
least enough about the relevant field of
research to judge whether it is polarised—
and then take steps (along the lines I have
suggested) to mitigate any associated biases
or conflicts of interest.
Acknowledgements Thanks are due to Julian
Savulescu and David Trafimow for feedback on an
earlier draft of this commentary.
Competing interests None declared.
Provenance and peer review Not commissioned;
internally peer reviewed.
To cite Earp BD. J Med Ethics Published Online First:
[ please include Day Month Year] doi:10.1136/
medethics-2015-102891
Received 7 May 2015
Accepted 25 May 2015
J Med Ethics 2015;0:1–3.
doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102891
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2015 Vol 0 No 0
Response
REFERENCES
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
Ploug T, Holm S. Conflict of interest disclosure and
the polarisation of scientific communities. J Med
Ethics 2015;41:356–8.
Earp BD. How can journal editors fight bias in
polarized scientific communities? J Med Ethics Blog
2015a.
Earp BD, Wudarczyk OA, Sandberg A, et al. If I could
just stop loving you: anti-love biotechnology and the
ethics of a chemical breakup. Am J Bioeth 2013;13
(11):3–17.
Earp BD, Sandberg A, Kahane G, et al. When is
diminishment a form of enhancement? Rethinking
the enhancement debate in biomedical ethics. Front
Syst Neurosci 2014;8(12):1–8.
Earp BD. The ethics of infant male circumcision.
J Med Ethics 2013;39(7):418–20.
Earp BD. Sex and circumcision. Am J Bioeth 2015;15
(2):43–5.
Earp BD. Do the benefits of male circumcision
outweigh the risks? A critique of the proposed CDC
guidelines. Front Pediatr 2015;3(18):1–6.
Earp BD, Darby R. Tradition vs. individual rights: the
current debate on circumcision. The Conversation 2
November 2012. https://theconversation.com/tradition-vsindividual-rights-the-current-debate-on-circumcision10199
Earp BD, Darby R. Does science support infant
circumcision? The Skeptic 2015;25:23–30.
Betz G. In defence of the value free ideal. Eur J
Philos Sci 2013;3(2):207–20.
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2015 Vol 0 No 0
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
Longino H. Beyond “bad science”: skeptical
reflections on the value-freedom of scientific inquiry.
Sci Technol Hum Values 1983;8(1):7–17.
Dworkin G. Cutting edge bioethics. 3 Quarks Daily
23 September 2013. http://www.3quarksdaily.com/
3quarksdaily/2013/09/cutting-edge-bioethics.html
Merkel R, Putzke H. After Cologne: male circumcision
and the law. Parental right, religious liberty or
criminal assault? J Med Ethics 2013;39(7):444–9.
Sarajlic E. Can culture justify infant circumcision?
Res Publica 2014;20(4):327–43.
Goldman R. Circumcision policy: a psychosocial
perspective. Pediatr Child Health 2004;9(9):630–3.
Darby R. The riddle of the sands: circumcision, history,
and myth. N Z Med J 2005;118(1218):U1564.
Darby R, Svoboda JS. A rose by any other name?
Rethinking the similarities and differences between
male and female genital cutting. Med Anthropol Q
2007;21(3):301–23.
Fox M, Thomson M. A covenant with the status
quo? Male circumcision and the new BMA guidance
to doctors. J Med Ethics 2005;31(8):463–9.
DeLaet DL. Framing male circumcision as a human
rights issue? Contributions to the debate over the
universality of human rights. J Hum Rights 2009;8
(4):405–26.
Svoboda JS. Circumcision of male infants as a human
rights violation. J Med Ethics 2013;39(7):469–74.
Ungar-Sargon E. On the impermissibility of infant
male circumcision: a response to Mazor (2013).
J Med Ethics 2015;41(2):186–90.
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
Darby R. The child’s right to an open future: is the
principle applicable to non-therapeutic circumcision?
J Med Ethics 2013;39(7):463–8.
Darby R. Risks, benefits, complications and harms:
neglected factors in the current debate on nontherapeutic circumcision. Kennedy Inst Ethics J
2015;25(1):1–34.
Royal Dutch Medical Association. Non-therapeutic
circumcision of male minors. Amsterdam: KNMG,
2010.
Hammond T. A preliminary poll of men circumcised in
infancy or childhood. BJU Int 1999;83(Suppl 1):85–92.
