Experimental Philosophical Bioethics of Personal Identity
Brian D. Earp, Jonathan Lewis, Joshua A. Skorburg, Ivar R. Hannikainen, and Jim A. C. Everetti
This is the authors’ copy of a published book chapter.
Earp, B. D., Lewis, J., Skorburg, J. A., Hannikainen, I., & Everett, J. A. C. (2022).
Experimental philosophical bioethics of personal identity. In K. Tobia (ed.), Experimental
Philosophy of Identity and the Self (p. 183-202). London: Bloomsbury.
doi: 10.5040/9781350246928.0018
I. Introduction
The question of what makes someone the same person through time and change has long been a
preoccupation of philosophers. In recent years, the question of what makes ordinary or laypeople
(i.e., individuals from a wide range of backgrounds, including non-philosophers) judge that
someone is—or isn’t—the same person has caught the interest of experimental psychologists.
These latter, empirically oriented researchers have sought to understand the cognitive processes
and eliciting factors that shape ordinary people’s judgments about personal identity and the self.
Still more recently, practitioners within an emerging discipline, experimental philosophical
bioethics or “bioxphi”—the focus of this chapter—have adopted a similar aim and employed
similar methodologies, but with two distinctive features: (a) a special concern for enhanced
ecological validity in the examples and populations studied; and (b) an interest in contributing to
substantive normative debates within the wider field of bioethics (Earp et al. 2020a, 2021a;
Klenk 2020; Lewis 2020a).
Our aim in this chapter is to sample illustrative work on personal identity in bioxphi,
explore how it relates to studies in psychology covering similar terrain, and draw out the
1
implications of this work for matters of bioethical concern. Of course, the boundaries between
fields and disciplines are often blurry, and many of the same practitioners are conducting
research across these different areas. We are less concerned with whether a given study or line of
work counts as an instance of bioxphi than with characterizing bioxphi more generally and
exploring some of the ways in which data-driven studies using the methods of cognitive science,
moral psychology, and experimental philosophy (x-phi) can inform bioethical argumentation and
decision-making.
With this aim in mind, we begin by briefly reviewing classic studies in psychology and xphi that bear on questions concerning lay judgments about personal identity change versus
persistence: that is, the extent to which someone is regarded as the same person despite
undergoing significant psychological transformation. We will discuss some strengths and
limitations of this work with a view to articulating what is new and interesting about bioxphi
studies investigating similar judgments. Subsequently, we share some candidate strategies for
how empirical findings (i.e., descriptive information about how and why people make certain
judgments) might appropriately be used in the service of normative arguments: for example,
arguments about how personal identity should be understood in certain contexts or toward
certain ends. We also explore how such empirical information could profitably be employed in
the context of practical bioethical decision-making: for example, in helping us to draw
conclusions about what should be done in various medical situations involving judgments about
personal identity change.
In pursuing these issues, we highlight recent work in bioxphi that addresses a rich variety
of topics touching on personal identity. These topics include the perceived validity of advance
directives following neurodegeneration (Earp et al. 2020b), the right of psychologically altered
2
study participants to withdraw from research (Tobia 2016; Dranseika et al. unpublished), how
drug addiction may cause one to be regarded by others as “a completely different person” (Earp
et al. 2019), the effect of deep brain stimulation on perceptions of the self (Skorburg and SinnottArmstrong 2020), and the potential influence of moral enhancement interventions on intuitive
impressions of a person’s character (Fabiano 2021). We conclude with some general
observations and suggestions for future research.
II. A Broad Overview of Conceptions of Personal Identity Change in Philosophy, X-Phi and
Moral Psychology
What determines your personal identity through time and change? Are “you” at age five the
same person as “you” in old age, at the end of life? If you suffer a serious brain injury that causes
you to lose most of your memories—or which permanently alters key aspects of your
character—are you still yourself, and if so, in what sense? Suppose that two people could swap
bodies (Williams 1970); how could we decide or track who was who? A long tradition in
philosophy has debated puzzles like these. A prominent view, typically associated with John
Locke, is premised on a diachronic conception of the self as a reasoning and reflective entity that
persists over time (Locke 1689/1694 [1985], 2.27.9). For Locke, as he has classically been
interpreted, “consciousness” of past actions—via the faculty of memory—is at the heart of
personal identity (Reid 1785 [1969]). Broadly, according to this view, Person A who did x at
Time 1 can be identified as Person B at Time 2 if B has the same “consciousness” as A, where
this implies having a memory of doing x.
Whether this is the correct, or most justifiable, view of personal identity is an open
question. As some philosophers have argued, a theory of a given scientific phenomenon is
3
usually considered to be adequate if, among other things, it can explain the relevant data: for
example, if it can explain why the contents of a test tube turn green under certain conditions, but
red under others (Thompson 1986: 257; Kagan 2001: 47). When one seeks to explain personal
identity, however, it is not obvious what the relevant data are that need to be explained.
Certainly, many of us have a strong sense that we exist in the form of a person or self that
extends through time; and it seems that we live in a world full of other selves that are similarly
diachronic. Moreover, experiences of continuity or discontinuity in oneself or in the selves of
others—in the context of close interpersonal relationships, for instance—often matter a great
deal. When we “lose ourselves” in periods of mental illness; when a loved one starts to seem like
a stranger after developing an addiction (Tobia 2017); when a parent or grandparent with
dementia doesn’t recognize us, we may feel disoriented, disenchanted, or disturbed. Perhaps
these are the data that need to be explained: our everyday beliefs, perceptions, and experiences of
ourselves and the selves of others through time and change.
Philosophers, including Locke, have developed theories along these lines. However, in
doing so, they most often have simply consulted their own intuitions about particular cases—
whether real or imagined—that seem to implicate, or raise questions about, the nature of personal
identity (e.g., Williams’s “body swap” scenario mentioned in Chapter 1). Commonly, they will
ask what is entailed by a given theoretical claim if applied to such a scenario, and then check to
see whether the implication seems intuitively right or reasonable to them. If it doesn’t seem
reasonable, then they may go back to adjust the theory. But whether this is an appropriate
strategy for building a general account of personal identity is unclear.ii As Machery notes,
philosophers who rely on such an approach “are neither inquiring about the actual world,
collecting observational data or running experiments, nor examining our best scientific theories
4
to [decide] what determines personal identity” (Machery 2017: 189). Moreover, even if it is
granted that philosophers’ intuitions should play some role in theory development, it is doubtful
whether these intuitions should be accorded substantially more weight than those of nonphilosophers when it comes to providing answers to certain philosophical questions (Machery
2017: 149–84). At the very least, it seems pertinent to know whether the philosophers’ intuitions
or associated judgments about cases are idiosyncratic or widely shared among relevant
stakeholders.
