Catholic Values and
Australian Realities
James Franklin
BACK OF THE COVER
Catholic Values and
Australian Realities
James Franklin
BALLAN, VI CTORI A
First Published 2006 Connor Court Publishing Pt y Lt d
Copyright ( c) 2006 Jam es Franklin
All right s reserved
Connor Court Publishing Pt y Lt d
PO Box 967
Bacchus Marsh VI C 3340
Phone/ Fax ( 03) 5368 2570
ant hony@connorcourt .com .au
www.connorcourt .com .au
I SBN 0- 9758015- 4- 6
Cover by Connor Court Publishing
Cov er phot o: St . John's College fet e 1960, Cam pbellt own,
Aust ralian Phot ographic Agency ( APA) Collect ion:
Sydney people, places and event s, 1953- 1987,
St at e Library of New Sout h Wales, used wit h perm ission.
This book does not hav e any official endorsem ent by t he Cat holic
Church
Print ed in Aust ralia by Openbook Print , Sout h Aust ralia
CON TEN TS
1
I nt roduct ion
.
PART 1 : A D I STI N CTI VE AUSTRALI AN N ESS
3
1
Cat holics Versus Masons
2
Cat holic Thought and Cat holic Act ion:
Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
23
3
I m m igrat ion Versus Dem ocracy
47
4
Cat holic Schooldays w it h Philosophy
51
5
Cam pion’s Aust ralian Cat holics
57
6
Sant am aria’s European Sensibilit y
63
PART 2 : CATH OLI C VALUES N OW
7
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy:
Baby and Bat hwat er
65
8
Secular Versus Cat holic Concept ions of
Values in Aust ralian Educat ion
83
9
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
97
10 The Mabo High Court and Nat ural Law Values
115
11 I s Jensenism Com pat ible w it h Christ ianit y?
129
12 St ove, Hum e, and Enlight enm ent
135
I ndex
139
I nt roduct ion
A
USTRALIAN CATHOLICS have had a distinct “image”:
Irish tribal loyalties, Labor but anti-communist politics,
childhoods full of guilt and incense. There is more to their
distinctiveness than that. Their central contribution to Australian
thinking is an objective view of ethics. Ethics, Catholics believe,
is not a matter of the tribal mores a society happens to have
developed, nor is it an arbitrary command of God (or of our genes).
Instead, what is right and just is inherent in the way things are.
Because human beings are human beings, serious injustice to them
is an outrage, a violation of the order of the universe (ch. 7 below).
That perspective, explicitly or implicitly, has been behind the
unique Catholic contributions to Australian life described in this
book. A commitment to the inherent equality in the worth of
persons was behind the Mabo decision of the Catholic-dominated
High Court, which declared that aborigines had rights in land
that could not be ignored by the white colonisers (ch. 10). Similar
views were behind the Catholic view of the 1940s on immigration,
which held that refugees in war-torn Europe had some right to
Australia’s unused spaces (as well as being good for Australia) (ch.
3). On more detailed matters too, such as compensation for loss,
objective values based on the worth of persons are not vague
motherhood statements but provide a recipe for calculating rights
and exactly determining what ought to be done (ch. 9). The
untiring anti-communist organising of Dr Ryan (ch. 2) and B.A.
Santamaria (ch. 6) reflected not only knowledge of Stalinist
atrocities, but a presumption that a materialist philosophy like
Leninism could only result in a view of humans as expendable, fit
only to be shovelled into mass graves if they were not on the side
of “history”. To a lesser degree, Catholics were suspicious of the
1
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
ruling secular ideology of Australia and so maintained at great
expense their own school system with its distinctive values founded
ultimately on its objective ethical philosophy (chs. 4, 8). If
Freemasonry was a godless ideology, as Catholics believed, not
entirely correctly (ch. 1), then it was certainly unsatisfactory if
society in general and the school system in particular were
dominated by Freemasons. Catholics were equally suspicious of
evangelical Christianity which, they believed, replaced “in
accordance with the nature of things” in ethics with an ungrounded
and simplistic “the Bible says” (ch. 11).
This book is partisan. Though it contains history done fairly
as history ought to be, and arguments with a fair view of both
sides, the overall pattern points to a conclusion. If Australian
Catholics are to make the contribution they should to the Australia
of the new century, they need to understand the theory and practice
of what was done before. The Catholics of Australia had energy
because they knew where they were going. Let us understand what
they did and do likewise.
There are some important issues hardly treated in the book.
One is Catholic religious life – prayer, the Bible, liturgy, theology,
charity work and the other activities of the institutional Church.
Those are crucial, obviously, in understanding Catholics and their
values. But this book concentrates on a single basic issue, an ethical
one that can be understood by Australians who do not share
Catholic beliefs. It is natural for an outsider to respond to rosaries
and novenas with “just not my tradition”. It is not so easy to avoid
serious thinking about whether persons have intrinsic moral worth.
A second topic not dealt with here is the sexual abuse scandals
that have disfigured the reputation of the institutional Church. It
used to be thought that Catholics had somewhat exaggerated the
seriousness and objective wrongness of sexual sins and that less
guilt all round would be liberating. The scandals confirmed – not
in the way Catholics would have wished, but confirmed
nonetheless – that, for some of those sins at least, they were
absolutely right.
2
CH APTER ON E
Ca t holics Versus M a sons
A
S IS WELL KNOWN, one of the most significant
events in Australian Catholic history was the
withdrawal of state aid to Church schools late last century.
In 1880 in New South Wales, and at similar times in other parts of
Australia, the State Governments set up systems of ‘free, secular
and compulsory’ schools, and at the same time withdrew aid they
had paid to the Schools of the various churches. The Catholic
Church maintained its system at great expense, at the same time
as Catholics paid taxes for state schools. That situation lasted for
ninety years, and defined the shape of Australian education
thereafter, dividing Australian youth into three categories: those
in private schools, usually run by a Protestant Church, those in
Catholic schools, and the majority in the secular State school
system. It was one of the main reasons for the distinctiveness of
Australian Catholic culture.
The high point of the Catholics’ struggle against the withdrawal
of State aid came with Archbishop Vaughan’s First Pastoral on
education, attacking Henry Parkes’ plan for a free and secular
school system. Education without religion, Vaughan maintained,
Original source: Journal of the Australian Catholic Historical Society 20 (1999), pp. 1-15.
3
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
was impossible in principle. It was, he said, ‘a system of practical
paganism, which leads to corruption of morals and loss of faith, to
national effeminacy and to national dishonour’ and – in a phrase
that caused particular offence – the existing state schools were
‘seedplots of future immorality, infidelity and lawlessness, being
calculated to debase the standard of human excellence, and to
1
corrupt the political, social and individual life of future citizens.’
His extreme remarks caused a great deal of indignation in Protestant
circles.
So much is well-known. What is not so familiar is what Vaughan
thought about the enemy he was facing.
Va u gh a n a n d t h e M a son ic con spir a cy
t he or y
On 9 October 1876, he gave a speech on what he believed was
really behind the campaign for secular education, later printed as
a pamphlet called ‘Hidden Springs’. It is one of the great conspiracy
theories, combined with a vision of grand conflict of philosophical
systems. The three main currents of thought, he says, are Paganism,
Supernaturalism and Materialism. Paganism, whose ‘hidden spring’
is man’s animal passion, as shown by the gross immoralities of the
gods of Olympus, belongs to the past. The future, unfortunately,
may belong to Materialism; the threat is so great that the Catholic
and Protestant churches need to co-operate against it. But Vaughan
does not see Materialism as just a way of thinking into which it is
natural to fall when religion begins to seem less plausible. It would
soon disappear, he says, if it were not being ceaselessly revivified
by its own hidden spring. ‘The Hidden Spring of Materialism is
centred in, and derives its main energy from the Sect, the Church
of the Revolution, the International Secret Society, which is
weaving its network around the world’, that is, Freemasonry.
Promoting a Voltairean gospel of ‘absolute toleration’, its real
programme is deicide, and the deification of humanity. ‘The Sect
fixes savagely on one dogma of its own, whilst gnashing its teeth
at all dogmas, it is this, viz., that absolute liberty and unlimited
4
Cat holics Versus Masons
freedom to do, say, or think anything he likes, is the natural and
inalienable right of every man.’ It is true that ordinary Masons do
not know of the plots of the inner circle, and are often men of
character, even dukes, but such men are ‘paraded before the world,
that the world may be reassured, that, a blind oath of secrecy
notwithstanding, little harm could attach to a Craft, however secret,
so long as Dukes and Lords, and men of large estate, and of high
character were members of it. How could that Society be subversive
of the throne, which is patronised by Royalty itself?’ But the truth
is otherwise. ‘The Altar, the Throne, Civil Society as at present
constituted, are, under the action of its breath, to melt down into
an International Communism, when the impossible equality of
all men shall be achieved, when the Almighty God, and,
consequently, dogma and Christian morality shall be expunged.’
Earlier, the Masons sneaked out of their lodges to foment the
Revolutions of 1789, 1830 and 1848. But now they have a new
plan. Spreading from Belgium is an ‘Education League’, and Masons
around the world are now to rally behind their campaign. ‘Its
watchword or war-cry is “Universal Secular, Free and Compulsory
2
Education”.’
This outburst raises a number of questions. The first one is, is
it true? Was Freemasonry an international communist conspiracy,
plotting revolutions and the downfall of the Church, and secular
education in New South Wales? If not, who were the Masons,
why did the Catholic Church find itself in conflict with them,
and what is the relation of that conflict to job discrimination against
Catholics in the 1930s?
No, it is not true. Not of Australia, at least. Freemasonry was
not an atheist communist plot. An answer on behalf of the Masons
was written by Wazir Beg, earlier a Muslim of Poona but at this
period a Presbyterian minister in Redfern and editor of both the
3
Freemason and the Orangeman. His reply to Vaughan denies the
charges of atheism, immorality and disloyalty. Masonry inculcates
a ‘rigorous morality’ – without dispensations or indulgences – and
it is hardly likely that Masonry intends to subvert the State when
the last King and the present heir to the throne are not merely
5
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
4
members, but Grand Masters. Beg is right: the idea of an
international communist conspiracy led by royalty is ridiculous.
All the same, Vaughan is not exactly making his theory up out
of thin air. Nor is he alone. To understand what was happening
we need to look at the situation in Europe on a long time scale.
The Masonic conspiracy theory is part of a plot theory that
had wide appeal for the European political right from the time of
the French Revolution to the Second World War. The principals
in the supposed world conspiracy varied: Masons, Jews, Liberals,
5
Socialists, but the linking idea was that a world conspiracy of some
or all these was behind all revolutions real and potential, and all
anticlericalism. The Masonic plot theory came first. It appeared
in the Abbé Barruel’s Memoirs Illustrating the History of Jacobinism of
1797, which claimed to expose the French Revolution as a Masonic
conspiracy. After a long run in the nineteenth century, where it
6
was promoted by Pius IX as an explanation for his troubles (and
of course that was where Vaughan got it from), it acquired an
7
antisemitic tinge in the last two decades of the century. The most
famous expression of it, the Protocols of the Elders of Zion, written in
France probably in the 1890s, was Barruel’s theory over again,
with the addition that the Masonic plot was actually controlled
8
from the inside by Jews. Descendants of the Protocols theory include
the Nazis’ Jewish conspiracy theory, the Jewish-Bolshevik plot
theory that was an issue in Helen Demidenko’s The Hand That
Signed the Paper, and the Jewish-Masonic-Communist plot believed
9
in by such people as Franco.
Those full-blown conspiracy theories are all false. The Protocols
were a forgery, there was no world Jewish plot, and there was no
secret international organisation behind all revolutions.
It might seem, then, that although Vaughan was not alone, his
plot theory was a pure fantasy. That is not quite true. It does not
follow that there was no basis at all for the fears of the right. To
understand what was really happening, it is necessary to look at
what Freemasonry was, and why the Catholic Church was in
conflict with it. If it was not a communist plot, what was it?
6
Cat holics Versus Masons
Fr e e m a son r y in Eu r ope
It was an institutional embodiment of the Enlightenment, or
at least of one version of it. The difficulty with the common view
of the Enlightenment is that it portrays it as existing purely in the
realm of ideas. The philosophies are supposed to have written
learned books full of dangerous theories and radical ideas, which
somehow filtered down to the bloodthirsty souls who cut off the
aristocrats’ heads. Apart from making the mistake of conceiving
the Enlightenment as primarily atheist and an enemy of the state,
when in general it was neither, this is to take far too intellectual a
view of it. A church is not simply a creed and catechism, but also
an institution that supplies tradition, ritual, mutual comfort and
community support for right conduct and sanction for wrong,
and, at least in earlier times, a social security agency. The organ
through which the Enlightenment competed in these respects was
Freemasonry. After developing in a still obscure fashion out of
Scottish and English guilds of stonemasons around 1700, it spread
quickly to the Continent and the American colonies during the
eighteenth century, and included among its members such notables
as Walpole, Pope, Hogarth, Franklin, Washington, Voltaire, Haydn,
10
Mozart and Goethe. It was not the intention of Freemasons to
undermine the existing political or religious order. There was
nevertheless an inevitable tension between Freemasonry’s ideals
of internal constitutional self-government and the absolutist
regimes on the Continent. There was also a philosophical conflict
between Freemasonry’s ideals of religious toleration and the
Catholic view of dogma. As a result, there was a certain amount
of police action against the lodges in countries like France, and
11
the Catholic Church condemned Freemasonry. Up to the time
of the French Revolution, however, the conflict was not a matter
of great importance to either side. Indeed, the Church’s
condemnations of Freemasonry were not promulgated beyond the
English Channel, and around 1800 Irish Freemasonry was full of
Catholics.
7
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
The French Revolution was not a Masonic plot in any simple
sense, but it is true that Masonic ideals, symbols and organisation
12
had something to do with the origins of the Revolution. Liberty,
equality and fraternity were originally Masonic ideals, which one
needs to read free of associations with the Terror – in the spirit of
13
the American Revolution, not the French. In the years of the
Napoleonic Wars and the Restoration, the lodges did act as covers
for the spread of revolutionary brotherhoods, even if Freemasonry
14
as a whole was not revolutionary. It must be emphasised that
Freemasonry does not have any international central controlling
body – something, of course, which the Catholic Church found
hard to understand. That means, on the one hand, that an actual
international Masonic plot is unlikely; on the other hand, it means
that individual lodges or groups of lodges and shadowy quasiMasonic organisations can be captured by strange ideas, and develop
in their own, sometimes revolutionary, directions. For example,
around 1820, there were genuine Masonic connections to the
Decembrist revolutionaries in Russia, the Carbonari in Italy, and
15
Spanish liberals resisting the Restoration. Even in early New
South Wales, there were fears of Masonic revolutionary activity.
Governor King feared the French might sail up the Hawkesbury,
unite with the Irish at Castle Hill, and leave him defended only
by the mutinous rabble of the New South Wales corps. Since all
three of these threats were riddled with Masons, he took seriously
the possibility of their cooperation on the basis of brotherhood,
16
and suppressed attempts to form a lodge.
For the rest of the nineteenth century, Freemasonry was
associated with the anticlerical ‘liberal’ political faction in Catholic
17
countries. Latin America was a scene of perennial conflict. An
article in the Australasian Catholic Record of 1899 on ‘The just man of
the nineteenth century’ tells the story of the Catholic President
of Ecuador, Gabriel Garcia Moreno, who dedicated Ecuador to
the Sacred Heart, gave the state education system to the Catholic
18
Church, and then was assassinated by, it was thought, Masons. It
19
was the same in Spain. The unification of Italy, with the
8
Cat holics Versus Masons
confiscation of the Papal States, was a success for Freemasonry,
20
among other forces. By and large, the Catholic right fought a
losing battle. As we saw, they did not attribute that to their being
out of touch with the spirit of the age, or to a lack of concern for
social problems, but to a literal plot.
The control of primary education was one of the main issues
in the conflict. Vaughan’s story that the Education League in
Belgium was a Masonic front promoting free, compulsory and
21
secular education is entirely true. In France, laws instituted by a
heavily Masonic government in 1879-82 took public money from
Church schools, and instituted general moral education in public
22
schools. When the Catholics added a Jewish conspiracy theory
to the Masonic one, they were discredited over the Dreyfus affair,
and in the early years of the twentieth century, a vigorously
anticlerical and largely Masonic government took advantage of
having the upper hand to expel the religious teaching orders from
23
France and seize their property without compensation. There
24
was a lot of interest in these events among Australian Catholics,
and Australia benefited by the immigration of the De La Salle
Brothers, whose first Australian school, in Armidale, was founded
25
in 1906 by brothers just expelled from France. At the same time,
it came to light in the ‘Affaire des fiches’ that there really was a Masonic
conspiracy: the French Masons were keeping a huge card index on
public officials who went to Mass, with a view to preventing their
26
promotions. The animosity between French Freemasonry and
the Catholic Church waned somewhat in the next decades, but
revived when the Vichy regime published long lists of Masons,
27
and sacked them from state schools and other employment.
Naturally, not much has been heard of these things since 1945.
There was, however, a problem with Vaughan’s theory that
what was happening in Australia was the same as what was
happening in France and Belgium. It is significant that all the
Masonic documents Vaughan quotes as evidence are Continental,
and all Beg’s British. British (and hence Australian) Freemasonry
is not the same as the Continental variety. It was not in conflict
9
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
with the Established Church or the state – on the contrary, kings,
prime ministers and Archbishops of Canterbury have been
Freemasons. There is no need to plot revolution against a state
one controls already or if not ‘controls’, at least has an easy
relationship with. Catholic propagandists knew their theory had
a problem here, and made the most of the occasional meeting
28
between the Prince of Wales and an Italian Mason.
Fr e e m a son r y I n Au st r a lia
The story of the influence of the Masons is one of the great
untold narratives of Australian history. Manning Clark, for
example, though seeing Australian history as an epic struggle
between Christian and Enlightenment principles, hardly mentions
the main Enlightenment institution, and even full-length
biographies of famous Australians often fail to mention they were
Masons. They were involved in most of the significant
developments in Australia. Joseph Banks was a Mason, and in the
early colony, so were Governor Macquarie, Francis Greenway, and
29
the explorers Oxley, Hume and Leichhardt. More than thirty of
the hundred and eleven members of the first Commonwealth
Parliament were Masons, either at the time or later, ‘some
indication’, according to Masons, ‘that our Commonwealth was
in its beginning also based on righteousness and virtuous
30
character.’ Almost all of the conservative Prime Ministers up to
1972 – Barton, Reid, Cook, Bruce, Page, Menzies, Fadden,
31
McEwen, Gorton and McMahon – were Masons. Many governors
32
were Masons, often the Grand Masters of their states. Masons
prominent in other fields include Edward Hargraves, the discoverer
of gold, Lawrence Hargrave, the pioneer of flight, and such
quintessentially Australian heroes as Sir Charles Kingsford Smith,
Sir Don Bradman and Sir Edward ‘Weary’ Dunlop. The Masonic
33
Historical Society’s web site is informative.
The first recognised Lodge, the Lodge of Social and Military
34
Virtues, arrived with the regiment it was attached to in 1814,
and Freemasonry was associated with wealth and the party of
10
Cat holics Versus Masons
35
political reform by the 1830s, in both Sydney and Hobart. The
lodges spread widely, especially in the 1890s and again between
36
the Wars. Specialised lodges included Lodge Cricket, of which
37
Bradman was a member, Lodge Literature, for newspapermen,
and lodges for the old boys of particular schools, such as Sydney
38
Grammar, Fort Street, Sydney High and Shore. Melbourne
University, Sydney University and later the University of New
39
South Wales had lodges for academics and graduates. Freemasonry
was particularly strong in the Armed Forces, the police, banks,
AMP, the state and commonwealth public services, and the councils
40
of country towns. Freemasonry in the army was an issue in the
conscription campaigns of 1916 and 1917, since Catholics were
not enthusiastic about being drafted as fodder for an officer corps
dominated by Freemasonry, ‘the most insidious enemy of God
and country … a huge tumour growing upon the life and blood of
41
the whole of the country’ (Mannix). Membership increased again
after the Second War, as returned servicemen used the lodges to
continue the mateship of the armed forces, and a high point of
membership was reached in the mid-1950s, with some 330,000
42
members in about 2,000 lodges, or one Australian man in sixteen.
Since there were no Catholic members, and very few blue-collar
workers, this represents an extraordinary penetration of the target
group, the ‘managerial classes’.
This leaves the question, what did Masonic membership mean?
It could, of course, mean nothing: like religious membership, it
could simply be a way of getting out of the house, meeting people
who might help one get a better job, or providing security for
one’s widow. Masonic membership seems to have meant nothing
to Menzies, for example. He was a club man rather than a lodge
man. But for those who took membership more seriously, and
many did, more was on offer. Freemasonry is a philosophy. It is
not easy to say precisely what that philosophy is, not only because
part of it is kept secret, but also because putting ‘doctrines’ into
propositional form is not the preferred method of exposition of
the Masonic point of view, even to initiates. Freemasonry is
11
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
43
officially ‘a system of morality veiled in allegory’. The allegory
and symbolism, intended to assist the imagination and memory
44
of the initiate, is the main method of instruction, and the
interpretation of the symbols is to some extent left to the individual.
But the general outline of the system is not secret. The only
Masonic ‘dogma’, strictly speaking, is the existence of God, belief
in which is a condition of entry. Belief in immortality is, however,
45
strongly suggested. Beyond that, religious matters are left to the
individual’s own sect; a Mason is expected to pursue his own faith,
which may be of any Christian or other theistic persuasion.
The centre of Freemasonry is not doctrinal but moral. ‘The
whole purpose of Freemasonry is to teach the Moral Law and
show that man should live rightly with his fellow man under the
46
all-seeing eye of God.’ The normal meanings of the symbols
mostly concern morality. The well-known symbols of square and
compasses, for example, symbolise respectively rectitude in general
and the circle separating right behaviour from wrong. Truth and
47
honesty in dealings are crucial.
Harmony has not characterised the relations of Freemasonry
with the more dogmatic religions, and the reasons for conflict
concern basic matters of the relation between philosophy and
religion. Freemasonry insists that it is not a religion, but admits to
being ‘religious’, or having something to say in areas already
48
occupied by religion. Its tolerance of all religions can easily give
rise to the impression that dogmatic differences do not matter,
even though that is never asserted explicitly. Suspicion in this regard
is encouraged by the phrase ‘the Religion in which all men agree’,
49
in the original 1723 Constitutions of Freemasonry.
It is clear why Masons should have generally felt happy with a
system of secular education. Vaughan’s suspicion that a large-scale
movement inimical to his position was under way, and that the
Masons had something to do with it, was not altogether without
foundation, even if there was no plot. W.C. Wentworth and John
Woolley, the earlier leaders of the campaign for secular education,
were Masons, while William Wilkins, the effective decision-maker
12
Cat holics Versus Masons
on the syllabus, was a prominent Mason, who wrote in favour of
50
the possibility of moral education free of dogma. Parkes was not
a Mason, but that was not much consolation for the Catholics,
since his views were actually closer to those of the anticlerical
51
European Masons.
The conflict between Catholics and Masons did not rest so
clearly on any matters of principle. There is nothing explicitly
anti-Catholic in Freemasonry (unlike the Orange lodges), and
Catholic objections, other than on the secular education question,
rested mostly on supposed Masonic plots in Europe and job
discrimination in Australia. The main objection of principle was
to Masonic oaths, committing Masons not to reveal secrets before
52
they knew the nature of the secrets. Since the 1960s, better
53
relations have prevailed, mainly because Catholic theology has
itself adopted a more tolerant view of other religions. The reasons
for this are probably not, as some think, that the last four popes
have been secret Masons.
D iscr im in a t ion in Em ploym e n t in Au st r a lia
This brings us to the vexed question of job discrimination.
Catholics believed that up to about 1960, at least, most positions
of power in organisations like the armed services, many public
service departments, the private banks, and so on, were virtually
barred to them by a conspiracy of Masons looking after one
54
another. It is very hard to discover any undeniable facts about it.
It has not even proved possible to establish whether the best-known
story about the whole matter is literally true: that NSW Police
Commissioners were by arrangement alternately Masons and
Catholics.
For one thing, it is difficult to prove that any given failure to
get a job is due to underhand motives. And even if there were hard
statistical evidence that there were almost no Catholics in, say, the
management of the Bank of New South Wales – which there is
55
not – it is hard to demonstrate anything about the reasons for it.
And even if there was discrimination against Catholics, it may
13
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
have been due to Protestant sectarian feeling, or anti-Irish racism,
rather than to the Masons. I know of no admissions by anyone
that they ever discriminated against a Catholic in favour of a less
qualified applicant for a job, though the Masons have informally
agreed that they did provide a certain amount of help to one another
56
with jobs. As one senior Mason explained it to me, Freemasonry
is intended to make good men better – unlike religions that hope
also to make bad men good. So being a Mason is, other things
being equal, a sign of being a good man, and hence a
recommendation for a job. Applicants for membership who
appeared to be interested simply in improving their employment
prospects were supposed to be denied membership.
There are hardly even any complaints by Catholics that they
were passed over for any definite job. There is one case, though,
recently described in some detail. It is in a life of Frank Letters,
recently written by his widow. Letters was a classical scholar who
applied for and failed to get positions in the late 1930s.
When Frank was a young graduate hoping for an academic post,
there was not one practising Catholic senior staff member at
Sydney University. In 1938, of the forty professors at Sydney
University there was no Catholic. It was little different in the
higher echelons of education departments, the police force, the
public service, banking, and in many businesses. Equally obvious,
when you looked closely, was the absence of Catholics from the
top legal appointments and among hospital specialists.
For a start, Catholics could not be Freemasons, and were
therefore automatically excluded from the mutual help towards
promotion that Freemasons gave one another. There were of
course men with high ideals – and good friends of ours – who
enjoyed the convivial nights out at the local Masonic lodge with
men friends, helping one another, perhaps even relishing a night
out away from the wife. The rank-and-file Mason probably didn’t
realize that helping his buddy get ahead in business or career
could and often did mean that a better-qualified applicant didn’t
stand a chance. That is not justice.57
14
Cat holics Versus Masons
It is not entirely obvious, nevertheless, that Masonic influence
was responsible in this case. The Professor of Latin, Todd, was a
peculiar person, who disliked Letters on personal as much as
sectarian grounds. Letters eventually obtained one of the
foundation lectureships at the New England University College.
When the College became an autonomous University in 1954, all
58
the pioneers were given chairs, except Letters. He never did
become a professor, despite his international reputation based on
respectable books on Sophocles, Virgil, Thomas Mann and
Huysmans, and successful essays and poetry. Academic excellence
is more open for inspection than talent in, say, the public service,
and it is fair to say that for Letters to fail to get a chair at a provincial
university was an obvious scandal. The book has some actual
evidence about the role of Masonic influence.
All Armidale could see the university men’s cars on Thursday
nights near the Masonic Lodge on the corner of Faulkner and
Barney Streets. Frank could not fail to deduce that he, a Catholic
and the only one not a Lodge member, ‘would never get
anywhere’. The dice were loaded against his professional
advancement …
Frank also recalled the invitation to a welcome for a Supreme
Court judge and two barrister friends of Frank’s at Tatt’s Hotel.
One had just won a spectacularly interesting case and offered to
send some details to Frank, asking for his address. ‘Send it to
The Lodge’ was the answer. [The Letters family lived in a former
gatekeeper’s lodge at the University.] One of a nearby group,
half-hearing the answer but not the question, complained, ‘You
university men have taken us over’, assuming that Frank had
meant the Masonic Lodge. This was news to Frank who had not
up to that point seen the close link between Freemasonry and
his colleagues.
Once, when delivering a packet of Leaving Certificate
English papers to Sid Musgrove [the only other member of his
department], Frank looked over the bookshelves where to his
surprise he saw books to do with Freemasonry.
15
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
‘Oh no! not you, Sid’, he said, laughing heartily at the
thought of Sid, the cynic, being caught up in a conservative secret
society.
‘I wouldn’t get anywhere if I didn’t belong’, Musgrove said
simply.59
Catholics didn’t take things lying down, of course. Their best
chance for advancement came through the system of public service
entry through competitive examination, and promotion by
seniority. It is an expensive solution to job discrimination, but an
effective one. The Knights of the Southern Cross, a kind of
60
Catholic Masons, acted frequently as an employment agency. In
due course, there were networks of Catholics as well as networks
of Masons in public service departments; if anyone had a just
complaint, it was those in neither camp. The best opportunity for
Catholics to use raw political power to recover territory from the
Masons was in Queensland, where there were Catholic-dominated
Labor governments for decades. Freemasons lost ground in the
61
Queensland public service after 1915, and in 1957 the Premier,
Vince Gair, took on the University of Queensland for, among
62
other things, an alleged bias in favour of Masons. He failed.
Nationalising the banks might have helped, but Chifley and
Calwell did not succeed with that particular plan. They did achieve
a major change in the ethnic composition of Australia, away from
the Anglo-Saxon Protestant mould that prevailed up to then, by
importing 180,000 displaced Eastern Europeans, mostly Catholics.
It is the multiculturalism of Australia that has done as much as
anything to make the old conflicts irrelevant.
Finally, a moment of speculation. Possibly the most significant
effect for the Church of its long conflict with Freemasonry has
been that many of the men in the highest positions in the Church
have not understood the English-speaking countries. With the
English kings being Grand Masters, and many American presidents
being Masons and operating under a Constitution embodying
Masonic ideals, how could the mind of the Roman Curia be
anything but gravely suspicious of anything coming out of England
or America? In particular, ideals of ‘freedom’, toleration and
16
Cat holics Versus Masons
constitutional government have not been well understood by the
Roman mind. There has been a grave misunderstanding between
the international Church and the international language, which
has been a great misfortune for both.
N OTES
1
Archbishop and Bishops of N.S.W. Pastoral, Catholic Education Sydney, 1879,
repr. in P. O’Farrell (ed.), Documents in Australian Catholic History, vol. 1,
London, 1969, pp. 386-99.
2
R.B. Vaughan, Hidden Springs, or the Perils of the Future and How to Meet Them,
Sydney, 1876; brief summary in J.N. Molony, The Roman Mould of the
Australian Catholic Church, Melbourne, 1969, p. 150; similar later in Anon,
‘Freemasonry versus Church and State’, Australasian Catholic Record 10, 1904,
pp. 23-41; by Archbishop Kelly, in M. Clark, Sources of Australian History,
London, 1957, p. 577, Sydney Morning Herald 15/7/1913, p. 8.
3
‘Wazir Beg’, Australian Dictionary of Biography, vol. 3, p. 130.
4
W. Beg, Dr. Vaughan’s Ignorance of Freemasonry Exposed, Sydney, 1876, pp. 10, 1921, 34; other replies: D. Allen, Reply to Dr Vaughan Upon Hidden Springs (Sydney,
1877) (on Allen’s anti-Catholic struggles, see F. Beedel, Letters and Other
Writings of the Late Pastor Daniel Allen (Sydney, 1901), ch. 13); J.A. Downie,
Rome’s Polluted Springs (Sydney, 1877).
5
J.Rogalla von Bieberstein, Die These von der Vershwörung 1776-1945. Philosophen,
Freimauer, Juden, Liberale und Sozialisten als Vershwörer gegen die Sozialordnung, Berne,
1976 (see reviews in Annales 33, 1978, pp. 754-6; History of European Ideas 4,
1983, pp. 109-11).
6
R.F. Esposito, Pio IX. La Chiesa in conflitto col mondo. La S. Sede, la massoneria e il
radicalismo settario, Rome, 1979 (see review in Catholic Historical Review 68, 1982,
pp. 667-8); L. Leoni, La massoneria e le annessioni degli Stati pontificii, Viterbo,
1892-3; summary in F.A. Ferrer Benimeli, Masoneria español contemporanea,
Madrid, 1980, vol. 2 pp. 36-41; Australian comment in T.A. Fitzgerald,
‘The present condition of Italy’, Australasian Catholic Record 4, 1898, pp. 36179, 460-74, at p. 467.
7
R.F. Byrnes, Antisemitism in Modern France, vol. 1, New Brunswick, New Jersey,
1950; pp. 126-40, 187-92; R. Millman, ‘Jewish anticlericalism and the rise
of modern French antisemitism’, History 77, 1992, pp. 220-36; J. Katz, Jews
and Freemasons in Europe, trans. L. Oschry, Harvard, 1970, chs. 10-11.