Boyle GJ, Goldman R, Svoboda JS, et al. Male
circumcision: pain, trauma and psychosexual
sequelae. J Health Psychol 2002;7(3):329–43.
Sorrells ML, Snyder JL, Reiss MD, et al. Fine-touch
pressure thresholds in the adult penis. BJU Int
2007;99(4):864–9.
Bell K. Genital cutting and Western discourses on
sexuality. Med Anthropol Q 2005;19(2):125–48.
Carpenter LM. On remedicalisation: male
circumcision in the United States and Great Britain.
Sociol Health Illn 2010;32(4):613–30.
Bell K. HIV prevention: Making male circumcision the
‘right’ tool for the job. Glob Public Health 2015;10
(5–6):552–72.
Collier R. Ugly, messy and nasty debate surrounds
circumcision. CMAJ 2012;184(1):E25–6.
3
Response
Addressing polarisation in science
Brian D Earp
ABSTRACT
Ploug and Holm argue that polarisation in
scientific communities can generate conflicts of
interest for individual researchers. Their
proposed solution to this problem is that
authors should self-report whether they are
polarised on conflict of interest disclosure
forms. I argue that this is unlikely to work. This
is because any author with the self-awareness
and integrity to identify herself as polarised
would be unlikely to conduct polarised research
to begin with. Instead, I suggest that it is the
role of (associate-level) editors of journals to
detect and report on polarisation. One
consequence of this view is that they need to
be sufficiently familiar with the field of research
they are evaluating to know whether
polarisation is at stake.
INTRODUCTION
In a recent issue of the Journal of Medical
Ethics, Ploug and Holm1 point out that
scientific communities can sometimes
become rather polarised.i This happens
when two different groups of (comparably
respectable) researchers argue for more or
less opposite positions on some hotbutton empirical issue or question of
public policy.
The examples they give are debates
over the merits of breast cancer screening
and the advisability of prescribing statins
to people at low risk of heart disease.
Other examples can be easily brought to
mind.ii It is important to note, however,
that—according to Ploug and Holm—
i
Note: This article is adapted from a blog post by
the author2 originally published at the Journal of
Medical Ethics blog. This post is available at the
following link: http://blogs.bmj.com/medicalethics/2015/04/30/how-can-journal-editors-fightbias-in-polarized-scientific-communities/.
ii
For instance, there is the ‘enhancement’ debate
in biomedical ethics, which pits so-called
bioconservatives against so-called bioliberals
(eg, ref. 3, p.12)—with each group taking
roughly opposite positions on the question of
using medical technologies for purposes other
than treatment.4 Another example, familiar to
me from my own research focus, is the debate
over the health benefits versus risks of male
circumcision.5–9 I will say a little more about
this debate in a subsequent footnote.
Correspondence to Brian D Earp, Uehiro Centre for
Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, Oxford OX1 1PT,
UK; brian.earp@gmail.com
mere disagreement is not the same as
polarisation. Instead, the latter can (only?)
be said to happen when researchers
POLARISATION AS A CONFLICT OF
INTEREST
Ploug and Holm’s suggestion is this: the
polarisation of a scientific community can
generate conflicts of interest for particular
researchers. Specifically:
[T]he threat is that a polarised group
may nourish an interest in advancing the
position and views of the group, and
that this interest may come to be a main
criterion and goal for the choice of
methods, the reporting of findings and
the provision of policy advice. This
interest may well be based on an honest
conviction that one is right and thus not
be in any way morally reprehensible, but
even honestly held convictions can
introduce potential biases in research
and reporting. ( p.356)
(1) begin to self-identify as proponents
of a particular position that needs to be
strongly defended beyond what is supported by the data, and
(2) begin to discount arguments and
data that would normally be taken as
important in a scientific debate. ( p. 356)
But there is something peculiar about
criterion number (1). On the one hand, it
is framed in terms of self-identification: ‘I
see myself as a proponent of a particular
position that needs to be strongly
defended’. That much makes sense—and
there probably isn’t anything wrong with
regarding oneself this way. But on the
other hand, it states that this act of
position-defending must go ‘beyond what
is supported by the data’.
The problem is: who would self-identify
as someone who makes inadequately supported arguments? As it seems to me, if
one realises that one’s arguments are
getting too one-sided (to the point of
being biased), then one would have a hard
time carrying on producing them without
making some suitable adjustment. At least,
one would without losing a degree of academic credibility—and no small measure
of self-respect. This point will become
important later on.
