This is a post peer-review, pre-copy-editing author’s version of a paper now published as
Walker MJ, Franklin J. 2018. An argument against drug testing welfare recipients. Kennedy
Institute of Ethics Journal 28(3): 309-360. Available at: https://muse.jhu.edu/article/707066.
AN ARGUMENT AGAINST DRUG TESTING WELFARE RECIPIENTS
Mary Jean Walker and James Franklin
Abstract: Programs of drug testing welfare recipients are increasingly common in
US states and have been considered elsewhere. Though often intensely debated,
such programs are complicated to evaluate because their aims are ambiguous –
aims like saving money may be in tension with aims like referring people to
treatment. We assess such programs using a proportionality approach, which
requires that for ethical acceptability a practice must be: reasonably likely to meet
its aims, sufficiently important in purpose as to outweigh harms incurred, and lower
in costs than feasible alternatives. In the light of empirical findings, we argue that
the programs fail the three requirements. Pursuing recreational drug users is not
important in the light of costs incurred, while dependent users who may require
referral are usually identifiable without testing and typically need a broader
approach than one focussing on drugs. Drug testing of welfare recipients is
therefore not ethically acceptable policy.
Programs of drug testing welfare recipients have been introduced in a number of states of
the USA and in New Zealand. The practice has also been proposed but not implemented in
Canada and the United Kingdom (Wincup 2014). Recently, legislation was prepared to introduce
1
drug testing of welfare recipients in Australia, and more US states have drafted legislation.
Stated aims of these programs include: to identify people with drug problems in order to refer
them to treatment, with the longer-term aim of facilitating their gaining employment; to prevent
welfare payments being spent on illicit substances; and protecting the children of people
dependent on drugs (see, e.g., Bolen 2014, 86; Schaberg 2012, 575). But these different aims
imply quite different responses to drug test results, and ambiguity surrounding what these
programs aim to do complicates attempts to evaluate their success.
In this paper, we argue that programs of drug testing welfare recipients1 are not ethically
acceptable. We approach assessing the programs’ ethical acceptability as a question of
proportionality. This is an appropriate approach because drug testing imposes some costs and
burdens on welfare recipients, for the purpose of achieving aims thought to outweigh those costs
and burdens. Thus, their ethical acceptability relies on an assessment of the worth of their aims,
considered in relation to the costs and burdens. 2 Since the proportionality analysis allows an
ethical assessment that does not rely on any particular position about welfare rights or
government paternalism, this approach may have a broader appeal than ethical assessments made
from such positions (though it may also be consistent with some such assessments).
We first briefly overview information on existing programs, in section 1. In section 2 we
explain our approach to evaluating the ethical acceptability of these programs. The approach
implies that for ethical acceptability, a program of drug testing must meet three criteria: that the
program can plausibly be expected to meet its aim(s); that its aim(s) are sufficiently important to
justify its costs and burdens; and that it is not substantially more costly and burdensome than
feasible alternatives. This implies the need to further clarify what the aims of drug testing
welfare recipients are, undertaken in section 3; and to examine empirical studies relevant to
2
whether programs will meet the three criteria, undertaken in section 4. Drawing on this, in
section 5, we examine whether programs of drug testing can meet the three criteria in relation to
any of its possible aims. We argue that it cannot, and conclude that it is not ethically acceptable
policy.
1. EXISTING PROGRAMS OF DRUG TESTING WELFARE RECIPIENTS
In the USA, the federal Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act
1996 (PRWORA) granted states authority to drug test welfare recipients. In 1999, a pilot program
of drug testing was introduced in Michigan. This program was terminated following a legal
challenge on the basis that it “violated constitutional protections against unreasonable searches”,
as was a program in Florida a decade later (NCSL 2017).3 Despite this, drug testing of some
welfare recipients is increasingly becoming the norm. As of early 2017, 17 US states had drafted
and 15 states had passed legislation for a drug testing program (NCSL 2017).
Details of how the programs work differ considerably by state. Most relate to recipients of
the Temporary Assistance for Needy Families (TANF) payment, which provides cash assistance,
and programs promoting preparation for work, to low-income families. Some states have
introduced legislation to test recipients of other assistance programs such as the Supplemental
Nutrition Assistance Program (SNAP) or Medicaid (NCSL 2017).4 Some test new applicants,
others test recipients on an ongoing basis. In most states, applicants or recipients are first
screened for potential drug problems using a psychological assessment tool or questionnaire, and
only those indicated as likely to be drug dependent are tested. This process circumvents legal
challenges based on drug testing constituting a suspicionless search proscribed by the Fourth
Amendment (NCSL 2017). In some locations, people testing positive or refusing a test are
3
excluded from benefits; in others, benefits may be retained on condition of attending drug
treatment, or (for payments intended for the support of dependent children) benefits may be paid
to an alternative adult (Hall 2016). There are also various procedural differences, such as in how
programs guard against the possibility of false positives (DHHS 2011, 6).
Data collection and evaluation of the programs appears to be relatively scant, and
differences between the programs complicate drawing general conclusions. In a pilot program
run in Florida during 1999-2000, among 6,462 applicants, 1,447 or 22.4% were indicated by a
psychological assessment tool to have a drug dependence problem. Of the 1,447 referred for
urinalysis, 335 or 5.1% of the total screened population tested positive (Crew and Davis 2003).
Testing was in most cases undertaken immediately after the application was made, but
occasionally was done on the following day (Crew and Davis 2003, 42). Hall (2016, 2 of 7)
reports positive test rates within a range of 3.2% to 16.9% among those referred to a test
following screening. Hall’s data shows that the percentage testing positive of the total population
screened in 9 states was 0.19%; if refused tests (where reported) are treated as positives, the rate
is 0.57% (Hall 2016, appendix D). The cost per positive test varies considerably, from $200 in
Tennessee to $7,006 in Missouri (Hall 2016, 2 of 7).
The program in New Zealand is quite different, and could be considered a method of
subsidizing employer costs for pre-employment drug testing rather than a program of drug
testing welfare recipients. Since 2013, people receiving some welfare payments must undertake a
drug test where this is a requirement of a potential employer or trainer. 5 Though employers
usually pay for pre-employment testing in New Zealand, the reforms enable employers to invoice
the state for the cost of a positive test. New Zealand’s Ministry of Social Development passes
this cost on to the welfare recipient, and may impose a sanction. The sanction does not
4
automatically remove welfare payments, but is part of New Zealand’s system of graduated
sanctions (Wincup 2014; New Zealand Ministry of Social Development 2016).
Some data have been released in response to Freedom of Information requests. In 2015,
there were just under 32,000 referrals of job seekers to employers who required a preemployment drug test. In this time, 55 sanctions were imposed in areas which were reported on
(some areas where numbers were low were omitted to protect privacy), and less than 5 people
had their benefits cancelled or suspended. From September 2013 to September 2016, there were
466 drug test-related obligation failures, including test refusals as well as positive tests (New
Zealand Ministry of Social Development 2016).
2. ETHICAL ASSESSMENT OF DRUG TESTING WELFARE RECIPIENTS
We will assess the ethical acceptability of programs of drug testing welfare recipients using
a ‘proportionality’ approach. The approach is suitable for analysing policies which impose costs
or burdens in order to achieve some valued aim. This approach involves assessing whether drug
testing programs:
1) Are reasonably likely to meet their aim(s);
2) Impose costs/burdens that are not out of proportion to the importance of their aim(s);
and
3) Do not impose substantially more costs/burdens than feasible alternatives.
The criteria are similar to some of those used to assess the justness of wars, analogous to
principles of a reasonable chance of success, proportionality, and necessity (e.g., Walzer 1977).
5
Similar criteria are used in the jurisprudence of a number of countries and in international law, as
a tool for assessing laws that involve rights infringements (e.g., Cianciardo 2010). Similar
principles have also been proposed as useful in assessing the ethical acceptability of public
health measures (Childress et al 2002; Kass 2001) and in ethical decision-making in healthcare
generally (Hermerin 2012).
While we shall not attempt an in-depth justification of this approach, it is worth some brief
comments. The three criteria can be justified quite intuitively: a policy intervention cannot be
justified on the basis of its aims if those aims are not empirically linked to the policy; if it
imposes costs and burdens out of proportion to the importance of its aims; or if the aims could be
met in another way that involves fewer costs or burdens. This approach might appear
consequentialist, since it involves comparison of outcomes with and without the programs, in
terms of their costs and benefits. However, as Rodin (2011) has argued, proportionality
assessments incorporate both consequentialist and deontological thinking. Rodin notes that harm
can be justified either when someone has made themselves liable to being harmed (e.g., by
committing an unjust attack), or when the harm is a lesser evil (i.e., the harm prevents a greater
harm occurring). Similarly, the imposition of a rights infringement (whether or not this counts as
a ‘harm’) could be justified because the person on whom it is imposed is liable to it, or because it
will lead to the best overall consequences. In the former, we draw on deontological intuitions,
involving normative assessment of the liable person; in the latter, we draw on consequentialist
thinking and compare outcomes.
Rodin argues that judgements that someone is liable to harm – that it is justifiable to regard
their rights to be suspended in a localized way – relate to judgements of proportionality, because
liability is from the start assessed in relation to some good to be achieved by the harm (2011, 77).
6
For example, by threatening violence in the form of a punch, an aggressor might make
themselves liable to force that would prevent the threatened punch, but is not thereby liable to
force of any kind and degree. That is, the judgement as to whether someone is liable or not
already involves a judgement about proportionality, because the person can only be liable to a
harm that is proportionate (2011, 79). In the case of drug testing, analogically, we could consider
the general right not to be drug tested to be suspended, either because some feature of being a
welfare recipient makes people liable to bearing this rights infringement, or because imposing
the rights infringement leads to better outcomes overall than not imposing it. But at base, these
two approaches are linked. On the one hand, assessment of whether welfare recipients are liable
to accept drug testing must take into account the degree of seriousness of the rights infringement
in relation to the purpose it serves. This involves judging how valuable the aim is – and this
could derive from various ethical views including non-consequentialist theories. On the other
hand, the weighing of outcomes would include, among various other factors, the rights
infringement itself on the ‘cost’ side of the equation. Here again, the weighing would require an
assessment of how important the aim is (2011, 97).
We recognize that there are other kinds of ethical argument against drug testing welfare
recipients, for instance, those deriving from particular positions on welfare rights, government
paternalism, or considerations about ethics of drug use (Perez-Munoz 2017). But any such
argument is likely to be highly controversial, and its acceptance may rely on underlying
normative commitments or political preferences notwithstanding its philosophical rigour. Our
approach does not rely on premises about these matters, and as such, we hope, may have a
broader appeal.
The proportionality approach implies a structure for our assessment in the remainder of the
7
paper. First, we need to understand what the aims of drug testing welfare recipients are (section
3). Second, we need to consider whether the programs are likely to meet these aims, what costs
and benefits they are likely to result in, and whether there are other, less costly, methods of
meeting the aims (section 4). We can then apply this to assessing whether the programs meet our
three criteria (section 5).
3. AIMS OF DRUG TESTING PROGRAMS
In subsection 3.1 we examine aims that have been stated in media statements, legal debate,
and policy documents. We analyse these suggestions to show there are (at least) five proposed
final aims of drug testing, served by two intermediary aims, which drug testing might achieve via
different mechanisms. Some of the aims might, however, also be undermined by the alternative
aim or the mechanism used to achieve it. In subsection 3.2, we consider the suggestion of various
commentators that drug testing welfare recipients serves unstated or implicit aims related to
social biases, broader policy agendas, and/or political expediency.
3.1. Stated Aims
Media statements indicate several aims of drug testing programs: preventing welfare
payments being spent on illicit drugs, protecting the children of drug-using welfare recipients,
helping drug-dependent people on welfare, deterring drug use, and reducing government
spending. For example, explaining his support of a bill to drug test welfare recipients in
Alabama, one representative stated, “I don’t think it’s right for taxpayers to have to fund
somebody’s drug habit” (cited in Chandler 2014). A representative from Michigan explained his
support of a drug testing bill by saying, “[w]e have children that are starving in this state because
8
moms, dads or both are on methamphetamines or cocaine or some other horrible substance, and
they sell their bridge cards instead of feeding their children” (cited in Oosting 2014). An
Australian minister stated of the recently-planned trial that its aim was to help people overcome
drug problems and obtain work, rather than leaving them “at risk of a cycle of welfare
dependency" (cited in AAP 2017). In New Zealand, following news reports that during the first
six months of the program, only 22 out of 8001 tests were positive, government officials stated
that this showed the program was successfully deterring drug use (Fisher 2014). A news story
reporting that in Utah, only 262 of 30,000 tests during 2012-13 were either positive or refused,
and the total program cost was $350,000, quoted officials as saying this represented a good
investment, as denial of payments to 262 people would have amounted to more than the program
cost over time (Price 2013).
The aims of drug testing programs have also been discussed in relation to legal cases
surrounding several of the US programs. The Fourth Amendment requires that searches be
justified by reasonable suspicion of illegal activity, or serving a special need of the government.
Drug tests are legally recognized as searches, and while most programs now aim to meet the
requirement of ‘reasonable suspicion’, there has been debate about what ‘special needs’ they
could serve. In relation to the early program in Michigan, Courts considered government needs
to protect children from child abuse and neglect, and to ensure that public funds are not used to
buy illicit drugs (Schaberg 2012, 575). McLaughlin (2013, 581) suggests three special needs:
“promoting self-sufficiency, ensuring public funds are used for their intended purpose, and
protecting children in homes with drug addicted parents”. ‘Promoting self-sufficiency’ is
explained as helping people to stop using drugs in order to find work (2013, 581-2). Widelitz
(2011, 299-300) proposes the policy could serve five special needs: combating drug use among
9
people receiving welfare; protecting children in families receiving welfare; removing drug use as
a barrier to work; preventing children in families receiving welfare from developing future drug
problems; and public safety. The latter is explained by noting that drug use is statistically linked
to crime (2011, 305).
Similarly, the explanatory memorandum to the proposed Australian legislation stated two
aims of the testing. First was improving “a recipient’s capacity to find employment or participate
in education or training by identifying people with drug use issues and assisting them to
undertake treatment” (Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia 2017, 67). Second was to
“maintain the integrity of, and public confidence in, the social security system by ensuring that
taxpayer funded welfare payments are not being used to purchase drugs or support substance
abuse” (2017, 156).
Of course, a policy’s having more than one aim is not a drawback; it may be a positive. But
consideration of exactly how drug testing could bring about the various aims reveals some
underlying tensions. Notice that different aims imply two different responses to a positive drug
test result. The aim of reducing government spending indicates excluding people from payments
upon a positive or refused test, and contraindicates referral to treatment, which would increase
costs. The aim of improving employment outcomes would indicate referral to treatment as most
appropriate.6 The aim of ensuring welfare payments are not spent on drugs could be met by
removing payments, or by reducing drug use itself. Drug testing could lead to reduced drug use
either by referring those testing positive to treatment, or by deterrence (which could be an effect
of testing itself, or an effect of a threat of exclusion from benefits). The aim of reducing public
safety risks linked to drug-related crime might, again, be achieved by reducing drug use, while
exclusion from payments could increase crime, as people seek income from other sources. This
10
indicates the response of treatment referral (though the threat of a test or of exclusion upon a
positive test might, again, reduce use via deterrence). If the aim is to protect children, this might
be achieved by reducing use (again via treatment referral or deterrence), while exclusion from
benefits seems more likely to harm children.
The various possible causal links indicated between drug testing and its aims are mapped
in Figure 1. The diagram involves simplifications (e.g., we represent drug testing itself as a
deterrent but omit the deterrent effect of the knowledge that a positive test could lead to
exclusion from benefits; deterring people from claiming benefits might also impact on several of
the aims; some of the final aims might causally impact on each other; and so on). However, any
attempt at policy analysis of this kind must involve some such simplifications. The aim of
‘excluding drug users from benefits’ is also somewhat artificial as it is not typically explicitly
stated as an aim, but is an inferred intermediary aim serving the further stated aims.
Fig 1. Pathways for proposed effects of drug testing welfare recipients
This indicates that there are two ‘intermediary’ aims, of reducing drug use amongst welfare
recipients, and of excluding those using drugs from this population, and two mechanisms by
11
which drug tests could achieve the former aim. All but one of the five possible final aims could
be met by reducing drug use, while two could be met by payment exclusion.
3.2. Possible Unstated Aims
It has also been suggested that drug testing programs are actually motivated by negative
feelings about or moral disapproval of welfare beneficiaries, the poor, drug users, and/or
members of some races. For instance, media commentators have stated that drug testing is a way
to punish welfare recipients, that it reflects attitudes related to the stigmatisation of welfare
recipients, and that it relates to constructing poverty and/or drug use as individual rather than
societal problems (e.g., Forsyth and Banham 2017; Pollack 2013).
Welfare recipients have long been the subject of various stereotypes, including being likely
to use or abuse drugs. Evidence indicates that this stereotype is unwarranted: estimates of drug
use among welfare recipients range from 4 to 37%, but overall, drug use prevalence is likely to
be only several percentage points higher in the unemployed population than among the general
population (DHHS 2011, 2). Despite this, there is a widespread belief that drug use is much
higher among welfare recipients (Amundsen et al 2015, 446). US Policy discourse surrounding
drug testing programs often presents welfare recipients as not only generally drug-users, but also
as unworthy, and unemployed due to personal failings (including lack of moral principles) or by
choice (Amundsen et al 2015, 448; Amundsen et al 2014, 15). Drug testing may thus be
construed as having a punitive aim towards this stigmatized group.
In addition, drug testing welfare recipients is part of a broader trend towards welfare
conditionality, occurring in many countries over the last quarter-century. In the USA, this
coincided with moves toward harsher criminal sentencing, and harsh criminal justice policies can
12
also be seen to affect welfare policy. For instance, PRWORA bars those with drug felony
convictions from many kinds of welfare entirely, though states may opt out of this eligibility
rule. US drug testing programs can thus be interpreted as another extension of harsh criminal
justice policy into welfare systems (Amundsen et al 2015, 447), penalising not only drug users
but the entire welfare recipient population (Amundsen et al 2014, 23).
Further, drug testing of welfare recipients can be argued to have political motivations. As
with other anti-drug action, it has the effect of linking drug use to a marginalized group with low
electoral power (Amundsen et al 2015, 443-4). This has been raised in particular with regard to
US programs, where stereotyping of welfare recipients intersects with racial stereotyping, such
that welfare recipients are stereotypically Black people (Amundsen 2015, 445; Alexander 2010,
47-8). Indeed, Ledford (2016) shows that drug testing of welfare recipients is more likely to be
adopted in states where there is a higher proportion of Black people on TANF, and where there
are higher levels of ‘symbolic racism’ (a combination of negative affect towards a group and
beliefs that they violate certain cherished values, measured using survey data on social attitudes).
Ledford suggests that discrimination against Black people may be more fundamental to the
introduction of drug testing programs in the US than discrimination against welfare recipients in
general. In concert with various other policies (such as barring convicted felons from voting),
drug testing could be interpreted as not only reflecting racial biases, but as part of a widespread
effort to reinforce inequalities and social oppression, particularly of Black people, while
maintaining a veneer of ‘colour-blindness’ (Alexander 2010, 52). In this context, some suggest
that drug testing of welfare recipients has unstated and perhaps implicit aims, of punishing
welfare seeking, reducing access to government support in general, or more generally of
reinforcing current social inequities. (On the part of politicians proposing drug testing programs,
13
there could also be an aim of appealing to an attitude of approval of harsh treatment of welfare
recipients among the general public.)
Notice that if the aim of drug testing welfare recipients is understood in this way, the
policy would automatically fail on the proportionality approach. As explained above, the
proportionality approach is useful for evaluating policies that introduce costs or burdens for the
sake of some valued aim. But these unstated aims are ones that, even if they are valued by some,
are themselves unethical and should not be valued; or (we might say in an objectivist mood) are
valued but not valuable. If it is true that the aims of drug testing programs are actually unethical,
then drug testing cannot be an ethical policy, let alone do any work in justifying the harms or
costs its achievement involves. 7 Further possibilities are that some proponents of drug testing
programs are motivated by these unstated aims, while others genuinely believe the stated aims;
or that, though the programs are motivated in ways that are ethically suspect, they might still
meet their stated aims. In these cases – assuming the stated aims have some value – it is not clear
what the moral relevance of the motives behind a policy (as distinct from stated policy aims)
should be. At the very least, we would need the achievement of the stated aims to do the work of
justifying or compensating for not only the harms and costs of the programs, but also for
introducing a policy on the basis of unethical motives (raising further difficult questions about
whether anything could ‘compensate’ for such motives, which may be assessed differently on
different normative theories).
That is, if drug testing programs meet (at least some of) their stated aims in a way that
meets the criteria of the proportionality approach, we would need to assess whether these
unstated aims are playing a role, and how the ethically problematic status of these aims affects
the overall ethical acceptability of the policy. Thus, in order to have any chance of being
14
ethically acceptable policies, drug testing must meet some of its ethically acceptable, valued
aims – to do the work of justifying not only the costs and burdens imposed in introducing them,
but also of outweighing or silencing ethical concerns about such motivations. Since we will
argue that drug testing welfare recipients cannot meet their stated aims in a way that satisfies the
proportionality approach, however, this further question will not be dealt with here. 8 As such, we
will not discuss the unstated aims further below as aims of drug testing programs. We do of
course recognise that drug testing welfare recipients may in fact have such results as greater
burdens on welfare recipients that are experienced as punishments, reduced access to
government support, and the reinforcement of oppressive, often racist, norms, inequities, and
stereotypes. There is empirical evidence for some of these claims, though some are not easy to
measure, which is discussed below. These important issues are thus recognised in the
proportionality analysis, although we will treat them as costs or negatives of the policies, rather
than as aims that might help justify their other costs. We are therefore treating them as
unintentional consequences, whether or not this is always true, and we take this to be a way of
applying a principle of charity to the arguments provided for drug testing programs. It is possible
after all that, even if some proponents of drug testing programs are motivated by implicit biases,
others genuinely believe they will benefit drug users and their children, or hold a combination of
the ‘stated’ and ‘unstated’ aims. Focusing solely on the unstated aims runs the risk of targeting a
straw man by failing to apply the principle of charity sufficiently.
In the next section we thus turn to empirical evidence on the question of whether drug tests
are likely to meet any of their stated aims, what costs they will impose in the process, and
whether there are other means of achieving these aims.
15
4. EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE
4.1. Is Drug Testing Welfare Recipients Likely to Meet its Aims?
There is relevant empirical evidence available on some of the proposed causal links
represented in Figure 1, and on some of the assumptions that underlie them.
The first proposed causal link is between a drug testing program and a reduction in drug
use. There is no direct evidence available on whether reduced drug use would be achieved via
deterrence. Such evidence would be very difficult to obtain, though there is evidence that
deterrence can be effective in some similar cases, such as random breath testing of drivers (Terer
and Brown 2014). As to drug testing leading to reductions in drug use via treatment referrals, we
must first note that most people who use drugs are not dependent, and therefore not candidates
for treatment (Grant 1996). The outcomes of treating non-dependent people for drug dependence
are not known, though it is hard to see how it could produce desired outcomes.
This raises questions about the assumption that drug testing is a good method to identify
those with drug dependence, insofar as this is the targeted group (as treatment referral practices,
and some of the rationales linking to the final aims imply). Positive drug test results do not
provide information on whether someone is dependent, or uses drugs occasionally or
recreationally – and nor does a negative result establish that someone is not dependent. 9 The
sensitivity and specificity of drug testing for detecting dependence will differ depending on how
a program is run, but some indicative figures are developed by Pollack et al (2002a). This study
used survey data on drug use among welfare recipients in the USA to estimate that
approximately 4% of welfare recipients would be drug dependent, between 11 and 18% would
use drugs recreationally, and 22% would have alcohol use or other psychiatric disorders, but not
use drugs (2002a, 25). These estimates indicate that drug testing could identify as many or even
16
more recreational as dependent drug users (2002a, 30). Thus (even if drug tests could provide
completely accurate results), using drug testing to identify dependence will mean there will be
some ‘false positives’ (non-dependent drug users) and ‘false negatives’ (people who are drug
dependent but test negative).
For the ‘true positives’ (people who test positive who are dependent on drugs), evidence
about drug treatment suggests that it can effectively reduce drug use. There is a great deal of
research on a range of different treatment modalities, which cannot be discussed in detail here.
Reviews note some limitations on effectiveness (comparable with treatments for psychiatric
disorders), and many treatment facilities struggle for adequate resources which may reduce
potential effectiveness (Pollack 2017; Dutra et al 2008). Thus “[v]iewed at the individual level,
relapse and polysubstance use are typical experiences among clients in SUD [substance use
disorder] treatment interventions” (Pollack 2017, 165). Coerced or mandatory treatment might
have different outcomes to voluntary treatment (Werb et al 2015). Nonetheless, the large
evidence base surrounding drug treatment indicates that some reductions in use are likely.
There is some evidence indicating that drug treatment can increase welfare recipients’
likelihood of finding employment, but also some conflicting evidence. One US study found that
recipients who completed drug treatment were twice as likely to be employed two years later
than members of a control group, but no benefits were achieved when the program was scaled up
(Bloom et al 2001, 4-6). Metsch et al (1999, 42) found that amongst women leaving a drug
rehabilitation program in Florida, those who had completed the program were more likely to be
working than those who had not (37 versus 13%) (though such correlations might be best
explained by a common cause – a feature that could make people more likely to complete
treatment and to find work). Analysis of Florida’s pilot drug testing program concluded that
17
neither an indication of dependence on the psychological screening tool, nor testing positive to a
urinalysis, made much difference to the likelihood of employment or earnings (Crew and Davis
2003, 48-52; 2006, 76).
The idea that drug treatment could improve employability is given some credence by the
fact that drug dependence is a recognized factor in the literature on barriers to employment
(Atkinson et al 2001; Taylor and Barusch 2004; Pilkinton 2010). In one study of long-term
welfare recipients, about 20% were indicated by a questionnaire to have possible drug or alcohol
problems (Taylor and Barusch 2004). Nam’s (2005) analysis of welfare exits shows that
substance dependence significantly decreased the likelihood of a welfare recipient finding work.
Of course, a correlation between drug dependence and unemployment leaves open what the
direction of causation is, or whether there is a common cause (such as earlier life trauma).
Other evidence suggests that the causal relationships are complex. Several studies report
that long-term welfare recipients experience multiple barriers to employment. Among
participants in Taylor and Barusch’s study, 35% reported a physical health problem; 23% had
possible learning disabilities; 32% had not finished high school; 31% had a child with a medical
condition, disability, learning disability or mental health condition; up to 57% had clinical levels
of depression; and 36% had missed work due to domestic violence (2004, 180). A study in
Michigan reported that 25% of TANF recipients had major depression, 15% had PTSD, and 7%
had generalized anxiety (in Stromwall, 111; see also Morgenstern 2008; Nam 2005). Further,
those experiencing barriers to employment are likely to experience more than one barrier. In
Taylor and Barusch’s study, 8% of the sample had experienced none of the barriers being
investigated, 13% had one barrier, and 57% had 2-4 barriers (2004, 181). Atkinson et al report
that welfare recipients who use drugs are more likely than those who do not to report various
18
other barriers to employment (2001). Both welfare seeking and drug use are correlated with
poverty, low levels of education, and trauma (Pollack et al 2002b, 261). While drug dependence
may make it more difficult to gain employment, its relationship with employability is likely to be
causally complex, with each of these variables related to various common causes as well as to
each other. This indicates the presence of a group within the population of welfare recipients
whom we class as ‘polydysfunctional’, who experience drug dependence problems, but also a
range of other problems.
In relation to increasing the employability of non-dependent drug users by reducing use,
we have not identified any directly relevant studies. That some proportion of the working
population also uses drugs indicates that drug use is not always a barrier to working. This may
differ depending on the kind of work, and the kind of drug taken. However, if employers
undertake pre-employment drug tests, or otherwise suspect an applicant uses drugs, drug use
might be a barrier to being offered work, if not to undertaking work.
There is conflicting evidence relating to the link between reducing drug use and protecting
children. A correlation has been shown between child maltreatment and drug use, particularly
dependent use (Kepple 2017) – though neither drug use nor dependence necessarily lead to child
maltreatment or even reduced parenting capacity (Kepple 2017; Testa and Smith 2009).
Research into whether parental drug treatment has positive outcomes for children has conflicting
results. Several studies comparing parents in contact with child services receiving and not
receiving drug treatment found no significant differences in terms of later child maltreatment
allegations, and two studies reported an increased probability of later allegations (Testa and
Smith 2009, 155-6). This could reflect inadequacies in the treatment programs themselves. The
prima facie causal link is also challenged by recognizing that the population of drug-dependent
19
parents with children at risk of maltreatment also typically experience a number of other risk
factors for child maltreatment, e.g., low level of education, poverty, domestic violence, and
alcohol dependence (Testa and Smith 2009). They may fall into the polydysfunctional group,
suggesting that drug treatment, even where successful at reducing drug use, could be limited in
its effects for protecting children.
There are well-established correlations between drug use and criminal activity (even
excluding drug use itself as a criminalized activity). A recent review summarizes:
Psychopharmacological properties of certain substances directly increase individual risks
of violent behavior and victimization. […] Illicit drugs are costly, and this is a key driver
of acquisitive crime. (Pollack 2017, 164)
There is also some reason to think that drug use can be a cause of crimes, in the senses that
the intention to use drugs may motivate acquisitive crime to finance drug use, and that
intoxication (with certain drugs such as ice) could make a causal contribution to crime through
heightening recklessness or aggression (Reuter and MacCoun 2001, 21-2). An Australian study
of police detainees found that 19% self-attributed the offence to drugs (excluding alcohol),
primarily for one of these reasons (Payne and Gaffney 2012). There is also evidence that drug
treatment can reduce crime, though limitations on treatment effectiveness noted above apply
(Pollack 2017, 166).
It seems safe to assume without evidence that reduced drug use among welfare recipients
would lead to reduced spending of welfare payments on drugs, and that being excluded from
receiving benefits would also achieve this aim.
Finally, while it might be expected that a drug testing program could save the state money
20
by excluding people testing positive from benefits, in fact the evidence indicates that programs
typically increase government spending overall. Drug testing programs vary considerably in cost,
reflecting variations in how the programs are run. Drug tests themselves differ in cost depending
on the type of test. Programs will also involve delivery costs, such as staff training, staff time
diverted into test administration, and the costs of repeat tests. Where the program is linked to
treatment requirements, states have needed to increase treatment funding.
Carley (2012) estimates that for a program with a 6-month exclusion after a positive test to
save money, between 1.9 and 3.8% of welfare recipients would need to test positive (with the
range reflecting differences in program procedures). This estimate assumes that payments for
child upkeep would also be removed; if those payments were continued, the program would have
“minimal impact” on caseload or savings (Carley 2012, 4). Carley’s estimate also excludes the
costs of increased treatment funding, but notes in its review of other state programs that this is
their major cost. The US Department of Human Services review of drug testing programs reports
that “[n]one of the State cost estimates identified for this paper showed net savings resulting
from proposed drug testing programs” (DHHS 2011, 7).
4.2. Costs of Drug Testing Programs
We have already noted that drug testing welfare recipients is likely to have net financial
costs rather than savings. In addition, there are ethical ‘costs’, including infringing the rights of
welfare recipients, and other potential harms.
As noted above, legal scholars have debated whether and how an infringement of the rights
of welfare recipients can be justified, in terms of the Fourth Amendment’s provisions for
individualized suspicion or a governmental special need (e.g., Perez-Munoz 2017; Bolen 2014;
21
Schaberg 2012; Newell 2012). 10 This approach results from the recognition that the drug test is a
search, and thus involves some infringement on privacy rights.
Part of consideration of the justification of this infringement is its nature and extent. A
drug test could infringe either bodily or informational privacy. With regard to bodily privacy,
different kinds of tests have different levels of intrusiveness. Blood testing, though the gold
standard for detection of drugs or drug metabolites in the body, is highly invasive and generally
not proposed for drug testing programs. Urine tests, where samples are collected with
supervision (which may be judged necessary to prevent sample substitution or manipulation), are
highly invasive; sweat, hair, and oral fluid tests are less so (Pidd and Roche 2011). With regard
to information privacy, drug testing would require disclosure of personal information for some,
such as prescription medications or health status which could interfere with the test.
We shall not attempt to provide a general defence of privacy as a right. We assume for the
purposes of this argument that privacy has some importance, such that measures to protect it
have some ethical weight, but that it can be legitimately infringed upon in some situations and
for some purposes. This is consistent with our aim of providing an argument that does not rely on
potentially contentious normative commitments, and is broadly consistent with current legal
treatment of privacy in liberal democracies. Thus, the privacy infringement will be counted as
one cost of drug testing programs to be considered in assessing whether they can meet the three
criteria, in the following section.
Other than the loss of privacy, the process of drug testing may not impose a particularly
high burden on welfare recipients in its tangible aspects: the time to take a test is not long, and
methods used are not painful. There is evidence that being subjected to a drug test can be
psychologically burdensome: it is experienced as degrading or humiliating (Wincup 2014; Perez-
22
Munoz 2017). Some have argued that it is particularly ethically problematic to impose a
degrading experience on a group whose members are often already disadvantaged (in PerezMunoz 2017, 7). It has also been suggested that punitive measures related to welfare receipt can
reduce people’s confidence and self-efficacy, which might contribute to lowering their
employability (Murphy et al 2011; Perez-Munoz 2017). These effects could occur for the general
population of welfare recipients, i.e., a larger population than those using drugs.
In addition, since the burden of drug testing will be borne by a group that is the most
socioeconomically disadvantaged, it may enhance existing inequalities, such as racial
inequalities. In the US, for example, there is evidence that Black and Hispanic people are more
likely to experience poverty (and a number of its determinants, such as lower levels of
education), and are disproportionately enrolled in welfare schemes (McDaniel 2017, 22). 11
Insofar as drug testing constitutes an additional burden on those tested, it adds to the existing
inequalities that this represents.12
Another set of concerns relates to the effects of welfare exclusion. No studies have been
identified on the effects of removing welfare payments on the basis of a positive drug test.
However, research on welfare sanctions shows that they can increase mental health problems,
economic hardship (measured by utility shutoffs, food insecurity, lack of medical care, and
homelessness or eviction), and the risk of child maltreatment – though they may also increase
compliance and welfare exits (Wu et al 2015, 2-3). Several studies examined effects on drugdependent people who lost their eligibility for benefits after dependence was declassified as a
‘disability’ for the purposes of some US welfare payments. This group reportedly later
experienced worse psychological comorbidities, but no reduction in drug use (in Watkins and
Podus 2000). There was also an increase in arrests (Chatterji and Meara 2010, 239), and “one
23
year postdisenrollment, about half of the recipients reported monthly legal earnings below $500
and received no cash public aid” (in Pollack et al 2002b, 270). There is some evidence that
welfare sanctions can increase risks to children of hospitalisation and food insecurity, but also
that there are potential benefits for children if drug use is actually reduced (DHHS 2011, 8).
Other possible societal costs are an increase in crime, and increased financial pressure on
families and associates, as excluded people seek other sources of income.
Other concerns relate to referring people to treatment in response to a positive test. First,
there is an ethical concern about making welfare receipt conditional on attending drug treatment.
Since people in this situation may lack other options, this can be construed as coerced treatment
and so conflict with a generally recognized right to refuse medical treatment (insofar as drug
dependence treatment counts as ‘medical’). 13 The acceptability of coerced or mandatory drug
treatment (linked for instance to criminal justice procedures) differs greatly by jurisdiction,
however, and is somewhat normalized in some locations. Second, some have worried that drug
testing programs could inflate the population of people in drug treatment beyond those who
really need it. Even among those who use drugs in ways consistent with criteria for dependence,
not everyone needs treatment, and many ‘age out’ of such use (Pollack 2017, 166). Increasing
the treatment population could thus waste resources. In drug treatment programs that are grouprun, it could also alter the nature of the treatment experience for those who could benefit from
treatment, altering the effectiveness for this group.
Finally, some suggest that there are (non-financial) societal costs as drug testing programs
encourage stereotyping of welfare recipients as drug users, and contribute to a public discourse
that is derogatory and disparaging about people on welfare, portraying them as undeserving of
social supports (Amundson et al 2015). As a result, drug testing could contribute to
24
marginalisation and disconnection of unemployed people (Wodak 2017), and damage welfare
recipients’ job prospects (Crew and Davis 2003, 41). The implication that unemployment is
caused by individual rather than systemic factors could also lead to neglecting other barriers to
employment (Berger 2001). Such effects on societal attitudes may have follow-on effects that
exacerbate existing inequities. There are a number of studies showing that amongst welfare
recipients, Black and Hispanic people are more likely than whites to be sanctioned, particularly
where sanctions are applied at the discretion of case workers, demonstrating racial prejudices
(McDaniel 2017, 23-5). Drug testing programs play into and reinforce these harmful prejudices
(Ledford 2016).
4.3. Are There Other Potential Methods of Meeting the Aims?
There are several alternative possibilities for meeting the aims of drug testing programs.
Here we note just a few options by way of example. There are alternative methods for
identifying people with drug dependence problems. Prior to the introduction of drug testing
programs, some US states screened welfare recipients using questionnaires administered by
welfare caseworkers, with those indicated to have a potential problem being referred for
assessment by a professional (Morgenstern 2001). There was some dissatisfaction with such
systems because they resulted in treatment referral rates of around 1-5%, perceived to be much
lower than the rate of welfare recipients with drug problems (Henderson et al 2006, 218).
However, the rates of people testing positive on drug tests are not higher.
Indeed, if the aim is to identify drug dependent rather than recreational users,
psychological screening may be a more accurate measure. The psychological screening tool
utilized as part of some drug testing programs (the Substance Abuse Subtle Screening Inventory
25
or SASSI) has tested, in its most recent form, as having a sensitivity of 93% and specificity of
90% (Lazowski and Geary 2016). 14 This would also improve accuracy in terms of capturing
people dependent on substances that are not tested for (including alcohol, dependence on which
affects more people, and which is also statistically linked to lower levels of income, child
maltreatment, and crime). Though the accuracy of drug testing welfare recipients will depend on
a program is run, it is likely to be much lower than this (Pollack et al 2002a, 28).
Another option is the incorporation of ‘brief interventions’ (BIs) at welfare centres. BIs
involve a range of strategies that can be adapted for use in different settings. BIs utilize
‘motivational interviewing’ techniques, with a focus on encouraging people to regard their
substance use as not worth its costs, and themselves as capable of changing their behavior.
Measures include short, 5-minute advice, intensive counselling sessions, and provision of selfhelp information (Kumar and Malhotra 2000). There is extensive evidence for their effectiveness
and cost-effectiveness for alcohol use, and some evidence for its effectiveness in relation to other
drugs, though it may be more effective where problems related to the drug use are mild to
moderate (Bray et al 2017; Parmar and Sarkar 2017).
There are also alternative methods to meet the aim of preventing welfare payments from
being spent on illicit drugs. For instance, governments might provide support via methods other
than cash payments. Examples are the USA’s SNAP, or the ‘cashless welfare card’ used in some
areas of Australia, which provides credit that cannot be spent on alcohol or gambling, or to
obtain cash (Australian Government DSS 2017).
5. PROPORTIONALITY ANALYSIS
We have proposed that for a program of drug testing welfare recipients to be ethically
26
acceptable, it must be reasonably likely to meet its aim(s), not impose costs out of proportion to
the importance of its aim(s), and not be substantially more costly than feasible alternatives. For
brevity, we will refer to these below as success, proportionality, and necessity criteria. Since
achieving reductions in use via treatment referral and deterrence, and achieving other aims via
exclusion from benefits, seem mutually exclusive, we assess the aims in two groups, first in
relation to the aim of reducing drug use (and its various further aims), and then in relation to
aims served by welfare exclusion. The analyses also make clear the necessity of distinguishing
between two quite different populations of people who use drugs, for whom the effects of these
policies may be radically different.
5.1. Reducing Drug Use
We begin with the success criterion. People using drugs recreationally would not be
affected by a treatment referral. The probability of recreational users being deterred from using
by drug testing is not known. If drug tests are given at predictable times, such as on application,
deterrence might not be lasting. Random scheduling of drug tests might be more effective as a
deterrent, but does not appear to be used in any current programs, and may be practically
difficult to implement given the need to establish reasonable suspicion and the short detection
window for most drugs. Recreational use seems the least likely kind to impact on employability,
and recreational users are less likely to be implicated in child maltreatment cases or involved in
crime. They perhaps spend welfare payments on illegal drugs, but would be less likely to do so
in high amounts, or where this would divert funds needed for basic necessities. Thus, while there
may be some deterrence, overall it seems unlikely that drug testing programs will greatly reduce
recreational drug use, and so achieve the four further aims to a significant extent.
27
People who are dependent on drugs are unlikely to achieve reduced use via deterrence.
