Liverpool Law Rev (2010) 31:137–154
DOI 10.1007/s10991-010-9077-6
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
Peter Bartlett
Published online: 30 October 2010
The Author(s) 2010. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com
Abstract This paper addresses the appropriate legal and policy approach to sexual
conduct involving people with dementia in care homes, where the mental capacity
of one or both partners is compromised. Such conduct is prohibited by sections 34–42 of the Sexual Offences Act 2003, but this article asks whether this
blanket prohibition is necessarily the appropriate response. The article considers a
variety of alternative responses, eventually arguing that clearer guidance regarding
prosecution should be issued.
Keywords Sexual expression and human rights Sexuality Dementia
Care homes Senior Citizens’ homes Capacity and sexual conduct
A woman with dementia is living in care home. Her husband comes calling on
Saturday afternoons. Upon arrival, he closes the door to her room, and the care
home staff are reasonably sure that sexual congress is taking place. The
partners have been in a long and happy marriage, and as far as anyone can tell,
the wife enjoys the sexual activity. Because of her dementia, however, she has
Versions of this paper have been given to a conference of old age psychiatrists in the Nottinghamshire
Healthcare NHS Trust (November 2007), the Annual Conference of the Royal College of Psychiatrists
(July 2008), the Institute of Mental Health of the University of Nottingham (October 2008), the annual
conference of the National Care Association (October 2008), ‘Sex, Law and Mental Capacity’ (a joint
conference of the Nottinghamshire Healthcare NHS Trust and Nottingham and Nottinghamshire Social
Services, hosted by the Institute of Mental Health, University of Nottingham, 15 January 2009), and at
‘Sex, Relationships and Mental Health’ (a conference hosted by the Nottinghamshire Healthcare NHS
Trust, May 2009). I am grateful to the participants in those events for their comments and insights.
Opinions expressed are of course my own.
P. Bartlett (&)
Nottinghamshire Healthcare NHS Trust Professor of Mental Health Law, Institute of Mental Health
and School of Law, University of Nottingham, Nottingham, England
e-mail: Peter.Bartlett@nottingham.ac.uk
123
138
P. Bartlett
no real understanding of the sexual nature of the husband’s behaviour. What if
anything should the care staff do?
As part of my job, I speak with a wide variety of care professionals, advocacy
organisations and service users on issues about law relating to mental health and
mental capacity. Beginning in mid-2007, the above scenario was put to me on a
number of occasions in a period of a few months. This may be in part because an
Oscar-nominated film starring Julie Christie, Away from Her, was in circulation at
the time, although that film concerns sexual activity between residents with
dementia, a situation slightly different from the scenario above. In any event it
became clear that the above scenario, or situations very similar to it, was confronted
by care home staff on a frequent basis.
The legal response to the situation is clear. The woman lacks the capacity to
consent to the sexual activity. The husband’s actions are therefore criminal.
Depending on the specific circumstances, this will be either or both under the
general offences contained in the opening sections of the Sexual Offences Act 2003,
and under the more specific offences relating to sex with people with mental
disorders impeding choice in sections 30–37 of that statute. Assuming the care
home staff were not actively promoting the activity, nothing in that statute would
make them criminally liable; but tort law does impose a duty on carers to ensure that
vulnerable people are safe in their care. There is therefore a significant possibility
that the staff (and, by vicarious liability, the home) could be liable in damages for
the activity, if they did indeed know that it was happening and failed to prevent it.
The overwhelming response when I have given this answer in these seminars and
discussions (and, indeed, with friends and many law colleagues) is that this is the
wrong result, both on ethical and practical terms. Responses have ranged from the
charitable (‘it’s one of the few pleasures she has left’), to the pragmatic (‘he’s
paying for the care home; what are we supposed to do?’). A few of my feminist
friends have focussed on the violative nature of sexual relations (‘just because she’s
old, it doesn’t mean it’s not rape’), but more frequently in seminars feminist
arguments are used to support the sexual activity (as with women saying ‘what do
you mean I can’t decide in advance that I will allow this? It’s my body, isn’t it?’).
On a number of occasions, I have been told that the law is adopting an approach that
is simply inhuman, or manifestly absurd.
I have some sympathy with this critical view, but I am unable to see the issue as
simply as the seminar participants present it. This article will discuss some of the
ambiguities and problems both in the legal approach, and in the permissive
approach.
The Current Legal Approach
The criminal law in this area is covered by the Sexual Offences Act 2003. The
activity at issue may be criminal under that statute in either of two ways.
First, the general criminal law, codified in the initial sections of that statute,
defines a variety of offences based on a lack of consent. Most significant for the fact
123
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
139
situation above are likely to be rape (s 1), assault by penetration (s 2), and sexual
assault, an offence which in this statute includes intentional sexual touching (s 3).
Perpetrators of these offences are guilty if the victim does not consent, and if the
perpetrator does not reasonably believe that the victim consents. A person without
capacity cannot consent, and if the perpetrator is aware of this, he or she will be
guilty of one of these offences, depending on the sexual act in question.
Second, the 2003 statute includes a specific set of offences relating to people with
mental disorders. Some of these offences relate to sex between carers and persons
with mental disorders (s 38–42). An exception is made in these cases for spouses
(including civil partners) of the person with a mental disorder (s 43), and for sexual
relationships that pre-date the care relationship (s 44). These offences are
presumably primarily directed at ensuring professionalism in care relationships.
Other offences relate to the use of inducement, threats or deception to engage or
involve a person with mental disorder in sexual activity (s 34–37). All these
offences may be committed in the context of a care home for people with dementia,
but they involve facts that are outside the scenario noted above and are thus of
limited relevance here.
