0% found this document useful (0 votes)
64 views

Intermediate Value Theorem

The document discusses the Intermediate Value Theorem in calculus. It states that the theorem motivates the intuition that a function is continuous if it can be graphed without lifting chalk from the board. It then presents Lemma 1, which is essential to proving the theorem. Lemma 1 states that if a function f is continuous on an interval (a,b) and f(c)>0 for some c in the interval, then there is a neighborhood around c where f(x) remains positive. The document concludes by using Lemma 1 to prove the Intermediate Value Theorem, which states that for a continuous function f on an interval [a,b] where f(a) and f(b) are known values, every

Uploaded by

Eric Rogers
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
64 views

Intermediate Value Theorem

The document discusses the Intermediate Value Theorem in calculus. It states that the theorem motivates the intuition that a function is continuous if it can be graphed without lifting chalk from the board. It then presents Lemma 1, which is essential to proving the theorem. Lemma 1 states that if a function f is continuous on an interval (a,b) and f(c)>0 for some c in the interval, then there is a neighborhood around c where f(x) remains positive. The document concludes by using Lemma 1 to prove the Intermediate Value Theorem, which states that for a continuous function f on an interval [a,b] where f(a) and f(b) are known values, every

Uploaded by

Eric Rogers
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 2

The Intermediate Value Theorem

The intermediate value theorem is an important theorem in calculus. It is one of the results which motivates the intuition a function is continuous if I can graph it without lifting the chalk o the board. You are NOT responsible for its proof, but you should understand the following lemma, which is essential to the proof of the Intermediate Value Theorem. (You should draw a picture to understand why we c) in the proof of the lemma!) choose = f ( 2 Lemma 1. Suppose f is continuous on (a, b). Suppose there is a c (a, b) such that f (c) > 0. Then there is a > 0 such that f (x) > 0 for all x (c , c + ) (a, b). Proof. Since f is continuous at c, for all > 0, there is a > 0 such that |x c| < implies |f (x) f (c)| < . Since this is true for all > 0, it is true when we choose c) = f( > 0. Now we are assured there must be a > 0 such that 2 (1) (c , c + ) (a, b), and (2) if x (c , c + ), then |f (x) f (c)| < Note that the inequality |f (x) f (c)| < inequalities:
f (c) 2 f (c) . 2

is equivalent to the following pairs of

f (c) f (c) 3f (c) f (c) < (f (x) f (c)) < < f (x) < . 2 2 2 2

Hence (2) above is equivalent to (2) if x (c , c + ), then Since


f (c) 2 f (c) 2

< f (x) <

3f (c) . 2

> 0, we know f (x) > 0 for all x (c , c + ).

Remark 2. Lemma 1 is also true when we replace both >s above with <s. Using the lemma and the remark, we now prove the Intermediate Value Theorem Theorem 3 (Intermediate Value). Suppose f is continuous on [a, b] and f (a) = f (b). Then for every y between f (a) and f (b), there is a c (a, b) such that f (c) = y . Proof. It is enough to consider the case f (a) < f (b) and y = 0. (If f (a) > f (b), we replace f with f . If y = 0, we replace f with f y .) Let S = {x (a, b)|f (x) < 0}. Since f (b) > 0, b is an upper bound for S . By the completeness axiom of the real numbers, S has a unique least upper bound c. We claim that f (c) = 0. To show this, we will show (1) f (c) is not greater than 0, and (2) f (c) is not less than 0. 1

It will follow from these two facts that f (c) must equal zero. Proof of (1): We give a proof by contradiction. Suppose f (c) > 0. Then by Lemma 1, there is a > 0 such that f is strictly positive on (c , c + ) (a, b). Consider c = c 2 . Since f (x) > 0 for all x [c , c], and c is an upper bound for S , c is also and upper bound for S . But this is a contradiction to the fact that c is the least upper bound of S . Hence f (c) is not greater than zero. Proof of (2): Again, we give a proof by contradiction. Suppose f (c) < 0. Again by Lemma 1 and Remark 2, there is a > 0 such that f is strictly negative on . Then f (c ) < 0, so c S . But c > c, (c , c + ) (a, b). Consider c = c + 2 which is an upper bound for S , a contradiction. Hence f (c) is not less than zero.

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy