Mathematical Beauty 30062011 en
Mathematical Beauty 30062011 en
Mathematical Beauty 30062011 en
Mathematical beauty
Many mathematicians derive aesthetic pleasure from their work, and from mathematics in general. They express this pleasure by describing mathematics (or, at least, some aspect of mathematics) as beautiful. Sometimes mathematicians describe mathematics as an art form or, at a minimum, as a creative activity. Comparisons are often made with music and poetry. Bertrand Russell expressed his sense of mathematical beauty in these words: Mathematics, rightly viewed, possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty a beauty cold and austere, like that of sculpture, without appeal to any part of our weaker nature, without the gorgeous trappings of painting or music, yet sublimely pure, and capable of An example of "beauty in method"a simple and elegant geometrical proof that a stern perfection such as only the Pythagorean theorem is true for a particular right-angled triangle. the greatest art can show. The true spirit of delight, the exaltation, the sense of being more than Man, which is the touchstone of the highest excellence, is to be found in mathematics as surely as poetry.[1] Paul Erds expressed his views on the ineffability of mathematics when he said, "Why are numbers beautiful? It's like asking why is Beethoven's Ninth Symphony beautiful. If you don't see why, someone can't tell you. I know numbers are beautiful. If they aren't beautiful, nothing is."[2]
Beauty in method
Mathematicians describe an especially pleasing method of proof as elegant. Depending on context, this may mean: A proof that uses a minimum of additional assumptions or previous results. A proof that is unusually succinct. A proof that derives a result in a surprising way (e.g., from an apparently unrelated theorem or collection of theorems.) A proof that is based on new and original insights. A method of proof that can be easily generalized to solve a family of similar problems. In the search for an elegant proof, mathematicians often look for different independent ways to prove a resultthe first proof that is found may not be the best. The theorem for which the greatest number of different proofs have been discovered is possibly the Pythagorean theorem, with hundreds of proofs having been published.[3] Another theorem that has been proved in many different ways is the theorem of quadratic reciprocityCarl Friedrich Gauss alone published eight different proofs of this theorem.
Mathematical beauty Conversely, results that are logically correct but involve laborious calculations, over-elaborate methods, very conventional approaches, or that rely on a large number of particularly powerful axioms or previous results are not usually considered to be elegant, and may be called ugly or clumsy.
Beauty in results
Some mathematicians (Rota (1977), p.173) see beauty in mathematical results that establish connections between two areas of mathematics that at first sight appear to be totally unrelated. These results are often described as deep. While it is difficult to find universal agreement on whether a result is deep, some examples are often cited. One is Euler's identity:
Starting at e0 = 1, travelling at the velocity i relative to one's position for the length of time , and adding 1, one arrives at 0. (The diagram is an Argand diagram)
Physicist Richard Feynman called this "the most remarkable formula in mathematics". Modern examples include the modularity theorem, which establishes an important connection between elliptic curves and modular forms (work on which led to the awarding of the Wolf Prize to Andrew Wiles and Robert Langlands), and "monstrous moonshine," which connects the Monster group to modular functions via a string theory for which Richard Borcherds was awarded the Fields medal. The opposite of deep is trivial. A trivial theorem may be a result that can be derived in an obvious and straightforward way from other known results, or which applies only to a specific set of particular objects such as the empty set. Sometimes, however, a statement of a theorem can be original enough to be considered deep, even though its proof is fairly obvious. In his A Mathematician's Apology, Hardy suggests that a beautiful proof or result possesses "inevitability", "unexpectedness", and "economy".[4] Rota, however, disagrees with unexpectedness as a condition for beauty and proposes a counterexample: A great many theorems of mathematics, when rst published, appear to be surprising; thus for example some twenty years ago [from 1977] the proof of the existence of non-equivalent differentiable structures on spheres of high dimension was thought to be surprising, but it did not occur to anyone to call such a fact beautiful, then or now.[5] Perhaps ironically, Monastyrsky writes: It is very difficult to nd an analogous invention in the past to Milnor's beautiful construction of the different differential structures on the seven-dimensional sphere....The original proof of Milnor was not very constructive but later E. Briscorn showed that these differential structures can be described in an extremely explicit and beautiful form.[6] This disagreement illustrates both the subjective nature of mathematical beauty and its connection with mathematical results: in this case, not only the existence of exotic spheres, but also a particular realization of them.