8
N. Cohn, Warrant for Genocide, 2nd ed, London, 1996, ch. 3.
17
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
9
J.A. Ferrer Benimeli, El contubernio judeo-masonico-comunista: del satanismo al escandalo
de la P-2, Madrid, 1982?; Ferrer Benimeli, Masoneria español contemporanea, vol.
2 ch. 5; M.R. Marrus & R.O. Paxton, Vichy France and the Jews, N.Y., 1981,
pp. 76, 199.
10
European background in M.C. Jacob, Living the Enlightenment: Freemasonry and
politics in eighteenth-century Europe, N.Y., 1991; W.R. Weisberger, Speculative
Freemasonry and the Enlightenment, Boulder, 1993; R. van Dülmen, The Society
of the Enlightenment, trans. A. Williams, N.Y., 1992, pp. 52-65, 151-65; S.C.
Bullock, ‘Initiating the Enlightenment?: recent scholarship on European
Freemasonry’, Eighteenth-Century Life 20, 1996, pp. 80-92; Australian
knowledge of it in M. Conway, ‘Freemasonry and the Age of
Enlightenment’, Masonic Research in South Australia (South Australian Lodge
of Research), 1, 1990-4, pp. 19-21; K. Brindal, ‘Brother Mozart, Freemason’,
Masonic Research in South Australia 2, 1995, pp. 27-9; N.J. McDonald,
‘Desaguliers’, New South Wales Freemason 29, 1934, pp. 81-2; American
background in S.C. Bullock, Revolutionary Brotherhood: Freemasonry and the
transformation of the American social order, 1730-1840, Chapel Hill, 1996.
11
J.A. Ferrer Benimeli, Los archivos secretos vaticanos y la masonería, Caracas, 1976; G.
Adilardi, Un’antica condanna. le origini di un conflitto tra Chiesa Cattolica e massoneria,
Foggia, 1989; R.E. Jenkins, ‘The evolution of the Church’s prohibition
against Catholic membership in Freemasonry’, Jurist 56, 1997, pp. 735-55.
12
Annales historiques de la revolution française, special issue July-Sept 1969, especially
D. Ligou, ‘Structures et symbolisme maçonniques sous la révolution’, pp.
511-23.
13
Jacob, Living the Enlightenment, p. 12; emphasised in J.E. Carnegie, Freemasonry:
its origin, history, principles and doctrines, Melbourne, 1862, p. 7; also P. Carter,
‘Visions of God – a Masonic perspective’, Theosophy in Australia 58, 1, Mar
1994, pp. 16-19.
14
J.H. Billington, Fire in the Minds of Men: origins of the revolutionary faith, London,
1980, pp. 91-9.
15
L.G. Leighton, The Esoteric Tradition in Russian Romantic Literature: Decembrism and
Freemasonry, University Park, PA, 1994; Billington, pp. 141-2, 330; R.
Lansdown, ‘Byron and the Carbonari’, History Today 41, May, 1991, pp. 1825; B.R. Hamnett, ‘Liberal politics and Spanish Freemasonry, 1814-1820’,
History 69, 1984, pp. 221-37.
16
A. Atkinson, The Europeans in Australia, Melbourne, 1997, ch. 12; King to
Sullivan, 21/4/1804, Historical Records of Australia, series I vol v p. 142.
17
C. Gazmari, El ‘48’ chileno: igualiterios, reformistas, radicales, masones y bomberos,
Santiago, 1992; J.A. Ferrer Benimeli, ‘Bolivar y la masoneria’, Revista de
Indias 43, 1983, pp. 631-87; J.P. Bastian (ed.), Protestantes, liberales y francmasones:
Sociedades de ideas y modernidad en América Latina, siglo xix, Mexico, 1990; P.
18
Cat holics Versus Masons
Rich & G. de los Reyes, ‘Freemasonry’s educational role’, American Behavioral
Scientist 40, 1997, pp. 957-67.
18
J. Brennan, ‘The just man of the nineteenth century’, ACR 5, 1899, pp. 16272.
19
M.A. Ortiz de Andres, Masoneria y democracia en el siglo xix: el Gran Oriente Español
y su proyeccion politico-social, 1888-1896, Madrid, 1993.
20
R.F. Esposito, Le grande concordanze tra Chiesa et massoneria, Firenze, 1987; L.
Braschi, La massoneria e la Chiesa cattolica: un terribile scontro, un possibile incontro,
Firenze, 1984; A. Luzio, La massoneria e il Risorgimento italiano, Bologna, 1966;
A. Lattanzi, Bibliografia della massoneria italiana e di Cagliostro, Firenze, 1974.
21
R. Desmed, ‘A propos du mémoire de la Loge des Amis Philanthropes sur
l’enseignement primaire obligatoire et laïque’, Revue belge de philologie et d’histoire
53, 1975, pp. 357-401, especially pp. 385, 395-401.
22
J.S. Schapiro, Anticlericalism, Princeton, 1967, pp. 56, 60, 153-6; E. Acomb, The
French Laic Laws, 1879-1889, N.Y., 1941; T.F. Power, Jules Ferry and the Renaissance
of French Imperialism, N.Y., 1966, pp. 16-21; J. Fulton, ‘The revival of church/
state hostility in France: the affair of the religious decrees, 1879-80’, Journal
of Religious History 20, 1996, pp. 20-31; P. Nord, ‘Republicanism and Utopian
vision: French Freemasonry in the 1860s and 1870s’, Journal of Modern History
63, 1991, pp. 213-29.
23
M. Larkin, Church and State After the Dreyfus Affair, London, 1974, pp. 23-8, 91101, 138-41; C.S. Phillips, The Church in France, 1848-1907, 1936, repr. N.Y.,
1967, ch. 9.
24
J.J. Norris, ‘The Catholic Church and liberty’, ACR 3, 1897, pp. 564-72;
letter of Leo XIII, ACR 2, 1896, pp. 149-53; D. Lynch, ‘Freemasonry in
France’, ACR 8, 1902, pp. 529-46; P.S. Cleary, ‘Freemasonry – the enemy
of throne and altar’, ACR 17, 1911, pp. 467-510; M.Q., ‘A few notes on
Freemasonry’, Austral Light 4, 1903, pp. 672-4; ‘Hiram’, ‘Sidelights on
Freemasonry’, Austral Light 5, 1904, pp. 403-12, 467-73, 515-21, 609-14,
772-8.
25
Br Aloysius, The De La Salle Brothers in Australia, 1906-1956, Sydney, 1956, pp.
19-27; Fogarty, Catholic Education in Australia, vol 2, p. 274; P.V. Dwyer, ‘The
Marist Brothers and their work in France’, ACR 12, 1906, pp. 461-9; Count
de Mun, ‘The religious persecution in France’, ACR 13, 1907, pp. 398421, at pp. 414-16; R.S., ‘France and the Catholic schools’, Austral Light 3,
1902, pp. 726-9.
26
Larkin, Church and State after the Dreyfus Affair, pp. 138-41: ‘Freemasonry in
France’, Austral Light 6, 1905, pp. 164-72, 241-50.
27
D. Rossignol, Vichy et les francs-maçons. La liquidation des sociétés secrétes, 1940-1944,
Paris, 1981; R.O. Paxton, Vichy France, N.Y., 1972, pp. 4, 102, 156, 172-3,
255.
19
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
28
T.A. Fitzgerald, ‘The Jewish Masonic combination in France’, ACR 6, 1900,
pp. 342-88; Molony, p. 150; A. McLay, James Quinn, 2nd ed, Toowoomba,
1989, pp. 135-9.
29
G.H. Cumming, The Foundations of Freemasonry in Australia, West Pennant Hills,
NSW, 1992, pp. 1-10; ‘Was Sir Joseph Banks a Mason?’, NSW Freemason 47,
1952, pp. 185; ‘Francis Greenway’, NSW Freemason 46, 1951, pp. 133-6; P.
Krüger, ‘Ludwig Leichhardt: a German geologist of the “Vormärz” period’,
in H. Lamping & M. Linke (eds), Australia: studies on the history of discovery and
exploration, Frankfurt, 1994, pp. 127-38.
30
K.R. Cramp, ‘Federation and Freemasonry’, NSW Freemason 46, 1951, pp.
441-6, 47, 1952, pp. 313, 48, 1953, p. 5.
31
Freemasonry: Australia’s Prime Ministers, Masonic Historical Society of N.S.W.,
booklet 2, Sydney, 1994.
32
K. Henderson, Masonic Grand Masters of Australia, Bayswater, 1988, passim.
33
http://www.uglnsw.freemasonry.org.au/historic/historical.html
34
Cumming, p. 6; K.R. Cramp & G. Mackaness, A History of the United Grand
Lodge of New South Wales, Sydney, 1938, ch. 4.
35
A.Atkinson & M. Aveling, eds, Australians 1838, Sydney, 1987, pp. 330-1, 314;
Clark, History of Australia, vol. 2 pp. 300-1; G.M. Dow, Samuel Terry: the
Botany Bay Rothschild, Sydney, 1974, pp. 215, 225-6.
36
The Tongue of Good Report: Lodge Zion no. 218, Gunnedah 1894-1994, Gunnedah,
1994, and similar histories of individual lodges; A. Richards, The Centennial
Story: the history of Freemasonry in Queensland, Brisbane, 1959; D. Lauder,
‘Freemasons and Freemasonry in Queensland’, J. of the Royal Historical Society
of Queensland 14, 1990, pp. 33-40; R.W. Bell, ‘Freemasonry and early
Ballarat’, Ballarat Historian 4, 2, Mar, 1989, pp. 17-21 & 4, 10, Mar, 1991, pp.
6-12; W.C. Vahland, History of Freemasonry in the Bendigo District, Bendigo, 1904;
M. Chapman, ‘Jews and Freemasons in the Colony of Victoria 1840-1900’,
Journal of the Australian Jewish Historical Society 11, 3, Nov, 1991, pp. 415-91;
R.J. Linford, ‘Freemasonry in the Queanbeyan-Canberra area, 1877-1939’,
Canberra Historical Journal 36, Sept 1995, pp. 18-27.
37
Lodge Literature no. 500, Sydney, 1938.
38
Cramp & Mackaness, pp. 475, 587-8.
39
Cramp & Mackaness, p. 475; K.R. Cramp, Lodge University of Sydney, 1945.
40
J. Maguire, Prologue, Toowoomba, 1990, p. 63; R. Haldane, The People’s Force,
2nd ed, Melbourne, 1995, pp. 56, 171; B. Winter, The Intrigue Master, Brisbane,
1995, p. 174; Lieut-Gen H.G. Bennett, ‘Anzac Day, 1953’, NSW Freemason
48, 1953, pp. 133-6; R.J.W. Selleck & M. Sullivan, Not So Eminent Victorians,
Melbourne, 1984, p. 127; Henderson, Masonic Grand Masters, pp. 89, 91;
M. Cannon, The Long Last Summer, Melbourne, 1985, p. 62; ‘Clarke, W.J.’,
ADB vol. 3 pp. 422-4; G. Davison, J.W. McCarty & A. McLeary, eds,
20
Cat holics Versus Masons
Australians 1888, Sydney, 1987, p. 196; Bill Gammage & N. Spearritt, eds,
Australians 1938, Sydney, 1987, p. 237; D. Armstrong, ‘Freemasons on the
march again’, Bulletin 3/10/78, pp. 44-6, 51-4; M. Hogan, ‘The Sydney
style’, Labour History 36, 1979, pp. 39-46, at p. 42; P. O’Farrell, Catholic
Church and Community, Sydney, 1985?, p. 380; D. Horne, The Education of
Young Donald, rev. ed., Melbourne, 1988, p. 20.
41
Age 15/2/1916, p. 8 repr. in O’Farrell, Documents in Australian Catholic History,
vol. 2 p. 265; cf. pp. 107-9; reply in Argus 17/2/16, p. 9; also 10/7/16, p. 9;
‘The coadjutor-archbishop and the freemasons’, Austral Light 17, 1916, pp.
185-6; some facts about Catholics in the officer corps in D.J. Blair, ‘An
Australian ‘officer-type’? A demographic study of the composition of
officers in the 1st Battalion, First AIF’, Sabretache 39, Mar, 1998, pp. 21-7.
42
NSW membership figures in M.H. Kellerman, From Diamond Jubilee to Centenary:
history of forty years of the United Grand Lodge of Freemasonry in New South Wales,
1948-1988, Sydney, 1990, vol. IV, ch. 5.
43
M.H. Kellerman, ‘Freemasonry’, in Australian Encyclopaedia, 4th ed, Sydney,
1983, pp. 241-4; C.D. Morpeth, ‘A peculiar system of morality’, NSW
Freemason 30, 2, Feb 1935, pp. 43-5. W.C. Bowler, ‘Immortality’, NSW
Freemason 22, 1927, pp. 169-70.
44
E.A. Hough, ‘What is Freemasonry?’, NSW Freemason 33, 1938, pp. 561-2;
F.A. Maguire (ed.), Masonic Foundations, Redfern, 1940.
45
W.C. Bowler, ‘Immortality’, NSW Freemason 22, 1927, pp. 169-70.
46
‘Masonry and the moral law’, NSW Freemason 42, 1947, p. 185.
47
F.S. McDowell, ‘Masonic philosophy’, in K.R. Cramp, From Jubilee to Diamond
Jubilee: history of ten years of the United Grand Lodge of Freemasonry in New South
Wales, 1938-1948, pp. 262-4.
48
‘Masonry not a religion’, NSW Freemason 28, 1933, pp. 208, 223.
49
‘The charges of a Freemason’, Anderson’s Constitutions of 1723, repr. in M.C.
Jacob, The Radical Enlightenment: pantheists, Freemasons and republicans, London,
1981, p. 280; see L. Vibert, ‘Anderson’s Constitutions of 1723’, NSW
Freemason 47, 1952, pp. 397-404, 451-8, 467, especially p. 453.
50
‘Woolley, John’, ADB vol. 6 pp. 435-7; ‘Wilkins, William’, ADB vol. 6 pp.
400-2; W. Wilkins, National Education: an exposition of the National System of
New South Wales, Sydney, 1865, p. 12; elsewhere, L. Fletcher, (ed.), Pioneers
of Education in Western Australia, Perth, 1982, pp. 72, 159; for Queensland,
T.L. Suttor, Hierarchy and Democracy in Australia, 1788-1870, Melbourne, 1965,
pp. 302-3.
51
H. Parkes, ‘Darkness or light – which is to conquer?’, Empire 13 Oct 1851, p.
250, partly quoted in Martin, Henry Parkes, pp. 105-6; discussion in A.W.
Martin, ‘Henry Parkes and the political manipulation of sectarianism’,
Journal of Religious History 9, 1976, pp. 85-92; NSW Parliamentary Debates
21
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
1879-80, vol. 2. p. 1284; discussed in P.F. Cardinal Moran, History of the
Catholic Church in Australasia, Sydney, 1895, p. 875, cf p. 869.
52
P.J. Lynch, Freemasonry: Its Incompatibility with Practical Catholicism, Sydney, 1923,
pp. 30-2; A.J. Dunn, ‘Christianity and Freemasonry’, Austral Light 8, 1907,
pp. 179-90; E. Cahill, The Truth About Freemasonry, Australian Catholic Truth
Society pamphlet, Melbourne, 1936; L. Rumble, Radio Replies in Defence of
Religion, Sydney, 1936, pp. 292-9.
53
M. Baume, ‘Masons and Catholics: a new understanding’, Bulletin 13/1/68,
pp. 20-2; Jenkins, ‘The evolution’.
54
M. Hogan, The Sectarian Strand, Ringwood, Victoria, 1987, pp. 197-202, 217.
55
A preliminary attempt in Anon, ‘Catholics in the Australian public service’,
Australian Quarterly 32, 3, Sep, 1960, pp. 16-22.
56
‘The practical side of Freemasonry’, NSW Freemason 31, 1935, pp. 19.
57
K. Letters, History Will Out: F.J.H. Letters at the New England University College,
Armidale, 1997, pp. 37-8; see also E. Campion, Australian Catholics,
Ringwood, Victoria, 1987, p. 152.
58
History Will Out, ch. 10.
59
Ibid., pp. 67-8.
60
C.Kierce, ‘The men in the know?’, Observer 12/12/59, pp. 7-9; ‘The silent
knights’, Nation 13/1/60, pp. 8-10; ‘The meeting at Chapter Hall’, Nation
6/10/62, pp. 5-6.
61
R.Fitzgerald, From 1915 to the Early 1980s: a history of Queensland, Brisbane, 1984,
p. 13.
62
B.Costar, ‘Vincent Clair Gair’, in The Premiers of Queensland, D. Murphy et al
(eds)., 2nd ed, Brisbane, 1990, pp. 459-74, at p. 467; M.I. Thomis, A Place
of Light and Learning: the University of Queensland’s first seventy-five years, Brisbane,
1985, p. 138; cf. P. O’Farrell, UNSW: a portrait, Sydney, 1999, p. 133.
22
CH APTER TW O
Ca t holic Thought a nd
Ca t holic Act ion:
Dr Pa ddy Rya n M SC
M
ELBOURNE IN THE 1930S was the scene of the
vigorous Catholic intellectual life of the Campion
Society.1 Sydney was quite different, and for reasons
much debated but still far from clear, its version of the Campion
Society was much less impressive, and there was not much in the
way of a public or lay Catholic intellectual life.2 In Sydney, Catholic
philosophy, apologetics and controversy in the 1930s and early
1940s was almost a one-man show. The man was Father Paddy
Ryan. If it was a question of attacking Communists, or replying to
objections on radio, or debating philosophers, or setting up
Catholic adult education, or writing a pamphlet to prove the
existence of God, one contacted the Sacred Heart Fathers at
Kensington and got Father Ryan on the job. Born near Wodonga
in 1904, he had studied at the Gregorian University in Rome,
earning in 1929 doctorates in theology and philosophy with the
highest honours, with work on the ‘Question of God’ in modern
European philosophy.3 He taught philosophy, of a strictly scholastic
Original source: Journal of the Australian Catholic Historical Society 17 (1996), pp. 44-55
23
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
orientation, at the Kensington seminary thereafter. A series of
lectures for the Catholic Evidence Guild at Sydney University
which summarise scholasticism were printed in full in the Catholic
Press, at that time more hospitable than later to the discussion of
intellectual topics.4
His ability as a controversialist was first widely recognised in a
debate with the celebrated atheist Professor of Philosophy at
Sydney University, John Anderson, in a symposium on ‘Science,
philosophy and Christianity’, in 1936. Anderson argued that ‘in
so far as religion sets up a doctrine of meaning or explanations
above the facts (‘supernature’) it is unscientific’, and that Christian
morality wrongly ‘takes the standpoint of the individual recipient
of benefits’ instead of exalting cultural achievement. Ryan then
summarised the scholastic position on the knowability of God by
natural reason, the reasonableness of faith, and the evils of taking
scientific theories beyond their limits. He argued that
inconsistencies between the Catholic faith and modern
philosophies, such as materialism, were due to the faults of the
latter. 5
Anderson and Ryan met again in 1939, in a symposium with
two biologists on ‘The origin of life’, the topic of which was really
the theory of evolution. The largest hall in the University was
packed with 500 people; others were turned away. Ryan here
defended one of the most controversial assertions of mid-century
scholasticism, one in which he took a special interest: it was that
spontaneous generation of life from the non-living is impossible,
whether now or in the distant past, for purely philosophical
reasons. Ryan argued that the ‘immanent nature of activity in living
things’ meant there was a difference in kind, not degree, between
the living and the non-living, which could not be crossed without
divine intervention.6 Though Catholic philosophy generally was
giving up the fight against evolution by the 1940s,7 Ryan did not.
In his later pamphlet on the existence of God, he does however
argue that if the theory of evolution were true, God would be
even more needed, since ‘the Author of world order would have
24
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
endowed the primitive organisms with the powers necessary to
produce, by gradual development, the present order of the plant
and animal kingdoms’.8 Donald Horne recalled attending the debate
as a convinced Andersonian of long standing, and still being
surprised at the position Anderson took:
I had been a believer in Darwinism ever since I had read in
Cassell’s Book of Knowledge that ‘The protoplasm was the beginning
of the wonderful story of evolution’, and when Pritchett and I
stayed back at the university one night to attend a symposium
on evolution at which Anderson would be speaking I expected
that, since a Catholic priest was to be one of the other speakers,
Anderson would launch all his fury against the ignorance and
superstition of this clerical bigot. The large lecture theatre was
brimming with people, and Anderson sat intent, silent and sadeyed, while the priest jumped on the theory of evolution and a
scientist picked it up. Anderson sprang into the ring and floored
the priest with a couple of blows. I was astounded when, after an
obeisance towards Darwin because, like Freud, he had rejected
the dualism of man and nature, he then pummelled evolutionary
ethical theory, on, blow after blow, because it was full of
progressivist illusions. Things might not get better. They might
get worse. With Anderson one did not know where one was.9
There is a much greater sense of the cut and thrust of live
argument in the report of a debate Ryan held, also in 1939 and at
Sydney University, on freewill. His opponent was A.G. Hammer,
a lecturer in psychology at Sydney Teachers’ College, later Professor
of Psychology at the University of New South Wales. An audience
of 500 was again estimated. Hammer claimed that ‘all our decisions
are as necessary as the explosion of a bomb’, and asserted that ‘we
can predict all human acts with absolute certainty, granted a
sufficient knowledge of a man’s heredity, environment, and other
factors extrinsic to the will’. Ryan took his stand on the ‘clear and
unmistakable testimony of consciousness that it is very often in
his power to choose freely amongst various actions which he has
motives to perform’. He is reported, in perhaps a moment of
overkill, as having ‘proceeded to prove that the testimony of
consciousness is absolutely reliable’. Some interesting exchanges
during the discussion are reported, which give some sense of Ryan’s
25
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
ability to argue on his feet – as well as the style of public trading of
certainties that has come to play less part in the tradition of public
debate:
Mr O’Neill, an ardent determinist: Dr Ryan assumes the ‘self’ or ‘ego’
to be an abiding reality. But as a mere succession of states, the
‘ego’ could not be self-determining.
Dr Ryan: My appeal is to facts of experience. We have the
direct and immediate experience of the ‘self’ as an abiding reality
and the subject of successive states quite distinct from it. The
facts cannot be explained away by futile indulgence in
metaphysical speculations concerning the nature of the ‘ego’.
Mr O’Neill: Your proof from the validity of consciousness
means that all illusions are impossible. Yet there are illusions.
Dr Ryan: How do you know that there are any illusions except
from your consciousness of them? But the objection is pointless
because I appeal, not to the testimony of consciousness merely
as testimony, but as presenting objective evidence which enables
us to distinguish between illusion and reality, between deliberate
and indeliberate acts.
The chairman of the debate, John Passmore, perhaps less wellinformed about the history of philosophy than he was later to
become, then intervened with a historical point. ‘Relinquishing
his duties as chairman’, he accused Ryan of reviving Descartes’
philosophy, and ‘attacked the notion of a self-determining principle,
declaring it to be absurd’. Ryan said that Descartes’ philosophy
was not the same as Aristotelico-Thomistic philosophy.
Mr Passmore: The only person other than Descartes who adopted
Dr Ryan’s line of approach was St Augustine, a man not regarded
as a philosopher by anyone outside a certain religious
organisation.
Dr Ryan: Not one word of that is correct.10
Ryan did not confine his campaign to open debate. After
collecting statements from students at Sydney Teachers’ College,
he had a letter written by his superior to the Director of Education
demanding that something be done about the immoral teaching
at the College. The determinism taught by the Andersonians at
26
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
the College was the focus of the complaints. Dr Rumble’s Radio
Replies was used to publicise the campaign.11 Ryan’s interest in
Sydney University continued. He claims:
I personally have argued for hours with graduates of Sydney
University in a futile endeavour to convince them of their own
existence, – so deeply had their very reason been undermined by
scepticism and sophistry.
In condemning things of this sort, we are not condemning
critical or progressive thought. We are condemning a perverse
negation which spells the suicide of thought and makes all
progress impossible.
In defending self-evident truths like one’s own existence and
personality, or easily demonstrable truths like the existence of
God, we are merely defending the foundations without which
all talk of justice and injustice is so much meaningless twaddle.12
Donald Horne had the opportunity to tangle personally with
Ryan in 1941, when Horne, as editor of Honi Soit, was a
representative at a ‘Youth Parliament’ which saw a clash between
Stalinists and Catholics. Horne recalls, ‘In the evening I drank
beer with some of the Stalinists, infuriated by the unscrupulous
red-herring tactics of the clerical fascists, who were not concerned
with the constructive work of the Youth Parliament but with
disrupting it by obscurantist Gestapo methods . . . Whenever the
name “Catholic Action” was mentioned I would fall quiet with
hate. We didn’t know much about it, but there were rumours of
hysterical meetings and secret plottings in some kind of
conspiratorial Catholic anti-Communist campaign that was going
on in Sydney. Any Catholic student who wore a Holy Name badge
seemed a servant of a black and unscrupulous clerical reaction
which, under the subterfuge of anti-communism, represented an
ambition of Francoism in Australia.’13
The Catholic resolution which particularly disturbed the
‘Parliament’ was one affirming ‘its complete adherence to the
principles of democracy; its repudiation of the Totalitarian
27
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
ideologies whether Nazi, Fascist or Communist’. As Ryan said,
Catholic Action, like any genuine democratic Australian, would
be in favour, so it was fair to ask why the ‘Youth Parliament’
rejected it. ‘Characteristic in this respect’, Ryan adds, ‘is the letter
by Mr D.R. Horne, published in ‘Honi Soit’ issue of June 27, 1941.
Mr Horne writes with deep emotion – with more heat than light.
I gather from the references to the “unbalanced priest” who speaks
over Radio 2SM, “the vaporisings of Dr Ryan”, the “Catholic
papers” and sundry threats of Blitzkriegs to come, that he is making
some sort of attack on me. But he does not face the real point at
issue . . .A genuinely democratic Youth Parliament really
representative of the Youth of Australia would deserve support.
But the same cannot be said of a Youth Parliament which provides
a convenient cloak for anti-democratic and anti-British
propaganda.’14 Rumours of Catholic plots, Stalinists exposed . . .
much more was to be heard of these themes in the coming years.
Ryan gave a series of lectures on campus in 1943 which provoked
the usual polarisation of opinion.15 There is a thoughtful reply to
his arguments for the existence of God by medical student Doug
Everingham, later Minister for Health in the Whitlam
Government.16
Ryan was employed by the Church in a huge range of activities
during the 1940s and 50s. In 1936, during one of the hierarchy’s
periodic wringings of hands over the loss of young Catholics after
they left school, lecture courses on apologetics and social theory
were instituted, with Ryan as director.17 He was again involved,
providing much of the study material, when the movement was
reformed, with great but temporary success, in 1938.18 After the
War, he headed a ‘Workers’ School of Social Reconstruction’.19 In
1954, the problem was as unsolved as ever (‘There is practically no
such thing in Australia as the Catholic mind’, according to Ryan20)
and an Adult Education Institute (Director, Paddy Ryan) was set
up in the city to offer courses in apologetics, theology and public
speaking (but not philosophy, where it was presumably not thought
worthwhile to compete with the Aquinas Academy). Enrolments,
28
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
however, were never more than a few score. He debated on the
radio on more or less anything; in a single broadcast of 1941, he
dealt with the permissibility of moderate consumption of alcohol,
the idiocy of chain letters (‘shows the depth of absurdity to which
people can fall when they lack genuine religion’) and the
responsibility of H.G. Wells for the War (‘If people teach, as Mr
Wells does teach, that the Ten Commandments are so much junk,
they have no right to complain if Hitler presents them with a
working model of their own philosophy’).21 Radio Replies were
one area where Ryan did have a rival, however. His colleague at
Kensington, Dr Rumble, specialised in the genre, and books of his
replies sold millions in Australia and overseas.22
In 1943 Ryan shot dead a man in mistake for a rabbit.23
It was the Red Peril, however, that came to take up most of his
energy. Catholic emotional involvement in the Spanish Civil War
had resulted in Catholics being more concerned than most
Australians about the perils of international Communism. While
many Australians maintained a generally favourable view of the
USSR at the time when Stalin was on the same side during the
war against Hitler, and the membership of the Communist Party
of Australia reached a peak in 1944, Catholic circles remained
solidly hostile to Stalinism.
In 1943, Ryan answered one of the most effective leftist
pamphlets of the day, Dean Hewlett Johnson’s Socialist Sixth of the
World. This was the pamphlet which had converted to Communism
the young Frances Bernie, hitherto active in Catholic youth
organisations, leading to her leaking papers from Dr Evatt’s office
to the Communist Party and later to her appearance before the
Petrov Royal Commission.24 Ryan’s answer, concentrating on the
lack of freedom of religion in Russia,25 sold some 45,000 copies.26
There was a reply by the indefatigable Communist, Lance Sharkey,
long-time General Secretary of the Communist Party of Australia.
Sharkey says that Lenin is as much in favour of a moral way of life
as Father Ryan. But the fact that employers and their press laud
the strike-breaker as a hero, while the workers regard him as a
29
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
scab (‘the most immoral creature on earth’), ‘refutes Father Ryan’s
standpoint that there is a general, fixed system of morals that applies
to all conceivable conditions’. Further, Sharkey says, it is not part
of Communism to attempt to uproot religion. It must be allowed
to wither away with the ‘improvement of the material conditions
of the masses’ and ‘the development of knowledge of nature
through scientific investigation’.27 Ryan replied in a series of articles,
collected into a pamphlet with the title Said Comrade Sharkey. It is a
superior piece of propaganda. The chapter on ‘Comrade Sharkey’s
“Truth” about Spain’ is illustrated with pictures of murdered priests
in Spain; that on ‘Religion in Soviet Russia’ has an enormous
amount of evidence about the truth of Stalin’s persecutions.
Ryan’s finest hour came with a public debate at the Rushcutters
Bay Stadium on 23 September 1948, on the topic ‘That
Communism is in the best interests of the Australian people’. His
opponent was Edgar Ross, a member of the central committee of
the Party. Despite rain, 30,000 turned up, clogging the trams. Half
of the crowd had to hear the debate outside through loudspeakers.
Ross opened with a quotation from Pope Leo XIII on the need to
find a remedy for the misery and wretchedness of the working
class. He went on to condemn monopoly capitalism, Imperialism,
atomic bombs, American bases. ‘Against this, the Soviet Union
stood strong, secure, stable and prosperous (applause and boos)’.
‘The family was the bulwark of Soviet society (Laughter). In no
country of the world were human rights so explicitly
acknowledged. The Catholic Church in Russia enjoyed complete
freedom of activity. (Dr Ryan scribbles furiously and waves a gently
protesting hand to shush the audience)’. Ryan then spoke. He
alleged Communism was based on a degraded philosophy of life,
that its programme necessarily involved ruthless and unlimited
dictatorship, and that the Australian Party had no loyalty to God
or country but only to Moscow. ‘The audience broke out into
coughing as Dr Ryan went measuredly into the influence of the
philosopher Hegel on the thought of Karl Marx’, but perked up
when he waved the Communist Manifesto and discussed the
30
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
possibility of getting a divorce in Russia simply by sending a card
through the post to the registrar. Even more shockingly, he alleged
that workers in Russia were forbidden to strike. Ross, in reply,
‘claimed that Dr Ryan had given a lot of generalisations on
philosophy, a few lies about the Soviet, but nothing about the
practical tasks confronting the worker in the real situation today’.
Catholic preaching about the evils of society was like trying to
cure cancer with an aspro. To Ryan’s claim that all the Catholic
bishops in Russia were dead, in exile or missing, Ross replied that
the churches were open ‘in thousands’ in Russia. ‘To the laughter
he shouted, “Do you think I would pull the wool over your eyes?”
One solitary shrill feminine voice shouted: “Yes”.’ Ryan asked what
reliance could be placed on Ross’s word, when ‘according to Lenin,
Communist morality was wholly subordinated to the class struggle
of the proletariat’. ‘In saying that the Catholic Church supported
Fascism, Mr Ross was (again the quiet unimpassioned voice) a liar.
The Catholic Church was the deadliest enemy of Fascism, and of
Red Fascism, too (Wild applause)’.28
Ross writes briefly of the occasion in his memoirs. He
complains that ‘both sides were supposed to have equal rights in
admittance to the Stadium and ring-side seats. But when the doors
were thrown open the ring-side and many rows back were already
stacked with nuns, priests and students from catholic institutions,
who led the cheering and booing.’ (According to others, the
Communist Party Central Committee had done its best to round
up all available members of the Eureka Youth League and the New
Housewives Association.29) Of their action Ross writes, ‘A report
of the event took up half the front page of the Sydney Morning Herald
and had the positive effect of introducing communism to thousands
of people.’30 He omits to mention that the other half of the page
was taken up with the latest news on the Berlin blockade. An
ability to put an upbeat construction on the facts was becoming
increasingly necessary to Party members, and would become more
so. Ross was one of the leaders of the Coal Strike the next year
that did so much to assure Menzies’ election victory.
31
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Ryan’s wish to spend some of his time in such an abstruse matter
as the influence of Hegel on Marx is a perfect example of what
Frank Knopfelmacher was later to call the ‘seminarian-deductive’
attitude to political doctrines. It is characterised, according to
Knopfelmacher, by a ‘naive’ kind of intellectualism, which is preFreudian and pre-Marxist in believing in the ‘authentic force and
causal efficacy of intellectual convictions’.31 Ryan certainly did
believe that, though whether it is naive is arguable. In any case,
Australia has cause to be grateful for the ‘intellectualism’ that led
to the Cold War being fought here, not with the secret killings of
many other countries, but by nothing much worse than Dr Ryan
lecturing the Communist housewives of New South Wales on
Hegel.
Ryan continued to speak against Communism to large
audiences, notably at the time of the Coal Strike.32 During the
campaign for Menzies’ anti-Communism referendum of 1951, he
toured the country, earning headlines in local papers like ‘ ‘Peace’
movement part of Communist plot for war’ (Armidale Express),
‘Big audience hears Dr. P.J. Ryan talk on the Red menace’ (Goulburn
Evening Post), ‘Anti-Communist authority in Walcha’ (Walcha News).33
These speeches, and Ryan’s study materials, are the prototypes of
the thousands of Evils of Communism speeches in emotion-charged
church halls that are such a central element in the Catholic
Childhood of legend. An interesting feature of Ryan’s own
treatment of the issue, not always imitated, was his insistence on
the positive aspects of Catholic social philosophy, and its
incompatibility with laissez-faire capitalism:
What we need is not less capital, but more capitalists: not
the abolition of property, but the wider distribution of it among
private owners. We want this to enable the worker to become an
owner so that he might achieve economic independence and
political freedom. The industrial capitalist admitted in theory
the right of personal property, but denied it in practice to the
great majority of his fellow men.34
Ryan is of course not saying anything unusual here. His
programme is in line with the ‘corporatist’ view of society, as a
32
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
potentially homogeneous whole of organizations representing
various interests, which also found expression in the Catholic
bishops’ social justice statements.35 The project aroused little
enthusiasm outside the Catholic Church and was eventually
allowed to lapse as the fight against Communism took centre stage;
the Hawke government’s ‘politics of consensus’ has some
resemblances to it. Ryan’s position was average, except possibly
for his support for bank nationalisation, which did not find much
support from other Catholic leaders.36
The public speeches were only the tip of the iceberg of Ryan’s
anti-Communist crusade. Ryan had been during the 1930s a leading
proponent of ‘Catholic Action’, a phrase with a range of meanings
covering any lay action from prayer to politics.37 Party political
action was excluded, but political action to combat Communism
was not. As early as 1940, or possibly even in 1937, he had
investigated the possibility of setting up Catholic cells in the
unions,38 and around the end of the War he was effectively the
founder of the Movement in Sydney.39 B.A. Santamaria credited
Ryan with having achieved the difficult task of convincing Cardinal
Gilroy that enthusiastic support for secret anti-Communist action
was necessary.40 Gilroy appointed Ryan the Sydney director of the
Movement about 1946, with the title ‘Director of the Catholic
Social Science Bureau’ and an office in the city, though without
much in the way of money to run it.41
The story of the success of the Movement and its allies in Sydney
is still far from written. Suffice it to say that in 1949 there were
many Communist-controlled unions and within a very few years
there were almost none. Facts have come to light, however, about
one comparatively small but interesting aspect of the Movement’s
activities in Sydney, their collaboration with the security services.
The matter casts some light on Ryan’s opinions on the morality
of various actions.
The records of an ASIO investigation of 1953 into leaks of
information from the Commonwealth Investigation Service, the
forerunner of ASIO, to Catholic Action in the late 1940s provides
33
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
an insight into contacts between the security services and Ryan’s
operation. A senior officer, in the course of denying that he had
passed any information to Catholic Action, writes:
1. I was an officer of Commonwealth Investigation Service from
March, 1933, to October, 1949, when I transferred to ASIO. I
had official contact with Catholic Action over the greater part
of this period and visited the office of that organisation regularly
up to about 1946. My dealings were with Dr Ryan, [deleted] and
two persons whose names I do not now recall who were employed
by the organisation prior to [deleted]. I was aware that Brigadier
Alleghany and Mr Barnwell, of Commonwealth Investigation
Service, were in contact with Catholic Action in that period also.
2. From approximately 1946 my C.I.S. duties became
supervisory and I ceased to visit Catholic Action office, although
I was in telephone contact from time to time. Brigadier Galleghan
was also in contact, I think mainly by telephone, but Dr Ryan
visited Commonwealth Investigation Service’s office on at least
one occasion to see him.42
(Brigadier ‘Black Jack’ Galleghan, earlier commander of the
Australian troops in Changi, was at this time Deputy Director of
the C.I.S. in Sydney, and was soon to go to Europe to select nearly
200,000 anti-Communists, mostly Catholics, for Calwell’s
immigration program.43 Bill Barnwell was also an anti-Communist
specialist and also went to Europe to select refugees.44)
Further documents in the same ASIO file indicate that the
C.I.S., and later ASIO, continued to employ an officer at Catholic
Action headquarters, with Ryan’s approval, for the purpose of
acquiring information about suspected Communists which came
from Catholic Action members. (Payment, £2, subtracted by
Catholic Action from the officer’s salary). Catholic Action felt
the security forces were ill-informed about, especially, union
matters, and were happy to fill the gap.45 The relationship between
the two organisations was not close, and had its vicissitudes. From
the point of view of ASIO, the aim was to get information without
giving any in return, and Catholic Action sometimes resented
34
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
giving high-quality information, such as shorthand records of highlevel Party meetings, without sufficient reward in terms of
information usable for propaganda purposes. On the other hand,
C.I.S. and later ASIO suspected that information they gave
sometimes returned to them from other sources. To check this, in
1948 an officer supplied some false information, which was received
back via Naval Intelligence. More disturbing was a leak of security
information in 1948, though its nature is not disclosed. The
investigation of 1953 revealed that a Catholic Action officer had
actually worked from ASIO’s office at Edgecliff.
It will be appreciated that if [deleted] used the Edgecliffe
(sic) ASIO office for the purpose of carrying out Catholic Action
organisational work, it left ASIO open to grave repercussions, if
this became known to persons unkindly disposed toward this
organisation. Such persons could imply that ASIO and Catholic
Action were ‘hand in glove’, and working in common to the point
of sharing the same office.46
More alarmingly for all concerned, some information about
the liaison was publicly exposed. On 6 Aug 1949, W.T. Dobson,
secretary of the Industrial Group in the Federated Clerks Union,
dragged himself from Sydney Harbour into Nielsen Park, rang
the police, and claimed that Communists had thrown him from a
Manly ferry and stolen a bag containing secret documents relating
to Catholic Action. 47 Two days later, he changed his story,
confessing that he was a fanatical anti-Communist and had made
the story up to smear Communists.48 Dobson’s confession was a
relief to both sides. The Communists enjoyed portraying ‘Diver’
Dobson as typical of anti-Communists, and escaped any suspicions
that their political methods might include throwing their
opponents off ferries. The Catholics and security gained a general
scepticism about any documents that might be associated with
Dobson. That was just as well, because the Party still had the
documents (though no story as to how they came to have them),
and proceeded to splash photostats of them in Tribune and Labour
News. They led with a particularly choice item, an official letter to
Calwell agreeing to his request that a phone line be urgently
35
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
installed for Dobson in his hotel room.49 Calwell made no attempt
to deny its authenticity and was compelled to explain in Parliament:
Mr. CALWELL. – I did make representations to the PostmasterGeneral at the request of Mr. Dobson. He came to see me, and
fooled me. He came to me as the assistant secretary of the
industrial group of the Federated Clerks Union and said he had
the blessing of the head-quarters of the Labour party in New
South Wales. I plead those facts in extenuation of my lapse. He
was accompanied by another prominent representative of the
industrial group, and he told me that he was carrying on certain
work which, I believed, was of national importance. I made
representations to the Postmaster-General to the effect that Mr.
Dobson might by given telephone facilities, if that were possible,
and a silent number to enable him to carry on the work of the
industrial groups inside the union.
Mr. BEALE. – Was that work of national importance?
Mr. CALWELL. – That, to me, seemed to be work of very
great importance.50
Calwell went on to suggest Dobson was linked to the
Communists and to the Liberal Party, presumably on the principle
that the more theories about Dobson there were, the better. In
view of later events, it is not to be expected that either Calwell or
the Movement should be keen to mention their co-operation, but
the Parliamentary record is there. Calwell, one of the founders of
the Groups,51 had fallen out with them by 1948, but was still
prepared to support their anti-Communist initiatives in 1949, the
year in which the Groups caused his dumping from the Victorian
state executive of the Labor Party.52 Further documents, said to be
pages from Dobson’s private notebook, included such gems as
‘Ryan appears to get a lot of unofficial information from Security’.53
Since these facts are now confirmed by ASIO documents, there
seems no reason to deny that the Dobson notebook was as genuine
as the Calwell letter.
Dobson had committed an extraordinary series of frauds. In
1946 he had got a trip to Europe on Royal Navy ships by posing as
36
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
a war correspondent for fictitious publications. He had been jailed
for fraud in Hong Kong but escaped prosecution in Manila. In
Shanghai in 1948, he created a great deal of trouble with allegations
of corruption against an Australian member of Parliament and an
immigration official in Shanghai, and by claiming that one of the
‘top ten’ Nazis had got into Australia as an immigrant after escaping
in a U-boat to Japan. The allegations proved unfounded and
Dobson eventually confessed to fabricating them in order to
pressure the Australian consul to help him while he was imprisoned
by the Chinese (awaiting trial for fraud, naturally). Unfortunately,
one of the Dobson allegations had meanwhile turned out to be
true, namely that Australia had admitted as an immigrant a Mrs
Glatzel, alias ‘Diana Hamilton’, who had broadcast Nazi
propaganda in Shanghai during the War. Since the revelation of
this information would have created unfavourable publicity for
the immigration program, the matter was suppressed and Dobson
given a free trip home.54 The only good aspect from the antiCommunist point of view was that the combination of Dobson’s
falling on his sword and the revelation’s appearing in Tribune, whose
credit rating was poor, caused enough doubts about the whole
matter to have it forgotten among larger matters like the Coal
Strike and the coming election.
In connection with the takeovers of political bodies, there arose
a subtle question of moral philosophy, disagreements over which
caused much anguish in Movement and anti-Movement circles.
The question is, may one vote at meetings of organisations to which
one pretends to belong, but does not? James McAuley, generally
supportive of the Movement, had been most worried about the
question, and was assured by Santamaria that stacking of meetings
with people ineligible to vote had never been a Movement tactic –
or if it had once or twice happened, in Sydney, it had been put a
stop to.55 The NSW central office of the Movement did issue
instructions against stacking union meetings in general; approval
was occasionally given when there was considered to be a ‘moral
certainty’ that Communists would stack the meeting. The belief
that stacking was widespread is probably to be attributed to knee37
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
jerk reactions of those defeated in union elections by Movement
candidates.56 On the other hand, students at Sydney University,
where the Movement had spectacular success in 1951 and controlled
all major student organisations, reported that Ryan positively
encouraged Arts and Engineering students to vote at Medical
students’ meetings and vice versa. Father Pryke, then chaplain at
Sydney University and later a critic of the Movement, recalled
that ‘Dr Ryan had once come back from the Vatican and reported
to him and some Movement people that he had consulted some
top moral theologians at the Gregorian and Lateran Universities
and they had advised that Catholics were morally justified in doing
anything that Communists did’.57 Many Catholics were not
prepared to lie on demand, and left the Movement over such tactics.
Ryan’s point of view must be seen in an internationalist
perspective. The ‘top moral theologians of the Gregorian’ were of
course seeing the problem in terms of Hungary and Czechoslovakia
(and Italy, the subject of some very pessimistic assessments in
Church circles).58 There does seem something ridiculous in urging
the future victims of Stalinism in, say, Czechoslovakia in 1948, to
watch the people planning to hang them from lampposts vote
illegally at meetings, but to scrupulously avoid doing the same
themselves. Ryan and his supporters, like the Communists
themselves, transferred their vision of an international struggle of
immense forces of good and evil to the sleepy backwater of 1950s
Australia. Those who had lived all their lives in Australia, especially,
found it out of contact with local reality. The onus of justification
for dubious tactics, then, probably shifts to the question of whether
the Movement really believed a takeover of Australia by
Communists from within was possible. It is the moral consequences
of the question that account for its ability to generate so much
heat even now.59 Another factor to take into account is that the
inner Sydney branches of the ALP were not the scene of decent
and civilised exchanges of views in the first place. Branch-stacking
was a way of life in them long before the Communists, let alone
the Movement,60 and there would not have been much point in
getting involved at all in them without being prepared to match
38
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
‘normal’ tactic for tactic. Still, it is a high-risk strategy, to say the
least. What if (as Guy Fawkes no doubt wondered) one is found
out? That can be a problem even for those who do not pretend
any special ethical superiority, as Richo discovered. It is far more
of a problem for churchmen, whose raison d’être involves a bid for
occupation of the high moral ground. When it was discovered that
Ryan was, so to speak, subordinating morality to the struggle
against the proletariat, people came to suspect that ‘everyone, from
the Cardinal down, is guilty of conniving at arrant dishonesty’.61
Nothing came out into the full glare of publicity, but it is not
difficult to understand why the Sydney bishops and the Vatican
became extremely anxious to pull the plug on the Movement.
Computational casuistics is not easy.
Gilroy appointed his auxiliary, Bishop Lyons, to oversee the
Sydney Movement. Lyons did not get on with Ryan, nor, it appears,
with many other members. In 1953 Lyons had Ryan replaced as
director with a Jesuit seen to be a partisan of the Melbourne
Groupers. Ryan was widely thought to have been unjustly treated
and the resulting tension contributed to the parting of ways
between the Sydney and Melbourne branches of the Movement
that had such far-reaching consequences at the time of the Split.62
Ryan himself resented the Melbourne takeover.63 The tension is
illustrated by an event at the 1954 conference of the Movement in
Melbourne. Ryan moved that in future, not all the speeches be
given by Santamaria, as happened that year, but his motion was
soundly defeated.64 Ryan was a key speaker at the meetings in
1956 at which the vast majority of New South Wales Movement
men decided to accept the Sydney bishops’ policy of staying with
the Labor Party instead of joining their Victorian and Queensland
colleagues in what later became the DLP.65 At the meeting of seven
to eight hundred Movement leaders held at St Paul’s, Kensington,
on 30 September 1956, which finally saw the decision to ‘stay in
and fight’ agreed to by almost all, Ryan spoke after Bishop Carroll.
A participant recalled:
39
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
The substance of Dr Ryan’s address was that he would obey
his Bishop even if he thought he was wrong, but on this matter
he knew his Bishop was right – history proved that break-away
parties never lasted – ‘they were not worth two bob’.66
It was this meeting, as it happened, that provided the occasion
for the closest the bishops came to public exposure as liars. In
1959 the Catholic Weekly officially denied claims in the Sydney Morning
Herald that Catholics had been adjured to stay in the ALP ‘as a
matter of loyalty to the Cardinal’. One of the participants at the
Kensington meeting offered to name the speakers and the most
prominent of those present, if the claim were made again. Nothing
more was heard of the matter.67
In a brief document of 1962, ‘Why the Movement failed’, Ryan
argues that the original policy of purely fighting Communism
was not kept to, and the Movement began to target nonCommunists and thus became rightly seen by many Labor leaders
as a danger to themselves. Further, in some places – though not
Sydney – there was infiltration by the enemy.68 It is not entirely
clear what Ryan means by the ‘failure’ of the Movement. If it was
not intended to take control of the ALP, but only break the
Communist hold on unions, then it would appear to have
succeeded. If, on the other hand, its aim was to effect a spiritual
transformation of Australian workers and replace monopoly
capitalism with a harmonious society of medieval guilds, providing
contented artisans and farmhands with the leisure to master
scholastic philosophy, then doubtless it failed to do so, but the
prospects of success were surely so low as to make depression at
the outcome inappropriate.
Ryan was still on deck in 1968, complaining about the laxity of
Church responses to Humanae Vitae; there is no possibility, he
thinks, of a Catholic disagreeing in conscience with the Pope’s
ruling.69 He died in 1969.70
Catholic intellectual life has become more diverse since Paddy’s
day. Its leaders are, in their various ways, more professional, better
able to stay abreast of overseas developments. But who could get
thirty thousand on the trams out to Rushcutters Bay?
40
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
AFTERW ORD
In a meticulously researched article, Phillip Deery was able to
reveal how Dobson’s documents came to be in the possession of
the Communists. Dobson had sold them the documents. (P.
Deery, ‘Labor, Communism and the Cold War: the case of
“Diver” Dobson’, Australian Historical Studies 28 (1997), 66-87)
N OTES
1
C.H. Jory, The Campion Society and Catholic Social Militancy in Australia 1929-1939
(Sydney, 1986).
2
Jory, ch. 11; N. McDonald, War Cameraman: The Story of Damien Parer (Port
Melbourne, 1994), ch. 4; B.F. Duncan, From Ghetto to Crusade: A Study of the
Social and Political Thought of Catholic Opinion-Makers in Sydney During the 1930s
(PhD thesis, Dept of Government, Sydney University, 1987), pp. 221-4.
3
P. Ryan, De via morali quam ad Deum cognoscendum proposuit Eduardus le Roy, thesis,
1932.
4
P.J. Ryan, ‘The new scholasticism: its origin and history’, Catholic Press 26/4/
1934, p.6, ‘The fundamental tenets of scholasticism’, 17/5/34, p. 12, ‘The
fundamental tenets of scholasticism’, 7/6/34, p. 6, ‘Philosophy and
theology: the attitude of the moderns’, 12/7/34, p. 10.
5
O.U. Vonwiller, J. Anderson & P.J. Ryan, ‘Symposium on science, philosophy
and Christianity’, Science Journal (Sydney University), Michaelmas 1936:
24-36.1
6
‘Symposium on ‘The Origin of Life’, Catholic Press 20/7/1939, p. 27; ‘Symposium
on the ‘origin of life’, Catholic Freeman’s Journal 20/7/39, p. 30; cf. ‘Evolution’,
in Question Box, Catholic Freeman’s Journal 18/4/40, pp. 6-7; similar from
the Anglican camp in T.C. Hammond, Fading Light (London), ch. 6.
7
F.A. Mecham, ‘Evolution and man’, Australasian Catholic Record 26 (1949): 19-28,
262-8; J. Burnheim, ‘Biology versus Catholic philosophy: a new approach’,
Australasian Catholic Record 27 (1950): 267-71.
8
P.J. Ryan, The Existence of God: The Argument from Design, Annals publication no.
49 (Kensington, 1950), p. 22.
9
D. Horne, The Education of Young Donald (2nd ed, Ringwood, Victoria, 1988) pp.
179-80.
10
‘Have we freewill? Lively debate at Sydney University’, Catholic Freeman’s Journal,
27/5/1939, p. 20.
11
Reports on A.G. Hammer, W.H.C. Eddy and Dr Woodward, in Ryan archives,
section Articles, folder Teachers’ College Reports, with letter of M.D.
Forrest MSC to G.R. Thomas, NSW Director of Education, 14/12/39; Dr
41
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Rumble, Question Box, ‘Must teachers be agnostics’, Catholic Freeman’s Journal
19/10/39, p. 10; ‘Is censorship immoral’, 2/11/39, p. 6; ’Methods at
Teachers’ College’, 16/11/39, p. 6; ‘Man not rational!’, 23/11/39, p. 6;
‘Teachers’ College dogmas’, 30/11/39, p. 6; ‘Teachers’ College defended’,
7/12/39, p. 6; ‘Animals at Teachers’ College’, 14/12/39, p. 12; ‘Action at
the Teachers’ College’, 21/12/39, p. 6.
12
P. Ryan, Question Box: ‘We stand for order and sanity’, Catholic Freeman’s
Journal, 3/7/41, p. 8.4I
13
Horne, pp. 262-4.
14
‘The cat got out’, in Dr Ryan’s Question Box, Catholic Freeman’s Journal 10/7/
41, p. 8; Horne letter in Honi Soit 18 (14) (27/6/41), p. 2.
15
‘Enquiry not hindered: Ryan on religion and science’, Honi Soit 15 (12) (22/
4/43), p. 1; ’2 aspects of Ryan’s 1 truth’, Honi Soit 15 (24) (26/8/43), p. 1.
16
D. Everingham, letter, ‘Dr. Ryan refuted’, Honi Soit 15 (26) (30/9/43), p. 3.
17
‘Catholic Action: Educational lectures inaugurated’, Catholic Press 19/3/1936,
p. 10; ’Catholic Action Association’, 3/12/36.
18
Jory, p. 105; Duncan, ch. 10; ‘Rev Dr Ryan’s course of public lectures’, Catholic
Freeman’s Journal 13/7/39, p. 21; see the regular ‘Secretariat of Catholic
Action’ page in the weekly Catholic Freeman’s Journal during 1939 to mid1941.
19
P. Macphail, ‘What’s being done about adult education’, Catholic Weekly 5/9/
1946, p.3; lecture notes of the School are in the Ryan archives.
20
Quoted in N. Turner, Catholics in Australia: A Social History, (Melbourne, 1992),
vol. II, p.111.
21
P. Ryan, ‘Radio replies and comments’, The Southern Cross 2/5/1941, p. 5; ‘Rev
Dr Ryan’s Question Box’ appeared weekly in the Catholic Freeman’s Journal
from 7/3/40 to18/12/41; Protestant objections in ‘Dr. Ryan and
intolerance’, The Watchman 2 (1) (February 1942), 8, 9, 13; ‘The Loyal Orange
Institution of N.S.W. replies to Dr. Ryan (R.C.)’, The Watchman 2 (3) (Apr
1942): 10-11.
22
E. Campion, Australian Catholics (Ringwood, Victoria, 1987), pp. 134-6;
biography in Who is Father Rumble?, pamphlet (St Paul, Minnesota, n.d.).
23
Sydney Morning Herald, 22/5/43, p. 12.
24
Royal Commission on Espionage: Transcript of Proceedings, vol. 3 p. 1329.
25
P.J. Ryan, Dean Hewlett Johnson’s Socialist Sixth: A Commentary, (Sydney, 1943).
26
Campion, Australian Catholics, p. 133.
27
L.L. Sharkey, Reply to Father Ryan (1943), summarised in The Sharkey Writings, ed.
L.H. Gould (Sydney, 1974?), pp. 159-62; also L.L. Sharkey, ‘Marxism and
morals: Dr. Ryan answered’, Tribune 2/10/48, p. 7.
28
‘Stadium’s record crowd hears political debate, with big anti-Communist
majority’, Sydney Morning Herald 24/9/1948, pp. 1, 3; ‘Huge stadium crowd
shows wide interest in Communism’, Tribune 29/9/48, p. 8; ‘Ryan versus
Ross’, The Watchman 8 (10) (November 1948): 219; full text of the speeches
in ‘Full report: Dr. Ryan in debate with Communist’, Catholic Weekly 30/
42
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
9/48, pp. 1-4, 19-20; the Russian ‘postcard divorces’ were an out-of-date
allegation, as other Catholic experts were well aware: F. Sheen, Communism
and the Conscience of the West (Garden City, N.Y., 1948), ch. 7; Ryan earlier
on this in ‘Divorce by postcard’, Catholic Freeman’s Journal 18/12/41, p. 8.
29
News Weekly 15/9/1948, reported in ASIO file on Catholic Action, Australian
Archives series A6122/30 item 1222
30
E. Ross, Of Storm and Struggle (Sydney, 1982), p. 113.
31
F. Knopfelmacher, Intellectuals and Politics (Melbourne, 1968), pp. 76-7.
32
‘Dr Ryan to lecture’, Catholic Weekly 13/3/47, p. 5; ‘Priest’s bitter attack on
communism’, Sydney Morning Herald 9/10/1947, p. 4; ‘Dr Ryan’s attack on
Communism at Religion and Life Conference’, Catholic Weekly 16/10/47,
pp. 7, 21 (full text in Ryan archives, section Articles, folder Communism);
‘Priest attacks Reds at Paddington’, Catholic Weekly 6/11/47, p. 7; ‘Public
meeting’, Canberra Times 18/2/1948; ‘Civil war only aim of communists’,
Argus 2/3/1948; ‘Challenge forced Ryan to retract’, Tribune 23/6/48, p. 7;
‘Communist debater answers “loaded” question by priest’, Tribune 11/12/
48, p. 8; ‘The red menace in Australia’, pamphlet printed by Record
Printing Company, Rockhampton, 1949, with text of Ryan’s address at
Rockhampton of 3/5/49; ‘Socialists’ cure is worse than disease, says priest’,
Sydney Morning Herald 29/9/1949, p. 4; ‘Military conquest of Australia
planned by Reds’, Sydney Morning Herald 21/4/1950, p. 3 (also Sun of same
date); ‘Communist aim – world conquest’, Honi Soit 22 (21) (14/9/50), p.
2; T.P. Boland, James Duhig (St Lucia, 1986) p. 328; J.P. Maguire, Prologue: A
History of the Catholic Church as Seen From Townsville (Toowoomba, 1990), p.155.
33
Dates respectively 26/5/1951; 20/8/51; 31/8/51.
34
‘Socialists’ cure worse than disease, says priest’, Sydney Morning Herald, 29/9/
1949, p. 4; more fully in ‘Social justice for all: Dr Ryan, MSC, expounds
Christian programme’, Catholic Press, May 1941; and P.J. Ryan, World Problems,
Annals publication no. 14 (Kensington, 1938); C. Lewis, People Before Profit:
The Credit Union Movement in Australia (Kent Town, S.A., 1996), p. 15.
35
M. Hogan, ed, Justice Now! Social Justice Statements of the Australian Bishops, First
Series, 1940-1966 (Sydney, 1990); M. Hogan, ‘Australian Catholic
corporatism: proposals for industrial councils in the 1940s’, Labour History
no. 62 (May, 1992): 91-105; for a very recent iteration of traditional Catholic
opposition to laissez-faire capitalism, see A. K. Dunstan, ‘Guilds and other
matters’, Annals Australasia 117 (1), January-February 2006, pp. 24-26.
36
G. Henderson, Mr Santamaria and the Bishops (Sydney, 1982), p. 71.
37
P.J. Ryan, An Outline of Catholic Action, Annals publication no. 5 (Kensington,
1935); summary in Duncan, pp. 158-60; other Ryan pamphlets in the Annals
series are On creed and dogmas and all that (no. 6, 1936); The restoration of all things
in Christ (no. 9, 1936); The Church and marriage (no. 10, n.d.).
38
Jory, pp. 119, 144 n. 6; Duncan, p. 232; see Ryan’s Question Box, Catholic
Freeman’s Journal: ‘Red attack on Catholic Action’, 14/3/40, p. 7; ‘Catholic
43
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Action versus Communism’, 28/3/40, pp. 6-7; ‘Join your union’, 22/5/
41, p. 8 and ‘What is Catholic Action?’, 13/11/41, pp. 9, 24.
39
P. Ormonde, The Movement (Melbourne, 1972), p. 3; G. Williams, Cardinal Sir
Norman Gilroy (Sydney, 1971), p. 51; Henderson, p. 26; J. T. Kane, Exploding
the Myths (North Ryde, NSW, 1989), p. 23; R. Murray, The Split (2nd ed,
1972), p. 46.
40
B.A. Santamaria, Against the Tide (Melbourne, 1981), p. 85.
41
Williams, pp. 52-3.
42
‘Liaison with Catholic Action’, (27/10/53), in ASIO file on Catholic Action,
Australian Archives series A6122/30 item 1222.
43
S. Arneil, Black Jack: The Life and Times of Brigadier Sir Frederick Galleghan
(Melbourne, 1983), pp. 131-45; A. Davies, ‘“Black Jack” Galleghan and
the ‘D.P.s’: Australian immigration and a modern Major-General’, Australian
War Memorial History Conference, February 1983, pp. 1-16.
44
M. Bialoguski, The Petrov Story (1955, repr. Melbourne, 1989), p. 36.
45
K.C. Davis (NSW State Secretary of the Movement) to author, 15/7/95.
46
‘Irregularities and improper control of sources – leakage of security
information’, in ASIO file on Catholic Action, as above; summary in D.
McKnight, Australia’s Spies and Their Secrets (Sydney, 1994), pp. 202-3.
47
‘Anti-Communist union official says he was thrown off ferry’, Sydney Morning
Herald 7/8/49, p. 1.
48
‘Police reject story of murder attempt on ferry’, Sydney Morning Herald 8/8/49,
p. 1; ‘Industrial group plot exposed: Australia saved from tragedy’, The
Rock 5 (33) (18/8/49): 1,8; ‘“Stupid, crude”: Dobson case’, Sydney Morning
Herald, 26/10/49.
49
‘Calwell linked with Dobson’, Tribune 13/8/49, p. 1.
50
Commonwealth of Australia, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives
21 September 1949 (vol. 204 p. 395; further pp. 463-6); see also ‘Calwell’s
bid to slide out of scandal won’t fool workers’, Tribune 24/9/49: 3.
51
Calwell, Be Just and Fear Not, p. 218.
52
Calwell, p. 172.
53
Tribune 27/8/49: 3; also 7/9/49: 6; copy of latter, with denials by CIS officer,
in CIS File on Dobson, Australian Archives series A432/82 item 1949/
851.
54
Australian Archives series A1838/1 item 1542/36 (Dept of External Affairs,
Security File on Dobson).
55
Santamaria, pp. 276-7; cf. Ormonde, pp. 36-8; S. Short, Laurie Short (Sydney,
1992), p.187.
56
K.C. Davis to author, 9/5/95 and 17/5/95.
57
Ormonde, p. 43.
58
See, e.g., R. Hall, ‘Should you ever go across the sea from Ireland . . .’, Eureka
Street 5 (2) (March 1995): 24-9, at p. 29.
44
Cat holic Thought and Act ion: Dr Paddy Ryan MSC
59
P. Ormonde, ‘A sort of healing’, Eureka Street 4(9) (November 1994): 16, and
letters of K. Davis and P. Ormonde, 5(1) (January/February 1995): 7 and
5(2) (March 1995): 8.
60
G. Richardson, Whatever It Takes (Sydney, 1994), pp. 57-8; Kane, p. 41.
61
McAuley to Santamaria, 30/8/1955, quoted in Santamaria, p. 276.
62
Henderson, pp. 103-5; Williams, pp. 54-5; Santamaria, p. 167; Murray, pp.
128-9; Ryan’s complaints about Lyons in ‘Memorandum to His Eminence,
Norman Cardinal Gilroy, Archbishop of Sydney, October 1952, Subject:
The present state of the organisation in the Archdiocese’, in Ryan archives,
section Articles, folder Communism.
63
K.C. Davis to author, 9/5/95.
64
G. Henderson, ‘B.A. Santamaria and the cult of personality’, in 50 Years of the
Santamaria Movement, ed. P. Ormonde (Sydney, 1992), pp. 43-58, at p. 44.
65
Santamaria, pp. 204-6; Kane, p. 127.
66
M. Carroll to Santamaria, quoted in Kane, p. 144.
67
Kane, p. 142; Santamaria, pp. 206-7; cf. Kane to Gilroy, 21/12/1956: ‘We are
unable to reconcile your Eminence’s reported intervention with the
statement of your Secretary that you take no part in the affairs of political
parties’.
68
P. Ryan, ‘Postscript 1962: Why the Movement failed’, typescript, Paddy Ryan
archives, St Paul’s Seminary, Kensington. I am grateful to Mr Tony Caruana,
archivist at St Paul’s, for help with these archives, which have provided
much of the information on Dr Ryan.