As Kagan (2001) notes, philosophers have for the most part simply assumed that others—
at least, other philosophers—will share their intuitions and judgments about cases. Until
relatively recently, this assumption had not been tested much empirically (Machery 2017).
However, this started to change in the early 2000s when “experimental philosophers” (Knobe
2007; Knobe et al. 2012) started to move away from proverbial armchair theorizing, toward
investigating how ordinary people think about questions such as what it means to be the same
person over time. For example, Blok et al. (2005) asked study participants to imagine that a team
of doctors removed the brain of a patient (“Jim”) and destroyed his body. In one scenario, the
doctors successfully transplanted Jim’s brain into a new body, so that Jim’s memories were fully
preserved: physically, he had a completely different body, but he could still remember
everything from before the surgery. In another version of the scenario, all the other details were
kept the same except that Jim’s memories were not preserved during the transplantation.
Philosophical debates in the Lockean tradition show that there are sophisticated
arguments both for and against someone’s being the same person in a case like this. However,
one argument concludes that the brain recipient is the same person as Jim when the latter’s
memories are preserved, despite the bodily changes. And that is what the researchers found:
5
participants agreed that the brain recipient was the same person as Jim when his memories
remained intact but disagreed when his memories did not survive the operation (Blok et al. 2005;
for a replication of the results of Blok, Newman, and Rips’s third-person investigation, see
Nichols and Bruno 2010). It seems, then, that ordinary people—not only those with advanced
philosophical training—intuitively regard autobiographical memories as being at least one
important contributing factor to personal identity.
Other factors matter as well. In a recent, influential line of work, it has been demonstrated
that moral attributes, even more so than memories, are widely judged to be at the core of
personal identity (Strohminger and Nichols 2014; Prinz and Nichols 2016). In these studies,
researchers gave participants a list of traits and asked them to imagine to what degree a change to
each trait would influence whether someone was still the same person. In what is now known as
the moral self effect, changes to a person’s moral qualities were consistently judged to be the
most identity-disruptive factor. As Strohminger and Nichols concluded, “moral traits are
considered more important to personal identity than any other part of the mind” (Strohminger
and Nichols 2014: 168). Furthermore, the direction of moral change also matters: evidence
suggests that improvements to moral character, compared to deteriorations, tend to be seen as
less threatening to personal identity persistence (Tobia 2015).
So far, these studies have overwhelmingly involved “WEIRD” participants (Henrich et
al. 2010), so that the range of cultural and other demographic contexts across which similar
results might obtain is not yet known (but see, e.g., Dranseika et al. unpublished).iii Nevertheless,
in the meantime, philosophers have begun grappling with the (meta)philosophical implications of
experimentally derived findings regarding people’s judgments of personal identity (e.g., O’Neill
and Machery 2014; Fisher 2015; Knobe 2016; Machery 2017; Nado 2021). In line with this
6
approach, but focusing specifically on philosophical bioethics, we will now explore some of the
implications of such findings for the burgeoning discipline of bioxphi.
III. From X-Phi and Moral Psychology to Bioxphi
The studies surveyed earlier, and others like them, have done much to increase our understanding
of how ordinary people think about personal identity change or persistence, albeit sometimes in
relation to unusual cases. Typically, these studies rely on vignette-based designs that hold
everything constant between experimental conditions apart from a specific feature—such as a
given trait or personal attribute—that is expected to make a difference to participant judgments.
Although questions have been raised as to whether this contrastive-vignette technique (CVT)
should be used so exclusively (Mihailov et al. 2021; Earp et al. 2021a), an advantage of the
approach is it allows researchers to zero in on well-defined aspects of the self that might change
as a result of some imagined intervention, so that fine-grained discriminations can be made
between potential factors shaping participant judgments (Reiner 2019).
When applied to questions of personal identity, such CVT studies oftentimes have
employed far-fetched, even science-fiction-like examples: brain transplants, body switches,
magic pills, time machines, reincarnation, and the like. This likely has to do with a typical aim of
such studies, which is to validate or refute the premises of arguments made from the armchair.
As Machery (2017, 113–16) argues, such “armchair” philosophizing often relies on cases that are
deliberately “unusual” in order to achieve certain theoretical goals. However, researchers are
increasingly showing an interest in how cases might be adjusted to be more realistic (or to track
features of the world that are more representative of everyday situations).
7
As alluded to previously, this includes researchers in bioxphi, an emerging discipline that
uses the tools of x-phi, moral psychology, and cognitive science to investigate topics in bioethics
with a heightened emphasis on ecological validity. In a bioethical context, judgments about
whether, to what extent, or in what sense someone is the same person despite having undergone
various changes often matter for real-life decisions about how someone should be treated: for
example, in the context of high-stakes decisions about what healthcare a person should receive at
the end of life. Understanding the factors that influence these personal identity-related judgments
in more realistic, ethically charged situations may thus be both theoretically and practically
relevant (but see Shoemaker 2010).
Some work in the more established tradition of moral psychology has already taken a turn
toward greater realism. For example, Strohminger and Nichols (2015) studied judgments of
identity persistence made by actual family members of patients with different neurodegenerative
diseases. The authors sought to determine the extent to which patients would be seen as a
different person as a function of three types of changes: changes to moral faculties (as in some
cases of frontotemporal dementia), changes to memories (as in Alzheimer’s disease), and
changes to physical motor functions (as in amyotrophic lateral sclerosis). Mirroring results from
earlier abstract thought experiments, Strohminger and Nichols found that family members of
patients with frontotemporal dementia—the condition most strongly associated with moral
change—saw the patient as more of a different person compared with family members of
patients with other forms of neurodegeneration (in line with the moral self effect). Strohminger
and Nichols also found that moral changes led to more severe deterioration in the relationships
between patients and family members. Reflecting on these results, the authors derived normative
recommendations:
8
While loss of identity may be feared as an undesirable clinical outcome unto itself, the
present research highlights that identity deterioration has significant downstream
consequences for healthy relationships. . . . Future therapies ought to be aimed at—and
take into account—preserving moral function, a previously unappreciated factor in the
well-being of patients and their families. (Strohminger and Nichols 2015: 1477, emphasis
added)
The bioethical analysis here is straightforward. First, it is noted that certain kinds of
neurodegeneration seem to impair both personal and interpersonal well-being through their
impact on moral functioning. Since one of the main normative commitments of healthcare is to
mitigate threats to well-being that stem from disease or disability—a premise Strohminger and
Nichols implicitly accept—then, assuming sufficient resources, among other relevant
considerations (e.g., ranking of research and funding priorities based on likely success, efficacy,
distributive justice, and so on), it follows that therapies should be developed to address this
mediating factor.