Now, we might chalk this up to
ambiguous phrasing. Perhaps the authors
mean that (in order for polarisation to
be diagnosed) researchers have to selfidentify as ‘proponents of a particular
position’, while the parts about going
‘beyond the data’ and ‘discounting’
important information are what an
objective third-party would attribute to
the researchers (even if it's not what they
would say about themselves). It is difficult to know for sure, based upon the
way the criteria are written.
But whatever the case, I am going to
suggest that this issue of self-identification poses a problem for Ploug and
Holm’s ultimate proposal – ie, for how
to combat polarisation. To see why this
is the case, I shall have to say a little bit
more about what they see as being the
matter with polarisation in the first
place.
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2015 Vol 0 No 0
Note: this is a corrected proof. For the published version, please see J Med Ethics 2015;41:782-784
doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102891, available at http://jme.bmj.com/content/41/9/782
That would be a serious problem.iii As
Ploug and Holm explain, it could ‘threaten
the objectivity of science, and may in turn
bias public debate and political decisionmaking’ ( p.356). Indeed, in many areas of
biomedicine (as well as in other scientific
fields), one often gets the feeling that a particular group of researchers—whether they
are direct collaborators or not—is ultimately more interested in scoring points for
their ‘side’ than in getting to the bottom of
a genuine dispute.
One situation in which this can occur is
when there is a contentious moral or political question hanging in the balance
(although perhaps at some remove), such
that individual studies start to look like so
many chess pieces in an extra-scientific
debate (see generally, eg, refs. 10 and 11).iv
iii
As David Trafimow ( personal correspondence,
4 May 2015) has pointed out, however, ‘Few
researchers are completely objective [and] the
history of science is full of examples where
researchers with considerable—even extreme—
biases made important contributions. [So,]
although [ polarisation] has the potential to
cause harm, it also can confer benefits. [For
example,] researchers with a strong bias may
gain extra motivation to support their point of
view or disconfirm an opposing one, [and] this
[may in turn] lead to more creative ideas
and new insights. Furthermore…polarised
researchers may [ultimately turn out to] be
right. [But] even when they are wrong,
polarised researchers can greatly aid the
progress of science by proposing conundrums
for the other side to attempt to solve’.
iv
This sort of phenomenon can be seen in the
debate over male circumcision (if I may pursue
the example from footnote number ii). Since
circumcision is a religious ritual for some
groups—and one that is at least prima facie
harmful12–14—it might be seen as important
(for some researchers) to show that ‘health
benefits’ can be ascribed to it, since these could
be used to mount a ‘secular’ defense of the
practice.15–18 On the other hand, there are
moral and even human rights objections to
1
Response
Simple career interests can play a role
here too. For example, there may be a
perceived need to save face by defending
one’s own prior work, or that of one’s
friends or ideological allies. There are
many other factors as well. And these can
apply to any contested topic in science or
medicine.
So polarisation may very well contribute to bias in research. How do Ploug and
Holm propose to address it?
A SIMPLE SOLUTION?
Their basic suggestion is that researchers
should self-report polarisation as a ‘conflict of interest’ on the standard forms
they fill out when submitting their papers.
After reflecting on a few diagnostic questions, that is, they might end up writing
something like this (from p.357):
(1) This article reports research in a
polarised field.
(2) The research group I/we belong to
generally believe that the intervention
we have researched should/should not
be introduced in healthcare.
Is this a promising solution to the
problem of polarisation?
SOME DOUBTS
I argue that it is not. Imagine that you are a
researcher with enough self-awareness and
personal integrity to identify yourself as
‘polarised’ on a conflict of interest disclosure form (if in fact that is what you are).
How likely is it, in this scenario, that you
are also the sort of person who would
conduct polarised research—and write up
polarised articles—to begin with? I do not
think it could be very likely.