Much more significant for current purposes are the offences in the 2003 statute
that concern a ‘person with a mental disorder impeding choice’. These offences
occur when the victim has a mental disorder of a type that renders them ‘unable to
refuse’ the activity in question, with inability to refuse further defined as ‘lack[ing]
the capacity to choose whether to agree to [the activity in question] (whether
because he lacks sufficient understanding of the nature or reasonably foreseeable
consequences of the activity, or for any other reason), or (b) [being] unable to
communicate such a choice to A.’ [s. 30(2), 31(2), 32(2), 33(2)] The offences extend
to engaging in sexual activity with such a person (s 30), causing or inciting such a
person to engage in sexual activity (s 31), engaging in sexual activity in the presence
of such a person (s 32), and causing such a person to watch a sexual act (s 33).
While there may be some room for discussion as to what constitutes ‘sexual’
activity,1 it seems likely from the scenario that the husband’s activity is within the
ambit of this term, and it seems equally likely that the wife lacks capacity2 and
therefore has a mental disorder impeding choice. Unlike the offences relating to
sexual activity with care staff, no exception is made for spousal relationships or preexisting sexual relationships. As such, it would seem that the husband’s actions are
criminal.
The Mental Capacity Act 2005 offers no assistance in these cases. While that
statute may provide some broad guidance as to how to approach questions of mental
capacity in this area,3 it specifically does not provide any mechanism to allow any
form of advance decision-making or substitute decision-making in sexual matters
when a person lacks capacity (s 27(1)(b)). If the person with dementia is unable to
consent to sexual activity, no one can consent in his or her stead.
1
Regarding the meaning of sexual activity, see further below.
2
Regarding definition of capacity, see further below.
3
See Re MM; Local Authority X v MM para 89–91.
123
140
P. Bartlett
The sentencing guidelines impose fairly stiff terms of imprisonment for such
crimes relating to persons with a mental disability impeding choice. They require
the judge to consider a public protection order, and convictions under these sections
are notifiable offences for purposes of the sex offenders register. Custodial
sentences are to be the norm, with penetration with aggravating factors generally
resulting in a sentence of eleven to seventeen years, a single offence of penetration
with no aggravating/mitigating factors eight to thirteen years, mutual genital contact
four to eight years, and contact that is non-genital from four weeks to eighteen
months. Aggravating factors include the predictable collection of issues relating to
compulsion or coercion and transmission of disease, but also ejaculation or causing
the victim to ejaculate; mitigating factors include a relationship of genuine affection
and the perpetrator also having a mental disorder that affected his or her
culpability.4 The inclusion of a relationship of genuine affection among the
mitigating factors is notable here. While the husband in the scenario above
apparently has such a relationship with the wife, and therefore could expect to
receive some mitigation, its inclusion as such a factor makes it clear (if it were
necessary to do so) that such a relationship does not constitute a defence: the
husband is still guilty.
The early cases regarding these sections of the Sexual Offences Act 2003
concerned persons with learning difficulties, and not in the context of old age.5 R v.
Adcock,6 from early 2010, appears to be the first reported case concerning dementia
in a care home for senior citizens. The case involved a man whose wife was in the
care home, but who was found engaging in sexual activity with another woman
resident. The sexual activity in question involved the stroking of the woman’s
vagina through her underwear and rubbing her right breast. Staff noted that both she
and the accused were smiling, and indeed the woman had a history of sexual
disinhibitedness in the home. The accused admitted that this was part of a series of
sexual encounters going back a few weeks, which had included insertion of his
finger in her vagina. There was no evidence of physical or emotional harm to the
woman. The accused pleaded guilty, albeit not immediately, and was of previously
unblemished character.
Adcock was sentenced to concurrent sentences of a maximum four years,
reduced to three on appeal. This is an ambiguous sentence. On one hand, three years
is a significant sentence. On the other, the sentence tariff for a single act of
penetration should have been eight to thirteen years, suggesting a markedly light
sentence. The good character of the accused, and the fact that his crime was one of
acquiescence to the sexual request of the victim (albeit an incompetent request)
appear to have been significant factors in the apparently low sentence. The overall
question of the gravity of sexual activity with a person with dementia is not
discussed. The significant but less than tariff sentence perhaps reflects some of the
ambiguities of the area, identified in this article: the court takes this sort of thing
very seriously, sort of.
4
Sentencing Guidelines Council, pp 70–71.
5
For a discussion of earlier cases, see Selfe, at 3 and Saunders in this volume.
6
R v Adcock.
123
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
141
Sex, Dementia and the Elderly
Until recently, there has been little explicit discussion of sex among the elderly. The
legal literature related to mental disability and capacity to engage in sexual
relationships has tended to focus on people with learning disabilities, rather than
people with age-related incapacity.7 While there are clearly some similarities
between these groups, there are also differences. Discussions of sex and people with
learning disabilities tends to focus on people who are socially expected to be
sexually active, typically late adolescents and young adults. For this group, issues
relating to the right to become parents are often relevant to the discussion. Often,
these discussions also concern people who are not in institutional care. These issues
do not transfer simply to the institutionalised elderly, for whom the right to become
a parent is unlikely to be a concern.
Empirical literature has similarly been slow to develop. As Kessel points out, sex
between elderly people has traditionally been perceived either not to exist, or to be a
topic of humour, or to be morally disgusting or otherwise grotesque.8 This silence
has begun to be broken regarding the elderly population generally. While it is true
that sexual activity tends to decrease in frequency as people age, it is still not
uncommon. A study by DeLamater and Moorman found that more than a quarter of
couples over the age of 75 had sexual relations at least monthly, and of those that
did, the average was three times per month.9 Their study suggests that medications
and illnesses have a relatively small effect on sexual activity.10 In a study by Gott
et al, thirteen of the twenty-one interviewees over the age of 70 considered sexual
activity was moderate to extremely important to them, and this included a majority
of both men and women interviewed.11 In Helgason’s study, almost half of Swedish
men aged between 70 and 80 had an orgasm at least once a month.12 Kesel notes in
a study of California retirement homes, 62 per cent of men and 30 per cent of
women continued to engage in sexual intercourse, and 87 of men and 68 per cent
of women to engage in physical intimacy.13
Certainly, therefore, it cannot be assumed that older adults are not sexually
active. It further appears that sexual and other intimate contact is healthy among
older people. Tenenbaum cites literature correlating sexual activity in this
population with an enhanced feeling of self-worth, longer life expectancies, better
cognitive functioning, and enhanced independence. The absence of such relationships, by comparison, she correlates to loneliness, depression, a higher usage of
medical and psychological services, and greater difficulties in acclimatising to life
in an institution, should such a move be necessary.14 The human side of this is
7
See, eg., Denno, and materials cited therein.
8
Kessel, 121.
9
DeLamater and Moorman, at 922.
10
DeLamater, 941.
11
Gott and Hinchliff, at 1620.
12
Helgason, Adolfsson, and Dickman, at 285.
13
Kesel at 121.
14
Tenenbaum, at 680–681.
123
142
P. Bartlett
evident from an interviewee in Roach’s study of staff responses to sexual behaviour
of people in nursing homes:
Everyone, everyone in nursing home, no matter how many visits from the
family, they are lonely. They’re crying for love, that’s what they want.15
These figures are helpful in dispelling the image of elderly adults as being
asexual, but they are of limited assistance in considering sex among people with
dementia, let alone who lack capacity to consent to sexual activity, as the studies do
not generally focus on these categories. Most do not focus on people in nursing
homes, let alone people with dementia. Sex among people with dementia is much
less studied. Ehrenfeld et al used an observational study to evaluate the sorts of
sexual activity in which people with dementia living in care homes engage. Seventy
per cent of the activity was between men and women, and it ranged from loving and
caring to eroticism.16 The study did not quantify the frequency of sexual contact,
however. Tabak states that with the onset of Alzheimer’s disease, desire for sexual
contact ‘frequently increases or, alternatively, there is complete disinterest’17 but
offers no empirical support for this claim. A study by Alagiakrishnan et al shows
that sexually inappropriate behaviour is rare among elderly people with dementia,
occurring in less than two per cent of that population, with rates not differing
between institutionalised people and those living in the community,18 but once
again no overall prevalence of sexual activity more generally is provided for these
populations. Nonetheless, it would appear from the limited empirical literature that
some sexual interests do remain among the elderly with dementia, and the quote
from Roach’s study above seems intuitively to be all the more compelling.
Indeed, the problem has an additional facet when one (or, perhaps, both) of the
partners lack capacity. With the progress of dementia, the nature of the relationship
will change. Conversation, upon which so much of relationship and expressions of
affection are based, will become less relevant. If a meaningful relationship between
the husband and wife is to be maintained, it seems likely that some form of physical
intimacy will be of enhanced importance. If this is correct, then too rigid a
restriction of such intimacy may have an adverse effect on the relationship, to the
detriment of both partners.
All this would support a view that sex and/or intimacy among the elderly is
something that ought at least in general to be encouraged.
At the same time, there is a serious risk of abuse. The incidence of abuse of
elderly people as a whole is well-known and, appropriately, a matter of public
concern.19 That said, it would seem that the incidence of sexual abuse among the
elderly is relatively small. In a study by O’Keeffe et al of 1784 persons in the United
Kingdom over the age of 66, only .2 per cent of those sampled had been subjected to
sexual abuse in the previous year. This is notably lower than any of the other
15
Roach, at 377.
16
Ehrenfeld, Bronner, Tabak, Alpert and Bergman.
17
Tabak, at 159.
18
Alagiakrishnan, Lim, Brahim, Wong, Wood, Senthilselvan, Chimich, and Kagan.
19
See, eg., Joint Committee on Human Rights of the House of Commons and House of Lords.
123
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
143
categories measured in the study—neglect, and financial, psychological and
physical abuse.20 Further, the abuse uncovered was relatively uninvasive—being
talked to in a sexual way, and being touched in a sexual way, complaints the study
authors viewed as classifiable as harassment.21 While this study is useful in
counteracting any image that sexual abuse of the elderly is epidemic in society, this
survey is problematic for present purposes, in that it excluded both the
institutionalised elderly and people with sufficiently severe dementia that they
were unable to engage in the research. It would seem that the institutionalised and
incapable elderly are more likely to be subject to abuse, suggesting that this is not a
question that should be simply dismissed.
The question of abuse is arguably circular, in that any sexual congress with a
person lacking capacity is arguably abusive. That would be the starting point in the
general criminal law, and any movement from that standard requires us to ask a
range of very difficult questions about sexuality, and why sexual behaviour with
older adults lacking capacity would be approached differently from other persons
lacking capacity. Our current law is clear: sexual activity with someone unable to
consent is a sexual offence. Issues such as whether the person ‘enjoyed it at the
time’ may be relevant to sentence, but they are not relevant to culpability. Why
would we create an exception for older people? Further, overlaying such a structure
onto existing law would be problematic. Tennenbaum and Ehrenfeld both note
instances of an institutionalised woman with dementia in a sexual relationship with
a man living in the care home, thinking incorrectly that the man in question was her
husband.22 Elsewhere in law, such a mistake of identity would vitiate consent; is
there any reason that we should adopt a different standard because the woman has
dementia? Does it matter if the person with dementia does not really understand
who the other party to the encounter is?
The current law takes a purely prohibitive approach to sex with the incapable
adult. If it is allowed that this is at least potentially counterintuitive, in that some
sexual activity may be helpful and healthy for such persons, the question becomes
how law could approach these difficulties.
Attempts to Escape the Dilemma
The 1957 Approach
The 2003 Act superseded the Sexual Offences Act 1957, which prohibited sexual
activity with any woman with a mental impairment, whether that woman had
capacity or not. Certainly, it would be theoretically possible to return adopt a statusbased prohibitory approach, where any sexual activity with a person with a mental
illness or learning disability would be criminal.
20
O’Keeffe, Hills, Doyle, McCreadie, Scholes, Constantine, Tinker, Manthorpe, Biggs, Erens, at 38.
21
O’Keefe et al. p. 42.
22
Tennenbaum at 686, Ehrenfeld at 147.
123
144
P. Bartlett
This direction is mentioned merely for completeness, and can be dismissed
summarily. It is not consistent with the developments in the rights of persons with
mental disabilities over the last half century. It would also not solve the difficulties
identified above. The question is whether too many people are currently precluded
from sexual activity, not too few, and a move to a status-based approach would
exacerbate rather than alleviate the difficulties discussed above.
The road to the future is thus not a return to the past.
The Definition of Capacity23
One way to minimise the effect of the tensions identified above would be to apply
the definition of capacity to maximise the number of people who can consent to
sexual activity. Such an approach is consistent with the approach of the Mental
Capacity Act 2005, with its requirements that a person ‘is not to be treated as unable
to make a decision unless all practicable steps to help him to do so have been taken
without success’ (s 1(3)) and should not be held to lack capacity if that person ‘is
able to understand an explanation of [the matter of the decision] given to him in a
way that is appropriate to his circumstances (using simple language, visual aids or
any other means)’ (s 3(2)). While this Act is not directly relevant to the
interpretation of the Sexual Offences Act 2003, its approach is consistent with the
direction of human rights law in the last decades.24 If this is correct, a procedural
standard is created: a person who can make a capable decision with appropriate
support is capable of consenting to the sexual activity.
The jurisprudence suggests that the substantive knowledge required for capacity
to consent to sexual activity is relatively low. Certainly, to have capacity the
individual must understand that the act in question is sexual, but the court in Re
MAB holds that this is not to be read in too restrictive a way:
Crucially, the question is whether she (or he) lacks the capacity to understand
the sexual nature of the act. Her knowledge and understanding need not be
complete or sophisticated. It is enough that she has sufficient rudimentary
knowledge of what the act comprises and of its sexual character to enable her
to decide whether to give or withhold consent.25
This raises the question of how the ‘sexual character’ is to be understood. The
court in MAB quotes R v Morgan [1970] VR 337 on this point:
The better view is that, in order to protect those with a mental disorder, a
person is to be treated as understanding the ‘‘nature’’ of the touching if they
understand its sexual nature, as opposed to the fact that the physical touching
is taking place. This interpretation focuses on the complainant’s knowledge or
understanding of the meaning or consequences of sexual relations, and so
23
Regarding the definition of capacity generally, see the papers by Suzanne Doyle and Ezra Hasson in
this volume.
24
The 2005 Act has also held to be consistent with the standards and approach of the 2003 Act: see Re
MM at 89–91.
25
Re MAB; X City Council and MB, NB, MAB, 74.
123
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
145
moves firmly away from the heavily criticised and old-fashioned view that a
mentally disordered person can legally consent to sexual activity if their
‘‘animal instincts’’ take over.26
The court in MAB expressly does not reach a decision as to whether the
individual must understand the nature and character of the sexual act, or instead (or
in addition?) understand the reasonably foreseeable consequences of that act. In
particular, it does not decide whether a knowledge of possible pregnancy or sexually
transmitted diseases is necessary to have capacity. The court’s concern here is in
placing capacity determination in a formalistic straight-jacket.27 The same judge, in
Re MM, elaborates on this concern, that the traditional framework of capacity
determination—understanding, retention, belief and appreciation of relevant
information—was unduly complex for questions relating to capacity to marry, or
to engage in sexual activity.28 Whether this less formalistic approach by the court
will stand over time remains to be seen. The fourfold structure of capacity
determination was well-established in common law,29 and (with the exception of the
removal of belief and the addition of the ability to communicate the decision) is
contained in the Mental Capacity Act 2005 (s 3(1)). Nonetheless, it would seem that
a simplified framework has so far been adopted by the Court in the context of
capacity to consent to sexual activity.
Capacity is not to be determined by whether it is a good idea to engage in the
behaviour in question, but rather of having the requisite understanding of that
behaviour. Nonetheless, an ability to understand specific issues that may be relevant
to the desirability of the sexual activity proceeding may be relevant, but only, of
course, if it relates to the specific relationship in question.30 Thus it is usual that
sexual congress between men and women can lead to pregnancy. Insofar as this is a
factor that one would normally expect to be a prerequisite to capable decisionmaking in this area, an exception must surely be made if one or both of the parties
are unable to have children by reason, for example, of being beyond child-bearing
years. Insofar as the assessment is based on the ramifications of the activity, the
assessment must surely be based on the actual ramifications that are possible from
the liaison in question. In the case of elderly people beyond child-bearing years, this
may well limit the understanding required for capacity, and correspondingly
increase the number of capable people.