69
P. Ryan, ‘Catholic conscience and “Humanae Vitae”,’ typescript, Ryan archives.
70
Obituary, ‘Crusader for truth’, Catholic Weekly 23/1/69, p. 3.
45
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Dr P.J. Ryan (centre), 1948
46
CH APTER TH REE
I m m igra t ion Versus
Dem ocracy
O
NE OF THE awkward features of democracy is that
some of the stakeholders in a government’s decisions
do not have votes. They include orphans in institutions,
those suffering severe mental disability, foreign nationals and
refugees seeking asylum, and it is no surprise to find them at various
times the victims of governmental interventions ranging from
bureaucratic hassles to indefinite confinement. Special difficulties
arise if a government decides, for one reason or another, that it
needs to act on behalf of one of these groups, but the voters are
unlikely to be convinced. Should the government conspire against
the electors, and pull the wool over their eyes?
A case in point is the Australian immigration program since
World War II. The transformation of Australia into a multicultural
nation since 1947 is not something that the Australian people were
asked to approve. Nor were they told the reasons why their
successive governments agreed to it.
Original source: IPA Review (June 2002), p. 29.
47
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
In 1946, Australians were almost entirely of British and Irish
descent. There were no plans to change that. Meanwhile, there
were a million anti-Communist Eastern Europeans – Baltic peoples,
Poles, Ukrainians and various others – in camps in Germany and
Austria, refusing to be shipped back East. They threatened to
disturb the reconstruction of western Europe. In contrast to the
ineffectual responses of the international community in almost
every other refugee crisis, this one was solved firmly, efficiently
and soon. In 1950, the camps were empty and were burned down.
The million refugees had been parcelled out to countries with
plenty of money and space. 180,000 of them – 2% of the Australian
population – were New Australians, and Australia’s road to
multiculturalism had begun.
The Australian people were not told any of this – of the behind
the scenes arm-twisting to round up reluctant host countries, of
the cables from Whitehall instructing the Australians to get on
with it, of the worldwide lobbying efforts by Catholic
representatives (Immigration Minister Arthur Calwell, later a Papal
knight, wrote in reply to his thank-you note from the Vatican, ‘no
letter which I have written in the six years in which I have been
privileged to hold Ministerial office in this country has given me
greater pleasure than this acknowledgement of the Holy Father’s
appreciation of my humble efforts in the cause of distressed
humanity.’) For local consumption, the story was cast in terms of
‘populate or perish’ considerations and arguments about labour
for national development. Those reasons were genuine enough as
far as they went, but they were far from the full story. The
Australian people were told only what they were likely to want to
hear.
When overpopulation threatened the political stability of Italy
and Greece in the early 1950s, the same co-ordinated action was
undertaken and Australia was again among the largest recipients.
Australia helped again with the smaller Hungarian refugee crisis
of 1956. It was not so keen to help after the fall of Saigon in 1975;
according to Employment Minister Clyde Cameron, Whitlam
48
I m m igrat ion Versus Dem ocracy
angrily refused to have any ‘f***ing Vietnamese Balts’ coming
here. But when South-east Asian nations began towing boat people
back to sea in 1979, the U.S. State Department organised
international pressure, and Australia, by then under the Fraser
government, was yet again among the largest contributors to the
resettlement of all the Vietnamese in the camps.
Contrasting those events with recent ones, Malcolm Fraser
noted that Calwell knew unionists in his time would not have
agreed to large-scale immigration, so he avoided asking them.
Similarly, Fraser said, ‘If I had asked Australians, do you want me
to embrace policies which will lead to about 200,000 Vietnamese
… coming to Australia; … if I’d taken that vote people would have
said ‘no’. But we believed that it was necessary in Australia’s interest
…’
As a reason for policy change, ‘we were pressured by great and
powerful overseas friends’ is not something a democratic
government can sell to its constituents. It may be a sound and
honourable reason for action nevertheless.
N OTE
James Franklin is, with R.J. Stove, writing a book on the
international dimensions of Australian immigration, especially of
Calwell’s Displaced Persons program of the late 1940s.
49
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
50
CH APTER FOUR
Ca t holic Schoolda ys w it h
Philosophy
I
N HIS autobiography, B.A. Santamaria recalled his
schooldays at Melbourne’s St Kevin’s College:
The type of Catholic ‘apologetics’ which was the strength
of religious teaching at St Kevin’s prepared my mind for John
Henry Newman and later C.S. Lewis, who both provided
confirmation of my religious beliefs. To the professional
philosopher, Newman and C.S. Lewis might appear to be no
more than popularizers of other men’s ideas. Yet I do not despise
the popularizer, since it seems that there are few new objections
to religious belief. What one normally encounters are new
formulations of the old objections – except, of course, for those
contemporary philosophic systems which, in complete selfcontradiction, pretend to prove the uselessness of reason as a
mechanism in the search for truth … In the last analysis, the
‘apologetics’ we absorbed could not lift religion above dependence
on an act of faith, but an act of faith sustained by, and consonant
with, reason. It was not an act of faith standing, as it were,
unsupported or contrary to reason ... Sheehan’s Apologetics and
Christian Doctrine provided me, as a schoolboy at matriculation
standard, with the rational justification for my act of faith in
Catholic Christianity. When I examine what so many Catholic
students at the same level are offered today, I stand appalled not
merely at the intellectual poverty of the offering but at the ease
with which so many so-called teachers of religion dismiss the
intellect as a convincing support for religious belief in favour of
highly subjective ‘religious experience’. I can understand why so
few students believe anything at all: for that which reason does
not sustain rests on most unsubstantial foundations when
confronted with the challenges of the ‘new morality’ (which, as
someone remarked, is only the old immorality writ large).1
51
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Santamaria here recalls a time when Catholic intellectual life, from
primary school up, was informed by a complete official philosophy,
the scholasticism of St Thomas Aquinas. Thomas Keneally’s
memoirs at the corresponding point also describe the impact of
the ‘nifty’ arguments for the existence of God in Sheehan’s
Apologetics, and represent the author as briefly inspired to combat
the evil forces of atheistic Sydney University philosophy.2 The
Catholic childhood of legend was more than guilt and incense,
and one of the essential extra ingredients was philosophy.
The Catholic Church has always been more hospitable to
philosophy than other religious bodies. It has taken the view that
if ‘reason’ is a danger to faith, as it obviously is, then the solution
is not less reason but more. It is true that the Australian Church
has always had at least its fair share of anti-intellectuals, and some
leaders of the local church have regarded the pursuits of the mind
as an irrelevance and a nuisance, but others argued the opposite,
as a response to the pluralism of a colonial society. According to a
writer of 1896:
The simple rudimentary Christian knowledge which was
sufficient for the poor exile of Erin while yet in his own saintly
island village, where his humble home was perhaps sheltered by
the ivy-clad ruins of some ancient church or monastery, where
he saw ‘books in the running brooks, sermons in stones, and
good in everything,’ did not suffice when he found himself in a
land where both press and pulpit teemed with calumny against
his Holy Faith, and where there were then few shepherds to ward
off the wolf from the fold.3
In any case, decisions on such matters were made in Rome. Official
policy was to ensure that even primary school children understood
their faith as clearly as possible, through instruction in the
Catechism. At a time when tertiary and even upper secondary
education was a rarity, the Catechism was the text that did most
to create a difference between a Catholic and a secular education.
It began on an abstract note:
Q. Who made the world?
A. God made the world.
Q. Who is God?
52
Cat holic Schooldays wit h Philosophy
A. God is the Creator of heaven and earth and of all things and
the Supreme Lord of all.
Q. How do we know that there is a God?
A. We know that there is a God by the things that He made ...
Q. If God be everywhere, why do we not see Him?
A. We do not see God, because He is a pure Spirit, and therefore
cannot be seen by us in this life …
Q. Had God a beginning?4
And that is just part of the first page. The later parts of course
do not deal in such abstract and philosophical issues, but the
precision of the definitions is notable throughout. They are a
philosophical education for those with an ear for such things:
Q. What is man?
A. Man is one of God’s creatures, composed of a body and soul,
and made to God’s likeness.
Q. How do you know that you have a soul?
A. I know that I have a soul because I am alive, and because I can
think, reason and choose freely.5
Q. What is sin?
A. Sin is any wilful thought, word, deed or omission contrary to
the law of God.6
Q. What is presumption?
A. Presumption is the expectation of salvation without making
proper use of the means necessary to obtain it.7
Q. What is a lie?
A. A lie is the saying of anything that we believe to be false.8
As an intellectual training, it was not without effect either. Little
girls came up with curly questions like ‘How could Our Lady
have free will if she couldn’t sin?’9 and ‘How could a God of
intrinsic goodness create evil?’10 The risk in relying on argument,
of course, is that the audience may not be convinced. ‘I remember
Sister Amard who tried to teach me the philosophical proofs of
the existence of God, and thereby destroyed my faith completely
because she didn’t know them; rather, she did know them but
they weren’t valid’, says Germaine Greer. She adds: ‘the nuns were
53
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
dreadfully incompetent at teaching Catholic philosophy. The
Jesuits on the other hand were very good at it, and if I’d been
taught by Jesuits I’d probably still be a Catholic.’11 The reputation
of the Jesuits for increasing the validity of arguments is no doubt
exaggerated.
The passage from Santamaria refers to the two central themes
of Catholic philosophy, the consonance of faith and reason, and
the objectivity of ethics. The Church has welcomed the search for
arguments for the existence of God,12 and has tried to resolve the
apparent incompatibilities of faith and reason, such as conflicts
between science and religion, and the problem of evil. It has also
been committed to natural law ethics. The reason murder is wrong,
on this view, is neither an arbitrary command of God (or of society,
or of our genes), nor a free-floating rule, nor some fact about the
greatest happiness of the greatest number, nor its failure to be
‘free and enterprising’ in John Anderson’s sense, but the intrinsic
worth of persons, which makes their destruction wrong. As Paddy
Ryan explained it:
Ultimately, then, the morality of human acts is not to be
explained by the civil legislation, public opinion and tradition,
nor the authority of great men, nor mere utility, nor by gradual
evolution from brute beginnings, nor their relation to the
production of the super-man, but by their conformity to the law
of God, founded in the nature and essential relationships of things,
and known by reason. On the other hand, the morality or
immorality of our acts does not depend wholly on God’s will. In
other words, a thing is not always bad because God forbids it;
God forbids it because it is bad.13
The two themes themselves stem from a more basic doctrine,
also mentioned by Santamaria. Thomas Aquinas inherited from
Aristotle an unusually optimistic view of reason’s ability to know
important truths. While sense knowledge may be subject to
manifold errors, the human mind, it was believed, has an ability
to understand with certainty important matters of principle, like
mathematics, philosophy and ethics. It is this capacity to
understand objective general facts about the world that grounds
both our reasoning about God and our ethical conscience.
54
Cat holic Schooldays wit h Philosophy
N OTES
1
B.A. Santamaria, Santamaria: A Memoir (Melbourne, 1997), p. 8.
2
T. Keneally, Homebush Boy (Melbourne, 1995), pp. 37, 43, 45; similar in Sweet
Mothers, Sweet Maids, ed. K. & D. Nelson (Ringwood, 1986), pp. 168-9.
3
M.J. Treacy, ‘The necessity of being able to give a reason for the faith that is
in us’, Australasian Catholic Record 2 (1896), pp. 412-24, at pp. 415-6.
4
Catechism of Christian Doctrine: Adapted for Australia by 2nd and 3rd Plenary Councils
(4th ed, Sydney, 1944), p. 11; almost identical, but lacking the third
question, in Catechism: Approved for General Use by the Cardinal Delegate, Archbishops
and Bishops (Sydney, 1905), p. 9; see M. Sheehan, ‘Some remarks on the
catechism problem’, ACR 14 (1937), pp. 182-9; recollections in J. Redrup,
Banished Camelots: Recollections of a Catholic Childhood (Sydney, 1997), pp. 127-8.
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
Catechism, 1944, p. 12.
Catechism, 1905, p. 25, ‘actual sin’ in 1944, p. 29.
Catechism, 1944, p. 34.
Catechism, 1944, p. 38; cf. A. Coady, ‘The morality of lying’, Res Publica 1 (2)
(Winter, 1992), pp. 6-9.
Nelson, Sweet Mothers, Sweet Maids, p. 130.
J. Arnold, Mother Superior Woman Inferior (Melbourne, 1985), p. 101, cf. pp.
143-4.
G. Greer in There’s Something About a Convent Girl, ed. J. Bennett & R. Forgan
(London, 1991), pp. 88, 92; also in C. Packer, No Return Ticket (Sydney,
1984), p. 88.
12
Arguments for the existence of God in the apologetic style in L. Rumble,
Radio Replies in Defence of Religion (Sydney, 1936), ch. 1; L. Rumble, Questions
People Ask About the Catholic Church (Kensington, 1972), ch. 1; L. Dalton, Can
We Prove There Is A God? (Kensington, 1939); P.J. Ryan, The Existence of God:
13
The Argument from Design (Kensington, 1950).
P.J. Ryan, ‘The fundamental tenets of scholasticism’, Catholic Press 17/5/1934,
p. 12 & 7/6/1934, p. 6.
55
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
56
CH APTER FI VE
Ca m pion’s Aust ra lia n
Cat holics
E
DMUND CAMPION’s book, Rockchoppers, published in
1982, was a major publishing success, for a book about
religion. There was more to this than the novelty of a priest
writing something that people wanted to read. It was a very
personal, readable and direct account of the author’s reaction to
the changes in the Church in his lifetime. Since his reaction was
that virtually all the changes were good, Campion came in for a
good deal of fire from conservatives; a particularly severe review
in Quadrant (November 1982) was entitled, ‘The disintegration of
intellectual Catholicism.’ But the critics found little of what the
Catholic Weekly film reviews used to call ‘objectionable scenes and
other reservations’ – no heresies, no really nasty political
commitments, no scurrilous attacks on saintly elders. Many
readers, both members and non-members of the Church, found
the book a valuable account of one man’s faith.
The natural question about any author’s second book is, is it
as good as his first? Or even, is it different from his first? Australian
Catholics is a much less personal book than Rockchoppers, much more
an objective social history. Campion has certainly taken to heart
the criticism that Rockchoppers was too much about the author and
Review of Australian Catholics, by Edmund Campion (Viking). Original source:
Quadrant 32 (1/2) (January-February 1988), pp. 114-6
57
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
his coterie. There is even an element of overkill in his determination
to include every Catholic group, of every persuasion. Everything is
in it – frontier nuns, the Holy Name Society, Catholic homosexuals,
seminaries, relief agencies, the Assumption Society for Invalids.
That account is throughout clear, well-written and fast-moving.
The impression left is of an Australian Catholic culture of immense
size. ‘The apron bar had sold 250 aprons by early afternoon’, said
the report of the 1967 Moonee Ponds parish fête; how many times
does that item have to be multiplied to give an idea of the size of
the Catholic enterprise? The impression is often of huge energy,
too, especially in the early years. Like the universe, Australian
Church history seems to have been a slow working out of massive
clashes of elemental forces in its early minutes.
The famous conflict between Mary McKillop and the Bishop
of Adelaide, which resulted in her (temporary) excommunication,
was apparently only one of such clashes of titans. Vows of poverty
and celibacy left these people with a large surplus of energy to
expend. Joined to a vow of obedience, and confined, such energy
could produce a St Thérèse of Lisieux; the Australian Church
represents the opposite extreme, where there was a continent to
expand in. In fact, Australia did not even get a random sample of
those who took vows as priests and nuns. Our presbyteries and
convents were largely built by Irish who had not only taken vows,
but also volunteered to go to the other end of the world for life.
Such a sample has an over-representation of the power-mad,
naturally, leading to the spectacular struggles between bishops and
mothers superior at one level, and at another the impact on young
minds that has produced the ‘Catholic childhood’ of literature.
Generations of seven-year-olds believing they will be eternally
burnt if they miss Mass on Sunday is a part of Australian Catholic
history that celebratory volumes like Campion’s omit, but that
has to be included in a fair evaluation. Balancing that is an opinion
of a pupil of the nuns, quoted by Campion:
Convent girls are inducted into life by a rare and eccentric
breed of women who reject the servility of marriage with all the
paraphernalia of middle-class acquisitiveness. If it hadn’t been for
58
Cam pion’s Aust ralian Cat holics
the nuns, I might well have gone to a secretarial college, had streaks
put in my hair and married a stockbroker.
This is from an Australian Women’s Weekly article by Germaine
Greer.
As Campion’s story approaches the present, more of it is taken
up with Left-Right battles. Of course, this in-fighting is only
pursued by a minority, and the majority reasonably enough takes
no notice and continues with the serious work of the Church, like
its spiritual life and the St Vincent de Paul Society. On the other
hand, the matter looms large in public perceptions – during the
papal visit of 1986, the newspapers wrote about little else. The
outcome of these struggles also affects the future, by influencing
what is taught in the schools.
The ‘Left’ and ‘Right’ in the Church are not to be simply
identified with the Left and Right generally; to begin with, both
sides regard politics as of secondary importance. This complicates
the picture, so here is a very quick guide to the two camps.
The Left can generally be recognised by the use of the Greek
words like ‘charism’ and ‘kerygma’. They are in favour of
contraception (but not usually abortion), home Masses, and
married and women priests, and find the terms ‘dialogue’ and
‘social justice’ inspiring. Their vocabulary is further explained by
their belief that the language of serious theology is German. They
see the Right as a clique of grim-faced clerics and poorly-educated
fathers of ten, unable to open their minds to the modern world.
They believe that the Right will die off in due course, but in the
meantime has too much influence with the bishops.
The Right may be recognised by saying, ‘Vatican II was only a
pastoral Council.’ They are in favour of the Pope and St Thomas
Aquinas, and find the terms ‘magisterium’ and ‘the family’
inspiring. They see the Left as a small band of café intellectuals
and pregnant social workers, who adhere to various heresies already
condemned by many Councils. They believe the Left will gradually
disappear, as trendy priests marry and leave the Church, but that
in the meantime the Left has too much influence with the bishops.
59
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Though Campion is by now the chief spokesman of the
Catholic Left in Australia, Australian Catholics represents a certain
attempt to be even-handed. Give or take a few patronising remarks,
he succeeds, up to about 1960. Unfortunately the account of the
last thirty years is both perfunctory and one-sided. There is even a
slight suggestion that he tried to be fair earlier in order to be partisan
later. Campion thinks that the loss of numbers and confidence in
the 1960s and 1970s is giving way to a revival, led by dynamic
people on the Left like himself. Certainly there is a revival.
Catholics are now the largest religious denomination in Australia;
their numbers showed an increase in the last census, and in the
one before, while all other major denominations declined.
Catholics schools are bulging, and the vigour of groups at the parish
level is obvious. But there is nothing especially Left-leaning about
any of this. Opus Dei is as vigorous as any other Catholic
organisation.
There is another gap in Campion’s story. Australian Catholics
are numerous, and a picturesque lot, but what are they for? Perhaps
it is too much to ask a historian to answer that question, but since
the only readable books about Australian Catholicism are by
historians – notably Campion, Patrick O’Farrell and Tim Suttor
– it is not too much to expect them to give some idea of what
Catholics have to offer.
Australians’ problems are not primarily about wealth. The
concern for most is not how to acquire material things, but what
to do with them, and themselves. Australia is much afflicted by
materialism, in both the philosophical and the jacuzzi-owning
senses. Neither kind has anything to say about what is worth doing;
everyone knows this. But some things are worth doing, others are
not, others are wrong; everybody knows this too. So the supply
of moral indignation is siphoned off by the political Left, or by
the political Right’s reaction to the idiocies of the Left. Surely this
is getting us nowhere. In Rockchoppers, Campion tells of going to
one of James McAuley’s last major speeches, and being shocked
that the main subject matter was the importance of parliamentary
democracy. This is not very fair to McAuley, but the instinct is
60
Cam pion’s Aust ralian Cat holics
sound. Defending liberalism and the literary classics does not
constitute much of an aim in life. Catholics have something
different to say: the moral and spiritual parts of a person can go
together with thinking of the highest standard, resulting in the
best possible understanding of the world and the clearest view of
what should be done.
Thinking, regrettably, has not been one of the strong points
of the Australian Church. Campion treats well one of the bestknown facts about Australian Catholic history; so much effort
was put into building a complete education system that there wasn’t
much left over for other things. Thought, for example. Individuals
have emerged who could think constructively: B. A. Santamaria
and Ronald Conway have produced intelligent comment over many
years, and Francis Xavier Costigan and Tony Fitzgerald have given
us intelligence-led action. But in encouraging Santamaria and his
colleagues in the 1930s, Mannix was as out of step with other
Church leaders as he was in other ways. The organised Church
had done little to encourage a serious Catholic intellectual life,
and one has not emerged. This is especially true in Sydney, where
St John’s College of Sydney University stands as a symbol. The
uneducated Catholics of Sydney gave generously to build it, and
got a nice building full of beer and football.
Poor performance on the intellectual front must be the
fundamental cause of the recent shambles over the Catholic
Commission for Justice and Peace. Of course the bishops had to
support justice, and that meant being associated with efforts to
keep the problem of Third World poverty on the national agenda.
But there was just no-one intelligent to do the work. Consequently,
the level of argument in the CCJP’s statements and its associated
journal, National Outlook, was so low that it had to be put a stop to.
If Australian Catholics are going to make the impact they
should, something must be done. Campion and others have done
well with Catholic history. Now the Church has to find, encourage
and pay for Catholic philosophers, novelists, psychiatrists and
theologians who can tell Australians what they need to hear.
61
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
62
CH APTER SI X
Sa nt a m a ria ’s Europea n
Sensibilit y
N
O OTHER COUNTRY’s Catholicism produced a
figure like B.A. Santamaria. And if he had been
destined to exist somewhere, Australia should have been
the least likely place for him to fall to earth. The sceptical, secular,
isolated Anglophone society of mid-twentieth-century Australia
was stony ground for an ideologue with a European sensibility
and a vast plan to reorder society according to a rational and divine
order. Any new book on the sources and meaning of the Santamaria
phenomenon is welcome. Santamaria: The Politics of Fear is not
however exactly new. It is largely a rerun of Paul Ormonde’s 1972
book, The Movement. Santamaria’s opponents from the leftist Catholic
Worker group of the early 1960s, Max Charlesworth, Xavier
Connor, James Griffin, Val Noone and Ormonde, regroup to have
the last word on why they were right all along. They take no
notice of anything that has come to light since 1972, such as boat
people or Soviet archives, that might suggest there was anything
whatever in Santamaria’s claims about the reality of Communist
threats. It is a book that would look naive if it had appeared in,
say, Czechoslovakia.
Review of Paul Ormonde (ed.), Santamaria: The Politics of Fear (Spectrum
Publications, Melbourne). Original source: Journal of the Australian Catholic Historical
Society 22 (2001), pp. 82-3
63
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
From the point of view of Catholic history, the most
interesting chapter is Colin Thornton-Smith’s trawl through all
the surviving evidence of Santamaria’s early speeches and writings.
Some lurid quotes are turned up, such as his 1936 defence of the
Italian invasion of Abyssinia: ‘Italy had only two alternatives, Haile
Selassie or Marie Stopes, war or race suicide!’ An attempt to pin
antisemitism on Santamaria is not entirely successful. There are
no actual anti-Semitic statements in his name, although a filler in
one issue of the Catholic Worker under his editorship is an item
downloaded from Action Française propaganda that arguably has an
antisemitic tinge, while Santamaria’s mentor Denys Jackson took
European Catholic theories about a world Jewish-Masoniccapitalist-pinko plot more seriously than they deserved. ThorntonSmith touches more on the true origins of the Santamaria thoughtworld in his remark that ‘Any twinges of theological doubt he
may have had were dispelled by the triumphalist certitudes of
Archbishop Sheehan’s Apologetics and Christian Doctrine.’
‘Triumphalist’ Sheehan may have been, but he knew a valid
argument from a piece of cheap rhetoric. The reason Sheehan
worked so hard with argument was that he knew outsiders were not
convinced by the alleged certainties of Christianity, and that
convincing argument was the only way to challenge them. The
message of Sheehan’s Apologetics was that anyone could promote an
ideology as far out of step with the historically limited platitudes
of the day as he liked, provided he had a chain of rigid deductions
from first principles to rely on. By the late 1960s, when the leftward
tide of opinion was running at its strongest, there was only one
accessible media outlet where a coherently argued response could
be found. It was Santamaria’s weekly TV slot, Point of View. Many
a student radical surreptitiously tuned in to it, and more than a
few came to wonder if all the good arguments were on one side.
64
CH APTER SEVEN
Tra dit iona l Ca t holic
Philosophy:
Ba by a nd Ba t hw a t er
I
FIRST ATTENDED the Aquinas Academy in 1973. That
was the last full year its founder, Dr Austin Woodbury, taught,
and the operation had seen better days by then – ‘the Doc’ was
inclined to repeat his anecdotes, the examples of racehorses in the
notes dated from the 1940s, attendance was down. That was hardly
a surprise since it was getting on for thirty years since he founded
the Aquinas Academy and about fifty years since his own intensive
study of scholastic philosophy in Rome. (I use ‘scholastic’ as a
shorthand for the philosophy he taught; the word refers to the
‘schools’ of philosophy of the middle ages, especially that of St
Thomas Aquinas.) It was primarily an evening school, aimed
principally at the laity, and was for many years a remarkably
successful operation. In 1961, for example, it was running nineteen
classes a week, with a total enrolment of some 500 – and that in a
city much smaller than today.1
Woodbury was a charismatic classroom teacher. The artist
John Ogburn recalled:
Frequently Woodbury would send me to the canvas with
his answer and I responded to this as a miner greets the fresh air
after working a double shift underground. Through the teaching
65
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
of these two men [Woodbury and the artist Orban] I had at last
found the source of that clear stream of loveliness and beauty,
the Being from which or in which all other beings are. I could
now start to paint seriously.2
That was not quite my experience. I found the lectures full of
unintelligible formulas. So I went back to Thomas Aquinas to find
what was behind it. I was still not much the wiser, so I went back
a step further to Aristotle, the philosopher from whom Aquinas
took his main ideas. I finally made some progress.
Woodbury was well known for his aggressive views on other
philosophers, notably the atheist Professor John Anderson at
Sydney University. In 1952 Woodbury claimed publicly, ‘The
department of philosophy in the University of Sydney is a cancer
at what ought to be the heart of the scholastic life of this city. It is
a disgrace to the University of Sydney, and would be a disgrace to
any university anywhere. I would warn students, and the parents
of students, that a grave risk to their future intellectual and moral
life is incurred by students who follow the course of philosophy at
the University of Sydney without at the same time taking courses
at this academy.’ Anderson deigned to reply, at least briefly,
describing Woodbury’s attack as ‘sheer rubbish and propaganda’.
‘Dr Woodbury not only knows nothing about philosophy, but he
knows nothing about the department of philosophy at the
University.’ Intellectual polemic in Sydney is not what it used to
be … As the Melbourne philosopher Rai Gaita says, in Sydney we
not only put the boot in, we make sure it is steel-tipped to begin
with.
Like many forms of thought and organisations still found in
odd corners at the end of the Sixties (the DLP, for example), the
scholastic philosophy that Woodbury taught came to be regarded
in many circles as hopelessly outmoded. The Aquinas Academy
itself fell to a kind of coup by people of a Jungian orientation,
more interested in modern psychology than in mediaeval
philosophy. The present Aquinas Academy descends from them.
The spirit of the Second Vatican Council was hostile to the old
66
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy: Baby and Bat hwat er
style of philosophy that had dominated seminary training – or at
least, many people thought it was, though of course the ‘spirit of
Vatican II’ is a hotly contested article, and there is nothing in the
letter of the Council’s documents that denies scholastic philosophy.
***
My purpose is to put forward three views:
·
·
·
Scholastic philosophy is still very much with us,
in the teaching of the present and previous Pope
and those who agree with them.
The basics of scholastic philosophy, especially its
views on the natural law foundation of ethics, are
right and we cannot do without them.
Some of its more esoteric deductions on ethics
from the principles are not adequately justified.
Vatican pronouncements on contraception, euthanasia, glutenfree hosts3 and so on are still driven by deductions from the
scholastic philosophy of Thomas Aquinas and his followers. That
is why they are at odds with the consensus of early thirdmillennium Western intellectuals. Pope John Paul II had the same
thesis supervisor as Dr Woodbury and has never given any
indication of doubting any of Aquinas’s doctrines (though unlike
Woodbury he did add to his scholastic formation a serious study
of certain twentieth-century philosophers). He makes clear his
commitment to the thought of Aquinas many times. For example
near the beginning of his 1993 encyclical on the foundations of
morality, The Splendour of Truth, he complains that ‘the traditional
doctrine regarding the natural law, and the universality and the
permanent validity of its precepts, is rejected [by many]; certain
of the Church’s moral teachings are found simply unacceptable;
and the Magisterium itself is considered capable of intervening in
matters of morality only in order to “exhort consciences” and to
“propose values”.’4 There are many other pro-scholastic statements
of the same kind.
67
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Not everyone approves of the conclusions the Pope drew from
his philosophy. But the attempted answers to him have mostly
been disappointing. If one does not like some of the deliverances
of his philosophical thought – for example, its policy on condoms
and AIDS – then it is not satisfactory to condemn it as outmoded,
or patriarchal, or out of touch with reality, or reactionary, or
pigheaded, or clerical, or Polish. It or some of those promoting it
may or may not suffer from those defects, but that does not bear
on whether the philosophy itself or the conclusions from it are
true. The proponents of those ideas are rightly unimpressed by
those accusations. They put forward a philosophy and arguments
for it, and answers to them must be in the same terms – either an
explanation of why the principles of that philosophy are wrong,
or argument that the conclusions deduced about particular cases
from those principles do not follow. A dryer task that expressing
indignation, perhaps, but the only relevant way to proceed.
***
Natural law ethics is based on a simple idea. A caricature of it
has it saying ‘If God had meant us to fly, he would have given us
wings.’ That is not what it is about. It would be better to start
with the Nuremberg trials. The judges at Nuremberg said that it
was not up to the Nazis to develop historical understandings of
morality as they saw fit, understandings, for instance, that Jews
were vermin who deserved to be exterminated. What prevents the
Nazis doing that is the fact that Jews, like other humans, have an
intrinsic worth that makes killing them wrong. That is an objective
fact – not a scientific fact, but a moral one.
The central idea in scholastic or ‘natural law’ ethics is that
the objectivity of ethics is founded on the nature of humans. The
reason murder is wrong, on this view, is neither an arbitrary
command of God (or of society, or of our genes), nor a free-floating
rule, nor some fact about the greatest happiness of the greatest
number, but the intrinsic worth of persons, which makes their
68
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy: Baby and Bat hwat er
destruction wrong. Dr ‘Paddy’ Ryan, the celebrated Sydney
scholastic philosopher and anti-Communist crusader of the 1940s,
explained:
Ultimately, then, the morality of human acts is not to be
explained by the civil legislation, public opinion and tradition,
nor the authority of great men, nor mere utility, nor by gradual
evolution from brute beginnings, nor their relation to the
production of the super-man, but by their conformity to the law
of God, founded in the nature and essential relationships of things,
and known by reason. On the other hand, the morality or
immorality of our acts does not depend wholly on God’s will. In
other words, a thing is not always bad because God forbids it;
God forbids it because it is bad.5
Surely there is something fundamentally right about that. If
we were to deny that there is some sort of intrinsic worth of
persons, we would be agreeing with the view of atheist materialism
that humans are fundamentally the same kinds of things as galaxies
– just heaps of atoms. In that case, there is no distinction between
an exploding galaxy and the death of a human. But we all really
know that the explosion of a lifeless galaxy is just a firework but
the death of a human is a tragedy. The concept of tragedy, and a
serious reading of all our other moral vocabulary, does not make
sense in the absence of a concept of the objective worth of persons.
What makes us Catholics philosophically as opposed to both
atheists and religious fundamentalists is a strong sense of the
inherent value of people, prior to any wishes of people or
commands of God.
Although the worth of persons is a high-level principle, it
makes a difference at a very detailed level. The most dramatic
outcome of Catholic philosophy in Australia in recent times has
been the High Court’s Mabo judgement on Aboriginal land rights.