Drug dependence is known to change decision-making surrounding drug-taking and is a chronic
relapsing condition. While dependent people appear to retain some measure of choice over their
use, an intermittent or one-off drug test is unlikely to impact much on overall use. Some
proportion of drug-dependent welfare recipients might achieve reduced drug use through
treatment. The evidence does not provide clear guidance on whether they are thereby more likely
to gain employment, and there are reasons to doubt this, especially if other employment barriers
are unaddressed. We also lack good evidence that treatment benefits children, and there are again
reasons to doubt it will have much effect if other issues are not addressed. The evidence-base
surrounding drugs and crime indicates that some reductions could be expected to follow
reductions in use, though it is not known how many drug-dependent people receiving welfare are
also involved in crime. These would also reduce the amount of welfare money being spent on
drugs. Noting some lack of evidence, we will allow for the sake of argument that there might be
effects for increased employability and improvements for children, and consider that a drug
testing program could meet the success condition in relation to these four aims, for dependent
users, to some extent. However, this is unlikely to be a very great extent, given what is known
about the low-to-high-moderate effectiveness of treatment for reducing drug use (Dutra et al
2008), and the low rate of positives detected by drug testing programs.
In terms of the aim of reducing drug use (and its further aims), then, programs seem more
likely to meet the success criterion via treatment than deterrence. We will therefore focus on this
mechanism in the remainder of this assessment, in order to follow the principle of charity. We
then need to assess whether such an outcome is sufficiently important to justify the various costs
of the program. These include: the broader population of welfare recipients have their privacy
28
infringed and might be negatively impacted; people testing positive are enrolled in treatment that
could be considered coerced and may be irrelevant for them; financial costs (quite high given the
need for additional treatment investment); and the reinforcement of harmful stereotypes,
including in some locations racial stereotypes. Though these various problems would be difficult
to quantify, it seems implausible that these costs would be compensated for by reductions in drug
use among a small proportion of welfare recipients, with some (partly uncertain) ensuing
benefits.
For this end to justify such costs, it would need to be considered highly important. Some
might consider it so, perhaps due to holding a ‘zero-tolerance’ approach to drug use or
considering drug use intrinsically unethical. While some do hold such a view, it is difficult to
justify once its basis made explicit: it appears to rely on premises that one’s mind should not be
manipulated, and/or that there is something intrinsically wrong with seeking pleasure through
substances, but in general these are not held by those arguing that drug use is itself unethical, or
are not held consistently (Husak 2004, 407-11). While some reduction in drug use among
welfare recipients may have some value, then, it is implausible to consider it to have sufficient
value to justify its costs and thus it will not meet the proportionality criterion for this aim.
It is also unlikely that a program could meet the necessity criterion for this aim. There are
alternative methods for the identification of people with drug dependence, which is the kind of
use most relevant to this aim. These could avoid some of the costs (enrolling non-dependent
people in inappropriate treatment, and many of the financial costs), while having similar effects
for drug use reduction and ensuing benefits. There may be other policy options possible to better
further children’s interests. Since families with at-risk children and drug-dependent parents are
likely part of a polydysfunctional group, they are likely to come to the attention of relevant
29
authorities through other means than drug tests performed by welfare agencies – and are likely to
need a broader set of interventions if outcomes are to be improved.
The aim of reducing use in order to increase employability, protect children, reduce drugrelated crime, and prevent welfare money from being spent on drugs, is thus largely irrelevant to
recreational drug users, either by deterrence or treatment. For dependent users, available
evidence indicates it might meet the success criterion via treatment, although perhaps not to a
great degree, and it is unlikely to meet proportionality or necessity criteria.
5.2. Exclude People Who Use Drugs from Welfare
The aim of excluding people who use drugs from welfare – as a means to stated aims of
preventing welfare payments being spent on drugs, and reducing government spending – could
be achieved by a drug testing program. Such a program might either test all recipients, or use
pre-screening, excluding those who test positive or refuse a test. The former case would exclude
some recreational as well as some dependent drug users, while the latter would be likely to
exclude mainly dependent users (assuming the screening tool is reasonably accurate). Though
some drug users would likely test negative (if they have not used recently, or have used drugs not
tested for), either of these methods would reduce the amount of welfare payments being spent on
illicit drugs to some degree. This may or may not meet the aim of saving state money overall,
depending on program details such as rules relating to payments intended to support children.
For the sake of argument, we grant that this is possible, and will count programs which exclude
recipients who test positive as meeting the success condition for its further aims.
To meet the proportionality criterion, meeting these aims would need to be regarded as
highly important, as they need to outweigh high costs. Importantly, exclusion from benefits will
30
reduce people’s capacities to meet their basic needs. The evidence indicates that this is likely to
exacerbate mental health problems and economic hardship, both for the welfare recipients
themselves and their dependants and associates. In addition, it may increase crime, particularly
acquisitive crime, as people seek alternative means of support (Pollack 2017); could have
negative effects for children (Wu et al 2015); and, insofar as disadvantaged racial groups are
over-represented among those undergoing testing, could worsen existing socioeconomic
inequalities. In addition, non-drug-using welfare recipients would also have to undergo a rights
infringement; damaging stereotypes about welfare recipients, disadvantaged minorities, and drug
users would be encouraged; and marginalisation of drug users would be perpetuated.
We do not consider the aim of preventing welfare payments being spent on drugs to be
sufficiently important that meeting it would compensate for all of these costs. It does not seem
plausible to us that preventing a person from spending welfare payments on illicit drugs is more
important than that person, and others, being able to access basic necessities – and there would
be more costs than this. Nor can aims concerning government spending be plausibly considered
to outweigh these negative effects, particularly considering that they are likely to increase
financial costs in other areas in any case (the costs caused by increased crime are likely to be
particularly high, especially in locations with high rates of drug-related incarceration) (Pollack
2017, 168-9; 174-5). Accordingly, drug testing programs that exclude people testing positive
from payments will not meet the proportionality criterion.
We recognize that, again, some might consider the aim of preventing welfare payments
being spent on illicit drugs to be extremely important, again perhaps due to beliefs held about the
ethical status of drug use, or to beliefs about the obligations of citizens receiving government
assistance. Thus some might regard this aim to be sufficiently important that meeting it would
31
compensate for all these costs, and so take drug testing for this purpose to meet the
proportionality criterion.
However, even if this possibility is granted, following a principle of charity, such a
program would be unlikely to meet the necessity criterion. In relation to this aim, alternative
methods for identifying people who are drug-dependent may not be relevant, if the aim applies to
spending on recreational drug use as well as dependent use. However, there are alternative
methods available to prevent spending of welfare payments on illicit drugs, such as cashless
support. While there are also various objections to this form of welfare to be considered, any
costs associated with it may be less than the costs of drug testing combined with exclusion from
welfare. Thus drug testing to exclude people from welfare payments does not meet the necessity
criterion.
6. DRUG TESTING OF WELFARE RECIPIENTS IS NOT ETHICALLY ACCEPTABLE
POLICY
We conclude that programs of drug testing welfare recipients, however their aims are
construed, are unlikely to be able to meet those aims, or where they do meet them, will not be
able to do so in ways that meet proportionality and necessity criteria. As such, programs of drug
testing welfare recipients are not ethically acceptable.
Our analysis suggests a number of general points that often remain implicit in discussion of
drug testing welfare recipients, contributing to lack of clarity in both public and academic debate.
Programs are likely to affect different populations of drug users in quite different ways. There is
little point targeting recreational users with drug testing, as this will not have great effects for
any of the aims of programs, and will have some costs. A smaller, dependent group could
32
possibly derive some benefits from drug testing linked to treatment interventions. However,
members of this group, many of whom will be polydysfunctional, are likely to come to the
attention of authorities in other ways, and often face a complex set of difficulties which require a
broader set of interventions.
REFERENCES
Alexander M. 2010. The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness. New
York: The New Press.
Australian Associated Press (AAP). 2017. Drug test trial for welfare recipients ‘all about love’,
says Turnbull. SBS News, 22 August 2017,
https://www.sbs.com.au/news/article/2017/08/22/drug-test-trial-welfare-recipients-all-aboutlove-says-turnbull, accessed 13 December 2017.
Amundson K, Zajicek AM, Kerr B. 2015. A social metamorphosis: Constructing drug addicts
from the poor. Sociological Spectrum 35(5):442-464.
Atkinson J, Lee D, Dayton-Shotts C, French C. 2001. Self-perceived job skills and employment
barriers among non-drug using and chronic drug using welfare-to-work participants. Journal
of Drug Issues 31(3):747-756.
Australian Government Department of Social Services (DSS). 2017. Cashless debit card –
Overview. https://www.dss.gov.au/families-and-children/programmes-services/welfareconditionality/cashless-debit-card-overview, accessed 13 December 2017.
Berger PB. 2001. Science misapplied: mandatory addiction screening and treatment for welfare
33
recipients in Ontario. Canadian Medical Association Journal 165(4):443-4.