The courts remain coy however on what it means to understand that the activity is
‘sexual’. As will be noted in the next section, the line between sexual and other
physically intimate behaviour can be illusive. It might mean that the behaviour does
or is intended to provoke a reaction of sexual arousal. It will be argued below that
this is a problematic definition in its own terms, but it is certainly problematic to be
included in an assessment of capacity. Some people come from religious or other
26
MAB, 80.
27
MAB, 90–91.
28
MM, 84, This is presumably also what the judge means at MAB 90.
29
See, eg., Re C (Adult: Refusal of Treatment); Re MB (Medical Treatment); NHS Trust v T.
30
See R v Cooper, 1793.
123
146
P. Bartlett
social or cultural traditions where this is certainly well-understood, but not the topic
of polite conversation. It is difficult to see that people with dementia who come from
such traditions, even if they have capacity, will be happy to discuss their
understandings of these private matters with care home staff in an assessment of
capacity. It cannot follow from this that these people are held to lack capacity. It
may also be the case that care home staff are uncomfortable probing residents on
these topics.
Alternatively or in addition, ‘sexual’ can be an abstract and complex concept. In
some psychological and sociological theories, it is a matter of social conditioning or
knowledge production. Consistent with this, Denno notes that seven American states
require that an individual must understand the ‘moral dimensions’ of the decision to
engage in sexual activity in order to have capacity to do so,31 and Tenenbaum gives
detailed consideration to religious factors in the assessment of whether sexual
relationships involving a person with dementia are appropriate.32 Such considerations suggest that the understanding of the social meaning of sexuality is complex,
and their inclusion in a test of capacity might well result in a much-restricted set of
people able to make sexual decisions. They also raise theoretical problems as to
what religious belief, or what moral code. People with dementia will usually have
had capacity at an earlier time in life, so it would be possible to use this as a guide to
decide what the individual must now understand in order to have capacity, but this is
counterintuitive. Generally, previous views are a guide to best interests,33 not to a
decision as to whether an individual now has capacity. Adoption of a more objective
approach is similarly problematic, however, as it is difficult to see a consistent set of
morals or social beliefs about sex shared across society. The social nature of
definitions of sex may be inescapable; but they do not seem in any meaningful way
shared, so they would be difficult to incorporate into a definition or assessment of
capacity.
Indeed, even though they may be social, conceptions of the sexual are often
unarticulated. Frequently, it is a case of we know it when we see it (or, alternatively,
feel it), and our decisions about it are often instinctive rather than academic. If that
is the case, it is once again difficult to see how that is to be tested, to determine
whether someone is able to understand that behaviour in question is indeed sexual.
The Meaning of ‘Sex’
One way to escape part of the potential harshness of the law is to interrogate more
closely what is meant by ‘sexual’ activity. It is clear that the offences are broader
than penetrative sex and genital contact, as the sentencing guidelines provide for
sentences of four weeks to eighteen months for non-genital touching. Particularly in
the realm of this conduct, what is it that makes conduct sexual, rather than merely
intimate?
Section 78 of the 2003 statute defines ‘sexual’ in the following terms:
31
Denno, at 344–345.
32
Tenenbaum at 715, 717–719.
33
See, eg., Mental Capacity Act 2005, s 4.
123
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
147
For the purposes of this Part (except section 71), penetration, touching or any
other activity is sexual if a reasonable person would consider that–
(a) whatever its circumstances or any person’s purpose in relation to it, it is
because of its nature sexual, or
(b) because of its nature it may be sexual and because of its circumstances
or the purpose of any person in relation to it (or both) it is sexual.
It would seem that this says that behaviour is sexual if it either (a) is sexual, or (b)
might be sexual and the perpetrator intends it to be sexual. In the current context, it
is difficult to see that this helps much.
Certainly, one might understand the sexual nature of an act in the context of the
inducement of or the intent to induce sexual arousal in a genital, physical sense.
Such a definition would be problematic in practice. Assume in the scenario above
that the husband greets his wife with an affectionate cuddle. If he finds himself
becoming aroused, he would on this test be required instantly to stop the cuddle,
whatever the effect of that on his wife. This seems both unrealistic and unduly
unkind both to him and to the wife.
Further, such an approach constitutes a remarkably impoverished notion of
sexuality. As it is experienced, sexuality is not merely about physical arousal. It is
about a particular form of intimacy. That is much more difficult to define,
particularly when one presumably wants the intimate relationship between the
husband and wife in the scenario above to continue. Defining when that is sexually
intimate and when that is merely emotionally intimate is likely to be either absurd
(since the distinction is nonsensical in the way the parties experience it) or
impossible (as the two meld together).
The secondary literature shows some of the ambiguities and arbitrariness of the
scope of the ‘sexual’ as opposed to the emotionally intimate. Tenenbaum, for
example, states:
Although it may at first seem counterintuitive, sexual contact is especially
important in nursing homes. Nursing homes are places of isolation and loss,
especially for dementia patients. By the time Alzheimer’s patients are placed
in nursing homes, they may be suffering from loss of memory, self-esteem,
and some ability to express themselves. Physical contact is an important
method of communicating with Alzheimer’s patients. It is a good way to calm
and reassure them and to show love and caring.34
This may well be true—but what about this contact makes it sexual, rather than
merely intimate? The question may well be nonsensical, as the participants may not
divide their feelings or their activity in this way. The uncertainty of the ‘sexual’ as a
category is further evident in Ehrenfeld’s study:
Several cases could not be classified, such as eight of the 46 (17%) reports of
residents found in their neighbours’ beds. This happened between women,
between men, and between men and women. It was not possible to conclude
34
Tenenbaum at 684.
123
148
P. Bartlett
that lying together was for sexual stimulation or an erotic interlude; perhaps
the intent was closeness and intimacy, resulting from fear of loneliness.35
Alternatively, the authors might presumably have added, it might be for all of the
above.