The fundamental issue in the case was the conflict between the
existing law based on the principle of terra nullius and what the
judges took to be objective principles of justice. The existing law
held that the white settlers of Australia had found the land
unoccupied, as if the aboriginal inhabitants were just tourists who
walked over the land without in any sense possessing it; therefore
69
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
the land belonged to no-one and the whites could occupy it. The
judges in the Mabo case agreed that it is a very serious matter to
overturn existing law, and that it could only be done if the doctrine
of terra nullius could be found inconsistent with one of the basic
underlying principles of the law. That principle, they said, is a
simple one: equality before the law. ‘No case can command
unquestioning adherence if the rule it expresses seriously offends
the values of justice and human rights (especially equality before
the law).’6
Sir William Deane, one of the judges in the case, was happy to
mention (later) his commitment to natural law principles. ‘The
basis of natural law’, he says, ‘is the belief that some things are
innately right and some innately wrong, flowing from the nature
of things, including our nature as human beings. That approach
provides a philosophical basis for seeing such things as human
rights as going deeper than any particular act of Parliament or
what have you. That is not exclusively Catholic. It runs through
Christian belief.’7
Deane also emphasised how much detail it is possible to derive
from the principles. In a remarkable passage on the natural law
basis of international law, as founded by Aquinas and his Spanish
followers, he had earlier said ‘This basis gave international law a
rich philosophical foundation which was a source of unlimited
development. In it there is a reservoir of rules for all situations and
cases. A law based on natural law can never grow out of touch
with the current needs of nations.’8 Sir Gerard Brennan, one of
the other Mabo judges, has an equally remarkable passage where
he advises that the point of the endless complications of commercial
law is not to provide many opportunities for legal loopholes, but
so that the lawyer can advise his client’s conscience with due
complexity.
Those beliefs about natural law are not agreed to by the kind
of judges appointed to the High Court by the Howard
Government. They regard the attempt to make law conform to
principles of justice as an unwarranted ‘judicial activism’, and
70
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy: Baby and Bat hwat er
complain that the ‘activists’ replace ‘strict rules with flexible
standards based on their own notions of reasonableness, fairness
and efficiency.’9 Without their explicitly saying so, it is clear that
these lawyers do not believe in the existence of any objective
standard of justice to which law ought to conform. The conflict
about these very basic matters of the philosophy of ethics makes a
difference.
***
To clarify our ideas on natural law ethics, let us run briefly
through some objections to it.
In the light of our strong grasp of human worth, should we
be impressed by arguments that ethics cannot be objective because
different tribes have different moral views, or we understand how
ethical views have developed historically, or we know from
psychology what makes us believe our ethical opinions? As the
Pope put the problem, ‘The great concern of our contemporaries
for historicity and for culture has led some to call into question
the “immutability of the natural law” itself, and thus the existence
of “objective norms of morality” valid for all people of the present
and the future, as for those of the past. Is it ever possible, they ask,
to consider as universally valid and always binding certain rational
determinations established in the past ... ?’10
(Now, it is true that on the natural law view, our ethics could
change to some degree if we came to know human nature better.
In fact that has happened, as when a better grasp of human equality
made it clearer that slavery was wrong. Perhaps the last century’s
advances in psychological understanding made some difference too,
but the best of psychological research has been continuous with
what we knew already. For example, the discovery that abuse of
children caused long-term trauma means we understand that child
abuse is worse than we thought; but still, we always knew it was
serious. And psychology has given us a better idea of when blame
is appropriate and when treatment is needed instead of moral
71
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
advice, but those things are only marginal to the questions about
right and wrong that natural law is concerned with. By and large,
ethics should not change with time, on the natural law view, except,
like mathematics, by being better understood.)
The objections from historicity, psychology and so on all claim
to undermine the objectivity of ethics by finding causes for our
ethical views. But the argument that the objectivity of a belief is
undermined by knowing what caused it is a bad argument. It is an
instance of what my philosophy teacher David Stove named as
the winner in his ‘competition to find the worst argument in the
world’ – the argument that we can only know things through our
perceptual organs, or through or cultural understanding or
whatever, therefore we cannot know things as they are in
themselves. It is like saying that the display on a calculator is just
caused by its wiring, so there is no reason to believe it is right. Or
even more bluntly, it is like saying ‘we have eyes, therefore we
can’t see.’11
The objection that morals are diverse among different tribes is
not convincing either. It needs longer discussion than I can give it
here, but I would argue that it is taken care of by a combination of
the replies that at the more fundamental levels, there is not a great
deal of diversity in morals (John Paul II mentions respect for parents
as they deserve as almost universal)12 and that we can dismiss some
ethical conclusions of some tribes as simply mistaken, the way we
would dismiss the views of tribes who thought there were no
numbers bigger than four.13 For example, we dismiss the Nazi
tribe’s view that Jews are vermin because we understand that the
reasons they gave for those views were rubbish. Skull measurements
cannot possibly be relevant to the ethical worth of any persons.
So to the question ‘Who are we to say (that other cultures have
made mistakes in ethics)?’, natural law thinking would answer ‘It
is everybody’s job to say (that blowing up infidels is wrong)’.
The same reasoning applies to the idea that we must ‘make
our own values’ (as in, ‘I’m not going to take orders from any
Church, I need to do my own thinking and determine my own
values.’) That has a Nazi tinge about it too – it is no accident that
72
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy: Baby and Bat hwat er
the most famous Nazi film was called Triumph of the Will. On a
natural law view, making your own values is as misconceived as
making your own additions. Sure, you can add up a column of
figures and write down any answer you like at the bottom. A
number of prominent Sydney businessmen availed themselves of
that freedom, and several of them are before the courts at the
moment. Any sum is possible, but only one sum is right. Any
estimation of the ethical worth of other people is possible, but
one that estimates others as worth less than yourself is wrong.
***
It is by now clear that it is very hard to do the things one
normally does in ethics, such as defend human rights, condemn
injustice and so on, without committing oneself to the basics of
natural law ethics. If humans do not have an objective worth, why
are we bothering with the injustices done to them?
One last reason for believing in the objective worth of persons
comes from the problem of evil. As is well-known, it is very difficult
for religion to deal with the question, How could God allow so
much evil to happen? That is a very fair question, but it only
makes sense if the evil happens to beings for whom evil really
matters, that is, ones of objective worth. There is no problem for
evil for cockroaches, because it does not matter what happens to
cockroaches. There is only a problem of evil for humans because
humans have great worth, so that it matters a great deal if they
suffer. Any conclusions drawn from the problem of evil need to
take account of that. Which is not so easy.14
***
Now we come to some more detailed ethical matters. The
principle that all humans have worth, indeed an equal worth, is
very general, whereas moral questions are very particular. Plainly
there is work needed to fill in the gap between the ethical principle
73
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
and the particular cases. Concerning euthanasia, for example, does
a respect for the worth of persons imply keeping them alive at all
costs, or assisting them in a decision to end life?15
Here, Catholic thinking has again turned to the concept of
the ‘nature’ of humans, but in a way that appeals to more detailed
facts about humanity than merely their equal worth.
***
There is an interesting diagnosis of Catholic ethics by Alan
Donagan, originally from Melbourne but for many years Professor
of Philosophy at the University of Chicago. He was broadly
sympathetic to Catholic ethics but believed it had made a
fundamental mistake at this point, where Catholic thought
attempted to ‘read off’ morality from the purposes of various
organs. He considers Aquinas’s analysis of what is wrong with
lying. Aquinas says ‘since words are naturally signs of thoughts, it
is unnatural and wrong for anyone by speech to signify something
he does not have in his mind.’16 So Aquinas is not appealing directly
to anything about the worth of persons, but just to what is natural
for the part of the person that deals with language production.
Donagan argues that Aquinas has gone wrong on two points. First,
he says, Aquinas has not established that it is the natural purpose
of speech to express what is in the speaker’s mind: speech is to
communicate, but an act of misinformation, for which there could
be a good reason, is not unnatural. Secondly, Donagan says, Aquinas
has not explained why it is wrong to prevent natural activities
reaching their natural end; for example, we prevent animals
performing naturally if we eat them, but there is nothing wrong
with that. To explain why lying is wrong, Donagan says, one must
recall that in the normal case with communication, one lies for
the purpose of harming someone, and the harm explains why it is
wrong; if, however, telling the truth is what would harm someone,
it is telling the truth that is wrong.17 His analysis thus appeals
directly to the worth of persons. He went on to write a book, The
74
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy: Baby and Bat hwat er
Theory of Morality, that shows how the morality we normally assume
can be deduced from implicit principles of the worth of persons.
Donagan is right to emphasise that appeals like Aquinas’s to
what is natural are something added to the original idea of natural
law based on the equal worth of persons. He comments ‘one reason
why the scholastic theory has had less influence outside Catholic
circles than it merits, is that it is assumed to be a seamless unity,
and that little is known of it but arguments like St Thomas’ against
lying. It is widely believed that if you reject such arguments (that
against artificial contraception is, of course, the best known) then
you must deny that there is a natural law: that is, you must abandon
the conception of the moral law as a matter of human reason.’
(He could have mentioned also that the ‘seamless unity’ theory
has the problem that the Church has admitted to mistakes a few
times – on usury and on religious freedom and the Inquisition.)
In summary, he suggests that natural law in the style of the
Nuremberg trials is all right, but that Catholic morality has been
misled by arguments that really do amount to saying ‘if God had
meant us to fly, he would have given us wings.’
Is he right?
I am sorry to complicate things further, but not so fast.
We will find ourselves more in sympathy with Aquinas’
thought on lying if we recall that language production is done by
the whole cognitive and speech system – the mind that knows the
truth and decides to utter either the truth or its opposite. Surely
there is something to be said for the idea that the point of the
cognitive system is be aligned with the truth, as far as possible,
and hence that forcing it to serve falsehood is a perversion that is
unworthy of its dignity and its role in human life? Do we not
think of people gaoled for fraud, ‘You’re only on the planet once,
what are you doing wasting your life and your intelligence deceiving
people?’ If we are forced to lie, as in the classic case of misleading
a would-be murderer on the location of a knife, that is the right
thing to do, but still does a kind of violence to the cognitive system
– indeed, the point of the example is the need for a serious reason
75
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
to overcome the natural orientation of the system to the truth.
Cognition is integral to being human, not a tool, which is why
the notions of perversion and violence apply.
That is the kind of appeal to natural use of organs that has
ethical credibility.
However, in the case of misleading the would-be murderer with
a lie, we should not think of ourselves as doing something
‘intrinsically evil’, lying, so that good may come of it. The case
simply presents a conflict between the worth of the potential victim
and the normal orientation to truth of our cognitive system.
Obviously the rights of the potential victim prevail in this case.
***
Let us take another example where reasoning from what is
natural for humans is strong. Consider what advice you would
give to a daughter of yours who told you she was considering
starring in porn films as a career. (True, the scenario is not very
realistic, since a daughter with an adequate parent is probably not
thinking of that particular career.) She says she has found a
recommended place of employment, the Occupational Health and
Safety guidelines are in place, and she asks what is wrong with
simulated sex for money. What would you say (after you’d
recovered)?
You might reply along these lines:
‘That is not looking after yourself. Sex is too close a part of
the personality to be exposed for money. It is just the nature of sex
that it is a way of giving yourself very one-to-one and privately.
That’s why rape is worse than an assault of similar physical severity
and why we’re especially concerned about sexual abuse of children:
it is because the sexual part of the personality is close and private
that a violation of it is serious. For the same reason, doing
something else that doesn’t suit it, like trading it for money, is
harming yourself even if you consent. It is like staying deliberately
ignorant by refusing to learn anything at school – doing that harms
the intellectual part of the personality, and it’s wrong whether
you consent or not.’
76
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy: Baby and Bat hwat er
Those arguments, both as to sex and education, are appeals to
details about what human nature is like: starring in porn films
and deliberate ignorance are perversions of our nature, or failures
to develop what is good about our nature.
***
It is an argument of that sort that Paul VI gave against
contraception in his 1968 encyclical Humanae Vitae. This is the full
argument, which is intended to be free-standing and apply to all
humans, irrespective of their religious beliefs.
Each and every marital act must of necessity retain its
intrinsic relationship to the procreation of human life. This
particular doctrine … is based on the inseparable connection,
established by God, which man on his own initiative may not
break, between the unitive significance and the procreative
significance which are both inherent to the marriage act. The
reason is that the fundamental nature of the marriage act, while
uniting husband and wife in the closest intimacy, also renders
them capable of generating new life – and this as a result of laws
written into the actual nature of man and of woman.18
That is the complete argument. It is hard to argue further either
for or against it. It seems to me inadequate, but if someone does
find it adequate, I would call that reasonable, as it is very close to
the argument about why lying disturbs the natural relation between
our cognitive faculties and the truth. If the argument is right, it
still seems not to have established that the wrongness of
contraception is serious.
***
In cases like this, it would be simplistic to dismiss those who
take a laxer view of morality than the traditional one as simply
infected by modern ideas of freedom or autonomy. John Paul II
had a certain view of his opponents. While recognising a certain
variety among them, he came back repeatedly to the idea that the
77
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
main trouble arises from Enlightenment ideas on absolute freedom.
He had absorbed an idea once very colourfully expressed by
Archbishop Vaughan, the leader of Sydney Catholics in their fight
against the withdrawal of state aid to church schools in the 1870s.
Vaughan gave an extraordinary talk with the title ‘Hidden Springs’
on the conspiracy that he thought lay behind plans for secular
and compulsory education. It was a plot, he believed, by the sect
of the revolution, international Freemasonry. ‘The Sect fixes
savagely on one dogma of its own,’ he said, ‘whilst gnashing its teeth
at all dogmas, it is this, viz., that absolute liberty and unlimited
freedom to do, say, or think anything he likes, is the natural and
inalienable right of every man.’19
That diagnosis of the opposition to natural law theory does fit
a number of cases – not the Masonic plot theory, of course, but
the Enlightenment freedom one. Peter Singer, Australia’s bestknown philosopher, has views on the permissibility of infanticide
(of healthy but unwanted babies) that fit that scheme exactly. But
seeing Catholic natural law theory as a seamless unity and all its
opponents as infected to one degree or another by rabid ideas on
freedom is simplistic. It fails to see and hence fails to answer those
who take their stand on natural law but draw different conclusions
in detail. (For one thing, the most famous Enlightenment
document is the American Declaration of Independence, which
says ‘We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created
equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable Rights, that among these are Life … etc.’ That is a
natural law theory too – and one that joined well with Catholic
theory in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights in 1948,
largely written by an American lawyer and a Catholic Lebanese
follower of Aquinas.)20
***
We need to discuss condoms and AIDS. If the average Muslim
is asked whether he is distressed by Islamic practices of terrorism
78
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy: Baby and Bat hwat er
and female genital mutilation, the answer is often ‘Nothing to do
with me’: those practices are said to be un-Islamic and only
practised in primitive parts of the Islamic world or by strange
subsects. That is a reasonable answer, but at the same time one
might hope for something a little more forceful in condemning
practices done in the name of Islam and perhaps some agitation to
encourage the authorities to suppress the practices. In the view of
many in our community, the Vatican’s opposition to condom
campaigns against AIDS is as bad as Islamic terrorism and probably
kills more people. There is a great deal of anger about it. Catholics
should be thinking about what is being done in their name and
asking themselves if they agree with it. We need to consider it in
the present context because the Vatican’s position is a direct
consequence of its arguments on natural law and contraception,
described earlier.
The main official Vatican document on the question is a long
article, ‘Family values versus safe sex’ (2003), by Alfonso Cardinal
López Trujillo, President of the Pontifical Council for the Family.21
It contains mostly argument about factual matters rather than
philosophy. In brief summary, it claims:
·
There is no such thing as safe sex: although
condoms reduce the risk of transmission of AIDS
considerably, they have failure rates in both normal
and perfect use that mean ‘safe sex’ is a false
promise (he suggests that if American legal practice
is followed, victims of so-called safe sex campaigns
might like to sue).
·
Although condoms reduce AIDS infections, that
has to be set against an increase in AIDS infections
that a condom campaign brings about, by
suggesting ‘everyone is doing it’ (and safely), which
leads to promiscuous behaviour. The Cardinal
points out that AIDS is rampant in Thailand,
79
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
which has had a large condom campaign, but not
in the Philippines, which hasn’t.
It is not my business to evaluate complicated matters of health
policy and the physics of latex and so on, but I would say the
evidence the Cardinal provides for these assertions is substantial.
Perhaps there are some facts he does not mention, such as the
reasonable success of Australian policy against AIDS and the
effectiveness of imperfect methods of protection in reducing
epidemics. Still, it would not be good to maintain that it is obvious
that Vatican policy is killing people without looking at the evidence
very carefully. It would not be desirable to find oneself saying ‘Of
course black people and gays can’t be expected to show restraint,
but I certainly don’t want condom vending machines in the toilets
at my daughter’s expensive private school – that would be sending
the wrong message.’ And if it seems unlikely that there would be a
world conspiracy to pretend condoms work better than they do,
as the Cardinal in effect claims, one might compare with a point
he makes in passing – that in Western countries, cervical cancer
kills more people than AIDS, and it is almost always caused by
sexually transmitted HPV virus, against which condoms have poor
effectiveness. That is ‘well-known’, in principle (well-known to
the health authorities to the extent that they are considering mass
immunisation of twelve-year-old girls against HPV)22 but not much
mentioned in the newspapers. It means that safe sex campaigns
here are fraudulent.
Having said that, there is still something disturbing about
Cardinal López Trujillo’s position. It is that if the facts were
different, he would still be saying the same thing. He maintains
that the use of condoms is a natural evil and cannot be excused if
it did turn out that they saved lives. That is like arguing that it
would be wrong to lie to save someone’s life. It is not seeing
correctly the need to balance the natural worth and rights of
potential victims against the natural use of personal faculties.
In conclusion – the essentials of the Catholic natural law view
of ethics provide the only way to make sense of the foundations of
80
Tradit ional Cat holic Philosophy: Baby and Bat hwat er
ethics: the only way to explain what rights are, what rules ought
to be adopted, what ought to be considered in individual acts of
decision. Some of the bathwater of detailed deductions needs to
be thrown out, but the baby of basic principle needs to be kept.
Then fed and displayed.
N OTES
1
J. Franklin, Corrupting the Youth: a history of philosophy in Australia (Sydney, 2003),
pp. 80-82.
N. Turner, Catholics in Australia: A Social History (Melbourne, 1992), vol. II, pp. 286.
2
3
‘Hosts that are completely gluten-free are invalid matter for the celebration
of the Eucharist. Low-gluten hosts (partially gluten-free) are valid matter,
provided they contain a sufficient amount of gluten to obtain the
confection of bread without the addition of foreign materials and without
the use of procedures that would alter the nature of bread.’ Letter of
Cardinal Ratzinger, 24 July 2003, http://www.usccb.org/liturgy/innews/
1103.shtml
4
John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor (1993), section 4; similar in Fides et Ratio (1998),
sections 43, 61, 78.
5
P.J. Ryan, ‘The fundamental tenets of scholasticism’, Catholic Press 17/5/1934,
p. 12 & 7/6/1934, p. 6; Franklin, Corrupting the Youth, p. 67; a more recent
exposition in N. Brown, The Worth of Persons: A Study in Christian Ethics
(Catholic Institute of Sydney, 1983).
6
G. Brennan, in The Mabo Decision with Commentary by Richard H. Bartlett (Sydney,
1993), p. 19.
7
T. Stephens, Sir William Deane: The Things That Matter (Sydney, 2002), p. 100;
Franklin, Corrupting the Youth , pp. 388-98.
8
W.P. Deane, ‘Crisis in the law of nations’, Social Survey 6 (1957), 8-15, at p. 12.
J. Gava, ‘The Rise of the Hero Judge’, UNSW Law Journal 24 (2001), pp. 747-
9
59; D. Heydon, ‘Judicial Activism and the Death of the Rule of Law,
Quadrant 41 (1) (January-February 2003), pp. 9-22.
10
John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor, section 53.
81
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
11
J. Franklin, ‘Stove’s discovery of the worst a rgument in the world’, Philosophy
77 (2002), pp. 615-24.
12
Veritatis Splendor, section 52.
J. Franklin, ‘On the parallel between mathematics and morals ’, Philosophy
13
14
15
16
17
79 (2004), pp. 97-119.
J. Franklin, ‘Two caricatures, II: Leibniz ’s best world ’, International Journal for
Philosophy of Religion 52 (2002), pp. 45-56.
Survey in the Australian context in Franklin, Corrupting the Youth, pp. 425-30.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae II-II q. 110 art. 3.
A. Donagan, ‘The scholastic theory of moral law in the modern world’, in
A. Kenny, ed, Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays (Garden City NY,
1969), pp. 325-339.
18
19
Paul VI, Humanae Vitae, sections 11-12.
R.B. Vaughan, Hidden Springs, or the Perils of the Future and How to Meet Them,
(Sydney, 1876), discussed in J. Franklin, ‘Catholics versus Masons’, Journal
of the Australian Catholic Historical Society 20 (1999), pp. 1-15.
20
21
22
‘A conversation with Habib Malik’, usinfo.state.gov/journals/itdhr/1098/
ijde/habib.htm; see C.H. Malik, ‘The search for absolute values’, in The
Search for Absolute Values in a Changing World: Proceedings of the Sixth International
Conference on the Unity of the Sciences (New York, 1978), pp. 1251-70.
A. López Trujillo, ‘Family values versus safe sex’, http://
www.catholicculture.org/docs/doc_view.cfm?recnum=5836
Australian Medical Association press release, ‘Immunisation against cervical
cancer?’, 15/6/2003, http://www.ama.com.au/web.nsf/doc/WEEN5NG4JQ
82
CH APTER EI GH T
Secula r Versus Ca t holic
Concept ions of Va lues in
Aust ra lia n Educa t ion
T
HE DEBATE ON VALUES in schools, especially values
in state schools, has proceeded with very little attention
to philosophical discussion of ethics. Yet it is hardly possible
to discuss values without some philosophical framework to organise
the material. Whether implicitly or explicitly, one will have some
idea on what ethics and values there are and which ones should be
implemented in schools. Since it is better to be explicit than
implicit, we begin with a very brief overview of the foundations
of ethics and how the different views on that question will tend to
work themselves out in education. We avoid traditional divisions
of ethical theories into such categories as deontological and
utilitarian, since these classify according to the rules of decisionmaking which the theories advocate, and here we prefer a more
fundamental classification that accounts for the difference in
perspectives on values in different educational traditions.
The simplest position on ethics is: there is really no such thing
as ethics. That was the view defended in John Mackie’s ‘error’
theory:1 there is just no place in the scientific world view for
anything ethical. It does not follow from that position that values
Original source: Catholic Institute Biennial Conference in Philosophy,
Religion and Culture, 3 October 2004.
83
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
should not be taught in schools – no-one wants to be murdered in
their beds by the younger generation, so it might be prudent to
teach them that values, like weapons of mass destruction, exist
somewhere even if they do not show up in satellite images. The
reasons for not accepting any such moral scepticism are well
expressed by Rai Gaita, who asks us to imagine ‘a tutorial in which
one of its members had been a victim of terrible evil of which all
the other members were aware, and in which the tutor invited
them to consider whether our sense of the terribleness of evil was
not an illusion. Everyone would be outraged if the tutor were not
serious and struck by unbelieving horror if he was.’ That kind of
scepticism, Gaita says, is not merely an intellectual mistake but an
evil act against the victims of evil.2
That sceptical position is not often seen in the debate on values
in schools, for obvious reasons. What is more common, however,
is the view that although there are values, it is not a good idea to
delve too vigorously in their foundations, since we may find that
they are not as secure as we imagined. In any case, it is thought,
since the youth tend to be critical and sceptical at the best of times,
it is better to protect them in particular from too much unsettling
discussion of where values come from. That view too has not been
found very explicitly in the values in schools debate, again for
obvious reasons. It was found in the parallel debate on values in
law, where Australia’s most distinguished Chief Justice of the High
Court, Sir Owen Dixon, connected his view that values should
not overturn ‘black letter’ precedent with his opinion that ‘An
enquiry into the source whence the law derives its authority in a
community, if prosecuted too far, becomes merely metaphysical.’3
As we will see later, it is a view implicit in a good deal of earlier
Australian work on secular education.
If one does think ethics has some foundations that ought to be
made explicit, there are three basic choices one can make. They
are set out with the most fundamental reasons for and against in
the following page’s table. The last two of the table’s theories have
been represented in Australian education respectively by the
Catholic and the extreme evangelical Anglican positions.
84
Secular Versus Cat holic
Th e Ca t h olic n a t u r a l la w t r a dit ion
Catholic tradition has always been informed from the ground
up by a commitment to natural law thinking. As we saw in Chapter
4, the essence of that view was explained by Dr ‘Paddy’ Ryan; the
reason murder is wrong, he says, is neither an arbitrary command
of God (or of society, or of our genes), nor a free-floating rule, nor
some fact about the greatest happiness of the greatest number, but
the intrinsic worth of persons, which makes their destruction
wrong. What is right is “founded in the nature and essential
relationships of things, and known by reason.” 4 We saw, too, that
at least some students at Catholic schools, such as B.A. Santamaria,
accepted as important the idea of rational justification of religious
ideas.
A colourful aspect of natural law theory in its Catholic version
was its tendency to issue in detailed casuistics, with
pronouncements on many particular cases of conscience said to
be deduced from the principles – for example, the characteristically
Catholic prohibition on contraception is justified in the Pope’s
encyclical purely on natural law grounds. And discussion descended
to much finer levels of detail than that: May one deliberately confess
to a deaf priest? (Of course not, since that defeats the essential
purpose of confession.)6 Is an excommunicate obliged to attend
Mass? The answer is complicated.7 The unique feature of Catholic
schools’ approach to values was the assumption that there is a
correct answer to any ethical question, no matter how detailed,
and that answer can be discovered by reasoning that attends to
both general principles and the particular case. Sir William Deane,
many years before his appointment to the High Court, wrote of
the natural law basis of international law that ‘This basis gave
international law a rich philosophical foundation which was a
source of unlimited development. In it there is a reservoir of rules
for all situations and cases. A law based on natural law can never
grow out of touch with the current needs of nations.’8 Deane
acknowledges the role of natural law philosophy in the Mabo
85
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
judgment, which overturned precedent in the interest of the
principle of human equality, a principle which the judges argued
was a value inherent in the law.9 The same went for questions of
conscience in ordinary life. Values should inform individual
decisions in such a way as to give rise to detailed prescriptions.
Since the Second Vatican Council in the 1960s, Catholic
education has tended to lose contact with the natural law tradition,
which was identified with the ‘old order’ in the Church. Though
papal encyclicals continued to promote natural law theory, it was
much less visible at the school level. As more ‘experiential’ styles
of religious education became prominent, conservatives complained
that children would inherit a ‘watered-down and wishy-washy
Catholicism’.10 It was certainly true that the children who grew
up in this regime, though they had fewer complaints than earlier
generations, were unable to give a clear account of what was
distinctive about Catholic values.11 In theory, Catholic education
retained some commitment to objectivity in values,12 but in practice
any distinctiveness was maintained more by the inertia of having
teachers who had grown up in the old system than by any visible
theory.
That is all reasonably clear in principle. So is the commitment
of Sydney-style evangelical Anglicanism to a divine command
theory of ethics. Archbishop Peter Jensen believes, contrary to
the natural impression one might receive from gospel stories like
the Good Samaritan, that ethical behaviour is not pleasing to God
unless badged with explicit Christian faith. That would be the
error of ‘moralism’: ‘The final sin of religious people,’ he says, ‘is
moralism, by which we trust that we can come to know the living
God and to gain his approval by the quality of our lives.’ He is
against any religious system that involves ‘even a modicum of
human merit.’13 Taken literally, that would mean that God is not
pleased with Mother Teresa.
However, Anglican schools have by and large not taken that
position, though they have often experienced stresses between
evangelicals and other factions. The complex question of the range
86
Secular Versus Cat holic
NATURALIST
Customs
tribes
evolved
x
have
NATURAL LAW:
Based on ‘natural’
preciousness or worth of
humans
THEOLOGICAL:
What God(s) command(s)
x
FOR
Fits
well
with science
Explains
well
both
similarities
and
differences
among tribes
x Fits well
with actual
intuitions:
We
understand
our own
worth, and
know others
are the same
x Scriptures
give clear
answers
x Has stood
the test of
time
87
AGAINST
Does not allow
moral criticism of
other tribes (e.g.
Nazi tribes)
x Does not give a
reason
to
be
moral;
x Moral progress is
meaningless
x Is hard to fit with
the scientific
world picture?
x
x Existence of God
is doubtful
x Alleged
revelations
conflict
x Socrates: ‘Is
something good
because the gods
command it or do
the gods
command it
because it is
good?’
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
of values in non-Catholic church schools deserves study, but is
outside the scope of the present article, which concentrates on the
contrast between the two largest systems, state and Catholic.
Th e va lu e s of se cu la r e du ca t ion : h ist or ica l
pe r spe ct ive
It might be expected that if Australian secular education was
committed neither to Catholic natural law theory nor to any
version of divine command theory, it must have been committed
to some kind of naturalism. That is not the case. Instead it avoided
foundational questions but continued to teach actual morals. The
consequences have been significant for the recent values debate,
where secular schools have had to defend themselves but have had
no theory to fall back on to do so.
The original attack on the values of public schools, and a much
more vigorous one than the recent mild questions by John Howard
about values and political correctness, was in Sydney Catholic
Archbishop Vaughan’s First Pastoral Letter of 1879, during the
political conflict over the withdrawal of state aid to church schools.
He attacked the secular schools then in existence as ‘a system of
practical paganism, which leads to corruption of morals and loss
of faith, to national effeminacy and to national dishonour’ and –
in a phrase that caused particular offence – ‘seedplots of future
immorality, infidelity and lawlessness, being calculated to debase
the standard of human excellence, and to corrupt the political,
social and individual life of future citizens.’14 (A Christian school
that resurrected Vaughan’s remarks in 2004 found itself heavily
criticised.)15 Secular schools then and since have not all been
observed to produce students of the exceptional levels of depravity
predicted by the Archbishop’s theory, but it was certainly a fair
question as to where they were going to find their values if not
from Christianity. Vaughan took the attempt to separate religion
and morality as a Masonic plot, an accusation not wholly true but
not wholly false either.16
88
Secular Versus Cat holic
The secular schools had a plan. Many plans. The one thing
they did not think of doing was abdicating responsibility by simply
confining schooling to instruction in matters of fact.
The New South Wales Act, following the Victorian, laid down
‘the words “secular instruction” shall be held to include general
religious instruction as distinguished from dogmatical and
polemical theology.’ 17 On the one hand, ‘No sectarian or
denominational publications of any kind shall be used in school,
nor shall any denominational or sectarian doctrines be inculcated.’
On the other, ‘It shall be the duty of all teachers to impress on the
minds of their pupils the principles of morality, truth, justice and
patriotism; to teach them to avoid idleness, profanity and falsehood;
to instruct them in the principles of a free Government; and to
train them up to a true comprehension of the rights, duties and
dignity of citizenship.’18
That was not window-dressing. It was implemented by a subject
called ‘Civics and morals’ in the higher primary school years, which
incorporated Authorised Scripture lessons and dealt with such
subjects as moral courage, pride in thorough work, temperance,
the evils of gambling, patriotism, courtesy, kindness to animals
and gratitude to parents and teachers. The teacher was advised to
use moral examples rather than abstract ethical principles. ‘The
moral influence of the teacher should be felt in a special manner
in the freedom of the playground.’19
Training in values was not limited to the classroom. Into the
great maw of the youth’s indifference to virtue was thrown a huge
range of solutions besides the lessons in civics and morals. Team
sports. The Boy Scouts. Cadets. Surf lifesaving. School mottoes.
The Empire. The classical languages and the heroes of ancient
Rome. The Anzac legend. Wordsworth. Improving literature and
literary criticism.
It is impossible do justice to all of these, but some short samples
will illustrate how these were intended to work in the area of
reinforcing values.