As I suggested earlier, once one realises
that one is getting dogmatic about pressing a particular viewpoint (so: failing to
engage seriously with the best arguments
from the other side, discounting important information, and so on), one cannot
go on submitting the same sorts of
papers, as though this realisation has had
no force. At least, one cannot if one has
even a modicum of academic integrity—
which is precisely what (self ) disclosure of
potential conflicts of interest requires.
circumcision,19–24 which are quite a bit easier
‘sell’ if one can demonstrate harm.25–27 This
ends up resulting in a strange—and contentious
—cocktail of religion, science and ethics in the
circumcision literature,9 28 29 with extremely
polarised camps making largely incompatible
empirical
claims
and
related
policy
suggestions.30 31
2
A ROLE FOR EDITORS?
So what about shifting the onus to
editors? Ploug and Holm touch on this
issue themselves when they write ‘Journal
editors have important roles to play here’
(p.357). Specifically, ‘[i]f editors are aware
that a field is polarised’, they should
factor this into their editorial process
regarding, for example, ‘choosing referees
or when scrutinising the quality of the
science or the policy recommendations’
(ibid.). But what if an editor is not aware
that a specific field is polarised, in the
sense defined by Ploug and Holm?
As Ploug and Holm point out, there are
‘many cases where [ journal editors] are
not themselves able to identify polarisation because they are in a similar position
to the average user of scientific evidence’
(p.357). This is where they suggest that
author self-reporting could be a helpful (if
admittedly partial) solution. If I am right,
however, and this is not likely to be a feasible strategy, then what alternative is there
for these problematic cases?
I would like to make the following suggestion. Any associate-level (handling)
editor who is charged with making a publication recommendation about a particular manuscript, should know at least
enough about the field in question to
judge whether it is polarised (in the Ploug
and Holm sense) and—if it is—on which
side of the fence the manuscript falls.
They do not need to be experts in
every field. But if they do not know
enough about the relevant subject matter
to assess if something as ‘big picture’ as
polarisation is an issue, then I do not see
how they could be qualified to make the
other sorts of important editorial decisions that are involved in, say, selecting
appropriate peer reviewers for the manuscript, or making an informed recommendation about whether to publish the paper
on the basis of the peer reviews.
Here is what this means in practical
terms. If a journal editor is not sure about
whether a given field (or manuscript)
show signs of being polarised, then she
should probably take the time to do some
background reading in the relevant area
of research. If she cannot, however—or if
she doesn’t have the time, etc—then she
should consider recusing herself from the
review process (for that paper) and
sending it to a different editor who knows
more about the field. Of course, it would
be important to make sure that this alternative editor was not herself a polarized
participant in the same scientific debate.
On the other hand, if the original
editor can assess polarisation—and sees
that the manuscript sits at one extreme
pole—then she can choose from among
the following options:
A. encourage the author(s) to resubmit
the manuscript in a less polarised
form (ie, by taking more seriously the
best arguments and data from the
other side and responding to them in
a charitable fashion),
B. invite a commentary or response paper
( prior to publication) from a respectable researcher on the ‘other side’,
C. publish the paper as it is, but with an
editorial statement alerting the reader
to the polarised nature of the research
and/or its author(s) (perhaps with a
list of references to credible opposing
arguments) or
D. some combination of the above.
These kinds of measures, in my view,
would have a decent chance of mitigating
some of the bias that may come with
polarisation, without relying on individual
researchers to self-characterise as making
polarised arguments.
CONCLUSION
In conclusion, it should not be the responsibility of authors to ‘out’ themselves (on a
conflict of interest disclosure form) as
being polarised: ie, as making inadequately
supported arguments. After all, anyone
with the integrity to do this would not be
making such arguments in the first place!
Instead, journal editors who are directly
handling manuscripts (ie, at the associate
level) should make sure that they know at
least enough about the relevant field of
research to judge whether it is polarised—
and then take steps (along the lines I have
suggested) to mitigate any associated biases
or conflicts of interest.
Acknowledgements Thanks are due to Julian
Savulescu and David Trafimow for feedback on an
earlier draft of this commentary.
Competing interests None declared.
Provenance and peer review Not commissioned;
internally peer reviewed.
To cite Earp BD. J Med Ethics Published Online First:
[ please include Day Month Year] doi:10.1136/
medethics-2015-102891
Received 7 May 2015
Accepted 25 May 2015
J Med Ethics 2015;0:1–3.
doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102891
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2015 Vol 0 No 0
Response
REFERENCES
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
Ploug T, Holm S. Conflict of interest disclosure and
the polarisation of scientific communities. J Med
Ethics 2015;41:356–8.
Earp BD. How can journal editors fight bias in
polarized scientific communities? J Med Ethics Blog
2015a.