Given the complexity of sexuality as a concept, one could imagine that the
legislators might have been advised to take a different course, clarifying more
specifically what activities are permitted and what not when a person lacks capacity
in these circumstances. Thus one could imagine that acts of penetration might
appropriately be prohibited, but non-genital touching permitted unless there were
evidence of objection by the party lacking capacity, irrespective of whether or not
that touching induced a physical response of sexual arousal.
For better or worse, this is not the approach that the legislator took. It may be that
litigation may bring about some helpful clarification of section 78, but that may
prove problematic, as this section applies not only to the current context, but to all
sexual offences. If behaviour would be non-sexual for purposes of the current
sections, it would also be non-sexual, for example, in the context of the sexual
offences relating to children and minors, as section 78 applies to both. This is likely
to militate against restricting the scope of ‘sexual’ acts.36
Balancing of Interests, and Analysing Harm
Pressing the boundaries of capacity to consent and of the range of behaviours
covered by the 2003 act in a sense constitutes tinkering at the edges of the problem.
Certainly, effective jurisprudence may increase the range of people who may
consent to sexual activity, and the range of quasi-sexual activity that does not offend
the statute. The results are problematic however. First, the point of those who
advocate a more permissive policy is that some people who lack capacity by any
meaningful measure should be allowed to engage in activity which, on any sensible
reading of the 2003 Act, would be illegal. Their argument would be that such
activity is not merely not harmful, but is actually beneficial to the individual lacking
capacity. That core problem is not addressed by frittering at the edges of the
problem. Second, and equally problematic, a lowering of these thresholds may
expose more vulnerable people of marginal capacity to relationships which are
abusive. To protect against such abuse, it would be better to allow a more robust
threshold of capacity, and to allow non-abusive relationships to continue or develop
with people who lack capacity. A move to such a higher standard of capacity would
be criticised, in that it suggests a return to the old paternalism that has been under
attack in much of the disability rights movement for the last half century. While this
would be true for intrusive sexual behaviour, the paternalist tendency would be
offset by allowing less invasive and non-abusive activity to be engaged in by people
who did not have capacity.
35
Ehrenfeld et al, 147.
36
For a somewhat expansive reading of s 78 to the effect that touching an individual’s clothing could
constitute a sexual offence, albeit in a very different context than under consideration in this paper,
see R v H (Karl Anthony).
123
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
149
Taking account of these concerns would mean a move away from capacity as the
sole determinant of the permissibility of sexual activity—a significant change from
the status quo, but one proposed by a number of commentators in the field.
Tenenbaum suggests a four-step approach:
1.
2.
3.
4.
Determination of whether the individual has the ability to express a choice,
capable or otherwise;
Determine the interests or values might be affected by acting on these desires,
including the effects on the feelings of others;
Determine whether the resident can consider these interests in making a
decision. If so, the relationship should be allowed to continue.
If not, determine whether the values of the relationship outweigh the critical
ssues.37
Everett proposes an approach that would balance a variety of factors including
risks and benefits to the individual, and offence to others.38 Like Tenenbaum,
Everett argues that interference is only acceptable if the individual lacks capacity,
but this of itself is not enough. The activity must also pose an unreasonable risk, and
any interference will be effective, not creating more harm than it prevents, as mild
as possible, non-discriminatory, and if at all possible, considered justifiable by the
person upon whom it is imposed.39
These approaches have their appeal, but are potentially problematic. Both allow
people who have capacity to make their own decisions as to whether or not to
engage in sexual conduct: to that extent, both approaches must be right. A balancing
approach when the individual lacks capacity is more problematic, in that the factors
to be taken into account in the balancing process are not clearly defined. Certainly,
relations that caused physical or emotional distress to the person lacking capacity
should not be permitted; that too is surely uncontroversial, and constitutes a ‘trump
card’ in the balancing calculation. Equally convincingly, any direct positive
physical or emotional effects of the activity on the individual would weigh in favour
of allowing continuation of the activity. Both Tenenbaum and Everett move beyond
these relatively narrow parameters, however, considering for example the views and
feelings of others in determining the balance. This is potentially of concern, in that
the decision as the balancing act ceases to be focussed on the person lacking
capacity alone. Is it obvious for example whether the continuation of sexual activity
ought to be determined by whether the children of the person lacking capacity are
uncomfortable with the behaviour? Certainly, the literature concerning sexual
conduct between elderly care home residents contains accounts of cases where
family members are supportive of the sexual behaviour, but this is by no means
universal. Ehrenfeld’s study is interesting in this regard, in that it finds that ‘in
almost all cases in which a woman was erotically active, her relatives reacted
37
Tenenbaum at 713–716.
38
Everett, at 87. Everett’s scenario involves an elderly man who periodically hires an escort for dinner
and sexual services, so financial harm is included in her framework.
39
Everett, 95.
123
150
P. Bartlett
angrily and demanded that the staff should protect her.’40 This suggests a gendered
view of sexuality by the family, expressed in the notion of the sexual behaviour as
uniformly abusive. Insofar as these findings are representative (and Ehrenfeld’s was
a relatively small study), it is fair to ask how far such factors should be taken into
account in the balancing process.
A similar set of questions arises regarding care home staff. The literature
suggests that they may have firm views on the appropriateness of sexual behaviour
in care homes. Among the staff in the nursing homes studied by Ehrenfeld, romantic
behaviour apparently provoked mixed reactions, with some staff members seeing it
as amusing: ‘[t]o a certain extent, the staff treated these elderly people like small
children.’41 Generally such romantic activity was allowed to continue, but eroticism
aroused anger and objections. In Roach’s study, the responses of staff were found to
be a function of the staff member’s own comfort with sexuality issues.42 It is at best
doubtful whether, in such a fundamental area of personal life as sexuality, such
attitudes should be permitted to determine the permissibility of behaviour. At the
same time, this may be a practical reality: the administration of the balancing
process would presumably rest with the institutional staff of the care home.
