Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
10 pages
1 file
AI-generated Abstract
This paper explores the concepts of identity and individuation through the lens of Thomism, particularly drawing on the insights of Thomas Aquinas. It provides an analysis of identity as sameness across time and context, emphasizing the significance of substances and their independence from accidents. The discussion mainly focuses on individuation, which raises questions about what constitutes an individual entity distinct from others, while also addressing the unity of identity over time.
Metaphysica, 2007
The distinctions between A-series and B-series, between synchronic and diachronic identity and between perdurance and endurance are basic in the philosophy of time; yet they are flawed. McTaggart’s claim that the B-series is static and that a series has to be changing to be really temporal arises from a misunderstanding of temporal relations and of the task of ontological analysis. The dynamic appearance of the A-series results from the incompleteness of the analysis. “Synchronic identity” is synonymous with “strict identity”, which has nothing to do with simultaneity. “Diachronic Identity” is another designation for persistence of an ordinary thing through time and change. Now, strict self-identity holds independently of whether a thing has a short or a long duration. Hence, diachronic identity is synchronic identity. Lewis’ distinguishes two kinds of ontological analyses of persistence, the perdurance and the endurance analysis. This dichotomy is in several respects not exhaustive. Above all, his definition of “persist” is inadequate being based on the notion of multiple temporal localisation which is apt with interrupted but misplaced with persistent, i.e., temporally continuous objects.
2006
It is nearly impossible to produce an adequate historical balance of the various contemporary interpretations of the metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas. The article pays special attention to the numerous studies recently published concerning the Thomistic doctrines of being, personal being, participation, and the metaphysical concept of creation.
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 1983
XT is not without reason, though I would argue that it is without argument, that various philosophers have been driven to advocate mereological essentialism and concomitantly to reject the view that physical objects persist, in any ordinary sense, through changes in their parts. Mereolog ical essentialism, roughly the view that the parts of a physical object are essential to it, stands in radical contrast to what we might call the Ordinary View, roughly that physical objects can, and do, undergo mereological change.^ Even brief reflection on a typical persistence problem, that of the Ship of Theseus for exam ple, is often sufficient to persuade us that the Ordinary View may be misguided or, worse yet, based on a mere illusion, no matter how well-established. Rendered vulnerable by challenges to the Ordinary View, a view Wiggins calls a "datum so fundamental and so deeply entrenched" [7], we may fall prey to mereological essentialism. Even Chisholm, the most enthusiastic and articulate of its recent proponents, is willing to concede that it is a doctrine we entertain in defeat rather than in victory. Nevertheless, the advocate of mereological essentialism is hardly in an enviable position: we must be persuaded not only that he can solve the puzzles raised by problems like that of the Ship of Theseus, but also that whatever he offers as a substitute for a theory of persistence is ultimately accountable to the "fundamental datum" to which Wiggins refers. The theory formulated by Chisholm in Person and Object [3] seems to me to fail on each of these scores. It is not, however, the purpose of this paper to explain why I think so. Rather, I intend to give the Ordinary View one last run. There are important reasons for doing so: (i) our doubts about persistence typically arise from consideration of "problem cases". As a result, there is a tendency to ignore what the Ordinary View amounts to in ordinary cases. Without a clear handle on the ordinary cases, it is hard to determine precisely what causes the difficulties in the problem cases; (ii) Given that we aren't clear as to what causes the difficulties in the problem cases, it is a fortiori difficult to assess the extent to which alternative accounts (e.g., mereological essentialism) dispense with them; (iii) If the Ordinary View is indeed lifeless, it deserves a proper burial. Common sense rests comfortably on the bottom line. If we are to abandon it, it should be by reason of argument
Philosophy of Thomism, 2023
The revival of Thomism is a controversial issue. Those who love knowledge, on the one hand, will argue for its revival (Rickaby, 1908; Weisheipl, 1968). This is particularly true for Christians, theologians, and students of religion. On the other hand, those who do not believe in God, or atheists, including philosophers who argue against metaphysics or the existence of God, are happy for Thomism’s demise (Brosnan, 1924; Houdmann, 2023a). Yet, a third group of thinkers might be interested in the revival of Thomism to pursue philosophical ideals and know the world (Houdmann, 2023b).