Bloom D, Loprest PJ, Zedlewski SR. 2011. TANF recipients with barriers to employment. Office
of Planning, Research and Evaluation, Urban Institute, Brief #1. Available at
https://www.urban.org/research/publication/tanf-recipients-barriers-employment, 13 Nov
2017.
Bolen J. 2014. Screening the poor: The legality of drug testing for welfare benefits. Richmond
Journal of Law and the Public Interest 18(1):77-88.
Bray JW, Del Boca FK, McRee BG, Hayashi SW, Babor TF. 2017. Screening, brief intervention
and referral to treatment (SBIRT): rationale, program overview and cross-site evaluation.
Addiction 112(Suppl. 2):3-11.
Carley F. 2012. Drug testing welfare recipients: a review of potential costs and savings. State
Notes: Topics of Legislative Interest. Michigan Senate Fiscal Agency, Summer 2012.
http://www.senate.michigan.gov/sfa/publications/notes/2012notes/notessum12fc.pdf,
accessed 13 Nov 2017.
Chandler K. 2014. Alabama lawmakers approve welfare drug testing. The Washington Times, 3
April 2014. https://www.washingtontimes.com/news/2014/apr/3/alabama-lawmakersapprove-welfare-drug-testing/, accessed 13 December 2017.
Chatterji P, Meara E. 2010. Consequences of eliminating federal disability benefits for substance
abusers. Journal of Health Economics 29:226-240.
Childress, JF, et al. 2002. Public health ethics: mapping the terrain. Journal of Law, Medicine
and Ethics 30:170-178.
Cianciardo J. 2010. The principle of proportionality: The challenges of human rights. Journal of
Civil Law Studies 3(1):177-186.
34
Crew RE, Davis BC. 2003. Assessing the effects of substance abuse among applicants for TANF
benefits. Journal of Health & Social Policy 17(1):39-53.
Crew RE, Davis BC. 2006. Substance abuse as a barrier to employment of welfare recipients.
Journal of Policy Practice 5(4):69-82.
Department of Health and Human Services (DHHS). 2011. Drug Testing Welfare Recipients:
Recent proposals and continuing controversies. ASPE Issue Brief, US Department of Health
and Human Services. https://aspe.hhs.gov/basic-report/drug-testing-welfare-recipientsrecent-proposals-and-continuing-controversies, 13 Nov 2017.
Dutra L, et al. 2008. A meta-analytic review of psychosocial interventions for substance use
disorders. Am J Psychiatry 165:179-87.
Fisher D. 2014. Minister claims low drug result as victory. New Zealand Herald, 11 January
2014, http://www.nzherald.co.nz/nz/news/article.cfm?c_id=1&objectid=11184479, accessed
13 December 2017.
Forsyth M, Banham C. 2017. Drug testing welfare recipients is not about love, Malcolm
Turnbull, it’s about punishment. The Guardian Australia, 11 May 2017.
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2017/may/11/drug-testing-welfare-recipientsis-not-about-love-malcolm-turnbull-its-about-punishment, accessed 31 January 2018.
Grant BF. 1996. Prevalence and correlates of drug use and DSM-IV drug dependence in the
United States: Results of the National Longitudinal Alcohol Epidemiologic Survey. Journal
of Substance Abuse 8(2):195-210.
Hall R. 2016. Drug testing and public assistance. CLASP: Policy solutions that work for lowincome people. Washington, DC.
https://www.clasp.org/sites/default/files/publications/2017/04/2016.02.04-Drug-Testing-
35
and-Public-Assistance-Brief-FINAL.pdf, accessed 13 Nov 2017.
Henderson S, Dohan D, Schmidt LA. 2006. Barriers to identifying substance abuse in the
reformed welfare system. Social Service Review 80(2):217-238.
Hermeren G. 2012. The principle of proportionality revisited: interpretations and applications.
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 15:373-82.
Husak DN. 2004. The moral relevance of addiction. Substance Use & Misuse 39(3):399-436.
Kass NE. 2001. An ethics framework for public health. American Journal of Public Health
91(11):1776-1782.
Kayanan M. 2013. Shaping a legal challenge to the drug testing of welfare applicants.
Clearinghouse REVIEW Journal of Poverty Law and Policy 47:114-118.
Kepple NJ. 2017. The complex nature of parental substance use: Examining past year and prior
use behaviors as correlates of child maltreatment frequency. Substance Use & Misuse
52(6):811-821.
Kumar S, Malhotra A. 2000. Brief interventions in substance use. Indian Journal of Psychiatry
42(2):172-183.
Lazowski LE, Geary BB. Validation of the Adult Substance Abuse Subtle Screening Inventory4(SASSI-4). European Journal of Psychological Assessment (online first).
https://doi.org/10.1027/1015-5759/a000359.
Ledford C. 2016. Symbolic racism, institutional bias, and welfare drug testing legislation: racial
biases matter. Policy Studies Journal (online ahead of print). DOI:10.1111/psj.12192
Metsch LR, McCoy CB, Miller M, McAnany H, Pereyra M. 1999. Moving substance-abusing
women from welfare to work. Journal of Public Health Policy 20(1): 36-55.
36
MacCoun RJ, Reuter P. 2001. Drug War Heresies: Learning from other Vices, Times and
Places. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McDaniel M, Woods T, Pratt E, Simms M. 2017. Identifying racial and ethnic disparities in
human services. Urban Institute, Washington, DC.
https://www.urban.org/research/publication/identifying-racial-and-ethnic-disparities-humanservices/view/full_report, accessed 22 December 2017.
McLaughlin BW. 2013. Drug testing, welfare, and the special needs doctrine: An argument in
support of drug testing TANF recipients. Cleveland State Law Review 61:567-98.
Morgenstern J, et al. 2001. Specialized Screening Approaches Can Substantially Increase the
Identification of Substance Abuse Problems Among Welfare Recipients. Research Notes.
Office of the Assistant Secretary for Planning and Evaluation, US Department of Health and
Human Services. https://aspe.hhs.gov/report/specialized-screening-approaches-cansubstantially-increase-identification-substance-abuse-problems-among-welfare-recipients,
14 Nov 2017.
Morgenstern J, Hogue A, Dasaro C, Kuerbis A, Dauber S. 2008. Characteristics of individuals
screening positive for substance use in a welfare setting: Implications for welfare and
substance-use disorders treatment systems. Journal of Studies on Alcohol and Drugs
69(4):561-70.
Murphy J, Murray S, Chalmers J, Martin S, Marston G. 2011. Half a Citizen: Life on Welfare in
Australia. Allen and Unwin, Sydney.
Nam Y. 2005. The roles of employment barriers in welfare exits and reentries after welfare
reform: Event history analysis. Social Service Review 79(2):268-93.
National College of State Legislatures (NCSL). 2017. Drug testing for welfare recipients and
37
public assistance. 24 March 2017. http://www.ncsl.org/research/human-services/drugtesting-and-public-assistance.aspx, accessed 14 Nov 2017.
New Zealand Ministry of Social Development. 2016. FOI requests. Available at
https://www.msd.govt.nz/about-msd-and-our-work/publications-resources/officialinformation-responses/2016/index.html, accessed 14 Nov 2017.
New Zealand Ministry of Social Development. 2018. Obligations.
https://www.workandincome.govt.nz/on-a-benefit/obligations/index.html, accessed 30
January 2018.
Newell W. 2011. Tax dollars earmarked for drugs – The policy and constitutionality of drug
testing welfare recipients. Columbia Human Rights Law Review 43:215-254.
Oosting J. 2014. Welfare drug testing bills win final approval in Michigan Senate, head to
governor’s desk. Mlive, 10 December 2014, http://www.mlive.com/lansingnews/index.ssf/2014/12/welfare_drug_testing_bills_win.html, accessed 13 December 2017.
Payne J, Gaffney A. 2012. How much crime is drug or alcohol related? Self-reported attributions
of police detainees. Trends and Issues in Crime and Criminal Justice 439. Australian
Institute of Criminology, Australian Government.
http://www.aic.gov.au/publications/current%20series/tandi/421-440/tandi439.html, accessed
13 Dec 2017.
Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia. 2017. Senate Social Services Legislation
Amendment (Welfare Reform) Bill 2017 - Revised Explanatory Memorandum.
https://www.aph.gov.au/Parliamentary_Business/Bills_Legislation/Bills_Search_Results/Re
sult?bId=r5927, accessed 14 Nov 2017.