An alternative approach would be to remove the restriction in the Mental
Capacity Act 2005 that takes sexual decision-making out of its ambit. If this
occurred, decisions regarding sexual behaviour could be made according to the best
interest test of that statute, a test which focuses on the best interests specifically of
the person lacking capacity rather than others, and requires consideration of•
•
•
•
The person’s past and present wishes and feelings, and in particular any written
directions provided while he or she had capacity
The beliefs and values that would be likely to influence his or her decision if he
or she had capacity;
The other factors he or she would be likely to consider if able to do so (s 4(6))
All other relevant circumstances (s 4(2))
The open-ended criteria permitted to be considered by s 4(2) would allow objective
harm or benefit to the individual to be considered, and the remaining factors would
require factors specific to the individual and his or her previous beliefs to be
expressly taken into account. In evaluating these factors, the Mental Capacity Act
2005 requires the decision-maker to consult persons involved in the care of the
person lacking capacity, holders of a lasting power of attorney for that person, and
consultees identified by the person lacking capacity. The views of these individuals
are intended to be sought merely as they relate to the best interests of the individual
lacking capacity. The consultee’s own views of (in this case) the morality or
propriety of the sexual activity would be irrelevant, unless those views were also
those of the person lacking capacity.
These criteria would if properly applied move a considerable distance towards an
approach centred on the person lacking capacity, rather than the professional and
40
Ehrenfeld et al, 148.
41
Ehrenfeld et al, 148.
42
Roach, 371.
123
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
151
family group surrounding that person. If the approach of the Mental Capacity Act
2005 were carried to its full remit, the person while competent could include sexual
decision-making in a lasting power of attorney, designating the individual named in
that power to make decisions regarding sexual behaviour on his or her behalf, in the
event of the donor’s incapacity. This would take the decision-making right out of
the hands of the care home staff.
In some of the seminars I have given, this is greeted as the obvious and desirable
way forward. I am more sceptical. My concern is whether the best interests test
above can be successfully and accurately applied in the context of sexual decisionmaking. As Tenenbaum notes, it is not obvious even outside a sexual context that
families are particularly adept at predicting how one of their members would decide
in a specific situation, or what criteria that person would bring to the situation, and I
am sympathetic to her suspicion that these inaccuracies will be greater in matters of
sexual choice.43 Sexuality is so often not discussed in families, let alone the
question of consent to sexual activity in the event of subsequent incapacity. Can we
know what values the individual would have brought to the decision, if that
individual did not discuss those values with third parties prior to losing capacity?
This creates particular problems regarding sexuality. If an individual does not
discuss the values he or she would bring to consent to medical treatment with family
members, there is the objective test to fall back on, and in the context of provision of
medical treatment, that seems acceptable. Would we be comfortable relying on an
objective test to decide whether sexual behaviour was in the best interests of an
individual? And if so, what would that test look like? We are back to the
Tenenbaum and Everett approaches, discussed above.
The unreliability of evidence for choice is a theme which pervades any movement
away from the current law. Consider the facts in the scenario with which this paper
began. The length of the couple’s marriage can presumably be verified, but how
reliable will the information be that it was happy? The attraction of the scenario is its
unspoken suggestion that the woman would, if competent, consent to the sexual
activity, as it is implicit that she freely did throughout her cohabitation with her
husband. Once again, it is difficult to see that this will be known by anyone other than
the husband, if indeed by him; is his word to be taken uncritically on this matter?
A problem with the sort of test in the Mental Capacity Act is that it does not take
account of the fact that people change as they age. What was once unthinkable
becomes the norm. This is a problem with many decisions under the Act, but sexual
behaviour is a clear example. Even if we had a good sense of the views of the
individual at some point in the past, while of robust capacity, does it follow that the
individual’s views would remain unchanged at this later time?
Conclusion
The current situation is certainly problematic. Indications are that care staff are
uncertain how to deal with sexual behaviour involving people incapacitated by
43
Tenenbaum, 704.
123
152
P. Bartlett
dementia, and deal with it in different ways. In the Adcock case, the care home staff
alerted the care home manager, albeit it would seem after letting the sexual conduct
continue for some time, and the police were called. By comparison, in its report, The
Human Rights of Older People in Healthcare, the Joint Committee of the House of
Commons and House of Lords on Human Rights cites the case of an eighty year old
woman who was seriously sexually assaulted by another resident in 2004. While the
assault was reported in the institutional log book, it was not reported to the victim’s
daughter until the following year, and it was she, rather than the care home, that
alerted the police.44 My experience in speaking with practitioners suggests that
much sexual activity, but no doubt not all, is not reported to the authorities; but
equally it is clear from those discussions that this is an area where they are left in
real doubt as to how to respond.
As noted above, some wiggle room may be possible around the edges of the
problem, through juridical manipulation of the definitions of capacity and of sexual
and non-sexual behaviour, but these are unlikely to be sufficient to provide clear and
defensible indicators of what activity is and is not permitted. The possibilities
discussed in the final section, on ‘balancing’, would require amendments to the law.
It is equally difficult to see that the law can come up with a particularly convincing
answer to the problem. The reality is that some of the sex that would occur in these
settings would be healthy, happy and desirable; some would be abusive. It is
difficult to see that the law can come up with a sufficiently clear set of criteria that
could be enacted in legislation that would sensibly permit the good sex, and outlaw
the bad. This would be the case even if there were the political will to enact such
legislation, which there almost certainly is not: any move away from a capacity and
consent threshold for sexual conduct might well provoke a political firestorm that
would not necessarily encourage considered legislative change.