89
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Sport was not just to develop the body and give the less
academic pupils something to do. The New South Wales Public
Instruction Gazette of 1911 explains:
The recreative effect of games is always of great importance,
as through them so much can be done to make the lives of children
brighter, more joyful and less monotonous. The educational effect
on the mind and character is equally valuable. Children can learn
more easily perhaps in this way than in any other the value of
co-operation with others, and the need to sacrifice when necessary
personal desires and wishes for the common good. The faculty
of initiation is at the same time developed, and the habit of
obedience is encouraged.20
The Empire, like the Environment in the present, was not
just a heap of ground, but a moral entity that, on the one hand,
was where you were, but on the other, had a mystical vastness
about it yet needed your action to ensure its very survival. Its
moral point is expressed in the 1919 history textbook A Story of the
English People: Issued by the Department of Public Instruction for Use in Schools:
For British rule, in spite of a mistake here and there, has
brought peace, justice, liberty and prosperity in its train wherever
it has been established. And the size, wealth and population of
the Empire is a kind of guarantee that those ideals of Peace,
Justice, Liberty and Prosperity must be respected. For they endear
British rule to the native races.21
Empire Day was the culmination of the year’s reflection on
the significance of Empire. The 1937 textbook New Syllabus English
and Australian History for Fifth Classes, with Civics and Moral Stories says:
On that day, in almost every school in the Empire, children
are reminded, not so much of the greatness and wealth of the
Empire, but of the need to keep it bound together by ties of
good will and love. This can be done by helping one another,
and being fair to one another ... In a small way, even a boy may
become an Empire builder, for so long as he works honestly,
strives for the right, and keeps his mind clean, he is adding
something to the greatness and glory of our Empire.22
The Greek and Roman classics, including the grammar of their
languages, provided training in a different but compatible style of
90
Secular Versus Cat holic
virtue – exactitude of thought and a perception of nobility. Sir
Charles Nicholson’s speech at the inauguration of Sydney
University extolled the benefits of classical study:
No better discipline for the intellect of the young can be
found than that which is afforded by a careful and thorough
initiation into the forms of the Greek and Latin languages. Such
a process involves with the learner a practical acquaintance with
those fundamental principles of logic of which the grammar of
every language is more or less an exemplification. To regard a
knowledge of the ancient languages as a mere futile exercise of
memory is to betray an ignorance or a perverseness which it is
scarcely necessary to attempt either to enlighten or combat …
From whence can the poet, the orator, the statesman draw such
pure draughts of inspiration as from the immortal literature of
Greece and Rome? As the majesty, the unequalled grace, and
unapproachable beauty of the Parthenon have been the envy
and admiration of all ages, so will the works of Homer and
Aeschylus, of Demosthenes and Plato, be regarded as the
archetypes of all that is sublime in poetry, eloquent in oratory,
and profound and original in philosophy.23
‘Whatever else may be the result of a classical training,’ Sir
Owen Dixon wrote, ‘it does implant what is a very useful thing in
the law – a fear of error.’24
The role of the Anzacs, rural virtue, surf lifesaving, the Boy
Scouts, improving literature and so on in training for virtue are
described in Franklin.25
Those various efforts at training in virtue had success in their
day. But their Achilles heel was revealed when they came under
attack by the corrosive scepticism of the Sixties. Because there
was no intellectual foundation or attempt at philosophical
explanation of morality, when the old value system began to look
dog-eared and antiquated, it had no way of defending itself other
than through censorship. As Shirley Hazzard puts it ‘the battle
against knowledge was fought from an emotional and incoherent
concept of “morality”.’26 It was no match for the destructive and
relentless criticism of such intellectuals as Sydney University’s
atheist Professor of Philosophy, John Anderson. ‘Tradition itself
91
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
invites criticism’, he said, ‘because it represents certain things as
worthwhile but is unable to give any account of their value.’27 The
problem is one that faces any attempt to implement values merely
by listing them and urging they be taught.
Cu r r e n t de ba t e s on va lu e s in e du ca t ion
Some of those plans of fifty and a hundred years ago can appear
quaint or naïve from a twenty-first-century perspective. A
supercilious attitude would be better founded if the present day
were doing any better. Secular education before the Second World
War at least had a strategy. The Sixties and Seventies mostly
dropped those plans without replacing them with any other.28 As
with the Catholic system, explicit teaching of values in the secular
system drifted for want of any accepted theory to base it on.
In more recent times, there have been some serious attempts
to revive at least a skeleton of basic moral education and to state
the principles that are to be inculcated. The New South Wales
Education Department’s instructions of the 1990s divide the values
to be ‘fostered’ into three categories: those relating to education
(curiosity, logical and critical thinking, among others), those
relating to self and others (accepting one’s own worth, being honest,
caring and punctual, and ‘accepting the importance of developing
a positive personal belief and value system’), and those relating to
citizenship (including being in favour of democracy, liberty,
economic development and conservation, and conforming to the
school rules). A primary school subject, ‘General Religious and
Moral Education’, helps students to understand these matters
through a ‘study that is objective and non-sectarian’,29 but it is
much less clear what is to happen in high school. It is also unclear
whether lessons or any other mere talk about values performs the
function of developing character in the way that training in real
action, such as sport, was intended to do.30
The latest attempts in the field, the 2003 Federal Government
‘Values education study’31 and the resulting ‘Draft National
Framework for Values Education in Australian Schools’32 lack both
a philosophical basis and a coherent plan. There are some positive
features, certainly, that would not have been found in an older
92
Secular Versus Cat holic
document, such as the reference to developing ‘resilience’ in
students at risk of suicide and drugs. But in the Study, there are
excessive efforts to make sure there is nothing offensive to any
possible interests. The schools in the case studies were mostly
unclear as to what values they were promoting and why, with the
exception of Al Faisal College, whose program ‘incorporates a range
of Islamic values (including honesty, respect, tolerance, modesty,
courtesy, trust, politeness in manner and speech, cleanliness,
industriousness and hospitality).’33
The Draft Framework’s list of values is reasonable enough:
1. Tolerance and Understanding (Accepting other people’s differences and being aware
of others).
2. Respect (Treating others with consideration and regard).
3. Responsibility – personal, social, civic and environmental (Being accountable
for and in charge of a course of action – responsibility for one’s own actions,
including the exercise of self-discipline; responsibility for the way in which
one interacts and cooperates with others especially for resolving differences
in constructive, non-violent and peaceful ways; responsibility for one’s role
in and contribution to society; and responsibility for one’s own role in the
maintenance and preservation of the environment).
4. Social Justice (Being committed to the pursuit and protection of the common
good where all persons are entitled to legal, social and economic fair
treatment).
5. Excellence (Seeking to accomplish something noteworthy and admirable
individually and collectively, and performing at one’s best).
6. Care (Caring for self and showing interest in, concern for and caring for others).
7. Inclusion and Trust (Being included and including others, listening to one
another’s thoughts and feelings actively and creating a climate of mutual
confidence).
8. Honesty (Being truthful and sincere, committed to finding and expressing the
truth, requiring truth from others, and ensuring consistency between words
and deeds).
9. Freedom (Enjoying all the rights and privileges of citizenship free from
unnecessary interference or control, and standing up for the rights of others;
ensuring a balance between rights and responsibilities).
10. Being ethical (Acting in accordance with generally agreed rules and/or standards
for right [moral] conduct or practice).
93
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
The values are satisfactory and form a coherent whole. There
is a broad range of different and important values, and they are
free of the ‘political correctness’ that John Howard fears has become
endemic in state schools.34 But it is unfortunate that ‘tolerance’
appears first (though coupling it with ‘understanding’ does broaden
its scope). Tolerance is a genuine virtue, and one easy to reach
agreement on except perhaps among some fringe groups. But it is
hardly central to right action. To put it bluntly, to be tolerant, all
you really need to do is do nothing. And finishing with ‘being
ethical’ is content-free, especially when it is explained as acting in
accordance with ‘generally-agreed values’ – surely the difficult cases
of moral action are those where one’s values conflict with what is
generally agreed in one’s peer group and one must become a
whistleblower or dissident. And is the total effect a touch chilly?
There is little about positive warmth among families and friends.
Is love to be valued in Australian schools? It seems not.35
Whether the list of values is adequate or not, it is hard to see
them being realised in schools through the vapid managementspeak of the ‘Suggested approaches’ in the document, like ‘Schools
discuss values to be fostered with the local community’, ‘negotiate
and manage the process of clarifying school values’, ‘monitor their
approach to values education on an ongoing basis’, and so on. That
leaves it unclear what will be happening on the ground. The ‘values
roadshow’ promised in the 2004 Federal Budget has yet to be filled
out, and at $1,600 per school, is possibly not planned to make a
big impact. Until something more definite is provided (a textbook,
or plans for school talks by visiting community representatives
such as small business employers and refugee advocates), it is hard
to see the process as a serious operation. Meanwhile private schools
will continue to make money from their marketing spiel claiming
they are stronger on ‘values’.36
94
Secular Versus Cat holic
N OTES
1
J.L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Harmondsworth, 1977).
R. Gaita, Good and Evil: An Absolute Conception, 2nd ed. (Abingdon, 2004), pp.
314-5.
3
O. Dixon, ‘The Statute of Westminster 1931,’ Australian Law Journal, 10
(Supplement): pp. 96-112, p. 96.
4
P.J. Ryan, ‘The fundamental tenets of scholasticism’, Catholic Press, 17/5/1934,
p. 12 and 7/6/1934, p. 6; a modern version in N. Brown, The Worth of
Persons: A Study in Christian Ethics (Manly, 1983).
5
B.A. Santamaria, Santamaria: A Memoir (Melbourne, 1997), p. 8.
6
J.J. Nevin, ‘Purposely confessing to a deaf priest,’ Australasian Catholic Record 20
(1943), pp. 258–9.
7
J.J. Nevin, ‘Is an excommunicate bound to go to Mass on Sunday?’, Australasian
Catholic Record, 22 (1945), pp. 232–5; further in P. Mullins, ‘Looking back
on the way we were’, Australasian Catholic Record, 75 (1998), pp. 264–70.
8
W. Deane, ’Crisis in the law of nations’, Social Survey 6 (1957), pp. 8–15, at p. 12.
9
T. Stephens, Sir William Deane: The Things That Matter (Sydney, 2002), p. 100.
10
Hamilton, W., What’s Been Happening in RE in Australia? (Blackburn, Victoria,
1981), p. 41; K. Lawlor, ‘Religious education in Victorian Catholic schools
– the 1960s and 1970s’, Journal of Religious Education, 48 (2000), pp. 8–15.
11
R. Rymarz, ‘Postconciliar Catholics: Generation X and religious education’,
Journal of Religious Education, 50 (2002), 4, pp. 52–56.
12
R. Tarlinton and F. O’Shea, ‘Values education: a Catholic perspective’. In S.
Pascoe (ed.), Values in Education: College Year Book 2002 (Deakin West, ACT,
2002), pp. 85–91.
13
P. Jensen, ‘The gospel and mission of Anglican evangelicals’ (2003), http://
www.anglicanmedia.com.au/index.php/
article/articleview/586/1/25/
14
R. B. Vaughan, Archbishop and Bishops of NSW Pastoral, Catholic Education
(1879), repr. in P. O’Farrell, Documents in Australian Catholic History, Vol. 1
(London, 1969), pp. 386-99; at pp. 388, 390, 393.
15
K. Burke, ‘Apologise, Christian school told’, Sydney Morning Herald, 21/8/04.
16
J. Franklin, ’Catholics Versus Masons’, Journal of the Australian Catholic Historical
Society, 20 (1999), pp. 1-15.
17
NSW Dept of Public Instruction, Public Instruction Act of 1880, and Regulations
Framed Thereunder (Sydney, 1886), p. 15.
18
Ibid., p. 40.
19
NSW Dept of Public Instruction, Course of Instruction for Primary Schools. (Sydney,
1905), pp. 9, 11, 40-1; further in C. E. Fletcher, ‘The teaching of civics in
the primary schools’, Public Instruction Gazette (NSW), 6 (1913), pp. 57–66.
20
Anon., ‘Organised games for junior cadets (from notes supplied by the
Department of Defence)’, Public Instruction Gazette, 5 (1911), pp. 334–6.
2
95
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
21
K. R. Cramp, W. Lennard, and J. H. Smairl, A Story of the English People: Issued
by the Department of Public Instruction for Use in Schools (Sydney, 1919),
p. 408.
22
G. T. Spaull, New Syllabus English and Australian History for Fifth Classes, with Civics
and Moral Stories (Sydney, 1937), pp. 214-5.
23
H. E. Barff, A Short Historical Account of the University of Sydney (Sydney, 1902), p.
26.
24
O. Dixon, ‘The teaching of classics and the law’, repr. in O. Dixon, Jesting
Pilate (Melbourne, 1965), pp. 276-8.
25
J. Franklin, Corrupting the Youth: A History of Philosophy in Australia (Sydney, 2003),
ch. 10.
26
S. Hazzard, Coming of Age in Australia (Sydney, 1985), p. 16.
27
Anderson, J. ‘Socrates as an educator’, repr. in J. Anderson, Studies in Empirical
Philosophy (Sydney, 1962), pp. 203–13, at p. 207.
28
A reminiscence in S.P. Kenaelly, ‘What happened to my school’, IPA Review,
42 (1988), 2, pp. 45–9.
29
NSW Dept of School Education, The Values We Teach. Revised (Sydney, 1991);
for comparison, recent Catholic primary school values education in P.
Reiher, ‘Values education and educating the virtues: definitions,
documentation sources and issues for the values and attitudes domain of
primary religious education in diocesan schools in NSW’, Journal of Religious
Education, 47 (1999), 4, pp. 9–13.
30
M. Freakley, ’The values cop-out and the case for character development in
moral education’, Educational Practice and Theory, 18 (1996), 2, pp. 29-37.
31
Curriculum Corporation, Department of Education, Science and Training,
Values Education Study Final Report (2003), http://
www.curriculum.edu.au/values/pdfs/VES_Final_Report.pdf
32
Department of Education, Science and Training, A Draft Framework for
Values Education in Australian Schools (2003), http://
www.curriculum.edu.au/values/pdfs/values_web.pdf
33
See further Salman, S. ‘Values in education: an Islamic perspective’, in S.
Pascoe, op. cit., pp. 115-24).
34
Crabb A. and O. Guerrera, ‘PM queries values of state schools’, The Age, 20/
1/04.
35
Some similar lists of values, to which the same comments apply, are in Aspin,
D.N., ‘The nature of values and their place and promotion in schemes of
values education’, Educational Philosophy and Theory, 31 (1999), 2, pp. 123-143,
and Hill, B., ‘Bridging the divides: a Christian brief for values education in
schools’, Journal of Religious Education, 51 (2003) 3, pp. 34-43; little beyond
equality is named in Connors, L., ‘The values that characterise public
schooling: A Thermopylae well worth defending’, in S. Pascoe, op. cit. (2002),
pp. 59-70.
36
L. Doherty, ‘Push for values drives public school exodus’, Sydney Morning Herald,
8/8/04.
96
CH APTER N I N E
Account a ncy a s
Com put a t iona l Ca suist ics
W
HEN BHP MANAGED to close the Newcastle
steelworks, its share price surged, to the benefit
especially of the directors who made the decision.1
There has to be a suspicion that capitalism is pulling its usual trick
of distributing the profits to itself and the costs to someone else.
That means that the accountancy is being done wrongly. That in
turn means that there is an obligation to discover how to do it
right.
There are plenty of other cases where costs are distributed to
people against their will, and where they have no legal or other
recourse, because of a combination of difficulty in measuring the
loss, and the lack of a legal regime to sheet home losses to those
causing them more or less indirectly. US buyers of oil do not pay
the cost of sending the USS Enterprise to the Gulf to protect the
source of the oil; that cost is not ‘internalised’, but paid by the
State.2 Financiers insist on their rights to global mobility of capital
and the freedom to invest where they like, but those in the third
Original sources: Business and Professional Ethics Journal 17 (4) (1998), pp. 21-37;
repr. Australian Accounting Review 9 (2) (1999), pp. 36-43; Eureka Street 9 (1)
(January-February 1999), pp. 2, 43-6. Winner of Eureka Street Ethics Essay Prize
for 1999, and contributor to ACU Eureka Prize for Research in Ethics, 2005.
97
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
world who lose their livelihood as a result cannot insist on any
right to global mobility of labour; nor are they compensated for
their not having the right to camp on Rupert Murdoch’s lawn.3
Or – to take an example that may appeal to a different part of the
political spectrum – the benefits accruing to small and isolated
nations from the United States’ role as global policeman are largely
unmeasured and unpaid for.
Now, whose business is it to study such issues? Prima facie it is
a problem for applied ethics, or some related discipline. But at
present, issues of that kind fall down the cracks between disciplines.
Law is not applicable, since there is no legal regime permitting
those suffering disadvantage of this kind to sue. Applied ethics
itself, which has developed from philosophy with some input from
law, has inherited those disciplines’ phobia about quantification,
and hence is in no position to handle the usually economic nature
of the rights and losses involved. Economists study such matters,
but typically in a ‘big picture’ way, and not from the point of view
of inquiring how the individuals affected might be able to do
something to recover their losses. Accountants have a good
awareness of the nature of small-scale quantified gains and losses,
but normally restrict themselves to costs that an entity will have
to pay, not ones it merely ought to pay.
The problems can only be attacked by a fusion of the relevant
parts of all these disciplines. Applied ethicists must embrace
quantification, and create a ‘computational casuistics’, while
accountants must measure not only the obligations that the present
legal situation places on entities, but those that morality requires.
They must create a ‘moral accountancy’ – which will be the same
thing as computational casuistics. (The name ‘casuistics’ is taken
from the art of casuistry, the application of moral principles to
particular cases, on which there were many books for confessors
in the period 1350 to 1650.)4
This has been done before, and recalling a few historical points
may help suggest how to restart progress. Aristotle’s discussion of
money and prices occurs in the middle of his treatment of justice,
98
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
in which he goes into some mathematical detail on the different
ways of calculating just outcomes in different cases. In the case of
a partnership, for example, it is just to distribute the profits in
proportion to the stakes invested, while when there is a matter of
compensation for wrong, only the amount of the loss arising is to
be calculated. He goes on to say that the advantage of money is
that it allows all such things to be compared.5 In the Middle Ages,
the scholastics developed Aristotle’s ideas, and caused them to have
meaning in the courts. In those days, they thought that everything
had a just price, normally the price determined by the market.
Selling something to an unsuspecting buyer for substantially more
than the just price was wrong, and that moral thought was backed
up by legal sanction. In ancient and mediaeval Roman law, one
could ask a court to nullify a contract of sale if the price had been
in error ‘beyond half the just price’.6 Many subtle and powerful
ideas were developed on how to find the just prices of futures
contracts, annuities and insurances, leading eventually to the morallegal problem whose solution created the mathematical theory of
probability: what is the just division of the stake in an interrupted
game of chance?7 One of the solvers was Pascal, who in his other
writings dealt casuistry, the application of morality to particular
cases, a blow from which it has only recovered with the rise of
applied ethics in the last thirty years.
In the meantime, there have been successive waves of
Calvinism, positivism, Marxism, utilitarianism, modernism,
postmodernism and so on, all of which have tended to drive apart
quantitative and ethical reasoning, and indeed, discouraged
reasoning about detailed ethical cases at all. Of the major modern
ethical traditions, only utilitarianism approved of calculation, and
that was calculation of pleasures rather than of something
specifically ethical, such as rights; in any case, the requirement to
calculate was generally taken to be one of utilitarianism’s weak
points. Modern applied ethics has revived casuistry, but not its
willingness to get involved with numbers.
There are two main issues, or difficulties, with implementing
any project that involves quantifying rights and making the answer
99
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
have effect. The first concerns the possibility of measuring rights.
Does it make sense to quantify rights with sufficient accuracy to
make intelligible the demand that they should be recognised by a
legally-backed system of accounting? Secondly, is it at all practicable
to create a legal regime that would enforce those rights? The natural
scepticism one feels about both these matters is, it will be argued,
unfounded. The technology to measure rights largely exists already
in accountancy and environmental economics, while the
international legal regime that is currently developing has the
means to enforce any measurable right. It needs some more work,
but only more of the same kind of thing that is happening already.
Doubts about the possibility of measurement of certain kinds
of rights are perhaps best assuaged by considering the one area
where there has been a fairly determined effort to quantify moral
rights for which there was at present no supporting legal regime.
This is the field of ‘environmental accounting’, studied mostly by
economists (as it has no legal significance, it has not been of interest
to most accountants and lawyers). It began with the recognition
that National Accounts, such as the Gross Domestic Product, were
measures of economic activity that failed to take into account
certain goods, and hence were mismeasures of progress. For
example, depletion of a scarce natural resource counts as a positive
item in the GDP. Thus the costs to future generations of
unrestricted economic growth in the present were not measured.
To use GDP as a measure of the Good is thus an instance of ‘Great
Leap Forward’ pricing, the name taken from the response of the
Chinese peasants to the Great Helmsman’s demand that they
increase the production of iron (they melted down their tools).
Economists attempted to devise a system of national accounts
that would take into account environmental goods, as well as, for
example, the health of populations, so that there would be a
measure of whether economic ‘progress’ was actually improving
the lot of humanity.8
Accountants have been rather behind in this field, but as legal
requirements to disclose costs of cleanup have increased, there has
been a certain amount of work.9
100
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
This is not to say that the economists have measured fairly.
Environmentalists have not been keen to recognise all the benefits
of normal economic activity. One needs also to measure the benefits
to future generations of unrestricted economic growth in present,
such as expensive taxpayer-funded medical research with cures for
the future, and the discrediting of Stalinist regimes. A focus on
just one kind of good, that of the environment, leads to distortions
as bad as those that gave rise to the demand for environmental
accounting in the first place. All relevant goods must be quantified,
if there is to be any plausibly rational attempt to calculate and
balance rights.
Cost-benefit analysis has made a concerted effort at weighing
all considerations relevant to such decisions as major infrastructure
projects. There have been some reasonable ethical objections to
some details of its methodology, which can weight the preferences
of the poor less than those of the rich,10 but the vigorous attempts
in the field to weigh all considerations are admirable.
These intellectual ferments have largely passed accountancy
by. While it may be admitted that the subject matter of accounting
is ‘equities’, that is, rights or titles,11 the profession has traditionally
adopted a conservative attitude to what may be quantified for
display on a balance sheet. There has been a strong preference for
recording tangible and saleable assets, for example, with a good
deal of emphasis on what they cost and what they could now be
sold for. But that attitude has tended to erode as modern business
has created a demand for information on the true financial position
of entities. There is regular criticism of accounting standards
whenever a giant corporation goes under shortly after reporting a
healthy profit, as happened regularly in the 1980s.12 While the
principles of measurement in accountancy are controversial, the
recent tendency has been to avoid artificial rules and to look for
the expected future economic benefit arising from the assets an
entity controls.13 ‘Expected’ has approximately the usual meaning
it has in mathematical probability theory.
Some of what is now becoming standard comes close to the
quantification of a moral obligation. For example, if a company is
101
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
engaged in open-cut mining, and has an established policy of site
restoration to a higher standard than that required by law, it must
make provision on its balance sheet for that ‘constructive
obligation’ as soon as the mining is undertaken. Failure to restore
the site to the higher standard ‘would cause unacceptable damage
to the entity’s reputation and its relationship with the community
in which it operates’; it is going to have to restore the site, so must
disclose its present obligation to do so.14
Further clarifications may be made by replying to various
obvious objections to the project.
•
Objection 1.
Rights are not the kind of thing that admits of quantification.
Surely a right to life, or a right of a people to land, are not
capable of being weighed in a balance, or subject to more
and less?
Answer.
It is not maintained that all kinds of rights admit of
quantification. Some obviously do. One’s right to be
compensated by someone who has stolen one’s goods, or to
be paid for one’s work, is limited to a fixed amount, and
that is unaffected by the cases considered in the objection.
But it is also true that there is pressure to quantify somehow
even rights to life, when they conflict. When scarce health
care resources or investments in safety are to be allocated,
someone will lose out, that is, have their rights recognised
little or not at all. It is usual to quantify claims somehow, in
order to balance them – for example, when there is a need to
allocate scarce health care resources. It may be alarming to
hear health economists talking about the dollars needed per
‘Quality Adjusted Life Year’,15 or experts on safety putting
a money value on life,16 but deviations from the results of
those methods are also alarming. It is hard to see any superior
way of proceeding.
What rights exactly can be quantified is a further question.
Perhaps one cannot improve on Aristotle’s opinion that
quantification is appropriate in two areas: distribution and
102
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
•
•
compensation. In that case, in a case like allocation of health
care resources, it may be preferable not to speak of rights to
life as themselves quantifiable, but rather to say that the
quantification arises only at the stage when distribution of
resources to support those rights is in question. Similarly, it
may be that the intrinsic or aesthetic value of endangered
species is not quantifiable, but quantification must enter
when resources are to be diverted from other uses to save
those species.
Objection 2.
The quantification of ‘rights’, if it is possible at all, arises
from something non-ethical. For example, if I promise you
$10, the quantification arises merely from what I said, while
the ethics of the matter is founded on a general obligation to
fulfil promises, which is not itself quantitative. So there is
no need for any kind of ‘computational ethics’.
Answer.
That may be so, and in that case pure ethics need not consider
quantification. But here we are considering applied ethics,
in which we wish to look at the actual obligations that arise
from ethical principles in particular cases (and compare those
arising from different principles, if necessary). It is not true
that because ethical principles are non-quantitative, the
obligations arising from them also are. You might as well
argue that because probabilities arise from symmetry, which
is not quantifiable, probabilities also cannot be measured.
Objection 3.
It is quite unrealistic to expect precise measurements of
anything so vaguely specified as one’s right to clean air, or
one’s loss of self-respect through being unemployed.
Answer.
Precise measurement is rarely relevant to action. As is wellknown in probability theory, a very rough estimate is all
that is needed in most cases. I don’t know the precise risk of
a crash when I get on a plane: maybe it’s one in a million or
one in ten million; but if I believe it has got to one in a few
103
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
•
thousand, I sweat on takeoff and wish I weren’t flying
Aeroflot. As this example also illustrates, what is often
needed is not so much a precise measurement, as a solid
minimum. If I can show that an environmental good is worth
at least a certain amount, that is enough to get its claims ‘on
the table’, even if there is no hope of a precise measurement.
And if precise calculations are needed to decide between two
alternatives, it probably doesn’t matter much one way or
the other.
But again, more entities can be priced exactly than was once
thought. Options (the right but not the obligation to buy
something for a fixed price at a future date) were once thought
too speculative to price, but their exact pricing now keeps
many mathematicians in comfort.
Reasonably exact measurement is also possible in the area
where quantification is most familiar in law: compensation
payments for loss of future earnings, as evaluated by
actuaries.17
Objection 4.
Some future outcomes are too speculative to measure even
approximately, and if something cannot be measured with
some reasonable accuracy, no-one is likely to take it into
account when acting in the present.
Answer.
The defence budgets of countries, and the advertising budgets
of companies, are not observed to be small. Yet the outcomes
of that spending are wildly speculative. The same is true of
research and development budgets, which are large in
countries other than Australia. Decision makers in such cases
are acting to insure against various small risks of large,
perhaps catastrophic, loss. The risks and payoffs may be
almost unmeasurable, but it is still necessary to distinguish
between real or appreciable risks and completely fanciful
ones.
As examples of quantities that might seem initially to be
too vague, but are in fact priced reasonably, consider the
104
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
•
goodwill of a business, and the intellectual capital of a
research and development company. The goodwill of a
business has a substantial causal effect on its future profits,
so it cannot be ignored when the expected future cash flows
of the business are to be estimated. It can be measured
approximately as the excess that a purchaser of the business
is prepared to pay for it over and above the value of its
tangible assets (including ‘visible intangibles’ like
copyright).18 Microsoft has few tangible assets (and not a lot
of goodwill, either), but it has ‘intellectual capital’ in the
sense of a team of researchers with a track record of successful
innovations, who can be expected to generate future profits.
Microsoft’s share price can be taken as an estimate by the
market of what that is worth (after tangible assets, licences,
etc are subtracted). On one estimate, 94% of Microsoft’s
worth is represented by such intangibles that do not rate a
mention on its balance sheet.19 The size of this figure
indicates, if nothing else, the need for accountancy to take
some risks over what it regards as measurable. Otherwise, it
will be sidelined as an irrelevance.
That completes the consideration of objections based on
difficulties over quantification. We now come to those
concerning the feasibility of any plans for morally restraining
large-scale enterprises.
Objection 5.
Capitalists are not nice people, and are not going to accept
more moral rules. They are more than sufficiently challenged
working around the few they already have.
Answer.
If capitalists really wanted a deregulated environment, they
would migrate to Russia, and take advantage of the free
market in judicial decisions, the liquidation of business rivals,
and so on. They do not do so, as they prefer to operate in
countries where exchange is protected by legally backed
moral codes against theft and fraud. A norm of fairness
underlies exchange: ‘to make exchange possible, we must
105
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
•
make theft unfeasible.’20 The same point arises from the
extensive work on modelling trust in exchanges through
iterated prisoners’ dilemma games, which shows the stability
of tit-for-tat strategies in a wide range of circumstances.21 As
one saying has it, ‘When trust is betrayed, stakeholders get
even.’22
Corporations worry incessantly about their ‘image’ of
probity, for the obvious reason that other capitalists don’t
trust sleazebags. After the crash of the late 1980s, there were
fears that Sydney’s place as the commercial centre of Australia
was at risk through its reputation for corporate fraud.23 Legal
pressure on insider trading and similar frauds seems to be
increasing (though that is hard to evaluate until years later).24
To return to the Middle Ages for a moment: when national
governments were weak and knew little about business,
capitalists created their own international legal regime, the
Law Merchant, based on commonly accepted basic moral
principles and business practice.25
Objection 6.
With all major political parties in the West captured by
economic rationalism, there is little prospect for plans that
involve an increase in legal control. In any case, the
globalisation of business means it can escape the efforts of
any nation state to regulate it.
Answer.
This is a problem for an approach like that of Mark Latham’s
Civilising Global Capital which takes the ways of capitalism
more or less for granted, and asks what ‘policy’ prescriptions
can restrain it from running amok. It is also a problem for
the idea that it is the ‘State’ whose business it is to coerce
business enterprises into internalising external costs.26 The
proposals here should act at an earlier stage, and should act
through liability at common law, not through action by
governments. How capitalism pursues profit depends on
what the profits are. And what the profits are, if any, depends
on the accounting. It is unclear, for example, if Bond Corp
106
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
etc ever made a real profit, yet it was able to ‘buy’ anything
it liked – including its choice of auditor.27 If it could have
afforded to buy only out of its real profits, it would not have
been heard of.
Legislative control of business may have been weakening, but
it is not so clear that legal control has been. The increases in
legal control represented by such decisions as Mabo in
Australia and the class actions against tobacco companies in
the US have nothing to do with legislation. They depend
instead on the common law reaching into the moral
underpinning or core of its tradition of decisions. Whatever
fads the highest courts of Western countries may be subject
to, free market theory is not among them. Robust ethical
theories seem to be more popular.
In a remarkable speech on ‘Commercial law and morality’,
Sir Gerard Brennan, later chief justice of the High Court,
said:
Moral values can and manifestly do inform the law ... The
stimulus which moral values provide in the development
of legal principle is hard to overstate, though the
importance of the moral matrix to the development of
judge-made law is seldom acknowledged. Sometimes the
impact of the moral matrix is obvious, as when notions
of un-conscionability determine a case. More often the
influence of common moral values goes unremarked. But
whence does the law derive its concepts of reasonable care,
of a duty to speak, of the scope of constructive trusts – to
name but a few examples – save from moral values
translated into legal precepts? 28
The complex maze of rules that make up commercial law
may seem an inhospitable domain for moral imperatives,
but the opposite is true, according to Brennan. It is for the
commercial lawyer to discern the moral purpose behind each
abstruse rule, and advise his client’s conscience of what is
just in the circumstances, not merely what he can legally
get away with.
Of course, not all judges of the High Court agree with
him. Ian Callinan perhaps does not – which is one reason
why Callinan is in a certain amount of trouble.