The moral self effect on judgments of personal identity also applies to the case of
addiction (Earp et al. 2019), another real-world issue that can have major implications for
personal and interpersonal well-being. Over a series of experiments involving contrastive
vignettes inspired by real-life stories—and designed to be as believable as possible—three of us
explored whether participants would judge that someone who became addicted to drugs would
thereby become, in some sense, a different person; and, if so, whether this judgment would be
driven by perceived changes in the individual’s moral qualities (Earp et al. 2019). In an initial
experiment, U.S. participants judged a character who became addicted to drugs as being closer to
9
“a completely different person” than “completely the same person,” while subsequent
experiments revealed that these judgments were indeed driven by a perceived worsening of the
moral character of the drug user. In particular, the user was seen as having drifted away from
their (presumably morally good) “true self” (Earp et al. 2019).
Could findings like these have normative implications? Although we could only
speculate based on our initial results, we suggested that public health messages framed around
(re)discovering one’s true self might be especially desirable in the case of addiction (for related
work, see Schlegel and Hicks 2011; Schlegel et al. 2009, 2011). Another possibility is that
campaigns aimed at dissociating drug use or addiction from negative moral character judgments
could be beneficial (Hart 2021), for example, by inclining the public to believe that individuals
who are dealing with addiction are still the same (good) people after all. In either case, the
underlying bioethical reasoning would be similar to that employed by Strohminger and Nichols
(2015). In short, if drug addiction harms individuals and relationships, and if some of this harm
comes from the perception that drug addiction undermines the identity of the user, then, ceteris
paribus, measures to address that perception should be pursued.
In the following section, we will look at other ways in which empirical results—derived
from bioxphi studies—can help inform normative conclusions about bioethical issues involving
judgments about personal identity. First, we will describe some general strategies for reaching
normative conclusions from premises that include empirical information about the mind. Second,
we will discuss these strategies in relation to specific examples drawn from the recent bioxphi
literature.
10
IV. From Empirical Studies to Normative Conclusions: Four Recent Strategies from the Bioxphi
Literature
We have argued that bioxphi studies should be designed with at least two aims in mind. The first
aim is scientific: it is to understand the cognitive processes and eliciting factors that shape
morally relevant judgments in the real world, so that we might build theoretically justified and
descriptively accurate models of the—realistically situated—moral mind (Mihailov et al. 2021).
The second aim is normative: it is to harness these models and associated findings to help reach
ethically warranted conclusions in bioethics (e.g., regarding public health policy or clinical
decision-making) (Earp et al. 2021a).
In a recent paper (Earp et al. 2021a), some of us drew on examples from the burgeoning
bioxphi literature to outline four main strategies for reaching normative conclusions from
premises that include empirical content about the mind: parsimony, debunking, triangulation,
and pluralism. Here is a brief description of each strategy, followed by an illustrative example of
how it might be applied to an ethical question involving judgments about personal identity:
1. Parsimony. If relevant stakeholders consistently make a judgment p which
encodes moral claim M, then M has prima facie normative weight (inspired, in
part, by consultative approaches to empirical bioethics as detailed in Davies et al.
2015).
2. Debunking. A strategy seeking to show that a judgment or moral claim is
unreliable using the following argument structure (inspired by Mukerji 2019):
(P1)
Judgment p is the output of a psychological process that possesses the
empirical property of being substantially influenced by factor F.
(Empirical premise)
11
(P2)
If a judgment is the output of a psychological process that possesses the
empirical property of being substantially influenced by factor F, then it is
pro tanto unreliable. (Bridging normative premise)
(C)
Judgment p is pro tanto unreliable.
3. Triangulation. Divergence among the judgments of various groups of experts
and/or between expert and lay judgments requires the following: adjusting,
pruning, or supplementing the normative conclusions derived from either expert
or lay judgments in order to accommodate: (1) the normative implications of the
opposing views; and (2) normative considerations derived from, for example,
ethical or legal principles, background theories, morally relevant facts, and/or the
best arguments for a normative position in the relevant expert literature (inspired,
in part, by the model of reflective equilibrium, and, in part, by the concept of
triangulation in philosophy of science as detailed in Kuorikoski and Marchionni
2016).
4. Pluralism. In cases where expert and lay stakeholders hold conflicting, yet pro
tanto reliable, judgments, or where multiple and independent communities each
reveal persistent disagreement between two or more conflicting yet pro tanto
reliable judgments, these judgments could all have comparable normative weight;
associated normative conclusions may justifiably be agent- or community-relative
and/or preference-sensitive (inspired by the model of Shared Decision-Making in
clinical contexts as discussed in, e.g., Elwyn et al. 2013; Lewis 2020b).
A. Illustration #1: Parsimony
12
In a recent study (Earp et al., in press), some of us asked participants to consider the case of a
late-stage dementia patient who currently lacks autonomous decision-making capacity. We told
participants that the patient had previously, autonomously signed an advance directive (AD)
instructing the withholding of treatment just in case she fell ill under certain conditions. When
those conditions are fulfilled, however, the patient seems to be living a happy life apart from the
illness, which is described as easily curable. We asked research participants whether the AD
should be followed, and how much they agreed that the dementia patient was “still her true self”
despite the effects of the disease on her personal characteristics.
We found that, among the participants who judged that the patient was still her true self,
almost all of them felt that the AD should be ignored or overridden: that is, they said that the
patient should be treated under the very conditions identified in the AD as sufficient grounds to
withhold treatment.
Some bioethicists argue that the preferences of an autonomous individual at Time 1—as
recorded in an AD—should determine how a non-autonomous individual at Time 2 is treated,
just so long as the individual at Time 1 is the same person as the individual at Time 2 (Buchanan
1988; Buchanan and Brock 1990; see also Dworkin 1993; for a critical discussion of the debate,
see Furberg 2012). Given such a bioethical argument, when we consider the relationship between
intuitions or judgments regarding an AD and judgments of personal identity change, the
empirical result we obtained might seem surprising. First, still being one’s true self at Time 2
(compared to Time 1) includes the concept of being the same person, which suggests that
participants do not perceive simply being the same person between the two time points to be
sufficient for following an AD. Instead, these participants judged that a person can at least
sometimes still be her true self even though she lacks autonomy (i.e., one’s autonomous self and
13
one’s true self can come apart), and that under such conditions, her Time 1 preferences as
recorded in an AD should not necessarily determine how she is treated at Time 2. Indeed, the
participants judged that the patient’s AD should be ignored or overridden despite her having
undergone substantial personal change through neurodegeneration—precisely the situation an
AD is meant to cover.