Mathematical beauty
Beauty in experience
Some degree of delight in the manipulation of numbers and symbols is probably required to engage in any mathematics. Given the utility of mathematics in science and engineering, it is likely that any technological society will actively cultivate these aesthetics, certainly in its philosophy of science if nowhere else. The most intense experience of mathematical beauty for most mathematicians comes from actively engaging in mathematics. It is very difficult to enjoy or appreciate mathematics in a purely passive wayin mathematics there is no real analogy of the role of the spectator, audience, or viewer.[7] Bertrand Russell referred to the austere beauty of mathematics.
Notes
[1] Russell, Bertrand (1919). "The Study of Mathematics" (http:/ / books. google. com/ ?id=zwMQAAAAYAAJ& pg=PA60& dq=Mathematics+ rightly+ viewed+ possesses+ not+ only+ truth+ but+ supreme+ beauty+ a+ beauty+ cold+ and+ austere+ like+ that+ of+ sculpture+ without+ appeal+ to+ any+ part+ of+ our+ weaker+ nature+ without+ the+ gorgeous+ trappings+ inauthor:Russell). Mysticism and Logic: And Other Essays. Longman. p.60. . Retrieved 2008-08-22. [2] Devlin, Keith (2000). "Do Mathematicians Have Different Brains?" (http:/ / books. google. com/ ?id=AJdmfYEaLG4C& pg=PA140& lpg=PA140& dq=Why+ are+ numbers+ beautiful?+ It's+ like+ asking+ why+ is+ Beethoven's+ Ninth+ Symphony+ beautiful. + If+ you+ don't+ see+ why,+ someone+ can't+ tell+ you. + I+ know+ numbers+ are+ beautiful. + If+ they+ aren't+ beautiful,+ nothing+ is. ). The Math Gene: How Mathematical Thinking Evolved And Why Numbers Are Like Gossip. Basic Books. p.140. ISBN9780465016198. . Retrieved 2008-08-22. [3] Elisha Scott Loomis published over 360 proofs in his book Pythagorean Proposition (ISBN 0873530365). [4] Hardy, G.H.. "18". [5] Rota (1977), p.172 [6] Monastyrsky (2001) [7] Phillips, George (2005). "Preface" (http:/ / books. google. com/ ?id=psFwdN6V6icC& pg=PR7& lpg=PR7& dq=there+ is+ nothing+ in+ the+ world+ of+ mathematics+ that+ corresponds+ to+ an+ audience+ in+ a+ concert+ hall,+ where+ the+ passive+ listen+ to+ the+ active. + Happily,+ mathematicians+ are+ all+ doers,+ not+ spectators. ). Mathematics Is Not a Spectator Sport. Springer Science+Business Media. ISBN0387255281. . Retrieved 2008-08-22. ""...there is nothing in the world of mathematics that corresponds to an audience in a concert hall, where the passive listen to the active. Happily, mathematicians are all doers, not spectators."