A possible way forward is perhaps provided by R (Purdy) v Director of Public
Prosecutions.45 That case concerned assisted suicide, a matter coming within article
8 (right to privacy and family life) of the ECHR. The House of Lords held in that
case that the uncertainties relating to prosecution in that situation were such that the
applicant, Ms Purdy, could not be sure that her ECHR rights would in the event be
respected. The House of Lords therefore required the Director of Public
Prosecutions to publish detailed guidelines on how prosecutorial discretion would
be exercised.
A parallel case can be made out in the current context. Sexual activity comes
within the purview of article 8.46 The argument can therefore be made that those
who are engaging in this illegal sexual activity—activity which may be desirable
and healthy for the person the law is designed to protect—are likely to be
prosecuted or not.
The current CPS advice regarding prosecution for offences relating to an
individual with a mental disorder impeding choice reads as follows:
44
Joint Committee of the House of Commons and House of Lords on Human Rights, at p 10.
45
R (Purdy) v Director of Public Prosecutions.
46
See MM, starting at 100; Niemietz v Germany at 29.
123
Sex, Dementia, Capacity and Care Homes
153
Code for Crown Prosecutors—considerations
A prosecution will usually take place unless there are public interest factors
tending against prosecution which clearly outweigh those tending in favour.
Given the seriousness of these offences a prosecution will almost certainly be
required in the public interest.47
Unless one takes the extreme hard line that all sex with a person lacking capacity is
abusive and harmful, this guidance must be incorrect. It is difficult to see that
prosecution of intimate cuddles between an elderly married couple will really
‘almost certainly be required in the public interest.’
If, as seems likely, statutory amendment is unlikely and would not improve
matters in any event, perhaps an improved guidance on prosecutorial discretion is
the best way forward.
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution
Noncommercial License which permits any noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any
medium, provided the original author(s) and source are credited.
References
Cases
C (Adult: Refusal of Treatment), Re, [1994] 1 WLR 290.
MAB, Re; X City Council and MB, NB, MAB [2006] EWHC 168 (Fam).
MB (Medical Treatment), Re [1997] 2 FLR 426.
MM, Re; Local Authority X v MM [2007] EWHC 2003 (Fam).
NHS Trust v T [2004] EWHC 1279 (Fam).
Niemietz v Germany (1993), 16 EHRR 97.
R v Adcock [2010] EWCA Crim 700.
R v Cooper [2009] 1WLR 1786.
R v H (Karl Anthony) [2005] EWCA Crim 732.
R (Purdy) v Director of Public Prosecutions [2009] UKHL 45.
Secondary Literature
Alagiakrishnan K. et al. 2005. ‘Sexually inappropriate behaviour in demented elderly people’.
Postgraduate Medical Journal 81: 463.
Crown Prosecution Service Guidance, Sexual Offences Act .2003. Version of 14 July 2009.
http://www.cps.gov.uk/legal/s_to_u/sexual_offences_act/#Offences_against_persons_1 Accessed
19 May 2010.
DeLamater, J. and Moorman, S. 2007. ‘Sexual behavior in later life’. Journal of Aging and Health 19(6):
921.
Denno, D. 1997. ‘Sexuality, Rape, and Mental Retardation’. University of Illinois Law Review 316.
Ehrenfeld, M., Bronner, G., Tabak, N., Alpert R., and Bergman, R. 1999. ‘Sexuality Among
Institutionalized Elderly Patients with Dementia’. Nursing Ethics 6(2): 144.
Everett, B. 2008. ‘Supporting Sexual Activity in Long-Term Care’. Nursing Ethics 15(1): 87.
Gott M. and Hinchliff, S. 2003. ‘How important is sex in later life? The views of older people.’ Social
Science and Medicine 56: 1617.
47
Crown Prosecution Service Guidance.
123
154
P. Bartlett
Helgason, A., Adolfsson, J., and Dickman, P. 1996. ‘Sexual Desire, erection, orgasm and ejaculatory
functions and their importance to elderly Swedish men: A population-based study. Age and Aging
25: 285.
Joint Committee on Human Rights of the House of Commons and House of Lords. 2006. The Human
Rights of Older people in Healthcare, PP 2006–2007 HL-156, HC-378.
Kessel, B. 2001. ‘Sexuality in the older person’. Age and Aging 30: 121.
O’Keeffe, M., A. Hills, M. Doyle, C. McCreadie, S. Scholes, R. Constantine, A. Tinker, J. Manthorpe, S.
Biggs, and B. Erens. 2007. UK Study of abuse and neglect of older people: Prevalence survey
report. London: National Centre for Social Research and King’s College London.
Roach, S. 2004. ‘Sexual behaviour of nursing home residents: Staff perceptions and responses’. Journal
of Advanced Nursing 48(4): 371.
Sentencing guidelines council, sexual offences Act 2003 Definitive guideline, April 2007. Available at
http://www.sentencing-guidelines.gov.uk/. Accessed 21 May 2010.
Selfe, D. 2008. ‘Sentencing of persons with mental disorder’. Criminal Lawyer 184: 2.
Tabak, N. 2006. ‘Sexuality and Alzheimer’s Disease: Can the two go together?’ Nursing Forum 41(4):
158.
Tenenbaum, E. 2009. ‘To Be or To Exist: Standards for deciding whether dementia patients in nursing
homes should engage in intimacy, Sex, and Adultery’. Indiana Law Review 42: 675.
123