Of course, much more work will be needed to clarify this finding,iv and to determine how
robust it is across different measures or operationalizations. It may turn out that the apparent
tension between the judgments of ordinary research participants about this case, and those of at
least some philosophers and bioethicists, is illusory, and that—if the case were described
differently, for example—there would be perfect agreement about what should be done in terms
of treatment. But let us assume for the sake of argument that the finding does hold up in future
studies. According to the parsimony strategy for reaching normative conclusions from empirical
findings about people’s morally relevant judgments, we should, in this case, assign at least some
normative weight to the view that dementia patients who still seem like their “true selves” should
be treated under the stated conditions (even if this conflicts with the person’s previously
expressed preferences as recorded in an advance directive).
An immediate objection to this approach is that it may seem to reduce bioethical
reasoning to a popularity contest. The mere fact that a majority of research participants—even
assuming that their views are representative of some wider population of relevant stakeholders—
reach a given moral conclusion about an identity-related case does not entail that this is the
correct, most reasonable, or (otherwise) most justifiable conclusion. Perhaps, after all, it is the
bioethicists and philosophers who have it right, while the laypeople are morally mistaken. In
some cases that may well be true (in which case an error theory may need to be given of why
14
ordinary people are reaching the wrong conclusion). The claim implied by the parsimony
strategy is not that we should rely directly on argumenta ad populum to reach normative
conclusions in bioethics. Rather, the claim is that the experimentally robust, consistent
judgments of ordinary people (or other relevant stakeholders) about a given case or set of cases is
one factor that counts in favor of the moral statement or conclusion embedded in, or entailed by,
those very judgments.
However, this factor alone will never be normatively decisive. For example, if people’s
judgments can be shown to be unreliable using a debunking strategy (see below), or if their
moral concerns are plausibly outweighed by other, competing moral considerations
(triangulation), then it could be reasonable to discount those judgments when deciding what to
do. Simply put, the parsimony approach puts the burden of proof on those who would argue that
no normative weight should be assigned to the consistent judgments of relevant stakeholders
about a given moral issue (Earp et al. 2021a).
B. Illustration #2: Debunking
The parsimony strategy is parsimonious in that it provides the simplest possible model for
deriving normative content from descriptive information about people’s moral judgments. It
holds that these judgments should, defeasibly, be given some normative weight. However,
suppose a researcher is skeptical about the normative conclusion consistently reached by a group
of stakeholders about some case. The researcher might want to engage in a debunking strategy as
outlined earlier, potentially using experimental methods to test whether the moral judgments in
question are the output of a normatively unreliable factor or process. For example, the researcher
might want to see if the judgments are susceptible to framing effects that should have no moral
15
relevance to the issue at hand (but see Demaree-Cotton 2016); or whether, perhaps, they are
influenced by factors that are themselves morally objectionable, such as racial bias or sexist
attitudes.
Consider the moral self effect by way of illustration. As discussed previously, this effect
refers to the tendency of participants to judge that someone who undergoes a significant moral
change—especially moral deterioration—becomes in some sense a different person. As Tobia
(2016) argues, whether someone is seen as undergoing a moral improvement versus a moral
deterioration will, therefore, often have different effects on judgments about their personal
identity persistence; and these effects, in turn, may influence judgments about matters of
bioethical concern. As an example, Tobia refers to an ongoing debate in bioethics concerning the
moral acceptability of cognitive enhancement.
Suppose that, in a society shaped by sexist values, a group of participants consistently
judged that a certain cognitive enhancement procedure (geared toward boosting one’s
intelligence and agency) was less ethically worrisome if pursued by men than if pursued by
women; and suppose this judgment was rooted in the perception that the procedure would be
more threatening to the personal identity of women. Suppose we grant that if a procedure is more
threatening to the personal identity of members of one group compared to another, then this is an
ethically valid reason to object more strongly to its use in the relevant group.
Given the moral self effect, we can imagine a possible explanation for this hypothetical
sex-based discrepancy in judgments: the procedure might be thought to cause greater moral
deterioration in women. This, in turn, could be due to a sexist societal conception of the “moral
woman” as passive, submissive, or (otherwise) lacking in agency (Garcia 2021). Our skeptical
researcher, then, might undertake an experimental study to see whether manipulation of this
16
sexist attitude has the predicted downstream effect on participants’ judgments (i.e., about the
perceived impact of the procedure on personal identity), and, hence, on the relative acceptability
of its use by women as opposed to men.
Of course, the very same stakeholders who might judge that it is worse for women than
for men to engage in cognitive enhancement might disagree with the researcher’s normative
premise, namely, that it is sexist (and therefore wrong) to believe that women ought to be more
“submissive” than men. This raises a simple but important point: the debunking strategy for
drawing normative implications from empirical findings about people’s judgments always
involves one or more normative premises which may themselves be a matter of contestation. As
a result, the form of the argument is necessarily conditional: if you agree with this normative
premise (e.g., that moral judgments rooted in sexist attitudes ought to be discounted, and that the
attitude in question really is sexist), and if the empirical data suggest that this particular moral
judgment is rooted in said attitude, then you should discount the judgment accordingly (i.e.,
assign less normative weight to it).
The point about potential normative disagreements between various stakeholders, and/or
disagreements in moral judgment regarding particular cases, leads to the triangulation strategy,
described next.
C. Illustration #3: Triangulation
The triangulation strategy holds that divergence among the judgments of various individuals or
groups of stakeholders requires the following: adjusting, pruning, or supplementing the
normative conclusions derived from the competing positions in order to accommodate: (1) the
normative implications of the opposing view(s); and (2) normative considerations derived from,
17
for example, ethical or legal principles, background theories, morally relevant facts, and/or the
best arguments for a normative position in the relevant expert literature (Earp et al. 2021a). To
illustrate this strategy, we will refer to recent work conducted by Dranseika and colleagues
(unpublished) on judgments about the right of study participants to withdraw from research after
undergoing significant personal change.
The study builds on earlier findings from Tobia (2016), who asked participants to
consider the case of a man who enrolls in a research study and then suffers a terrible accident, as
a result of which he experiences (depending on the experimental condition) either moral
improvement or moral deterioration. Tobia asked participants whether the morally changed man
should be allowed to have the research study data, which had already been collected before the
moral change, destroyed. Participants tended to judge that the morally deteriorated research
subject should be denied the right to destroy his data, whereas the morally improved research
subject retained the right.
In addition to probing the intuitions of ordinary citizens about Tobia’s case, Dranseika
and colleagues’ cross-cultural replication study included a group of lawyers, whose judgment is
especially consequential in real-world decisions involving legal rights. Potentially owing to a
legal concept of personhood, lawyers from different countries revealed a distinct pattern of moral
judgments: though they were still susceptible to the basic effect (i.e., asymmetry in judgments
between conditions), lawyers tended to ascribe identity persistence overall, regardless of the
subject’s direction of moral change. Thus, at a broad level, Dranseika and colleagues find that
(one of)v the lay intuition(s) regarding personal identity is morally laden in a wide range of
cultures, whereas among lawyers, the concept of identity is not equally affected by the same
moral considerations.