dialectica, 2023
Thomas Aquinas embraces a controversial claim about the way in which parts of a substance depend on the substance’s substantial form. On his metaphysics, a ‘substantial form’ is not merely a relation among already existing things, in virtue of which (for example) the arrangement or configuration of those things would count as a substance. The substantial form is rather responsible for the identity or nature of the parts of the substance such a form constitutes. Aquinas’ controversial claim can be roughly put as the view that things are members of their kind in virtue of their substantial form. To put it simply, Aquinas’ claim results in the implication that, every time the xs come to compose a y, those xs have to undergo a change in kind membership. This has been called the “homonymy principle,” and it follows from Aquinas’ view of substantial forms, and specifically from the position that substantial forms inform prime matter, rather than substance-parts. The aim of this paper will be to defend that the Thomistic claim that substantial forms account for the determinate actuality of every part of a substance is plausible and coherent. After defending the Thomistic account, I propose that approaching problems of material composition as a Thomist has a significant, oft-overlooked advantage of involving a thorough-going naturalistic methodology that resolves such problems by appeal to empirical considerations.
The Thomist, 2021
“Thomism” may designate the thought or perhaps the system of Aquinas. In this sense, Thomism can be neither more nor less perfect than the thought of its originator; only Aquinas is the ideal Thomist, and the best we can do is internalize his lessons and defend them as the need of the hour suggests. Alternatively, “Thomism” can name a set of positions on recognized questions. These positions can be identified in retrospect. But retrospect does not settle the present, the possibility of a living Thomism, open to dialectical purification and development in relation to new questions. Here, I take up the question of a living Thomism, but what I have to say is germane, I believe, to larger questions about the development and authority of theological traditions.
2006
This book expands the discourse in contemporary debate on Analytical Thomism. It explores crucial philosophical, theological and ethical issues such as: metaphysics and epistemology, the nature of God, personhood, action and meta-ethics. All those interested in the thought of St Thomas Aquinas, and more generally contemporary Catholic scholarship, problems in philosophy of religion, and contemporary metaphysics, will find this collection an invaluable resource.
2022
Thomistic metaphysics has been challenged on the grounds that its principles are inconsistent with our experiences of divine action and of our own subjectivity. Challenges of this sort have been raised by Eastern Christian thinkers in the school of Gregory Palamas and by contemporary Personalists; they propose alternative metaphysics to explain these experiences. Against these objections and against those Thomists who hold that Thomas Aquinas’ claims exclude Byzantine and Personalist metaphysics, I argue that Thomas’ metaphysical principles already have “flexibility” built into them, such that they can accommodate ways that reality is given in experience, which Thomas did not consider. I argue for this claim using the work of Byzantine and Personalist Thomists, and especially of Jacques Maritain, who outlines several ways in which Thomistic metaphysical principles can be expanded to explain experiences that he did not consider.
Revista do NUPEM, 2019
IOSR Journal Of Humanities And Social Science (IOSR-JHSS), 2024
JAMA: The Journal of the American Medical Association, 1993
2024
Innovative publication, 2016
Photon: Jurnal Sain dan Kesehatan
Addaiyan Journal of Arts, Humanities and Social Sciences , 2021
Proceedings of the Institution of Civil Engineers - Engineering Sustainability, 2019
Proceedings of the conference ‘Merde Alors! - An interdisciplinary conference on excrement, past, present, and future, 2024
Telemedicine and e-Health, 2009
Biology of Blood and Marrow Transplantation, 2019
Gyroscopy and Navigation, 2017
Veterinary Research, 2011
The Electronic Journal of Combinatorics, 2001