107
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
The accounting profession cannot set its own standards in
splendid isolation from legal opinion, since it must operate
in a legal environment not of its own choosing. This became
most evident through the legal cases of the early 1990s, when
victims of the large accounting firms’ view of standards sued
for huge sums, sometimes successfully. In one of the largest
cases, Deloitte’s faced damages of $340m for certifying
Adsteam’s 1990 accounts, which disclosed a profit of $236m
when the true figure was a $244m loss.29 In other cases, the
State of Victoria sued KPMG for $1bn over its audit of
Tricontinental, and KPMG settled for a reported $136m,30
while Andersens was lucky to avoid trouble over Bond.31 A
table as at October 1996 lists twenty-one such cases.32
The ability of law to have an impact on complex financial
matters is well illustrated by the move away from the legal
support for artificial tax schemes that the Barwick High
Court provided. ‘Literal’ interpretations of tax laws
permitted endless schemes that subverted the intent of the
law by appeal to its letter. Then the crucial section 15AA
was added to the Acts Interpretation Act in 1981. It provided:
In the interpretation of a provision of an Act, a
construction that would promote the purpose or object
underlying the Act (whether that purpose or object is
expressly stated in the Act or not) shall be preferred to a
construction that would not promote that purpose or
object.
In 1984, the revolutionary section 15AB was added, allowing
recourse to external evidence such as Hansard as evidence of
the legislators’ purposes.33 Australia’s tax avoidance industry,
hitherto one of the most cunning in the world, never
recovered from the blow.34
There are parallels in accountancy. The standards contain a
‘substance over form requirement’ (‘Transactions and events
should be accounted for and presented in accordance with
their financial reality and not merely their legal form’35 and
there is a long-standing ‘true and fair’ requirement.36 These
notions are sometimes thought of by accountants as
108
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
•
decorations surviving from the age of the dinosaurs,37 but
gross departures from them are subject to legal scrutiny.
All these developments put paid to the notion that can
sometimes be gained from both accountants and lawyers,
that accountancy and law are very technical fields in which
the common person’s crude notions of the right, the true
and the fair count for little. When the crunch comes, the
courts prove to be as scandalised by technical evasions of
what is fair as outside observers.
These considerations apply with minor changes in all major
jurisdictions: commercial law is remarkably international.
It is true that there are some countries where commercial
law is a dead letter. But then, there is not much commerce
to regulate in Somalia or Afghanistan, for reasons not
unrelated to the breakdown of law in those areas.
Objection 7.
The law has a poor track record of actually doing anything
to restrain capitalism, at least, restraining it from harming
anyone but other capitalists.
Answer.
An interesting historical precedent that may encourage
optimism is the gradual success of legal remedies in
promoting industrial safety. Accidents and polluted work
environments are one of the easiest means for a manufacturer
to lessen costs, but the standard of workplace safety is high,
and has been rising for at least a hundred and fifty years.
Legislation has played a part, but the role of common law
damages is far from negligible. Common law has been
important both in setting pre-existing standards of liability
by employers, and in providing the matrix of interpretation
for subsequent legislation.38
More recently, and especially relevantly for a general project
of internalising costs through legal means, has been the
expansion of legal liability for economic loss. Until recently,
the law was generally unwilling to recognise liability for
purely economic loss, such as loss of income, suffered as a
result of negligence (for example, in oil spills or incompetent
109
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
•
audits). There has been strong movement away from this
position in the last twenty years, and damages are now often
recoverable in such cases.39 The law does not yet recognise a
general duty of care in all cases of foreseeable harm, but the
tendency to approach that limit is strong.40 In the meantime,
the aggressive law firms who specialise in class actions are
continually forcing the pace. The firm of Slater and Gordon,
for example, have been involved in the Sydney water crisis,
pollution from Ok Tedi, asbestos, breast implants, tobacco,
peanut butter and the Christian Brothers.
One should not forget either the legal regime that is gradually
arising internationally from treaties, which has had some
success in areas like protecting Antarctica. The speed of
development of international e-commerce and Internet
gambling means that something dramatic will happen
concerning international laws governing finance. It remains
to be seen what it will be.
Objection 8.
Attempts to find complex surrogate measures of
environmental goods, subtle methods of valuing
contingencies and so on are undemocratic. Policy matters
about the environment and any other important matters
ought to be judged by the citizens in the light of argument,
not by alleged experts through measurement. Having experts
in back rooms deciding such matters would replace public
deliberation about ideas with a scientistic paternalism.41
Answer.
This style of argument will appeal to philosophers and
Americans more than non-philosophers and non-Americans.
Even American philosophers, though, are grateful to the
Food and Drug Administration’s experts who test their food
and medicines. If rights are quantifiable, no amount of talk
about democracy will make them otherwise, and expert
opinion as to the quantity of the rights will be part of the
information that ought to inform the political (or legal)
process.
110
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
•
In any case, the question of what rights exist and can be
measured is separate from public policy issues about how to
cause them to make a difference.
Objection 9.
No-one is going to be found who is expert in these issues.
Answer.
Australia is crawling with accountants and lawyers: many
with glowing testimonials from the best schools and
universities in the country. Here is an opportunity for them
to do something useful instead of wasting their lives devising
tax minimisation schemes.
N OTES
1
‘BHP’s decision lifts markets’, Sydney Morning Herald 30/4/97, p. 32; ‘BHP
unions set for fight ... while chiefs quit in style’, Sun-Herald 4/5/97, p.
29.
2
H.M. Hubbard, ‘The real cost of energy’, Scientific American 264 (4) (Apr, 1991):
18-23.
3
J. Seabrook, ‘A global market for all’, New Statesman 26/6/98, pp. 25-7.
4
A.R. Jonsen and S. Toulmin, The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning
(Berkeley, 1988); E. Leites, ed, Conscience and Casuistry in Early Modern Europe
(New York, 1988); J.F. Keenan and T.A. Shannon, eds, The Context of
Casuistry (Washington, DC, 1993).
5
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Book 5, chs. 3-4.
6
Justinian’s Code 4.44.2; J.W. Baldwin, ‘The medieval theories of the just price’,
Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 49 (1959), part 4, repr. in PreCapitalist Economic Thought (New York, 1972), at pp. 18, 23; J. Gordley, The
Philosophical Origins of Modern Contract Doctrine (Oxford, 1991), pp. 65-7; a
similar modern case in Taylor v. Johnson (1983) 151 CLR 422.
7
E. Coumet, ‘La théorie du hasard est-elle née par hasard?’, Annales 25 (1970),
pp. 574-598.
8
UNSTAT, c 1993, Handbook for Integrated Environmental and Economic Accounting; M.
Young, ‘Natural resource accounting: some Australian experiences and
observations’, in E. Lutz, ed, Toward Improved Accounting for the Environment
(Washington, DC, 1993), pp. 177-83; Australian Bureau of Statistics,
‘Natural resource and environmental accounting in the national
accounts’, in Australian National Accounts: National Income and Expenditure
OECD, Environment and Economics: A Survey of OECD Work (Paris, 1992);
J.A. Dixon, L.F. Scura, R.A. Carpenter and P.B. Sherman, Economic Analysis
of Environmental Impacts (London, 1986).
111
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
9
Journal of Accounting and Public Policy special issue 16 (2) (Summer 1997); R. Gray,
J. Bebbington and D. Walters, Accounting and the Environment: Green Accounting
(London, 1993). K.F. Herbohn, R. Peterson and J.L. Herbohn, ‘Accounting
for forestry assets: current practice and future directions’, Australian
Accounting Review 8 (1998), pp. 54-66; F. Micallef and G. Peirson, ‘Financial
reporting of cultural, heritage, scientific and community collections’,
Australian Accounting Review 7 (1) (May 1997), pp. 31-7.
10
D. Copp, ‘The justice and rationale of cost-benefit analysis’, Theory and Decision
23 (1987): 65-87; D.C. Hubin, ‘The moral justification of benefit/cost
analysis’, Economics and Philosophy 10 (1994), pp. 169-93.
11
L. Goldberg, A Philosophy of Accounting (Melbourne, 1939), p. 41.
12
F.L. Clarke, G.W. Dean and K.G. Oliver, Corporate Collapse: Regulatory, Accounting
and Ethical Failure (Cambridge, 1997).
13
G. Hampton and T. Bishop, ‘Measurement and the Australian conceptual
framework’, Australian Accounting Review 8 (1998), pp. 42-53.
14
Australian Accounting Research Foundation, Exposure Draft 88: Provisions and
Contingencies (December, 1997), p. 54.
15
A. Edgar et al. The Ethical QALY: Ethical Issues in Health Care Resource Allocation
(Surrey, 1998); A.M.D. Porter, ‘Measurement: health economics’, in The
Ethics of Resource Allocation in Health Care ed. K.M. Boyd (Edinburgh, 1979),
pp. 101-29; cf. J. Richardson, ‘The accountant as triage master: an
economist’s perspective on voluntary euthanasia and the value of life
debate’, Bioethics 1 (1987), pp. 226-40; A. Bowling, Measuring Health: A Review
of Quality of Life Measurement Scales (Milton Keynes, 1991).
16
J.W. Jones-Lee, The Value of Life: An Economic Analysis (London, 1976); criticism
in P. Dorman, Markets and Mortality: Economics, Dangerous Work and the Value
of Human Life (Cambridge, 1996).
17
D.A. McI. Kemp, The Quantum of Damages in Personal Injury and Fatal Accident
Claims (4th ed, London, 1975); H. Luntz, Assessment of Damages for Personal
Injury and Death (2nd ed, Sydney, 1983); on matters of principle, J.W.
Chapman, ed, Compensatory Justice (New York, 1991).
18
K.W. Chauvin and M. Hirschey, ‘Goodwill, profitability and the market value
of the firm’, Journal of Accounting and Public Policy 13 (1994), pp. 159-80; I.
Morley, ‘Debating goodwill’, British Dental Journal 176 (11) (11/6/94), pp.
409-10.
19
C. Leadbeater, ‘Time to let the bean-counters go’, New Statesman 17/4/98, pp.
30-1; on valuing ‘brand strength’: G.V. Smith and R.L. Parr, Valuation of
Intellectual Property and Intangible Assets (2nd ed, New York, 1994), pp. 289-96.
20
R.E. Goodin, Motivating Political Morality (Oxford, 1992), p. 24.
21
J.M. Guttman, ‘Rational actors, tit-for-tat types, and the evolution of
cooperation’, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 29 (1996): 27-56,
and many articles in Games and Economic Behavior.
22
L.L. Axline, ‘The bottom line on ethics’, Journal of Accountancy 170 (1990): 8791.
112
Account ancy as Com put at ional Casuist ics
23
P. Costello, ‘Restoring confidence in corporate morality’, Quadrant 34 (9)
(September 1990): 20-22; J. Hyde, ‘Trust, politics and business’, Quadrant
37 (4) (April 1993): 43-50; ‘Big business elders crusade for higher ethics’,
Sydney Morning Herald 26/5/90, p. 6.
24
S.S. Shapiro, Wayward Capitalists (New Haven, Connecticut, 1984).
25
L.E. Trakman, The Law Merchant: The Evolution of Commercial Law (Littleton,
Colorado, 1983).
26
A.C. Pigou, The Economics of Welfare (4th ed, London, 1932), part 2, ch. 9; W.J.
Baumol, Welfare Economics and the Theory of the State (London, 1965).
27
Clarke, Dean and Oliver, esp p. 179.
28
G. Brennan, ‘Commercial law and morality’, Melbourne University Law Review 17
(1989): 100-6, at p. 101; see also G. Brennan, ‘The purpose and scope of
judicial review’, Australian Bar Review 2 (1986): 93-113, at pp. 104-5; P.
Finn, ‘Commerce, the common law and morality’, Melbourne University
Law Review 17 (1989): 87-99.
29
‘ASC wins Adsteam appeal’, SMH 29/8/96, p. 25, also 9/4/97, p. 29; Clarke,
Dean and Oliver, Corporate Collapse ch. 12.
30
‘Victoria sues KPMG for $1bn over Tricon audit’, SMH 2/6/92, p. 31.
31
C. Ryan and K. McClymont, ‘Alan Bond: the untold story’, SMH 4/8/92, pp.
35, 38; comment in M. Walsh, ‘Morality wanes the more the law waxes’,
SMH 4/8/92, p. 29; R.G. Walker, ‘Window-dressing at Bond Corp’,
Australian Business 24/2/88, pp. 95-6; R. Gibson et al. ‘Bond: a commentary
on accounting issues discussed’, Accounting History 2 (2) (1990): 135-42;
R.G. Walker, ‘A feeling of déjà vu: controversies in accounting and
auditing regulation in Australia’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting 4 (1993):
97-109; Clarke, Dean and Oliver, ch. 13.
32
Clarke, Dean and Oliver, pp. 234-5; further in ‘Southern Cross sues former
auditor’, SMH 19/9/95, p. 29; ‘AWA auditor to pay $12.2m in damages’,
SMH 8/4/93, pp. 29, 34; ‘Court orders Deloitte and Corrs to pay $1.8m’,
SMH 21/7/97, p. 41; on Westpac’s 1991 accounts, E. Carew, Westpac: The
Bank That Broke the Bank (Sydney, 1997), ch. 12; legal discussion in B.
Feldthusen, Economic Negligence (3rd ed, Scarborough, Ontario, 1994), pp.
117-24; G.R. Masel, Professional Negligence of Lawyers, Accountants, Bankers and
Brokers (2nd ed, North Ryde, NSW, 1989), ch. 4; B. Chapman, ‘Limited
auditors’ liability: economic analysis and the theory of tort law’, Canadian
Business Law Journal 20 (1992), pp. 180-214.
33
See Mr Justice Bryson, ‘Statutory interpretation: an Australian judicial
perspective’, Statute Law Review 13 (1992): 187-208.
34
‘Interpreting statutes – a new challenge to accountants and lawyers’, The
Chartered Accountant in Australia 52 (2) (August 1981), pp. 42-3; M.L. Perez,
‘Wielding the axe on Australia’s tax laws’, Australian Business Law Review
20 (1992), pp. 362-71.
35
Australian Accounting Standard, AAS 6 (Australian Accounting Standards, Students
Edition [1982], p. 1051).
113
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
36
R.H. Parker, P. Wolnizer and C. Nobes, Readings in True and Fair (New York,
1996).
37
W. McGregor, ‘True and fair view – an accounting anachronism’, Australian
Accountant Feb, 1992, pp. 68-71.
38
H.H. Glass, M.H. McHugh and F.M. Douglas, The Liability of Employers in
Damages for Personal Injury (2nd ed, Sydney, 1979); J. Munkman, Employer’s
Liability at Common Law (11th ed, London, 1990); P.W.J. Bartrip and S.B.
Burman, The Wounded Soldiers of Industry: Industrial Compensation Policy 18331897 (Oxford, 1987), chs 1, 4.
39
J.M. Feinman, Economic Negligence: Liability of Professionals and Businesses to Third
Parties for Economic Loss (Boston, 1995); V.P. Goldberg, ‘Recovery for
economic loss following the Exxon Valdez oil spill’, Journal of Legal Studies
23 (1994), pp. 1-39; K. Hogg, ‘Negligence and economic loss in England,
Australia, Canada and New Zealand’, International and Comparative Law
Quarterly 43 (1994), pp. 116-41.
40
See Anns v. Merton London Borough Council [1978] Appeal Cases 728 at 751-2, 7578.
41
M. Sagoff, The Economy of the Earth: Philosophy, Law and the Environment (Cambridge,
1990).
114
CH APTER TEN
The M a bo H igh Court a nd
N a t ura l La w Va lues
B
Y THE 1970S Catholic philosophy of the traditional sort
was in an apparently decrepit state. The scholastic
philosophy descended from the middle ages came to be
thought a hopelessly antiquated embarrassment, both inside and
outside Catholic circles. But in the legal world the middle ages are
only yesterday. There, the scholastic method of arguing for and
against propositions with the citation of learned authorities is fully
preserved.1 So are practices like wearing robes and hiring champions
to fight one’s case. The scholastic natural law philosophy of ethics,
stressing objective principles of justice, has also survived and
flourished in the nourishing habitat of the Australian courts.
Consequently, the most dramatic outcome of Catholic
philosophy in recent times has been the High Court’s Mabo
judgement on Aboriginal land rights. The fundamental issue in
the case was the conflict between the existing law based on the
principle of terra nullius, and what the judges took to be objective
principles of justice.
Original source: James Franklin, Corrupting The Youth: A History of Philosophy in
Australia (Macleay Press, Sydney, 2003), pp. 388-98.
115
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
The relation between law and morality is a question on which
Catholic philosophy is dramatically opposed to traditional legal
theories. On one older view of the relation between the two, ‘the
King can do no wrong’: the law simply is whatever is laid down
by properly constituted authority. A less extreme position holds
that there may be moral constraints on law, as on any other human
activity, but that law is still not especially connected with morality.
Instead it is a set of customs that have arisen to allow society to
become organised. They could have been different, but once they
arise they are fixed so that everyone can get on with life, knowing
what is expected of themselves and others.2 It is hard to see what
other view is possible for those who lack the scholastic view that
morality is somehow founded on the objective facts of human
nature. At the opposite extreme, the scholastics hold that law and
morality are so closely related as to be almost the same thing. The
whole point of law, they say, is to implement the demands of justice,
whose standards are external and objective. Or rather, one should
not think of the standards of justice as external to law, since the
aim is that law should realise and internalise the principles of
justice: ‘the precepts of law are designed to be the precepts of
justice.’3 Father Farrell, the Dominican who denounced university
philosophy in 1961, was one of the most active in promoting this
view, and many other Australian Catholics have defended it.4
The two views come into conflict over the issue of whether a
precedent should be followed, even when it is unjust. Generations
of lawyers absorbed the fundamental doctrine of precedent: a
precedent cannot be overthrown in favour of some abstract
conception of ‘justice’; there is to be no private revelation of justice,
since that would make the law unstable, as each new judge imposed
his own opinions or the changeable opinions of society. Sir Owen
Dixon, often regarded as Australia’s most eminent Chief Justice
of the High Court, expressed the old consensus in 1956:
But in our Australian High Court we have had as yet no
deliberate innovators bent on express change of acknowledged
doctrine. It is one thing for a court to seek to extend the
116
The Mabo High Cour t and Nat ural Law Values
application of accepted principles to new cases, or to reason from
the more fundamental of settled legal principles to new
conclusions, or to decide that a category is not closed against
unforeseen instances which in reason might be subsumed
thereunder. It is an entirely different thing for a judge, who is
discontented with a result held to flow from long accepted legal
principles, deliberately to abandon the principle in the name of
justice or of social necessity or of social convenience ... The latter
means an abrupt and almost arbitrary change. The objection is
not that it violates Aristotle’s precept ‘that the effort to be wiser
than the laws is what is prohibited by the codes that are extolled.’
The objection is that in truth the judge wrests the law to his
authority. No doubt he supposes that it is to do a great right.
And he may not acknowledge that for the purpose he must do
more than a little wrong … It is for this reason that it has been
said that the conscious judicial innovator is bound under the
doctrine of precedents by no authority except the error he
committed yesterday.5
This means, in plain terms, that if the legal system as a whole
falls into a mistake, it can never dig itself out.
One will not find in Dixon’s works a discussion of such matters
as whether there is or could be any such thing as an abstract
standard of justice. His view on such large philosophical issues is
clear, though, from his remark, ‘An enquiry into the source whence
the law derives its authority in a community, if prosecuted too
far, becomes merely metaphysical.’6
Such inquiries were pursued nonetheless, by those less shy of
metaphysics. Besides the work of Catholics, the massive volumes
and long years of teaching of Julius Stone, Professor of
Jurisprudence at Sydney University, served to bring questions about
the source of legal authority to the fore. Though he did not precisely
agree with the view that there are moral principles that the law
must implement, that view was one he took seriously and
expounded sympathetically. His students, who included three of
the Mabo judges, were introduced to a range of opinions on the
matter, and a habit of looking for the principles that informed the
law.7
Dixon’s view was upheld by his immediate successors as Chief
Justice, Barwick and Gibbs.8 Barwick did indeed allow that there
117
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
is a community sense of justice and fairness that may occasionally
be ‘pandered to’ when interpreting ambiguous laws, but went on
to say, ‘it is not for the individual judge or judges to express his or
their own views as to the law, views perhaps tinged by a philosophy
of one kind or another. Such a course would, it seems to me, be a
complete deviation from the judicial tradition of the common law.
It would lead to a rule by men rather than a rule by law.’9 But by
the 1980s, doubts had set in at the highest level. Sir Anthony
Mason, Chief Justice at the time of the Mabo decision, wrote of
Dixon’s passage, ‘Yet in some respects his Honour’s outline
resembles an elegantly constructed mansion in which some of the
windows have been deliberately left open.’10 He means that Dixon
has neglected the possibility of inconsistency among precedents,
or between precedents and principles. ‘If applied too rigidly, the
doctrine of precedent produces both injustice and lack of rationality
– the very flaws whose purpose it is to expel. Thus adherence to a
past decision which reflects either a principle undermined by
subsequent legal development or the values of a bygone era, will
produce an unjust result, judged by the standards of today.’11 Mason
thus emphasised the conflict an outdated precedent may have with
‘community values’ rather than with an abstract standard of justice,
but the recognition that a precedent may conflict with something
more basic was the major step away from Dixon’s reasoning.
The most detailed and explicit answer to Dixon, in terms of
the conflict between precedent and absolute standards of justice,
came from Sir Gerard Brennan, the writer of first Mabo judgment
and Mason’s successor as Chief Justice. His theory of the relation
of morality and law is that of the Catholic natural law school. In
earlier works he had praised such Catholic legal heroes as Thomas
More, well known for his stand on the conflict of law and morality,
and the colonial Irish lawyers Therry and Plunkett, whose
‘impartial enforcement of the law’ secured the convictions of the
perpetrators of the Myall Creek massacre. He also commented
favourably on Higgins’s adoption in the Harvester judgment of the
phrase ‘reasonable and frugal comfort’, as the standard which a
118
The Mabo High Cour t and Nat ural Law Values
basic wage ought to support, from an outside moral source, an
encyclical of Pope Leo XIII.12 Lawyers, he also said, have moral
duties beyond simply applying the law they find in place. ‘If the
law itself is an obstacle to justice, the duty of a Christian lawyer
extends to seeking its reform.’13 Most remarkably, in a speech on
‘Commercial law and morality’, he said:
Moral values can and manifestly do inform the law ... The
stimulus which moral values provide in the development of legal
principle is hard to overstate, though the importance of the moral
matrix to the development of judge-made law is seldom
acknowledged. Sometimes the impact of the moral matrix is
obvious, as when notions of unconscionability determine a case.
More often the influence of common moral values goes
unremarked. But whence does the law derive its concepts of
reasonable care, of a duty to speak, of the scope of constructive
trusts – to name but a few examples – save from moral values
translated into legal precepts?14
The complex maze of rules that makes up commercial law
may seem an inhospitable domain for moral imperatives, but the
opposite is true, according to Brennan. It is for the commercial
lawyer to discern the moral purpose behind each abstruse rule,
and advise his client’s conscience of what is just in the
circumstances, not merely what he can legally get away with.
So when he comes to the specific matter raised by Dixon,
whether a precedent can be overturned for conflicting with justice,
it is no surprise to find him agreeing that it can: ‘The existing
body of law may yield no relevant legal rule, or, in rare cases, may
yield a legal rule which is offensive to basic contemporary
conceptions of justice.’ In overturning it, however, the judge does
not simply impose his private morality. ‘The reasons for judgment
in the higher appellate courts increasingly look behind the legal
rule to discover the informing legal principle and behind the
informing principle to discover the basic value.’15 The answer of
the innovators to Dixon’s charge that judges who upset a precedent
are imposing their idiosyncratic notions of morality is thus a
cunning one. Overturning an unjust precedent need not be a matter
of judges implementing their personal morality, but instead (in
119
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Dixon’s own words) ‘to reason from the more fundamental of
settled legal principles to new conclusions.’ It is simply that the
judges now perceive that the offending precedent conflicts with
more fundamental legal principles or values. Brennan’s successor
as Chief Justice, Murray Gleeson, asserts that all judges must be
for Dixon’s ‘strict and complete legalism’; what this means,
however, is not an adherence to the letter of the law but that judges
are appointed to ‘interpret and apply the values inherent in the
law.’16
In the Mabo case, such a conflict was found between the existing
law, which justified the dispossession of the Aborigines by the
doctrine of terra nullius, and principles of justice which, the judges
held, conflicted with that precedent. Terra nullius is not a phrase of
English law, but its substance is contained in a judgment of the
Privy Council in 1889, according to which New South Wales in
1788 was ‘a colony which consisted of a tract of territory practically
unoccupied, without settled inhabitants or settled law, at the time
when it was peacefully annexed to the British dominion.’ 17
Aborigines, in other words, have no more rights to the land they
walk over than tourists. To explain what is wrong with this, the
Court needed first to adopt a theory of native title. Obviously,
this cannot be part of the existing (British) law, and must be found
in more general principles of justice. An explanation close to that
adopted by the Court is found in a 1988 article by Frank Brennan,
Jesuit, barrister, son of Sir Gerard and adviser to the Catholic
bishops on Aboriginal affairs:
Where a traditional tribal community has continued to reside
on its traditional land, discharging its spiritual obligations with
regard to that land, and that land has never been occupied by
any other persons, that community is entitled to a legal title to
that land in legal recognition of the fact that they have always lived
on that land, land to which no other persons have any moral
claim. To deny legal title to that land would be to complete the
act of dispossession commenced 200 years ago, or else it would
be to deny the rule of law operation with respect to these citizens
and their most precious possession.18
120
The Mabo High Cour t and Nat ural Law Values
Insiders of scholastic philosophy will notice that the judges’
theory of native title is even closer to one of the scholastic classics,
and a founding work of modern international law, Francisco de
Vitoria’s De Indis. It was written in 1539 in response to the original
question of this kind, the rights of the American Indians to their
land.19
Having established that native title exists, the question of its
conflict with precedent arises. Both of the two main Mabo
judgments, the first written by Gerard Brennan and the second by
Justices Deane and Gaudron, admit that to achieve justice in the
case, the existing law will have to be overturned. Brennan writes,
‘According to the cases, the common law itself took from
indigenous inhabitants any right to occupy their traditional land,
exposed them to the deprivation of the religious, cultural and
economic sustenance which the land provides, vested the land
effectively in the control of the Imperial authorities without any
right to compensation and made the indigenous inhabitants
intruders in their own homes and mendicants for a place to live.
Judged by any civilised standard, such a law is unjust and its claim
to be part of the common law to be applied in contemporary
Australia must be questioned.’ 20 Both judgments treat the
overturning of precedent that this circumstance renders necessary
as a serious matter, needing careful justification. Not any unjust
law whatever can be overturned, they hold. ‘In discharging its
duty to declare the common law of Australia, this court is not free
to adopt rules that accord with contemporary notions of justice
and human rights if their adoption would fracture the skeleton of
principle which gives the body of our law its shape and internal
consistency.’
To overturn a law like that of terra nullius, it must be found
inconsistent with one of the basic underlying principles of the
law. That principle is a simple one: equality before the law. ‘No
case can command unquestioning adherence if the rule it expresses
seriously offends the values of justice and human rights (especially
equality before the law).’21 Even if there is such an inconsistency,
121
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
one must weigh whether the disturbance to the settled rule of law
would be ‘disproportionate to the benefit flowing from the
overturning.’ (Even this last point, which appears at first sight to
be a modern and sophisticated concession to the Dixonian view,
can be found in Aquinas.)22 One must also consider international
law. While the English legal system is not strictly bound by outside
decisions, an influence from them is legitimate, ‘especially when
international law declares the existence of universal human rights.’23
The same views are crucial to the other Mabo judgment, that
of Deane and Gaudron. In writing of the natural law basis of
international law, as founded by Aquinas and Vitoria, Deane had
earlier said that ‘This basis gave international law a rich
philosophical foundation which was a source of unlimited
development. In it there is a reservoir of rules for all situations and
cases. A law based on natural law can never grow out of touch
with the current needs of nations.’24 The legal principle drawn out
of the reservoir for Mabo is again that of equality before the law,
on which he had written more explicitly in an earlier case:
For one thing, there is the conceptual basis of the
Constitution. As the preamble and s. 3 of the Commonwealth of
Australia Constitution Act 1900 (Imp.) (63) make plain, that
conceptual basis was the free agreement of ‘the people’ – all the
people – of the federating peoples ... At the heart of that obligation
[to act judicially] is the duty of a court to extend to the parties
before it equal justice, that is to say, to treat them fairly and
impartially as equals before the law and to refrain from
discrimination on irrelevant or irrational grounds.25
The intrinsic equality of all people, he said, ‘might sound a
bit wet, but it is just basic to the whole of my thinking.’26 Deane
acknowledges the role of Catholic natural law philosophy in his
Mabo judgment. ‘The basis of natural law’, he says, ‘is the belief
that some things are innately right and some innately wrong,
flowing from the nature of things, including our nature as human
beings. That approach provides a philosophical basis for seeing
such things as human rights as going deeper than any particular
act of Parliament or what have you. That is not exclusively
122
The Mabo High Cour t and Nat ural Law Values
Catholic. It runs through Christian belief.’27 Similarly, Mary
Gaudron writes that ‘equality’ means more than a purely formal
requirement that there be no irrelevant discriminations among
litigants. The High Court, she says, has been embedding in
constitutional interpretation a theory of equality ‘not dissimilar
to that propounded by Aristotle.’ This theory, as she explains it,
involves an active taking into account of relevant differences, so
that true equality between persons is preserved; it implies, for
example, the provision of legal aid and interpreter services in court,
to prevent discrimination by default.28
The inevitable outcome of this philosophical orientation was
the rejection of the law’s unjust past, in the passage of great moral
force that became the most quoted part of the Mabo decision:
If this were any ordinary case, the court would not be
justified in reopening the validity of fundamental propositions
which have been endorsed by long-established authority ... Far
from being ordinary, however, the circumstances of the present
case make it unique. As has been seen, the two propositions in
question [that Australia was terra nullius, and that full ownership
vested in the Crown] provided the legal basis for the dispossession
of the Aboriginal peoples of most of their traditional lands. The
acts and events by which that dispossession in legal theory was
carried into practical effect constitute the darkest aspect of the
history of this nation. The nation as a whole must remain
diminished unless and until there is an acknowledgement of, and
retreat from, those past injustices. In these circumstances, the
court is under a clear duty to re-examine the two propositions.
For the reasons which we have explained, that re-examination
compels their rejection.29
For giving effect to philosophical principles, the law is
supreme.
Naturally, there were complaints from those who abhorred
such judicial ‘activism’. The complaints entirely ignored the careful
arguments of the Mabo judges concerning the basic principles of
the law. Instead they returned to Owen Dixon’s jibes about the
personal standards of judges. The ‘activists’ were said to replace
‘strict rules with flexible standards based on their own notions of
reasonableness, fairness and efficiency.’30 In assuming there were
123
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
no objective standards and moving discussion instead to the
sociological entity ‘their own standards’, the conservative
commentators were making the same move as the postmodernists
in replacing objective standards of truth with relations of power
and rhetoric. Why should we accept our laws as they stand? For
no other reason than this, that they are ours.
N OTES
1
J. Franklin, The Science of Conjecture: Evidence and Probability before Pascal (Baltimore,
2001), pp. 17, 345.
2
M. Krygier, ‘Law as tradition’, Law and Philosophy 5 (1986), pp. 237-62;
summary in article ‘Common law/custom’ in Routledge Encyclopedia of
3
4
Philosophy.
F.G. Brennan & T.R. Hartigan, An Outline of the Powers and Duties of Justices of the
Peace in Queensland (Brisbane, 1967), p. 200.
P.M. Farrell, Sources of St. Thomas’ Concept of Natural Law (pamphlet,
Melbourne, 1957), reprinted from The Thomist 20 (1957), pp. 237-94; ‘The
theological context of law’, Australasian Catholic Record 32 (1955), pp. 31925; ‘The location of law in the moral system of Aquinas’, Australian Studies
in Legal Philosophy, ed. I. Tammelo et al. (Berlin, 1963), pp. 165-94; earlier,
J.G. Murtagh, Australia: The Catholic Chapter (New York, 1946), pp. 252-3;
M.V. McInerney, ‘Natural law’, Twentieth Century 1 (4) (June 1947), pp. 5868; D.P. O’Connell, ‘The natural law revival’, Twentieth Century 7 (4) (Winter
1953), pp. 35-44; Anon, ‘The natural law and Catholic social principles’,
Social Survey 3 (7) (July 1954), pp. 13-17; later in ‘The natural law as a basis
of social justice’, Australian Catholic Bishops’ Social Justice Statement,
1959, in Justice Now!, ed. M. Hogan (Sydney, 1990), pp. 206-12; R.D. Lumb,
‘The scholastic doctrine of natural law’, Melbourne University Law Review 2
(1959/60), pp. 205-21; R.D. Lumb, ‘Natural law – an unchanging
standard?’, Catholic Lawyer 6 (1960), pp. 224-33; B. Miller, ‘Being and the
natural law’, Australian Studies, ed. Tammelo, pp. 219-35; F.A. Mecham,
‘Philosophy and law’, ACR 46 (1969), pp. 137-46; and Australian Society
for Legal Philosophy, Preliminary Working Papers, 1972; D.W. Skubik,
‘The minimum content of natural law’, Bulletin of the Australian Society of
124
The Mabo High Cour t and Nat ural Law Values
Legal Philosophy 12 (1988), pp. 101-46; J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights
(Oxford, 1980); on which V. Kerruish, ‘Philosophical retreat: A criticism
of John Finnis’s theory of natural law’, University of Western Australia Law
Review 15 (1983), pp. 224-44; J. Finnis, ‘Natural law and legal reasoning’,
Cleveland State Law Review 38 (1990), pp. 1-13.