18
Put another way, laypeople demonstrated a paternalistic attitude toward the hypothetical
research subject, willing to deny that an individual who underwent moral deterioration retained
the right to withdraw from research. This attitude conflicted with the legally informed opinion of
lawyers, who were more likely to protect the right to withdraw from research in the same
situation. When adopting the triangulation strategy, we would begin by acknowledging the
divergence in judgments between stakeholder groups (in this case, lawyers and ordinary
citizens); and, at least tentatively, assume that the application of either judgment is not
straightforwardly amenable to debunking (i.e., both judgments are pro tanto reliable). The
triangulation approach presents a possible pathway toward prescriptive insights in circumstances
like this.vi
In relation to the current example, it may be the case that the judgments of lay
participants concerning a change in personal identity drive their judgments regarding the right to
withdraw from research. If there is good reason to think that a legal conception of personal
identity or associated rights should control in such a context, the public might need to be
educated so as to clarify, or remedy confusions in, their conception as it bears on the legal right.
Alternatively, consideration of lay judgments might lead us to conclude that the legal
concept of identity is not fit for purpose when applied to the question of research subjects’ right
to withdraw. In such a case, we might advocate stakeholder-motivated “conceptual engineering”
in law, as has been done with respect to certain concepts in clinical medicine (see, e.g.,
McMillan 2018; Lewis 2020a).
D. Illustration #4: Pluralism
19
The pluralist solution to normative inference differs fundamentally from the previous three
approaches. Let us suppose that existing empirical studies reveal substantial disagreement on
questions of personal identity and/or associated moral implications, and, further, that follow-up
evidence does not provide a reason to deem either judgment normatively unreliable (i.e., in a
way that would help to establish a debunking argument). Furthermore, perhaps other normative
considerations (justice, autonomy, etc.) also fail to support one view over the other. In
circumstances like this, empirical evidence may lend itself to a different normative inference
strategy: the pluralist approach. This approach holds that in certain cases of two or more
conflicting, yet pro tanto reliable, judgments between stakeholders, multiple judgments may be
reasonably assigned comparable normative weight.
Here is an example. An important bioethical issue involving judgments about personal
identity persistence over time is the set of criteria that should be used to determine whether
someone has died. Consider a recent study by Neiders and Dranseika (2020), in which they
asked participants to express their preference for the stage in the process of dying at which their
death should be declared by healthcare practitioners. To support conditions for the prima facie
normative credibility of participants’ judgments, three of the stages from which participants
could choose mimicked three expert conceptions of death in the bioethics literature: higher-brain
death, whole-brain death, and cardiopulmonary death.
In terms of expert judgment, there is more than one medically and ethically reasonable
option, which suggests that decisions regarding death determination are, at least in part,
preference or goal sensitive (Veatch and Ross 2016). In other words, which concept of death we
should use may depend on our values or aims. Furthermore, the data gathered by Neiders and
Dranseika (2020) reveal different preferences concerning death determination criteria among
20
study participants. Taken together, the diversity of opinion among experts and laypeople alike
may support a pluralistic approach to death determination, according to which individuals should
be allowed to choose—among reasonable options—what criterion will be applied in the case of
their own death.
V. Two More Examples
In the previous section, we reviewed four strategies for reaching normative conclusions in
bioethics (in part) from experimental findings about stakeholders’ moral judgments concerning
identity-related cases. However, the examples we used cover just some of the topics being studied
in this area. To give a sense of the wider set of issues of potential interest to bioxphi, we will
explore two more interventions that have received considerable bioethical attention, and which
have potential implications for personal identity: deep brain stimulation and moral enhancement.
A. Deep Brain Stimulation
In recent work, Skorburg and Sinnott-Armstrong (2020) explored a bioxphi approach to personal
identity and deep brain stimulation (DBS). DBS involves a surgically implanted, batteryoperated device which delivers targeted electrical stimulation to a specific brain region. The most
common application of DBS is in the treatment of Parkinson’s disease. At least 200,000 people
worldwide live with neural implants for Parkinson’s and related conditions.
Many patients have reported significant changes to their identity after DBS. For example,
Schüpbach and colleagues (2006) found that in a population of twenty-nine patients undergoing
DBS for Parkinson’s, most reported improvements in motor symptoms, activities of daily living,
and quality of life. However, two-thirds expressed feelings of estrangement and unfamiliarity
21
with themselves, saying things like “I don’t feel like myself anymore,” and “I haven’t found
myself again after the operation” (2006: 1813). In another study, by contrast, patients who
underwent DBS for Obsessive Compulsive Disorder or Treatment Resistant Depression reported
feeling like themselves but without depression, and feeling “back to” themselves, “back to sort of
a baseline” (Klein et al. 2016: 144).
These kinds of case reports raise the question of whether, or in what sense, DBS changes
a person’s identity. We do not take a stand on this metaphysical question here (but see Gilbert et
al. 2018, for some important criticisms of the claim that DBS threatens identity). Instead, we
want to point out that perhaps the central issue in these ongoing debates is, according to Witt and
colleagues (2013: 501), “an explication of what we mean when judging that someone has
become ‘another person.’” Bioxphi could contribute to this project by manipulating key elements
of a hypothetical DBS/change case and measuring the effect of these manipulations on
judgments of personal identity across multiple operationalizations of the concept. This would
allow for an assessment of which specific senses of personal identity (Dranseika 2017) are at
play in debates about DBS-induced personal changes.
The real-life phenomenon of post-DBS personal changes provides a good example of the
kind of ecologically valid case that bioxphi seeks to study. In turn, the bioxphi of personal
identity could guide the construction of new forms of assessment of technologies like DBS.
Given the moral self effect, for example, assessment of the moral attributes of patients before
and after undergoing neurostimulation could shed light on what leads patients or their families to
say, “they’re not the same person anymore.”
B. Moral Enhancement
22
The bioxphi of personal identity is also relevant to ongoing debates about moral enhancement.
One argument holds that human psychology is ill-equipped to deal with the breakneck speed of
recent technological developments and the pressing existential risks that they engender (climate
change, nuclear weapons, artificial intelligence, and so on). As a result, proponents argue that
(biomedical) enhancement of moral traits may be required in order to adequately address these
and other issues (Persson and Savulescu 2012). Setting aside the many nuances of these debates,
it is worth highlighting that worries about identity change have figured prominently in the
enhancement literature from the outset (e.g., Douglas 2008). More specifically, the worry is that
enhancing some trait(s) might threaten the psychological continuity often thought to be
constitutive of personal identity.
As we noted earlier, much recent work in x-phi has treated these kinds of questions as
empirical ones. The evidence we described on the moral self effect sheds light on which traits are
more likely to be viewed as constitutive of identity, how the direction of change in these traits
might alter judgments of identity change, and how different contexts shape these judgments. A
recent paper by Fabiano (2021) explicitly connects this research program with the moral
enhancement literature. He argues that one way to preserve, or even strengthen, the kinds of
psychological relations constitutive of personal identity is “to focus on enhancing virtue because
virtue and personal identity are often deeply connected. The relationship between virtue and
personal identity is evidenced by the fact that many concepts of virtue are intimately related to
personal identity” (2021: 95). Fabiano claims that much of the evidence we discussed in this
chapter supports this conclusion. Whether or not virtues are indeed an appropriate target of moral
enhancement, we contend that bioxphi approaches to personal identity may meaningfully
contribute to these long-standing debates in bioethics.
23
VI. Conclusion and Future Directions
In healthcare or biomedical research contexts, judgments about whether a patient or participant is
the same person matter, and they have real-world implications that rarely arise in armchair
contexts. Rights, liberty, consent, autonomy, specific care decisions, social support, and
educational interventions are all potentially at stake. We do not claim that bioxphi can establish
or even seeks to establish a final theory of personal identity, including how personal identity
should be understood in various contexts or with respect to certain ends. Nor do we claim that
bioxphi can provide definitive answers to how patients or research participants should be treated
when changes to their personal identity are judged to have occurred.
Our vision for the bioxphi of personal identity is more modest. Through examples
discussed both here and in the burgeoning literature, we can see that this emerging discipline, at
least relative to traditional approaches to analytic philosophy and x-phi, is in a better position to
support ethical decision-making in healthcare-related contexts. This is because bioxphi seeks to
understand the factors that influence judgments regarding personal identity in real-world
settings: factors that include addiction, the effects of neurosurgical procedures such as DBS, and
the decline of cognitive function associated with certain disorders. And it seeks to understand
these factors in such a way that the resulting empirical data can be used to support normative
arguments.
In attempting to establish, for example, whether stakeholder judgments are pro tanto
(un)reliable, bioxphi approaches to personal identity can bring empirical data into the service of
reaching normative conclusions that are of significance to healthcare practice and policy. As we
have seen, these conclusions can relate to, for example, the conditions under which advance
24
directives should be respected or ignored, the specification and enactment of the right to
withdraw from research, and the development of therapeutic interventions for people with
substance abuse disorders.
The strategies that we have discussed for developing normative inferences from premises
that include empirical content are not exhaustive nor should this chapter be viewed as defending
any single approach. Furthermore, while bioxphi studies have relied on the employment of the
CVT, proponents of x-phi have argued that we should seek to employ the full range of
experimental methods used in the psychosocial sciences, in combination with non-experimental
approaches, such as interviews, qualitative studies, studies of linguistic corpus data, and
anthropological work (O’Neill and Machery 2014; Alfano et al. 2018; Nado 2021). We think this
lesson can be applied to bioxphi as well.
Another way in which research in this area could benefit is by expanding the boundaries
of how personal identity is conceived. So far, much of the attention has been on psychological
continuity, memories, the self-contained body, or the metaphysically distinct person. In broad
terms, the focus has been on “brains and bodies” (Tobia 2016). However, it is increasingly
recognized that the self and identity are not only diachronic but also relational (e.g., Mackenzie
and Stoljar 2000; Christman 2004; Meyers 2005; Earp et al. 2021b). Therefore, rather than
focusing so exclusively on a liberal conception of the self as a rational, reflective, and unitary
entity, future bioxphi research on personal identity could consider more relational approaches to
identity that take into account how the self is shaped or even constituted by social and
interpersonal relations, structures, and processes (Andersen & Chen 2002).
Persons are socially embedded. When social norms and interpersonal ways of relating are
internalized, “this contributes to the individual’s identity, and thus the identity of the self-as-
25
social is invested in a community and its cultural heritage” (Meyers 2005: 29-30). This suggests
that judgments regarding a change in one’s personal identity or that of a close friend or family
member may be causally affected by interpersonal relations and the social environment. The
psychologically continuous, reflective, and embodied self cannot be isolated from its socialrelational situatedness (Lewis 2021).
Consequently, interpersonal relations and social structures can support or impair not only
perceptions of personal identity continuity but also cognitive and moral capacities, character
traits, and other qualities relevant to such perceptions (Tobia 2016; Lewis 2021; Veit et al. 2021).
Doubts that an individual is the same person can arise “not only because of internal factors such
as illness, depression, addiction, anxiety and fatigue, but also on the basis of external causal
factors such as brainwashing, internalised oppression, stigmatisation, disrespect or inappropriate
normative expectations resulting from previous encounters with overly paternalistic, demeaning
or pressurising institutional practices” (Lewis 2021: 20).
These effects on judgments regarding personal identity are contingent rather than
necessary, meaning that whether a specific individual experiences these effects will, ultimately,
depend on their psychological states and dispositions, which, in part, constitute their identity. As
a concluding thought, we suggest that the bioxphi of personal identity should explore the effects
of interpersonal relationships and social situations on judgments regarding personal identity
change and the moral relevance of these social-relational factors.
26
References
0. Andersen, S. M., & Chen, S. (2002). The relational self: an interpersonal social-cognitive
theory. Psychological Review, 109(4), 619-645.
1. Alfano, M., D. Loeb and A. Plakias (2018). “Experimental Moral Philosophy.” In E. N. Zalta
(ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online:
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/experimental-moral/ (accessed October 26,
2021).
2. Blok, S., G. Newman and L. J. Rips (2005). “Individuals and their Concepts.” In W. Ahn, R.
L. Goldstone, B. C. Love, A. B. Markman and P. Wolff (eds.), Categorization Inside and
Outside the Laboratory: Essays in Honor of Douglas L. Medin, 127–49. Washington: American
Psychological Association.
3. Buchanan, A. (1988). “Advance Directives and the Personal Identity Problem.” Philosophy &
Public Affairs, 17 (4): 277–302.
4. Buchanan, A. and D. Brock (1990). Deciding for Others. The Ethics of Surrogate Decision
Making. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
5. Cath, Y. (2016). “Reflective Equilibrium.” In H. Cappelen, T. S. Gendler and J. Hawthorn
(eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology, 213–30. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
6. Christman, J. (2004). “Relational Autonomy, Liberal Individualism and the Social
Constitution of Selves.” Philosophical Studies, 117 (1/2): 143–64.
7. Davies, R., J. Ives and M. Dunn (2015). “A Systematic Review of Empirical Bioethics
Methodologies.” BMC Medical Ethics, 16 (15): 1–13.