Parmar A, Sarkar S. 2017. Brief interventions for cannabis use disorders: A review. Addictive
38
Disorders and Their Treatment 16(2):80-93.
Perez-Munoz C. 2017. What is wrong with testing welfare recipients for drug use? Political
Studies (online ahead of print).
Pidd K, Roche A. 2011. Workplace Drug Testing: Evidence and Issues. National Centre for
Education and Training on Addiction, Flinders University, Adelaide.
http://nceta.flinders.edu.au/files/5813/2200/5230/Workplace%20Drug%20Testings%20ml%
202.pdf, accessed 13 Dec 2017.
Pilkinton M. 2010. TANF recipients' barriers to employability: substance abuse and domestic
violence. Journal of Human Behavior in the Social Environment 20(8):1011-1023.
Pollack HA. 2013. States want drug tests for welfare recipients. That’s a terrible idea.
Washington Post, 5 June 2013.
https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/wonk/wp/2013/06/05/states-want-drug-tests-forwelfare-recipients-thats-a-terrible-idea/?utm_term=.887d7ed8156a, accessed 31 January
2018.
Pollack HA, Danziger S, Jayakody R, Seefeldt KS. 2002a. Drug testing welfare recipients—false
positives, false negatives, unanticipated opportunities. Women’s Health Issues 12(1):23-31.
Pollack HA, Danziger S, Seefeldt KS, Jayakody R. 2002b. Substance use among welfare
recipients: trends and policy responses. Social Service Review 76(2):256-274.
Pollack HA. 2017. Dealing more effectively with problematic substance use and crime. Crime &
Justice 46(1):159-200.
Price ML. 2013. Utah’s welfare drug testing saved more than $350,000 in first year, officials say.
Deseret News, 8 September 2013, https://www.deseretnews.com/article/765637435/Utahofficials-say-welfare-drug-tests-save-money.html, accessed 13 December 2017.
39
Rodin D. 2011. Justifying harm. Ethics 122(1):74-110.
Schaberg AE. 2012. State drug testing requirements for welfare recipients: Are Missouri and
Florida’s new laws constitutional? Missouri Law Review 77:567-89.
Stromwall LK. 2002. Mental health barriers to employment for TANF recipients. Journal of
Poverty 6(3):109-120.
Taylor MJ, Barusch AS. 2004. Personal, family, and multiple barriers of long-term welfare
recipients. Social Work 49(2):175-83.
Terer K, Brown R. 2014. Effective drink driving prevention and enforcement strategies. Trends
and Issues in Crime and Criminal Justice 472. Australian Institute of Criminology,
Australian Government.
http://www.aic.gov.au/media_library/publications/tandi_pdf/tandi472.pdf, accessed
December 14 2017.
Testa MF, Smith B. 2008. Prevention and drug treatment. The Future of Children 19(2):147-168.
USA.gov. 2018. Government benefits. https://www.usa.gov/benefits, accessed 30 Jan 2018.
Walzer M. 1977. Just and Unjust Wars. Basic Books, New York.
Watkins KE, Podus D. 2000. The impact of terminating disability benefits for substance abusers
on susbtance use and treatment participation. Psychiatric Services 51(11):1371-1372;1381.
Werb D, et al. 2015. The effectiveness of compulsory drug treatment: A systematic review.
International Journal of Drug Policy 28:1-9.
Widelitz J. 2011. Florida’s suspicionless drug testing of welfare applicants. Nova Law Review
36:253-398.
Wincup E. 2014. Thoroughfares, crossroads and cul-de-sacs: Drug testing of welfare recipients.
International Journal of Drug Policy 25:1031:1037.
40
Wodak A. 2017. People who think punitive measure help drug addicts haven’t seen what I have.
The Guardian, 22 August 2017,
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2017/aug/22/people-who-think-punitivemeasures-help-drug-addicts-havent-seen-what-i-have, accessed 14 December 2017.
Wu C-F, Cancian M, Wallace G. 2014. The effect of welfare sanctions on TANF exits and
employment. Children and Youth Services Review 36:1-14.
1
Since most existing and proposed programs focus on income support payments made to
working-age people who are unemployed (or under-employed), our argument will focus on this
group. Any future proposals to drug-test recipients of other welfare payments, particularly
payments that support those unable to work, may suffer from similar problems to those discussed
below, but will also raise other complex issues. Since there have thus far been no proposals to
drug test recipients of such payments (that we are aware of) we leave these aside in the current
paper, though we expect that if our argument against drug testing succeeds for a potentially
work-engaged population, it would also rule out drug testing of those unable to work.
2 And/or on some feature of welfare receipt that makes welfare recipients liable to bear some
burdens. As we argue below, this can be incorporated into the proportionality approach.
3 For detail on the series of legal decisions and appeals related to these programs (and analysis)
see, e.g., Bolen (2014); McLaughlin (2013); Newell (2012).
4 Details of TANF programs differ by state. SNAP (‘food stamps’) provides low-income families
or individuals with a debit card which can be used to buy food. Medicaid provides healthcare to
low-income families and individuals, with eligibility and types of care covered differing by state
(USA.gov 2018). Other countries that have considered drug testing programs all have universal
healthcare systems, do not distinguish between contributory and non-contributory government
assistance, and have only considered drug testing for recipients of unemployment benefits.
5 This applies to recipients of income support payments who have work obligations, and so is
relevant to New Zealand’s Jobseeker and Sole Parent Support payments, both means-tested
payments to support working-age people who are under- or unemployed. See New Zealand
Ministry of Social Development (2018).
6 Some have claimed that the threat of exclusion from benefits could motivate people to stop
using drugs and find work (Widelitz 2011, 303). While it may have some such deterrent effect,
this seems unrealistic for people who are drug dependent, and the instability involved in lacking
a basic income is unlikely to be conducive to finding work.
7
As a separate consideration, politicians’ aims of proposing drug testing programs to appeal to
voters may also be ethically suspect, though perhaps not as clearly so, since some political
41
dissimulation may be expected by voters or normalized (and politicians may also genuinely share
their electors’ views). But even if a political aim of appealing to voters is ethically permissible, at
least in some cases, it is hardly an aim of sufficient value to justify any of the costs or harms of a
particular policy.
8 It is worth making explicit that we are therefore treating these unstated aims as irrelevant to the
ethical assessment of drug testing welfare recipients for the purposes of the proportionality
analysis, even though the proportionality analysis is largely built around an understanding of
policy aims. This is not because we think it has no ethical relevance but rather for two other
reasons. First, that (as argued below) drug testing programs cannot be ethically justified even on
the basis of its stated, potentially ethically acceptable aims, making the inclusion of the unstated
aims as aims unnecessary to show that the policy is unethical. Second, we are wary of
contributing to further polarisation of drug policy debate. In saying this, we acknowledge that it
may also be true that such unstated aims are important to recognize in ethical investigations
which have a broader scope than our own, for instance in relation to broader practices of welfare,
drug, and criminal justice policy.
9 Most testing methods have a quite short detection window of one to several days (with a longer
detection window for cannabis) (Pidd and Roche 2011). People who are dependent might use
less frequently than this, or be dependent on alcohol, or illicit drugs that are not tested for. Any
program will also need a way to distinguish illicit from prescription use, including opioid
painkillers, prescription methadone, and medicinal cannabis in relevant jurisdictions. This issue
arose for some tested during the overturned Florida program (Kayanan 2013). Tests can also be
inaccurate due to medical conditions, such as kidney problems (DHHS 2011, 4).
10 US Courts have also considered drug testing justified in some situations by implied consent
(e.g., in voluntary school sports programs) and by a ‘diminished expectation of privacy’ attached
to some kinds of government employment (e.g., customs officials) (Newell 2012).
11 Rates of disadvantaged group members who are subjected to drug tests could be even more
disproportionate if people are selected for testing using some sorts of profiling, or informal
discretionary mechanisms.
12 Conversely, if drug testing programs actually benefit recipients, perhaps by aiding recovery
from drug dependence problems from treatment referrals, it could be regarded as an equalising
measure.
13 This might depend on the type of treatment (e.g., pharmacological versus counselling), as well
as whether drug dependence is considered a disease.
14 Of course, it is arguable that requiring people to undertake such tests might also constitute a
privacy infringement and be similarly stigmatising. Our point here is just that if the aim of the
program relates to identifying the population with drug dependence problems (rather than any
drug user) it is likely to be more accurate. There may well be good reasons not to adopt it either,
but these are beyond the scope of this paper.
42