O. Dixon, ‘Concerning judicial method’, reprinted in Jesting Pilate and Other
5
Papers and Addresses (Melbourne, 1965), pp. 152-65, at pp. 158-9; P. Ayres,
Owen Dixon (Melbourne, 2003), pp. 251-4; some doubts as to whether
Dixon’s practice accorded with his pronouncement, K. Mason, Continuity
and Change (Leichhardt, NSW, 1990), pp. 38-9.
6
O. Dixon, ‘The Statute of Westminster 1931’, Australian Law Journal 10
(Supplement) (1936), pp. 96-112, at p. 96.
7
J. Stone, Human Law and Human Justice (London, 1965), pp. 249-52; J. Stone,
Precedent and Law (Sydney, 1985), pp. 238-9; see L. Star, Julius Stone: An Intellectual
8
9
Life (Sydney, 1992), pp. 176-9.
G. Barwick, A Radical Tory (Sydney, 1995), pp. 224, 274-5; H. Gibbs, ‘Law and
government’, Quadrant 34 (10) (October 1990), pp. 25-9, at p. 28.
G. Barwick, ‘Judiciary law: Some observations thereon’, Current Legal Problems
33 (1980), pp. 239-53, at pp. 243-4; G. Barwick, ‘Courts, lawyers and the
attainment of justice’, Tasmanian University Law Review 1 (1958), pp. 1-19, at
pp. 3-7; criticism in M. Atkinson, ‘Trigwell in the High Court’, Sydney Law
10
11
Review 9 (1982), pp. 541-67.
A. Mason, ‘Future directions in Australian law’, Monash University Law Review
13 (1987), pp. 149-63, at pp. 155, 159.
A. Mason, ‘The use and abuse of precedent’, Australian Bar Review 4 (1988), pp.
93-111, at p. 94; also A. Mason, ‘Courts and community values’, Eureka
Street 6 (9) (November 1996), pp. 32-4; Lionel Murphy’s view in G. Sturgess
12
and P. Chubb, Judging the World (Sydney, 1988), p. 362; cf. pp. 346, 351.
G. Brennan, ‘The peace of Sir Thomas More’, Queensland Lawyer 8 (1985), pp.
51-66; G. Brennan, ‘The Irish and law in Australia’, in Ireland and Irish
Australia, ed. O. MacDonagh and W.F. Mandle (London, 1986), pp. 18-32;
Higgins and Leo XIII from J. Rickard, H. B. Higgins: The Rebel as Judge (Sydney,
1984), pp. 173-4; on which see also J. Dynon, ‘The social doctrine of Leo
XIII and Australia’, Twentieth Century 6 (1) (Spring 1951), pp. 12-21; full
details in K. Blackburn, ‘The living wage in Australia: A secularisation of
125
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Catholic ethics on wages, 1891-1907’, Journal of Religious History 20 (1996),
pp. 93-113.
13
14
G. Brennan, ‘The Christian lawyer’, Australian Law Journal 66 (1992), pp. 25961; cf. G. Brennan, ‘Pillars of professional practice: Function and standards’,
Australian Law Journal 61 (1987), pp. 112-8.
G. Brennan, ‘Commercial law and morality’, Melbourne University Law Review 17
(1989), pp. 100-6, at p. 101; see also G. Brennan, ‘The purpose and scope
of judicial review’, Australian Bar Review 2 (1986), pp. 93-113, at pp. 104-5; P.
Finn, ‘Commerce, the common law and morality’, Melbourne University Law
Review 17 (1989), pp. 87-99.
15
G. Brennan, ‘A critique of criticism’, Monash University Law Review 19 (1993),
pp. 213-6.
16
M. Gleeson, The Rule of Law and the Constitution (Sydney, 2000), p. 134; cf. p. 98;
similar in M.H. McHugh, ‘The judicial method’, Australian Law Journal 73
(1999), pp. 37-51, esp. p. 46; some backsliding from Dixon himself in Jesting
Pilate, p. 165.
17
Cooper v. Stuart (1889) 14 AC at p. 291, per Finding Common Ground, ed F. Brennan
et al. (2nd ed, Melbourne, 1986), p. 13; other philosophical perspectives in
D. Ivison, P. Patton and W. Sanders, eds, Political Theory and the Rights of
Indigenous Peoples (Melbourne, 2000); G. Lloyd, ‘No one’s land: Australia
and the philosophical imagination’, Hypatia 15 (2) (Spring 2000), pp. 2639.
18
19
F. Brennan, ‘The absurdity and injustice of terra nullius’, Ormond Papers 5 (1988),
pp. 51-5, at p. 54; see also F. Brennan, ‘Aboriginal aspirations to land’ in
Finding Common Ground, pp. 11-49.
Original in F. de Vitoria, Political Writings ed. A. Pagden and J. Lawrance (New
York, 1991), pp. 231-92, especially pp. 239-40 and 264-5; see J. O’Rorke,
‘Francis de Vitoria’, Australasian Catholic Record 17 (1940), pp. 308-20; Stone,
Human Law and Human Justice, p. 62; a slightly different discussion also from
scholastic principles in E. Azzopardi, Human Rights and Peoples (Drummoyne,
20
21
22
NSW, 1988), pp. 131-2, 159-64.
G. Brennan in The Mabo Decision with Commentary by Richard H. Bartlett (Sydney,
1993), p. 18.
The Mabo Decision, p. 19.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I-II q. 97 art. 2.
126
The Mabo High Cour t and Nat ural Law Values
23
24
The Mabo Decision, p. 29.
W.P. Deane, ‘Crisis in the law of nations’, Social Survey 6 (1957), pp. 8-15, at p.
12; also briefly in W. Deane, review of Oppenheim and Lauterpacht,
International Law, Sydney Law Review 2 (1957), pp. 382-4; W. Deane, ‘Vatican
diplomacy’, Twentieth Century 15 (1960-1), pp. 347-52; cf. W.P. Deane, ‘An
older Republic’, Hermes 1950, pp. 5-10.
25
26
27
28
Deane J. in Leeth v. The Commonwealth, Commonwealth Law Reports 174 (1991-2),
pp. 486-7; cf. CLR 168 (1980), p. 522; I am grateful to George Winterton
for calling these passages to my attention.
T. Stephens, Sir William Deane: The Things That Matter (Sydney, 2002), p. 94.
W. Deane to author, 14/5/1996; Stephens, Sir William Deane, p. 100.
M. Gaudron, ‘Equality before the law with particular reference to Aborigines’,
Judicial Review 1 (1992-4), pp. 81-9; implications in Dietrich v. The Queen,
Commonwealth Law Reports 177 (1992): p. 292; similar in Gleeson, The Rule of
Law and the Constitution, pp. 61-3; opposite view in Barwick, A Radical Tory,
p. 274.
29
Deane and Gaudron, in The Mabo Decision, p. 82; reflections in R. Gaita, A
Common Humanity (Melbourne, 1999), pp. 73-86.
30
J. Gava, ‘The rise of the hero judge’, UNSW Law Journal 24 (2001), pp. 747-59;
D. Heydon, ‘Judicial activism and the death of the rule of law’, Quadrant
41 (1) (January-February 2003), pp. 9-22.
127
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
128
CH APTER ELEVEN
I s Jensenism Com pa t ible
w it h Christ ia nit y?
A
RECENT BIOGRAPHY of Marcus Loane, evangelical
Anglican Archbishop of Sydney in the 1960s, records that
as a student at Moore Theological College he would read
during lectures to avoid having to listen to the liberal Principal.
When you are committed to a closed system of thought, you can’t
be too careful when it comes to letting ideas in from the outside.
But what about the ideas already inside? How does the Sydney
Anglican interpretation of Christianity compare to what Jesus said?
Sydney’s Archbishop Peter Jensen and Dean Phillip Jensen are
the public face of a proudly ‘narrow’ interpretation of the Bible
that has had an immense success in the English-speaking world in
the last quarter of Christianity’s history. The basic tenets of ‘Biblebased’ faith are clear. They are summarised in what Peter Jensen
calls the great alones of the Reformation: scripture alone, Christ
“alone”, grace alone, faith alone.
The point of the word ‘alone’ is what it excludes: there is no
role for good works as opposed to faith, for human effort in addition
to God’s help, for the insights of other faiths as well as Christ, for
Original source: Quadrant 48 (12), December 2004, pp. 30-1
129
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
the tradition of the church as well as the written word of scripture.
‘Faith alone’ means exactly what it says: what God wants is belief
in certain propositions about Jesus and salvation, and without that
belief good actions are not pleasing to God. In fact, they deserve
his punishment. ‘The final sin of religious people,’ Peter Jensen
writes, ‘is moralism, by which we trust that we can come to know
the living God and to gain his approval by the quality of our lives.’
He condemns ‘any religious system which involves even a modicum
of human merit’. That means, in plain terms, that Jensenites believe
God disapproves of the ordinary person’s virtue for the same reason
he disapproves of Mother Teresa’s charity – it is not badged by
them.
There are many objections that spring to mind – is that not a
narrow view, intolerant, prejudicial to the good health of society?
Jensenites rejoice in those criticisms – the best persecution going,
they think, in our sadly lion-free age. But what will immediately
strike anyone who has read even casually in the Bible is how grossly
it is out of tune with the Jesus of the Gospels. The big statements
of Jesus’ message that the Gospels themselves foreground, like the
Sermon on the Mount and the story of the Good Samaritan, are
all about God’s concern that humans should act rightly, with love
and compassion. ‘Blessed are the peacemakers,’ says Jesus, not
‘Blessed are the staunch subscribers to Reformation formularies
of doctrine’. The very point of Jesus’ choosing to illustrate care for
one’s neighbour by a Samaritan – by Jewish lights, one of woefully
heretical beliefs – is to emphasise that God does love compassionate
action irrespective of belief in doctrinal details.
In a key passage (Matthew 25) that so-called Bible-based
Christianity has always been keen to downplay, Jesus discusses
the principles on which God judges people: ‘I was hungry and
you gave me something to eat ... I was in prison and you visited
me.’ There is no mention of ritual observances, none of assent to
propositions. That is not to say Jesus was unconcerned by doctrine
– he was very eager to reveal that there is a God who cares for
humans and wishes humans to have a relationship with him. But
his emphasis was always on how that relationship plays out in
130
I s Jensenism Com pat ible w it h Chr ist ianit y ?
action, not on details of doctrine or religious ceremonies. It is
impossible to imagine him getting hot under the toga about
doctrinal and liturgical trivia like stained glass or church choirs.
What would Jesus have thought of a ‘Christianity’ that plays up
St Paul’s statements in a minor letter about women in church,
and hides in embarrassment the peaks of Jesus’ own teaching?
Jensenism believes it has an answer to these criticisms in the
words of St Paul on the importance of faith. In addition to the
obvious incoherence of preferring a follower of Jesus to Jesus
himself, Paul has a few choice remarks about those in his own day
who said, ‘I am for Paul.’ The faith Paul spoke of, he makes clear,
is not his own but refers back to Jesus. The extraordinarily low
profile of the Gospels in the writings of the Jensens – except for
carefully selected snippets – is the clearest indication possible of
what is really happening. They fear the Gospels, for the gospel
message is inconvenient.
Fear of the plain meaning of the Gospels explains several other
distortions in the Jensenite approach to the Bible. The Jensens are
not strict biblical literalists. Phillip Jensen admits that Jesus’
statement, ‘If anyone comes to me, and hates not his father and
mother and wife and children, he cannot be my disciple’, is an
exaggeration. That is plainly right, since a literal interpretation of
the text would be out of tune with the moral tone of the whole.
Why then are the Jensens uniformly suspicious of historical and
linguistic studies that might cast light on the meaning of the whole?
It can only be a fear of what might be revealed about the gospel as
it really is.
It also explains the evangelical practice of ‘Bible study’, in
taking a very tiny portion of text and embroidering obvious
comments on it for an hour. Will the text for comment ever fall
beneath the size of a sentence, as in the classic Tory political
broadcast from the British comedy Not the Nine O’Clock News, ’tis
easier for a rich man to pass through the eye of a needle, than for
a camel to’? If one could give a single piece of advice to those who
have fallen into the rut of this kind of ‘study’, it would be: read
the Gospels less often, but in longer portions.
131
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
It explains too the Jensenite hostility to the other (‘idolatrous’)
branches of Christianity. A fundamental contradiction in ‘Biblebased’ Christianity is that the Bible itself does not say that Jesus
left a book but a community. Yet evangelicals have cut themselves
off from the great body of Christian believers, Orthodox, Catholic
and Coptic, the church to which Jesus promised his unending help.
Evangelicals have created instead an inward-looking and recent
sect, interested neither in understanding the Hebrew background
of the Biblical text, nor in the person of Jesus, nor in the simplest
‘big picture’ understanding of the gospel message. The real gospel
does not make itself an object of worship, as in Peter Jensen’s talk
of ‘the gospel, by which men could be saved from the wrath due
to their sins’ (actually, he writes ‘saved for the wrath’ but I am
assured that is a Freudian typo). The slogan ‘scripture alone’ is
not just narrow, but self-contradictory.
The most unsavoury aspect of the Jensenites’ distortion of the
simple message of Jesus is its concentration on sin and guilt, without
a compensating sense of human worth. The Gospels are quite free
of the extreme evangelical ‘heads I win, tails you lose’ attitude to
guilt, where everything I do wrong deserves God’s wrath but
anything I do right is done by him. The dark mindset of guilt
alone is designed to prey on early teens and technically smart but
socially unconfident older teens who, for one reason or another,
have a shaky sense of self-worth. Missing is the sense, clear in the
Gospels, that God is only displeased when we have done something
evil that we might not have done. Harming ‘little ones’, the Gospels
record, was what made Jesus most angry.
As to Phillip Jensen’s accusing the Archbishop of Canterbury
of taking his salary under false pretences, there is no escaping the
obvious applicability of Jesus’ throwaway remark about noticing
first the beam in one’s own eye.
132
I s Jensenism Com pat ible w it h Chr ist ianit y ?
N OTE
There was considerable discussion of this article by the Rev Michael Jensen and
others on the Sydney Anglicans website, http://www.sydneyanglicans.net/
community/viewtopic.php?t=1148. In the course of the discussion I conceded
that the claim that ‘the Jensens are uniformly suspicious of historical and
linguistic studies that might cast light on the meaning of the whole’ is incorrect.
Moore College courses certainly include considerable attention to those matters,
though it could still be doubted if their choice of detail is ideal for casting light
on the meaning of the whole.
133
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
134
CH APTER TW ELVE
St ove, H um e, a nd
Enlight enm ent
T
HE DRUIDS WERE no doubt tempted to make as a big a
production as they could of the ceremonies at the winter
solstice, since bringing back the year was all they could
do. Just so, David Stove thought, the Enlightened persistently
exaggerated the evils that humankind labours under as a result of
priestcraft and superstition. Those were the only evils they knew
how to cure. True, they promised that the advance of reason would
cure wooden legs and old age, eliminate the need for hard work,
and relieve all the other ills of the species, but in the eighteenth
century, before the industrial and medical revolutions, those
promises were even more hollow than they are today.
But was the Enlightenment’s abolition of ‘superstition’ an
unalloyed blessing, or did it bring with it equal or worse evils?
That is exactly the sort of question that was not on its agenda. In
contrast to Leibniz’s Best of All Possible Worlds theory, which is
entirely about how the necessary interconnections between evils
makes it hard to remove all of them at once, the shallowness of the
Enlightened consisted especially in their invincible optimism that
eliminating evils is easy. Voltaire’s Candide portrays Leibniz as a
fatuous optimist, but he was not in the same class as Voltaire himself
135
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
and his allies. Superstition? Mock it and the dark clouds of blind
faith will evaporate, leaving the masses carefree atheists. Political
oppression? Overthrow the tyrants and the rule of the people will
usher in a golden age of liberty, equality and fraternity. Economic
inequality? Let the workers throw off their chains and communism
will see the state wither away. Imperialism? A paper tiger.
Economic inefficiency? Let the state and its virtuous bureaucrats
plan the allocation of resources for the good of all. No matter if
some of these plans contradict human nature, or one another.
Reason can keep itself occupied sorting out any loose ends.
Almost every twentieth century intellectual was a man of the
Enlightenment, but David Stove more so than most. His technical
work in philosophy was on Hume’s arguments about induction,
and he regarded Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion as an
unsurpassed and unanswerable demolition of the claims of religion.
Humans, he thought, have no greater hope of immortality than
any other land mammal. Where Stove differed from the
Enlightened was in being unable to delight in the results of the
end of faith. He belonged to the tradition of pessimism about
‘progress’. The first to blow the whistle on the facile optimism of
the men of Reason (unless one counts the practical demonstrations
of the Terror of 1793) were Joseph de Maistre and Malthus. De
Maistre’s remark about Rousseau, ‘You might as well say sheep
are born carnivorous, but everywhere they eat grass’, exposed the
difficulties in the Enlightenment’s assumption of the infinite
malleability of human nature (‘it’s all a question of education’).
Malthus – the subject of one of the essays in this collection – showed
the problems that would arise if Reason did eliminate the evils of
war, vice, pestilence and famine: namely, more war, vice, pestilence
and famine caused by over-population. Later high points in the
tradition include Sir James Fitzjames Stephen’s attack on John
Stuart Mill (Stephen’s victory in argument and defeat in practice
is described in Roger Kimball’s aptly named Experiments Against
Reality) and Keynes’ summary of the absurdity in Bertrand Russell’s
hyper-Enlightenment views: ‘Bertie in particular sustained
136
St ov e, Hum e, and Enlight enm ent
simultaneously a pair of opinions ludicrously incompatible: he
held that in fact human affairs were carried on after a most
irrational fashion, but that the remedy was quite simple and easy,
since all we had to do was to carry them on rationally.’ Hayek’s
arguments on the inevitable failure of state planning were an
application of the same line of thinking in social and political
theory – a field touched on in the same vein by Stove in his essays
‘Righting Wrongs’ and ‘Why You Should Be a Conservative’,
reprinted in this collection.
Good arguments certainly, but, as Stove was honest enough to
ask, were there not some grounds to support the forces of Progress
in their optimism, at least in the West? Has not progress actually
happened, in many ways, as the Enlightened predicted? They
enjoyed, Stove said, a series of lucky accidents. The Industrial
Revolution – not of their making – came along at just the right
time. When they sent an ill-planned colony to the ends of the
earth, devised on their principles, it was saved from the disaster it
richly deserved by the efforts of a Spanish-bred sheep, as described
in John Gascoigne’s The Enlightenment and the Origins of European
Australia. Malthusian disasters were later staved off by such
unlooked-for developments as the electric motor and contraception.
Can it go on?
To return to religion, and the question as to whether the
abolition of superstition did anyone any good. Stove quotes Hume’s
opponent James Beattie, ‘in the solitary scenes of life, there is many
an honest and tender heart pining with incurable anguish … racked
with disease, scourged by the oppressor; whom nothing but trust
in Providence, and the hope of future retribution, could preserve
from the agonies of despair. And do they [the Enlightened], with
sacrilegious hands, attempt to violate this last refuge of the
miserable … ?’ Stove comments, ‘I do not see, much as I admire
and love Hume, what satisfactory reply he could have made to it.
What reply could any of the Enlightened have made to it, at least
while they rested their case for Enlightenment on the happiness it
brings?’ If they had said that one must, sadly, prefer the hard truth
137
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
to consolation, that would have been understandable. But that is
far from what they said, as they believed in the happy harmony of
all goods.
The religious will not find any consolation in Stove’s work.
Neither will the village atheist heirs of the Enlightenment.
138
I N D EX
Accountancy: 88, 97, 100-101, 105-109
Action Française: 64
Affaire des Fiches: 9
ALP: see Australian Labor Party
Anderson, Professor John: 24-26, 54, 66,
91
Anglicanism, Sydney: 86, 129-133
Apologetics: 23, 28, 51-52, 64
Aquinas Academy (Sydney): 25, 65-66
Aquinas, Thomas, Saint: 52, 54, 59, 65-67,
70, 74-75, 78, 122
Aristotle: 54, 66, 98-99, 102, 117, 123
Armidale: 9, 15, 32
ASIO/CIS: 33-36
Australian Labor Party: 1, 16, 36, 38-41
Banks, Sir Joseph: 10
Barnwell, Bill: 34
Barruel, Augustin, Abbé: 6
Barton, Sir Edmund: 10
Barwick, Sir Garfield: 108, 117
Beattie, James: 137
Beg, Wazir: 5-6, 9
Belgium: 5, 9
Bernie, Frances: 29
BHP: 97
Bradman, Sir Donald: 10-11
Brennan, Frank, Father: 120
Brennan, Sir Gerard: 70, 107, 118, 121
Bruce, Stanley Melbourne: 10
Callinan, Ian: 107
Calwell, Arthur: 16, 34-36, 48-49
Cameron, Clyde: 48
Campion, Fr Edmund: 57-61
Campion Society: 23
Capitalism: 30, 32, 40, 97, 106, 109
Casuistry: 98-99
Carroll, James, Bishop: 39
Catechism: 52
Catholic Action: 27-28, 33-35
Catholic Commission for Justice and
Peace: 61
Catholic Worker: 63-64
Chain letters: 29
Charlesworth, Max: 63
Clark, (Charles) Manning (Hope): 10
Classics, Greek and Roman: 90
Communism: 5, 27, 29-33, 40-41, 136
Condoms and AIDS: 68, 78-80
Connor, Xavier: 63
Contraception: 77-79, 85, 137
Conway, Ronald: 61
Cook, Sir Joseph: 10
Costigan, Francis Xavier: 61
Czechoslovakia: 38, 63
Darville (‘Demidenko’), Helen: 6
Deane, Sir William: 70, 85, 121-122
Deery, P.: 41
De Maistre, Joseph: 136
Descartes, René: 26
‘Demidenko, Helen’: see Darville
Democratic Labor Party (DLP): 39, 66
Dixon, Sir Owen: 84, 91, 116-120, 122123
DLP: see Democratic Labor Party
Dobson, W. J. (‘Diver’): 35-37, 41
Donagan, Alan: 74-75
Dreyfus Affair: 9
Dunlop, Sir Edward (‘Weary’): 10
Edward VII, King: 10
Empire, British: 89-90
Enlightenment: 7, 10, 78, 135-138
Ethics, objectivity of: 1-2, 54, 67-68, 7174, 80, 83-84, 86, 98-99, 103, 115
Evatt, H. V.: 29
Everingham, Doug: 28
Evil, problem of: 53-54, 73, 136
Evolution: 24-25
Existence of God: 24, 27-28, 52-54, 67
Fadden, Sir Arthur: 10
Farrell, Fr P.M.: 116
Fitzgerald, Tony: 61
Franklin, Benjamin: 7
139
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
Franco Francisco, 6
Francoism: 27
French Revolution: 6-8, 136
Fraser, Malcolm: 49
Freemasonry: 1, 4-17, 78
Free will: 52
Gair, Vincent: 16
Gaita, Raimond: 66, 84
Galleghan, Sir Frederick (‘Black Jack’):
34
Garcia Moreno, Gabriel, President: 8
Gascoigne, John: 137
Gaudron, Mary: 121-123
Gibbs, Sir Harry: 117
Gilroy, Sir Norman, Cardinal: 33, 39
Gleeson, Murray: 120
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von: 7
Gorton, Sir John Grey: 10
Greece: 48, 91
Greenway, Francis: 10
Greer, Germaine: 53, 59
Griffin, James: 63
Haile Selassie, Emperor: 64
‘Hamilton, Diana’ (alias Glatzel): 37
Hammer, A.G.: 25
Hargrave, Lawrence: 10
Hargraves, Edward: 10
Hawke, Robert James Lee: 33
Haydn, Josef: 7
Hayek, Friedrich August von: 137
Hazzard, Shirley: 91
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: 30
Higgins, Henry Bournes: 118
Hitler, Adolf: 29; see also Nazism
Hogarth, William: 7
Horne, Donald: 25, 27-28
Howard, John: 70, 88, 94
Humanae Vitae: 40, 77
Hume, David: 136-137
Hume, Hamilton: 10
Immigration: 1, 16, 34, 37, 47-49
Irish origins of Australian Catholicism: 1,
52, 118
Italy: 8, 38, 48, 64
Jackson, Denys: 64
Jensen, Michael: 133
Jensen, Peter, Archbishop: 86, 129-132
Jensen, Phillip, Dean: 129, 131-132
John Paul II, Pope: 67, 72, 77
Johnson, Hewlett, Dean: 29
Keneally, Thomas: 52
Keynes, John Maynard: 136
Kimball, Roger: 136
King, Philip: 8
Kingsford-Smith, Sir Charles: 10
Knopfelmacher, Frank: 32
Latham, Mark: 106
Law and ethics: 97, 106, 116-117
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm von: 135
Leichhardt, Ludwig: 10
Leo XIII, Pope: 30, 119
Letters, Frank: 14-15
Lewis, C.S. 51
Loane, Sir Marcus, Archbishop: 129
López Trujillo, Alfonso, Cardinal: 79-80
Lying: 53, 74-75
Lyons, Patrick Francis, Bishop: 39
Mabo case: 69-70, 85, 107, 115-122
Mackie, John L.: 83
Macquarie, Lachlan: 10
Malthus, Thomas: 136
Mann, Thomas: 15
Mannix, Daniel, Archbishop: 11, 61
Mao Ze Dong: 100
Marx, Karl: 30
Mason, Sir Anthony: 118
Masons: see Freemasonry
Materialism: 4, 24, 60, 69
McAuley, James: 37, 60
McEwen, Sir John: 10
McKillop, Mary: 58
McMahon, Sir William: 10
Menzies, Sir Robert Gordon: 10-11, 31-32
Mill, John Stuart: 136
Microsoft: 105
More, Thomas, Saint: 118
Movement, the: 28, 32-33, 36-40, 63
Mozart, Wolfgang Amadeus: 7
Musgrove, Sid: 15
Natural law ethics: 54, 65, 68, 70-73, 75,
78-80, 85-88, 115, 118, 122
Nazism: 6, 28, 37, 68, 72-73, 87
Newman, John Henry, Cardinal: 51
Nicholson, Sir Charles: 91
Noone, Val: 63
Not the Nine O’Clock News: 131
Nuremberg Trials: 68, 75
O’Farrell, Patrick: 60
140
I ndex
Ogburn, John: 65
Opus Dei: 60
Orange Order: 5
Ormonde, Paul: 63
Oxley, John: 10
Paganism: 4
Page, Sir Earle: 10
Parkes, Sir Henry: 13
Pascal, Blaise: 99
Passmore, John (philosopher): 26
Paul, Saint: 131
Paul VI, Pope: 77
Petrov Affair: 29
Pius IX, Pope: 6
Plunkett, John Hubert: 118
Pope, Alexander: 7
Protocols of the Elders of Zion: 6
Pryke, Roger, Father: 38
Reid, Sir George: 10
Richardson, Graham (‘Richo’): 39
Ross, Edgar: 30
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques: 136
Rumble, Fr Leslie: 27, 29
Russia: 8, 29, 31, 105
Russell, Bertrand: 136
Ryan, Fr P. J. (‘Paddy’): 1, 23-41, 46, 54,
69, 85
Santamaria, B.A.: 1, 33, 37, 39, 51-52, 54,
61, 63-64, 85
Scholastic philosophy: 23-24, 40, 52, 6569, 75, 99, 115-116, 121
Second Vatican Council: 66, 86
Secular education: 5, 9, 12-13, 52, 84, 88,
92
Sexual abuse scandals: 2
Sexual ethics: 2, 76-77, 88-90
Sharkey, Lance: 29
Sheehan, Michael, Archbishop: 51-52, 64
Singer, Peter: 78
Socrates: 87
Spain: 8, 30, see also Franco
Split, Labor: 39-40
State aid for church schools: 3, 88
St Vincent de Paul Society: 59
Stephen, Sir James Fitzjames: 136
Stone, Julius: 117
Stopes, Marie: 64
Stove, David: 72, 135-138
Stove, R. J.: 49
Suttor, Tim: 60
Sydney University: 11, 14, 24-25, 27, 38,
52, 61, 66, 91, 117
Teresa, Mother: 86, 130
Thérèse of Lisieux, Saint: 58
Therry, Sir Roger: 118
Thornton-Smith, Colin: 64
Tribune: 35-37
Universal Declaration of Human Rights:
78
Values education: 92-94
Vatican II: see Second Vatican Council
Vaughan, Roger Bede, Archbishop: 3-6, 9,
12, 78, 88
Vietnamese: 49
Vitoria, Francisco de: 121-122
Voltaire: 4, 7, 135
Walpole, Sir Robert: 7
Washington, George: 7
Wells, H.G.: 29
Wentworth, William Charles: 12
Whitlam, Gough: 28, 48
Wilkins, William: 12
Woodbury, Austin: 65-67
Woolley, John: 12
141
Cat holic Values and Aust ralian Realit ies
142
A
ust ralian Cat holics have m ade a unique cont r ibut ion t o
t he nat ion. At it s cent re is a solid grasp of t he obj ect ivit y
of et hics. Persons or societ ies cannot “ choose t heir ow n
values”, because w hat is right and w rong is founded in t he w ay
t hings are. I n his wide- ranging book on Aust ralian Cat holic t hought
and act ion, Jam es Franklin, aut hor of t he m uch- praised polem ical
hist ory of Aust ralian philosophy, Corrupt ing t he Yout h, shows how
core Cat holic values have played out in t he issues where Cat holics
have challenged t heir host societ y - in debat es on land right s,
i m m i g r a t i o n a n d v a l u es i n sch o o l s, a n d i n co m b a t s w i t h
Freem asons, Prot est ant s and Com m unist s.
“ I n t his br illiant and hum ane collect ion, Jam es Frank lin effect iv ely
dram at izes t he dist inct ive shape of Aust ralian Cat holic life t oday. He is
bot h sound and accom m odat ing, r et aining t he m aj est y and m yst er y of
Cat holicism .... This is a lear ned and engaging volum e t hat w ill int er est
Cat holics and non- Cat holics alike.”
Roge r Kim ba ll, Edit or a n d Pu blish e r , Th e N e w Cr it e r ion
“ Jam es Franklin is sim ply t he best w r it er on t he hist or y of ideas now
pract ising in Aust ralia. His w or k is a com pelling r ead for anyone, of
w hat ever fait h, w ho want s t o under st and t he m ost decisive cont est s
ov er t he polit ical, philosophical, m oral and r eligious ideas t hat have
shaped t his count r y.”
Ke it h W indschut t le , Publishe r a nd Aut hor of The Killing of H ist or y
“ Deft ly br ings t oget her Aust ralia’s past and pr esent in explor ing t he
abiding int er play bet w een per ennial Cat holic values and t he shift ing
sands of cont em porar y et hical debat e.”
Pr ofe ssor Joh n Ga scoign e , Sch ool of H ist or y , Un iv e r sit y of N e w
Sou t h W a le s
Jam es Frank lin is t he aut hor of Cor r upt ing t he Yout h: A Hist or y of
Philosophy in Aust r alia ( 2003) and The Science of Conj ect ur e: Evidence
an d Pr ob ab ilit y Bef or e Pascal ( 2 0 0 1 ) . He w as aw ar d ed t h e 2 0 0 5
Aust ralian Cat holic Univer sit y Eur eka Pr ize for Resear ch in Et hics. He
lect ur es in Mat hem at ics at t he Univer sit y of New Sout h Wales.