8. Demaree-Cotton, J. (2016). “Do Framing Effects Make Moral Intuitions Unreliable?”
Philosophical Psychology, 29 (1): 1–22.
9. Douglas, T. (2008). “Moral Enhancement.” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 25 (3): 228–45.
10. Dranseika, V. (2017). “On the Ambiguity of ‘the Same Person’.” AJOB Neuroscience, 8 (3):
184–6.
11. Dranseika, V., I. R. Hannikainen, P. Bystranowski, B. D. Earp, K. P. Tobia, G. Almeida, K.
Kneer, N. Struchiner, K. Dolinina, B. Janik, E. Lauraityte, A. Liefgreen, M. Prochnicki, A.
Rosas, N. Strohmaier and T. Żuradzki. (unpublished manuscript). "Personal Identity, Direction
of Change, and the Right to Withdraw from Research."
12. Dworkin, R. (1993). Life’s Dominion. An Argument about Abortion and Euthanasia. London:
Harper Collins.
13. Earp, B. D., I. Hannikainen, S. Dale and S. Latham (in press). “Experimental Philosophical
Bioethics, Advance Directives, and the True Self in Dementia.” In A. De Block and K. Hens
(eds.), Experimental Philosophy of Medicine. London: Bloomsbury.
14. Earp, B. D., J. A. Skorburg, J. A. Everett and J. Savulescu (2019). “Addiction, Identity,
Morality.” AJOB Empirical Bioethics, 10 (2): 136–53.
15. Earp, B. D., J. Demaree-Cotton, M. Dunn, V. Dranseika, J. A. C. Everett, A. Feltz, G. Geller,
I. Hannikainen, L. A. Jansen, J. Knobe, J. Kolak, S. Latham, A. Lerner, J. May, M. Mercurio, E.
Mihailov, D. Rodríguez-Arias, B. Rodríguez López, J. Savulescu, M. Sheehan, N. Strohminger,
J. Sugarman, K. Tabb and K. P. Tobia (2020a). “Experimental Philosophical Bioethics.” AJOB
Empirical Bioethics, 11 (1): 30–3.
27
16. Earp, B. D., S. R. Latham and K. P. Tobia (2020b). “Personal Transformation and Advance
Directives: An Experimental Bioethics Approach.” The American Journal of Bioethics, 20 (8):
72–5.
17. Earp, B. D., J. Lewis, V. Dranseika and I. Hannikainen (2021a). “Experimental Philosophical
Bioethics and Normative Inference.” Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 42 (3-4): 91-111.
18. Earp, B. D., K. L. McLoughlin, J. T. Monrad, M. S. Clark and M. J. Crockett (2021b). “How
Social Relationships Shape Moral Wrongness Judgments.” Nature Communications, 12 (5776):
1–13 .
19. Elwyn, G., J. Tilburt and V. Montori (2013). “The Ethical Imperative for Shared DecisionMaking.” European Journal for Person Centered Healthcare, 1: 129–31.
20. Fabiano, J. (2021). “Virtue Theory for Moral Enhancement.” AJOB Neuroscience, 12 (2–
3): 89–102.
21. Fisher, J. C. (2015). “Pragmatic Experimental Philosophy.” Philosophical Psychology, 28
(3): 412–33.
22. Furberg, E. (2012). “Advance Directives and Personal Identity: What is the Problem?” The
Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 37 (1): 60–73.
23. Garcia, M. (2021). We Are Not Born Submissive: How Patriarchy Shapes Women's Lives.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
24. Gilbert, F., J. Viaña and C. Ineichen (2018). “Deflating the ‘DBS Causes Personality
Changes’ Bubble.” Neuroethics, 14 (1): 1–17.
25. Hart, C. L. (2021). Drug Use for Grown-Ups: Chasing Liberty in the Land of Fear. New
York: Penguin.
26. Henrich, J., S. J. Heine and A. Norenzayan (2010). “Most People are not WEIRD.” Nature,
466 (7302): 29.
27. Kagan, S. (2001). “Thinking about Cases.” Social Philosophy and Policy, 18 (2): 44–63.
28. Klein, E., S. Goering, J. Gagne, C. V. Shea, R. Franklin, S. Zorowitz, ... A. S. Widge (2016).
“Brain-Computer Interface-Based Control of Closed-Loop Brain Stimulation: Attitudes and
Ethical Considerations.” Brain-Computer Interfaces, 3 (3): 140–8.
29. Klenk, M. (2020). “Charting Moral Psychology’s Significance for Bioethics: Routes to
Bioethical Progress, its Limits, and Lessons from Moral Philosophy.” Diametros, 17 (64): 36–
55.
30. Knobe, J. (2007). “Experimental Philosophy.” Philosophy Compass, 2 (1): 81–92.
31. Knobe, J. (2016). “Experimental Philosophy is Cognitive Science.” In J. Sytsma and W.
Buckwalter (eds.), A Companion to Experimental Philosophy, 37–52. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
32. Knobe, J. (2019a). “Philosophical Intuitions are Surprisingly Robust Across Demographic
Differences.” Epistemology & Philosophy of Science, 56 (2): 29–36.
33. Knobe, J. (2019b). “Difference and Robustness in the Patterns of Philosophical Intuition
across Demographic Groups.” Unpublished manuscript. Available online: https://cpb-usw2.wpmucdn.com/campuspress.yale.edu/dist/3/1454/files/2019/12/Difference-Robustness-2.pdf
(accessed October 26, 2021).
34. Knobe, J. (2022). “Personal Identity and Dual Character.” In K. P. Tobia (ed.), Experimental
Philosophy of Identity and the Self. London: Bloomsbury.
35. Knobe, J., W. Buckwalter, S. Nichols, P. Robbins, H. Sarkissian and T. Sommers (2012).
“Experimental Philosophy.” Annual Review of Psychology, 63: 81–99.
36. Kuorikoski, J. and C. Marchionni (2016). “Evidential Diversity and the Triangulation of
Phenomena.” Philosophy of Science, 83 (2): 227–47.
28
37. Lewis, J. (2020a). “From X-phi to Bioxphi: Lessons in Conceptual Analysis 2.0.” AJOB
Empirical Bioethics, 11 (1): 34–6.
38. Lewis, J. (2020b). “Getting Obligations Right: Autonomy and Shared Decision Making.”
Journal of Applied Philosophy, 37 (1): 118–40.
39. Lewis, J. (2021). “Autonomy and the Limits of Cognitive Enhancement.” Bioethics, 35 (1):
15–22.
40. Locke, J. (1689/1694). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. P. H. Nidditch (ed.).
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975.
41. Machery, E. (2017). Philosophy Within its Proper Bounds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
42. Machery, E. and S. Stich (2019). “Demographic Differences in Philosophical Intuition: A
Reply to Joshua Knobe.” Unpublished manuscript. Available online:
https://www.dropbox.com/s/flndq44xjtyrsyi/Reply%20to%20Knobe%20-%20Demographic%20Difference%20in%20Philosophical%20Intuition%20-%2011-32019.docx?dl=0 (accessed October 26, 2021).
43. Mackenzie, C. and N. Stoljar (2000). “Autonomy Refigured.” In C. Mackenzie and N. Stoljar
(eds.), Relational autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, 3–
31. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
44. McMillan, J. (2018). The Methods of Bioethics: An Essay in Meta-Bioethics. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
45. Meyers, D. T. (2005). “Decentralizing Autonomy: Five Faces of Selfhood.” In J. Christman
and J. Anderson (eds.), Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays, 27–55.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
46. Mihailov, E., I. R. Hannikainen and B. D. Earp (2021). “Advancing Methods in Empirical
Bioethics: Bioxphi Meets Digital Technologies.” The American Journal of Bioethics, 21 (6): 53–
6.
47. Mukerji, N. (2019). Experimental Philosophy: A Critical Study. London: Rowman &
Littlefield.
48. Nado, J. (2021). “Conceptual Engineering Via Experimental Philosophy.” Inquiry, 64 (1–
2): 76–96.
49. Neiders, I. and V. Dranseika (2020). “Minds, Brains, and Hearts: an Empirical Study on
Pluralism Concerning Death Determination.” Monash Bioethics Review, 38 (1): 35–48.
50. Nichols, S. and M. Bruno (2010). “Intuitions about Personal Identity: An Empirical Study.”
Philosophical Psychology, 23 (3): 293–312.
51. O’Neill, E. and E. Machery (2014). “Experimental Philosophy: What is it Good For?” In E.
Machery and E. O’Neill (eds.), Current Controversies in Experimental Philosophy, vii–xxix.
London: Routledge.
52. Persson, I. and J. Savulescu (2012). Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
53. Prinz, J. J. and S. Nichols (2016). “Diachronic Identity and the Moral Self.” In J. Kiverstein
(ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of the Social Mind, 465–80. London: Routledge.
54. Reid, T. (1785/1969). Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
55. Reiner, P. B. (2019). “Experimental Neuroethics.” In S. K. Nagel (ed.), Shaping Children:
Ethical and Social Questions That Arise When Enhancing the Young, 75–83. Cham: Springer.
29
58. Schlegel, R. J. and J. A. Hicks (2011). “The True Self and Psychological Health: Emerging
Evidence and Future Directions.” Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 5 (12): 989–
1003.
56. Schlegel, R. J., J. A. Hicks, J. Arndt and L. A. King (2009). “Thine Own Self: True SelfConcept Accessibility and Meaning in Life.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96
(2): 473–90.
57. Schlegel, R. J., J. A. Hicks, L. A. King and J. Arndt (2011). “Feeling Like You Know Who
You Are: Perceived True Self-Knowledge and Meaning in Life.” Personality & Social
Psychology Bulletin, 37 (6): 745–56.
59. Schüpbach, M., M. Gargiulo, M. L. Welter, L. Mallet, C. Béhar, J. L. Houeto, D. Maltête, V.
Mesnage and Y. Agid (2006). “Neurosurgery in Parkinson disease: a Distressed Mind in a
Repaired Body?” Neurology, 66 (12): 1811–16.
60. Shoemaker, D. (2010). “The Insignificance of Personal Identity for Bioethics.” Bioethics, 24
(9): 481–9.
61. Skorburg, J. A. and W. Sinnott-Armstrong (2020). “Some Ethics of Deep Brain Stimulation.”
In D. Stein and I. Singh (eds.), Global Mental Health and Neuroethics, 117–32. London:
Academic Press.
62. Strohminger, N. and S. Nichols (2014). “The Essential Moral Self.” Cognition, 131 (1): 159–
71.
63. Strohminger, N. and S. Nichols (2015). “Neurodegeneration and Identity.” Psychological
Science, 26 (9): 1469–79.
64. Thomson, J. J. (1986). Rights, Restitution, and Risk. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
65. Tobia, K. P. (2015). “Personal Identity and the Phineas Gage Effect.” Analysis, 75 (3): 396–
405.
66. Tobia, K. P. (2016). “Personal Identity, Direction of Change, and Neuroethics.”
Neuroethics, 9 (1): 37–43.
67. Tobia, K. P. (2017). “Change Becomes You.” Aeon. Available online:
https://aeon.co/essays/to-be-true-to-ones-self-means-changing-to-become-that-self (accessed
October 26, 2021).
68. Veatch, R. M. and L. F. Ross (2016). Defining Death: The Case for Choice. Washington:
Georgetown University Press.
69. Veit, W., B. D. Earp, H. Browning and J. Savulescu (2021). “Evaluating Trade-Offs Between
Autonomy and Well-Being in Supported Decision Making.” American Journal of Bioethics, 21
(11): 21-24.
70. Wedgwood, R. (2007). The Nature of Normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
71. Wilkes, K. V. (1988). Real People: Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
72. Williams, B. (1970). “The Self and the Future.” The Philosophical Review, 79 (2): 161–80.
73. Witt, K., J. Kuhn, L. Timmermann, M. Zurowski and C. Woopen (2013). “Deep Brain
Stimulation and the Search for Identity.” Neuroethics, 6 (3): 49–511.
30
i
We are immensely grateful to Joshua Knobe and Kevin Tobia for their invaluable comments and suggestions
during the writing process, and we wish to thank Kevin for inviting us to contribute to this collected edition.
i
For a critique of the philosopher’s “thought-experiment” approach to questions concerned with personal identity,
see Wilkes (1988).
ii
For a critique of the philosopher’s “thought-experiment” approach to questions concerned with personal identity,
see Wilkes (1988).
iii
For a broader debate regarding whether intuitions vary across demographic groups in general, see Knobe (2019a);
Machery and Stich (2019); Knobe (2019b).
iv
See Earp et al. (in press) for details of a follow-up study.
v
See Knobe (2022) for a discussion of personal identity as a “dual character” concept, suggesting that, even among
ordinary people, there may be different concepts of personal identity at play.
vi
However, as with the debunking strategy, the path to a single normative conclusion about what to do in such an
instance is not straightforward. When attitudes are, for example, diametrically opposed, triangulation may not be as
simple as adjusting or supplementing two or more pro tanto reliable judgments in order to achieve some sort of
compromise. Instead, one might need to employ a model of “wide” reflective equilibrium (for discussion, see Earp
et al. 2021a). The aim here would be to achieve as much coherence as possible (given the data and information
available at the time) between not only the conflicting judgments in question, but also, for example, background
theories, legal or philosophical principles, morally relevant facts, etc. (Cath 2016).
31