Mathematical beauty
[8] Schechter, Bruce (2000). My brain is open: The mathematical journeys of Paul Erds. New York: Simon & Schuster. pp.7071. ISBN0-684-85980-7. [9] A. Moles: Thorie de l'information et perception esthtique, Paris, Denol, 1973 (Information Theory and aesthetical perception) [10] F Nake (1974). sthetik als Informationsverarbeitung. (Aesthetics as information processing). Grundlagen und Anwendungen der Informatik im Bereich sthetischer Produktion und Kritik. Springer, 1974, ISBN 3211812164, ISBN 9783211812167 [11] J. Schmidhuber. Low-complexity art. Leonardo, Journal of the International Society for the Arts, Sciences, and Technology, 30(2):97103, 1997. http:/ / www. jstor. org/ pss/ 1576418 [12] J. Schmidhuber. Papers on the theory of beauty and low-complexity art since 1994: http:/ / www. idsia. ch/ ~juergen/ beauty. html [13] J. Schmidhuber. Simple Algorithmic Principles of Discovery, Subjective Beauty, Selective Attention, Curiosity & Creativity. Proc. 10th Intl. Conf. on Discovery Science (DS 2007) p. 26-38, LNAI 4755, Springer, 2007. Also in Proc. 18th Intl. Conf. on Algorithmic Learning Theory (ALT 2007) p. 32, LNAI 4754, Springer, 2007. Joint invited lecture for DS 2007 and ALT 2007, Sendai, Japan, 2007. http:/ / arxiv. org/ abs/ 0709. 0674 [14] .J. Schmidhuber. Curious model-building control systems. International Joint Conference on Neural Networks, Singapore, vol 2, 14581463. IEEE press, 1991 [15] Schmidhuber's theory of beauty and curiosity in a German TV show: http:/ / www. br-online. de/ bayerisches-fernsehen/ faszination-wissen/ schoenheit--aesthetik-wahrnehmung-ID1212005092828. xml
References
Aigner, Martin, and Ziegler, Gunter M. (2003), Proofs from THE BOOK, 3rd edition, Springer-Verlag. Chandrasekhar, Subrahmanyan (1987), Truth and Beauty: Aesthetics and Motivations in Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL. Hadamard, Jacques (1949), The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field, 1st edition, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ. 2nd edition, 1949. Reprinted, Dover Publications, New York, NY, 1954. Hardy, G.H. (1940), A Mathematician's Apology, 1st published, 1940. Reprinted, C.P. Snow (foreword), 1967. Reprinted, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1992. Hoffman, Paul (1992), The Man Who Loved Only Numbers, Hyperion. Huntley, H.E. (1970), The Divine Proportion: A Study in Mathematical Beauty, Dover Publications, New York, NY. Loomis, Elisha Scott (1968), The Pythagorean Proposition, The National Council of Teachers of Mathematics. Contains 365 proofs of the Pythagorean Theorem. Peitgen, H.-O., and Richter, P.H. (1986), The Beauty of Fractals, Springer-Verlag. Reber, R., Brun, M., & Mitterndorfer, K. (2008). The use of heuristics in intuitive mathematical judgment. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 15, 1174-1178. Strohmeier, John, and Westbrook, Peter (1999), Divine Harmony, The Life and Teachings of Pythagoras, Berkeley Hills Books, Berkeley, CA. Rota, Gian-Carlo (1977). "The phenomenology of mathematical beauty". Synthese 111 (2): 171182. doi:10.1023/A:1004930722234 Monastyrsky, Michael (2001). "Some Trends in Modern Mathematics and the Fields Medal" (http://www.fields. utoronto.ca/aboutus/FieldsMedal_Monastyrsky.pdf). Can. Math. Soc. Notes 33 (2 and 3)
Mathematical beauty
External links
Is Mathematics Beautiful? (http://www.cut-the-knot.org/manifesto/beauty.shtml) Links Concerning Beauty and Mathematics (http://www.madras.fife.sch.uk/maths/linksbeauty.html) Mathematics and Beauty (http://www.chemistrycoach.com/science_mathematics_and_beauty.htm) The Beauty of Mathematics (http://users.forthnet.gr/ath/kimon/) Justin Mullins (http://www.justinmullins.com/) Edna St. Vincent Millay (poet): Euclid alone has looked on beauty bare (http://www.the-athenaeum.org/ poetry/detail.php?id=80) The method for transformation of music into an image through numbers and geometrical proportions (http:// creativelab.kiev.ua/eng/index_eng.htm) Terence Tao, What is good mathematics? (http://www.math.ucla.edu/~tao/preprints/Expository/goodmath. dvi)
License
Creative Commons Attribution-Share Alike 3.0 Unported http:/ / creativecommons. org/ licenses/ by-sa/ 3. 0/