Earp BD, Wudarczyk OA, Sandberg A, et al. If I could
just stop loving you: anti-love biotechnology and the
ethics of a chemical breakup. Am J Bioeth 2013;13
(11):3–17.
Earp BD, Sandberg A, Kahane G, et al. When is
diminishment a form of enhancement? Rethinking
the enhancement debate in biomedical ethics. Front
Syst Neurosci 2014;8(12):1–8.
Earp BD. The ethics of infant male circumcision.
J Med Ethics 2013;39(7):418–20.
Earp BD. Sex and circumcision. Am J Bioeth 2015;15
(2):43–5.
Earp BD. Do the benefits of male circumcision
outweigh the risks? A critique of the proposed CDC
guidelines. Front Pediatr 2015;3(18):1–6.
Earp BD, Darby R. Tradition vs. individual rights: the
current debate on circumcision. The Conversation 2
November 2012. https://theconversation.com/tradition-vsindividual-rights-the-current-debate-on-circumcision10199
Earp BD, Darby R. Does science support infant
circumcision? The Skeptic 2015;25:23–30.
Betz G. In defence of the value free ideal. Eur J
Philos Sci 2013;3(2):207–20.
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2015 Vol 0 No 0
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
Longino H. Beyond “bad science”: skeptical
reflections on the value-freedom of scientific inquiry.
Sci Technol Hum Values 1983;8(1):7–17.
Dworkin G. Cutting edge bioethics. 3 Quarks Daily
23 September 2013. http://www.3quarksdaily.com/
3quarksdaily/2013/09/cutting-edge-bioethics.html
Merkel R, Putzke H. After Cologne: male circumcision
and the law. Parental right, religious liberty or
criminal assault? J Med Ethics 2013;39(7):444–9.
Sarajlic E. Can culture justify infant circumcision?
Res Publica 2014;20(4):327–43.
Goldman R. Circumcision policy: a psychosocial
perspective. Pediatr Child Health 2004;9(9):630–3.
Darby R. The riddle of the sands: circumcision, history,
and myth. N Z Med J 2005;118(1218):U1564.
Darby R, Svoboda JS. A rose by any other name?
Rethinking the similarities and differences between
male and female genital cutting. Med Anthropol Q
2007;21(3):301–23.
Fox M, Thomson M. A covenant with the status
quo? Male circumcision and the new BMA guidance
to doctors. J Med Ethics 2005;31(8):463–9.
DeLaet DL. Framing male circumcision as a human
rights issue? Contributions to the debate over the
universality of human rights. J Hum Rights 2009;8
(4):405–26.
Svoboda JS. Circumcision of male infants as a human
rights violation. J Med Ethics 2013;39(7):469–74.
Ungar-Sargon E. On the impermissibility of infant
male circumcision: a response to Mazor (2013).
J Med Ethics 2015;41(2):186–90.
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
Darby R. The child’s right to an open future: is the
principle applicable to non-therapeutic circumcision?
J Med Ethics 2013;39(7):463–8.
Darby R. Risks, benefits, complications and harms:
neglected factors in the current debate on nontherapeutic circumcision. Kennedy Inst Ethics J
2015;25(1):1–34.
Royal Dutch Medical Association. Non-therapeutic
circumcision of male minors. Amsterdam: KNMG,
2010.
Hammond T. A preliminary poll of men circumcised in
infancy or childhood. BJU Int 1999;83(Suppl 1):85–92.
Boyle GJ, Goldman R, Svoboda JS, et al. Male
circumcision: pain, trauma and psychosexual
sequelae. J Health Psychol 2002;7(3):329–43.
Sorrells ML, Snyder JL, Reiss MD, et al. Fine-touch
pressure thresholds in the adult penis. BJU Int
2007;99(4):864–9.
Bell K. Genital cutting and Western discourses on
sexuality. Med Anthropol Q 2005;19(2):125–48.
Carpenter LM. On remedicalisation: male
circumcision in the United States and Great Britain.
Sociol Health Illn 2010;32(4):613–30.
Bell K. HIV prevention: Making male circumcision the
‘right’ tool for the job. Glob Public Health 2015;10
(5–6):552–72.
Collier R. Ugly, messy and nasty debate surrounds
circumcision. CMAJ 2012;184(1):E25–6.
3