Master Ethiopia
Master Ethiopia
Master Ethiopia
African Philosophy
in Ethiopia
Ethiopian Philosophical Studies II
with
A Memorial of Claude Sumner
Edited by
Bekele Gutema
Charles C. Verharen
Copyright 2013 by
The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy
Box 261
Cardinal Station
Washington, D.C. 20064
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication
Philosophy in Ethiopia: African philosophy today, I : Ethiopian philosophical
studies II / edited by Bekele Gutema, Charles C. Verharen
Pages cm. -- (Cultural heritage and contemporary change. Series II, Africa ;
volume 15)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. Philosophy--Ethiopia. 2. Philosophy, African. 3. Education, Higher-Ethiopia--Philosophy. 4. Education, Higher--Africa. 5. Philosophy--Study and
teaching--Ethiopia. 6. Oromo (African people)--Religion. I. Bekele Gutema.
II. Verharen, Charles C., 1941ISBN 978-1-56518-279-0 (pbk.)
B5407.P45 2012
2012035323
199.63--dc23
CIP
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Acknowledgements
Foreword: In Memory: The Significance of Claude Sumner SJs
Contribution to Africa Philosophy
Gail M. Presbey and George F. McLean
Introduction
Bekele Gutema and Charles C. Verharen
v
vii
17
29
37
53
69
95
iv
Table of Contents
117
139
159
185
203
List of Contributors
211
Index
213
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The idea of publishing this volume was conceived when Dr. Bekele
Gutema of the Department of Philosophy of Addis Ababa University and
Professor Charles C. Verharen of Howard University organized a
Conference here in Addis Ababa. The Conference took place on June 23,
2010 at the German Cultural Institute (Goethe-Institut). This volume
includes the conference papers as well as other papers selected for their
expression of current thinking in Ethiopian philosophy.
We would like to thank the following copyright owners for permission
to publish the materials. The Journal of Oromo Studies gave us permission
to republish Charles Verharens Comparing Oromo and Egyptian
Philosophy and Tenna Dewos The Concept of Peace in the Oromo
Gadaa System: Its Mechanisms and Moral Dimension. The Journal of
Ethiopian Studies gave us permission to reprint Tadesse Berissos The
Riddles of the Number Nine in Guji Oromo Culture. Rodopi allowed us
to re-print Messay Kebedes Harnessing Myth to Rationality from his
book, Africas Quest for a Philosophy of Decolonization. We were also
given permission to reprint Gail Presbeys article titled, Should Women
Love Wisdom: Evaluating the Ethiopian Wisdom Tradition by the Indiana
University Press from its journal, Research in African Literature (Summer
1999: 30, 2). Finally Taylor and Francis allowed us to reprint Teodros
Kiros article, Moral Economy: an Original Condition for the African
Condition that appeared in Volume 27: 3 of Socialism and Democracy.
We are grateful to all the copyright owners for allowing us to reproduce
these articles.
We would also like to thank our anonymous reviewers for reviewing
all essays not previously reviewed by journal or academic press referees.
We wish to thank Howard University for providing funds for the
Conference and publication of the volume. We also thank the Department
of Philosophy, Addis Ababa University for assistance in organizing the
Conference. The German Cultural Institute provided us with the venue of
the Conference for which we are grateful. Dr. Mamo Hebo of the
Department of Social Anthropology, Addis Ababa University did
invaluable work in editing and laying out the book, for which he deserves
our sincere thanks. We have not been able to name everybody that had a
role in this book. We would like to thank all who have cooperated with us
in preparing this book for publication one way or the other. The
responsibility for the mistakes lies with us, the editors.
Finally, we are honored to dedicate this volume of Ethiopian
Philosophical Studies to the late Professor Claude Sumner, S.J. and his life
of dedication to African philosophy in Ethiopia.
FOREWORD
IN MEMORY
THE SIGNIFICANCE OF
CLAUDE SUMNER SJs CONTRIBUTION TO
AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY
GAIL M. PRESBEY and GEORGE F. McLEAN
viii
ix
xi
xii
xiii
xiv
Ricci, Matteo (1985), The True Meaning of the Lord of Heaven, trans., I.
Lancashire and P. Hu Kuo-chen, A Chinese English Edition, E.
Malatesta, ed., Jesuit Primary Sources, St. Louis: Institute of Jesuit
Sources, 1985.
Sumner, Claude. (1974) Ethiopian Philosophy, Vol. 1, The Book of the Wise
Philosophers. Addis Ababa: Central Printing Press.
Sumner, Claude. (1978) "Seminar on African Philosophy, Addis Ababa,
1-3 December 1976." In Abba Salama, vol. IX.
Sumner, Claude. (1979) "The First Afro-Asian Philosophy Conference,
Cairo 13-16 March 1978: The Rise of Philosophical Thought Within
Black Africa." In Abba Salama vol. X (1979) pp. 229-244.
Sumner, Claude. (1981) Ethiopian Philosophy, Volume IV: The Life and
Maxims of Skendes. Addis Ababa: Commercial Printing Press
Sumner, Claude. (1986) The Source of African Philosophy: The Ethiopian
Philosophy of Man. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag Wiesbaden
GMBH
Sumner, Claude. (1991) "Problem of an African Philosophy," in Books For
Life, ed. by Negussay Ayele and Claude Sumner. Addis Ababa: Relief
and Rehabilitation Commission, 44-71.
Sumner, Claude (1993), "Independent Personal Thought in Ethiopian
Sapiential and Philosophical Literature," in Journal of African
Religion and Philosophy, vol. 2, no. 2.
Sumner, Claude. (1994) Classical Ethiopian Philosophy. Los Angeles:
Adey Publishing Co. See also the same title published in 1985, Addis
Ababa: Commercial Printing Press.
Sumner, Claude. (1995) Oromo Wisdom Literature, Vol. 1: Proverbs,
Collection and Analysis. Addis Ababa: Gudina
Tumsa
Foundation
Sumner, Claude. (1997) Oromo Wisdom Literature, Vol. 2: Songs,
Collection and Analysis. Addis Ababa: Gudina Tumsa Foundation
Sumner, Claude. (1997) Oromo Wisdom Literature, Vol. 3: Folktales,
Collection and Analysis. Addis Ababa: Gudina Tumsa Foundation
Wondyifraw Ambaye (1986). Classical Ethiopian Philosophy and
Traditional Attitude. Proceedings of the Ninth International
Conference on Ethiopian Studies, Moscow, 26-29 August.
Workineh Kelbessa (1993), The African Source of Greek Philosophy, in
Journal of African Religion and Philosophy, vol. 2, no. 2, 14-23.
Workineh Kelbessa (1994), Foreign Influence and its Impact on Ethiopian
Philosophy, in New Trends in Ethiopian Studies: Papers of the 12th
International Conference of Ethiopian Studies, Michigan State
University 5-10 Sept. Vol. 1: Humanities and Human Resources.
Harold Marcus, ed. Lawrenceville NJ: Red Sea Press.
INTRODUCTION
BEKELE GUTEMA and CHARLES C. VERHAREN
has been able to go beyond the assumptions that a philosophical text must
be only a written one. Richard Bell in his Understanding African
Philosophy: A Cross-Cultural approach to the Contemporary Issues has
shown that reducing the sources of philosophy leads to an impoverished
philosophy. Including not only literature but also orature amplifies the
power of philosophy, as Claude Sumner has demonstrated so well in his
three volumes on Oromo Wisdom Literature. Samuel Imbo argues that
orality itself constitutes a text that is embedded in practice: Systematic
analysis and past experiences of the community are telescoped into a folk
logic of survival. Right and wrong are important not as abstract concepts
but in proportion to which they make an empirical difference . [I]f the
traditions of a culture are wrong, that culture will not survive the sustained
onslaught of foreign influences (1998: 109).
We hope that this volume entitled, Philosophy in Africa Now: African
Philosophy in Ethiopia, serves as an example of intercultural polylogue. A
number of contributions focus on Oromo philosophy. The Oromo have
developed a unique culture, as exemplified by the Gadaa system, a truly
democratic form of government with over three centuries of recorded
history. Written sources on Oromo include accounts by early travelers and
missionaries. However, a rich anthropological literature has enabled
scholars to gain access to what was historically a purely oral culture. A
principal aim of this volume is to encourage philosophers to start research
on Ethiopian peoples other than the Oromo. Present-day Ethiopia is home
to around eighty distinct linguistic groups. True intercultural philosophy
must extend its range to the wider populations of Ethiopia.
This book consists of twelve papers divided into six sections. We will
give a very brief introduction to the papers. The first section, Philosophy of
University Education in Ethiopia, consists of three papers by Charles
Verharen, Bekele Gutema and the late Daniel Smith.
C. Verharens paper, Philosophy and the Future of African
Universities: Ethics and Imagination, argues that universities have an
ethical responsibility of supporting the communities that host them.
Drawing on W. E. Du Bois notion of Historically Black Colleges and
Universities, he makes the point that one of the important tasks of Ethiopian
universities is to be relevant to their supporting communities by trying to
solve their problems. What are the problems that Ethiopias diverse cultural
communities face? Ethiopias universities could be up to their tasks if such
questions constitute the foci of their research.
The second article in this section is B. Gutemas, Some Thoughts on
the African University. Tracing the origin of the African University to the
time when colonialism was starting to set the African countries free, he
questions the purpose behind the establishment of universities at that
particular juncture in history. He argues that the African university is an
extraverted institution that was meant to serve the purpose of colonialism,
rather than the aspirations of the African peoples. This is demonstrated by
the curricula, the research topics and the faculty that initially established
Introduction
Introduction
potential for resolving the moral crisis of the contemporary African state.
The term maat is translated as harmony, order, peace, justice, or balance.
Kiros describes maat as the foundational principle of ancient Egyptian
ethics.
In this essay Kiros sets himself the task of outlining how to create
human beings who can act generously, patiently, tolerantly and lovingly.
We do not have such human beings in sufficient numbers to construct an
economic form that values justice, uprightness, wisdom, tolerance and
loving patience. Taking everyday examples to illustrate how Maatian
ethics guides decision-making, Kiros sets the foundation for an ethical
reconfiguration of contemporary African states.
SECTION I
CHAPTER I
INTRODUCTION
This essay considers the ethical responsibilities of universities whose
supporting constituencies are marginalized. With particular reference to
African universities, the essay argues that the primary responsibility of a
university is to solve the problems of the communities that make the
universitys existence possible. With special reference to Ethiopian
universities, the essay contends that universities responsible for populations
with wide ranges of distinctive cultures must center their research programs
in those cultural contexts. Commenting on the distinctive nature of
historically black colleges and universities in the United States (HBCUs),
W.E.B. Du Bois (1975) claimed that all universities are embedded in
particular cultural contexts. The Sorbonne is both responsive to and
responsible for the French who make its existence possible. HBCUs must
address the concerns of African Americans. Ethiopian universities are
embedded in the contexts of over 80 diverse cultures, if language is indeed
a primary carrier of culture. On Du Bois model, Ethiopian universities
must direct their research towards the solutions of the problems faced by
those cultures.
ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF AFRICAN UNIVERSITIES:
SPECIAL ETHICAL RESPONSIBILITIES OF UNIVERSITIES
WHOSE CONSTITUENCIES ARE MARGINALIZED
Universities are differentiated by the problems of the populations who
make the universities existence possible. Would it be possible to have a
research university whose problems were completely isolated from any
population whatsoever? A Pure Research University? Of course, if the
research of that university were not supported by any population
whatsoever.
We could consider this hypothetical model: a Harvard with an
endowment so gigantic that it covered all the universitys expenses.
However, Harvards endowment covers only a portion of its expenditures.
University expenses are supported by endowment, tuition, federal or state
funds, private funds, and corporate funds.
10
Charles C. Verharen
11
12
Charles C. Verharen
13
14
Charles C. Verharen
Du Bois (1975) points out, universities are embedded in the cultures that
make their existence possible. Their primary mission should be usefulness
in solving the problems faced by those cultures.
Many African universities have an extraordinary advantage over
Western-style universities. Addis Ababa University, for example, is
embedded in around eighty cultures, if languages can be considered as a
primary instrument for cultural transmission. Cultures that have developed
their own rules for the direction of life, their own philosophies, can be
primary instruments for the stimulation of imagination that Rorty calls for
in announcing the passing of philosophys importance on the world-stage.
Addis Ababa University has the particular advantage of having access
to nearly two centuries of social science research on the Oromo cultures, the
home cultures of the majority of Ethiopias population. Of particular
interest are the ethical concepts of saffu, morality, and nagaa, peace or
harmony. These concepts serve as the foundation for the complex
democratic socio-political system comprised of the national assembly
(Gumi), the executive generational organization (Gadaa), and the electoral
institution (Qallu). Of particular interest to the University should be the
Oromo democratic separation of powers. Members of the electoral unit
cannot themselves hold office. Members of the executive unit cannot
themselves enact legislation, and they are subject to removal from office by
the national assembly (Lencho 2012).
Sage philosophy research on traditional African forms of democracy
may serve as stimuli for the reconceptualization of political structures
necessary for the unification of Africa to say nothing of the world.
Because of the cultural diversity of Africa, home to some 1500 languages,
African universities have an extraordinary advantage in offering ethical and
political models for global sustainability and social justice.
REFERENCES
Du Bois, W.E.B. 1975. The Education of Black People: Ten Critiques.
1006-1960. Ed. Herbert Aptheker. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Heidegger, Martin. 1977. Basic Writings. New York: Harper and Row.
Lencho, Taddese. 2012. The Spirit of Rousseau and Borana Political
Traditions: An Exercise in Understanding. In Gutema, B. and C.
Verharen (eds.) African Philosophy Now: African Philosophy in
Ethiopia. Addis Ababa: Addis Ababa University Philosophical
Studies.
May, Reinhard. 1996. Heideggers Hidden Sources: East-Asian Influences
on his Work. London: Routledge.
Rorty, Richard. 2009a. From Religion through Philosophy to Literature:
The
Way
Western
Intellectuals
Went.
http://www.crvp.org/book/Series04/IVA-30/chapter-6.htm, accessed
07/10/10.
15
______.
2009b.
Philosophy
as
a
Transitional
Genre.
http://mitpress.mit.edu/books/chapters/0262025671chap1.pdf,
accessed 07/10/10.
CHAPTER II
SOME THOUGHTS ON
THE AFRICAN UNIVERSITY
BEKELE GUTEMA
The Addis Ababa University celebrated its Golden Jubilee in 2000. The
University of Nairobi began in 1956 as part of the University of London;
Makerere began in 1949 under University College, London and the University
of Ibadan started in 1948 under the University of London. A more or less
similar pattern is to be observed with many of the Universities in the colonized
countries
18
Bekele Gutema
19
numerous addresses to university students in the 1950s and 60s stated that
instead of emulating the developed countries practices, students and
university graduates should concern themselves with problems confronting
Ethiopian society. He emphasized the role of education in improving
agriculture, exploiting mineral resources and the like. However, the only
university that the country had during the Emperors nearly half a century
rule carried out these tasks. Despite his rhetoric to the contrary, Haile
Selassie wanted his university to produce educated persons in line with
the Western model. His primary interest was in securing loyal, educated
subjects who were ready to use their acquired knowledge to consolidate and
legitimize the Emperors rule. To generalize, colonial administrators
established universities to shape their students in the service of colonialism.
Decolonizing minds was an objective remote from their intentions. Kom
summarises the purpose of education under the direct or indirect rule of
colonialism as follows:
For the colonizer, in fact, the colonized educated or not will
never be other than a subordinate, a subaltern, hardly prepared to
think by himself or to take initiatives of any importance without
the prior opinion of the master. University education simply
allows the latter to assign new tasks without allowing the
subaltern entire responsibility for directing his own destiny. The
local university simply allows for the training of mimics, puppet
men or women, since the power conceded to them must be
exercised in a dependent mode. Just as the colonial authority
defines the curriculum to be taught, it also exercises direct or
indirect control on the products put into operation by the
established system (2005:6).
The university definitely is something that every country needs and
Africa is no exception. What is different in the case of Africa is that
sufficient attempts have not been made to make this institution an African
institution. Its curricula, its functionaries including faculty and its sources
of funding reduced it to an institution that is there to serve the interests of
those who are responsible for its emergence.
Hountondji characterizes the African university as a highly extraverted
institution largely concerned with posing as an outpost of the metropolitan
universities. Its professors are ready to play a role subsidiary to the
professors in the North. It largely remained a foreign and an alien institution
that made little or no efforts to indigenize itself. It failed to be part of the
society in which it functions. The theories that it propagates are largely
foreign; the problems that it wants to solve are also largely not indigenous
problems. Research funders dictate the kinds of research to be undertaken at
African universities. Hence research projects amplify the interests of
funding agencies and countries in the end. African countries in the main
stand to benefit little or not in the case of donor-driven research.
20
Bekele Gutema
21
22
Bekele Gutema
23
24
Bekele Gutema
educational system were copied from either those of the West or of the then
Soviet Union and her satellites. Currently the forces of globalization and the
so called free market economy replace the communism/capitalism conflict.
The World Bank now leads the charge against a philosophy of higher
education that grounds the university in service of society.
The university must be an institution that spearheads the production
and dissemination of knowledge in all areas and fields. It should not be
restricted to focusing on producing immediately saleable skills. The
expansion of the horizon of knowledge in all fields and respects and
working particularly towards looking for ideas that are useful and key in
overcoming the problems of poverty must be the guiding principles of an
African university. Such universities are surrounded by poverty, ignorance
and the other attributes of so-called developing countries. Overcoming
these should be the cardinal aim of any African university.
Nyerere notes:
Thus our university, like all others worthy of the name, must
provide the facilities and the opportunities for the highest
intellectual inquiry. It must encourage and challenge its students
to develop their powers of constructive thinking. It must
encourage its academic staff to do original research and to play a
full part in promoting intelligent discussion of issues of human
concern. It must do all these things because they are part of being
a university; they are part of its reason of existing (Nyerere
quoted in Journal of Higher Education in Africa Vol. 4, No. 2,
2006: 54).
In conclusion we must bear in mind the kinds of assumptions under
which modern education began in many African countries. The Western
assumption that everything has to begin anew was an assault on everything
that was indigenous. It is through such an approach that the Africans were
uprooted and left only to mimic what the West considers universal. There is
no denying that formal education as it was started by the West did not exist.
However, it does not mean that Africans did not educate their children.
Indeed they educated their children in the different forms of knowledge
required to operate in the African environment. The young generations were
educated in skills that were necessary. They were also educated on the
values and morals of their own societies to become responsible citizens.
Julius O. Adekunle writes:
African education was collectively provided for the benefit of the
entire society. It was an education acquired for life in the
community through a continuous and consistent process and for
the continuity of the society. Education was both individual and
community-oriented. The patterns of a child and the community
25
26
Bekele Gutema
27
28
Bekele Gutema
CHAPTER III
30
Daniel Smith
31
specific issues that have emerged from such more abstract academic
exchanges, and then offer some tentative suggestions as to the general
direction or manner in which we might proceed.
During the course of interviewing potential students for our graduate
program a friend and colleague of mine prefaced a question concerning the
role of philosophy in Ethiopia with the phrase: Given the postmetaphysical
nature of contemporary philosophy ... (Departmental Proceedings,
Department of Philosophy, AAU, October, 2007). As a member of the
interviewing committee I found myself objecting, rather strenuously, that
this was an inappropriate and quite Eurocentric frame of reference within
which to force a potential student to respond to a question regarding the role
of philosophy in Ethiopia. My colleagues response to my criticism was that
the student was free to respond by challenging that frame of reference.
Upon further reflection it struck me that this was a perfect example of what
many have suggested is a major weakness of Jrgen Habermass use of the
ideal speech situation in developing his theory of communicative action
which is perhaps one of the most powerful attempts to reestablish a place
for a universally oriented discourse within contemporary philosophy, the
social sciences, and human knowledge in general (Habermas 1984/87).
Ideally, of course, my colleague, and still friend, was correct. The
student could have challenged the background consensus invoked
concerning contemporary philosophys postmetaphysical nature. Indeed
this would have been a paradigmatic example of a move from what
Habermas refers to as the normal level of communicative interaction to a
level in which the discursive vindication of validity claims becomes the
focus of the communicative exchange (Habermas 79: 63-64). However,
upon further reflection it struck me that this rather seemed like a good
example of where the admittedly counterfactual nature of the ideal
speech situation as universally acknowledged and the pragmatic value
orientation of communicative action becomes problematic. Somehow, the
extremely asymmetrical nature of the power relations, unavoidably
institutionalized in such proceedings, was deferred to the margins of the
interview process. Not only that, but the hegemony of what for many of us
are the existing Eurocentric regimes of truth was reinforced rather than
challenged as Foucault suggests they should be in the quotation invoked
above.
Of course such examples do not necessarily undermine Habermas
whole project, for surely no one is suggesting that the counterfactual
presuppositions of the ideal speech situation should ever be assumed to be
operant in any actual communicative interaction. However, in a collection
of essays entitled Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God, and
Morality, Habermas has argued that what he refers to as methodological
atheism is a necessary condition for the development of a discourse ethics
that would retain a rational claim to universal consent, and that a
philosophy that oversteps the bounds of methodological atheism loses its
philosophical seriousness (Habermas 2002: 160). Eduardo Mendieta, as
32
Daniel Smith
33
SECTION II
PHILOSOPHY AND CULTURE
CHAPTER IV
38
Messay Kebede
recent episodes in this long crusade to deprive the black race of its rightful
place. Everything appears as though the Marxist notion of the class struggle
could be extended to include the phase of the racial confrontation resulting
in the reduction of a creative race to servitude. In addition to being
immersed in the controversial thesis of black Egypt, Diops view sanctions
the idea of human races with all the drawbacks that the notion entails.
Is there a way to maintain the West as a culprit while avoiding the
racialization of the conflict between oppressors and oppressed? Such a
thesis would emphasize that Africa and Europe were at a comparable
traditional stage until the breakthrough of European modernity accelerated
the gap. Europe used this advance caused by circumstances to block the
progress of Africa by the hemorrhage of slavery and the imposition of
colonial rule. Franz Fanons theory of a polarized and terminal conflict
between the wretched of the earth and colonizers fully approves an
approach blaming the West for Africas underdevelopment. Similarly,
Kwasi Wiredus concept of comparable traditionality between the West and
Africa can be interpreted as supporting the idea of Western culpability.
Maurice Delafosse remains the incontestable precursor of the view
blaming Europe for Africas social and technological retardation. To dispel
the belief that the black race is intellectually inferior, Delafosse argues that
a historical review of the African continent clearly shows that many African
societies had attained a level of civilization comparable to the stage reached
by European countries during the time of Charlemagne. The rise of West
African empires, such as the Ghanaian, the Songhai, the Mandingo and the
Mossi empires, with their high degree of state organization and their centers
of religious, philosophic, and scientific studies, the most famous being
Timbuktu and Gao, gives evidence of the advances accomplished by the
African medieval age. The question that comes to mind is why the
advancement was not pursued.
Delafosses answer considers two interrelated matters. (1) He asks us
to appreciate that whatever Africans have accomplished, they have done so
without outside help. While other peoples were able to advance thanks to
contacts with and borrowings from other civilizations, Africans present the
unique case of complete isolation imposed by the formidable barrier of the
Sahara. To quote Delafosse:
... the negroes of Africa, isolated from the Mediterranean lake
which during millenniums, has been the only vehicle of world
civilization, were not able, in the absence of the emulation
created by constant contacts with the outside world, to progress
in a way that was possible, for example, in the case of the Gauls
under the influence of Roman civilization (1968: 279).
(2) He underlines the sad and unfortunate fact that, when technological
progress finally overcame the natural obstacle and ended the African
isolation, the purpose of the people who landed on the shores of Africa was
39
first to tear away, anew, thousands of slaves, then, to inundate them with
alcohol, and finally, without preparation, to thrust the civilization of the
nineteenth century in
the midst of other civilizations which had
remained contemporaries with Charlemagne (Ibid).
No lengthy demonstration is necessary to admit that the Western
predilection for slaves and colonies turned out to be utterly degrading for
Africans. Those African scholars, Marxists or otherwise, who attribute
African underdevelopment to Western domination and exploitation support
the thesis of the culpability of the West. Their approach agrees with the
analyses of the neo-Marxist school known as the dependency school. For
Andre Gunder Frank, the main thinker of the dependency school,
traditionality or backwardness simply means non development, whereas
underdevelopment is the product of the satellization of third world countries
(Frank 1969: 94). As a mechanism of surplus appropriation, satellization
ensures the enrichment of centers at the expense of peripheries. Implicit in
this analysis is the abstention of the dependency school from sanctioning
the idea of difference. Nor does it put the blame for African retardation on
the African past. This exculpation of the past avoids the endorsement of the
prelogicality of precolonial Africa.
Notwithstanding the promise of positive gains, the rejection of African
difference passes over the distinction between tradition and modernity.
Worse, the approach supports the Hegelian notion of unilinear history. It
simply substitutes the idea of peoples reduced to underdevelopment for the
notion of retarded peoples. Some such substitution does not challenge the
Hegelian scheme: underdevelopment is a confiscated, suppressed
modernity, not a state of affairs prompted more by cultural divergences than
by impediments or primitiveness. Not only does this conception of
underdevelopment completely underrate the crucial role of change in the
generation of modernity, but also endorses the universality of modernist
ventures.
The same oversight weighs down Delafosses approach. The thesis
concedes that Africans were on the same track as the West until isolation
prevented them from performing as well as Westerners. Compelled to
invent everything by themselves, they have lost much time, and so lag
behind. The understanding of the African situation in terms of lag definitely
intimates that Africans would have reached a level of development similar
to the West were they not hampered by environmental obstacles and, most
of all, by European conquest and colonization. Delafosse sees Western
civilization, not as a product of specific choices emanating a no less specific
historical orientation, but as a natural target of human beings wherever they
are. So he speaks of lag instead of difference.
This universalist approach prevents the perception of the real meaning
of modernity. It does not allow the radical understanding of the Western
venture, the singularity of its inspiration, and the formidable challenge that
the venture poses to non-Western cultures. The comprehension of Western
scientific and technological ventures as natural products of growth that
40
Messay Kebede
other cultures would produce were they not dominated glosses over the
painful choices and sacrifices implied in change as well as over the original
disparity of cultural orientations.
To become aware of the need to change is to reconnect with ones
specificity so as to map out a new direction in which a recovered centrality
inspires borrowings from and dealings with the West. The power to change
too is dependent on the reconnection with specificity, since historicity
without which no sense of mission arises feeds on continuity. This
backward journey into the past is how the new and the past fuse into a new
synthesis. But then, the best way to get out of the African dilemma is
neither to assert nor to deny the African difference; it is not to look for an
uncontaminated vision of the past essence either. The recognition of the
concomitance of myth and rationality, of traditionality and modernity, is the
appropriate way to defuse the African dilemma. No better refutation of the
colonial discourse is to be found than in the exposure of complementarity in
the alleged contrast between myth and reason.
The position that myth and rationality are concomitant makes room for
African difference without succumbing to otherness. It posits an original
orientation by which a culture makes sense of life and assigns a specific
task to rationality. The assignment suggests that the way rationality is used
can vary from one culture to another. In this regard, Placide Tempels
approach is exemplary: he argues that the way the mind of the Bantu
functions is different because rationality is harnessed to a different purpose,
not because it lacks rationality. To redirect rationality toward science and
technology, the correct path is less to initiate discontinuity through the
relegation of the past to prelogicality than to reformulate the inspiring
myths of the culture in accordance with present needs. The reformulation is
the recovery of historicity, which transcends the conflict between otherness
and sameness by the very act of making tradition pregnant with modernity.
Let us insist on the ability of historicity to succeed where universalist
and relativist definitions of Africa fail. The universalist option necessarily
brings back evolutionary concepts; the strategy of otherness takes
rationality away from Africa, while the relativization of commitment dilutes
the particularism of deconstruction. The different approach of historicity
starts by stating that what is wrong with negritude is not so much the claim
to difference as the ascription of the difference to racial attributes. If instead
of drawing the difference from racial, natural characteristics, negritude had
attributed it to an act of choice, it would have moved in the direction of
historicity. The intervention of choice invalidates the debate over the racial
reality or non-reality of the black essence. What is accomplished as a result
of choice refers to freedom, and so excludes objective determinism. The
accomplishment, however specific, does not bar other human potentials; it
simply springs from different utilizations of universal human aptitudes as a
result of divergent historical choices.
If depending on the initial value orientation or choice of a given
culture, rationality can assume different forms, the opposition that negritude
41
reads between the African and the European approaches to nature loses its
demeaning connotation. Choice avoids excluding the rationality of
Africans. By removing the social barrier, it also warrants the possibility of
changing lanes, of passing from one conception to another through an act of
choice. Most importantly, choice moves away from the evolutionary
approach: if differences are accountable to choice rather than to
backwardness or natural characteristics, the relativity of civilizations
becomes unavoidable. Choice is always relative in that the selection of
some goals entails the suppression or the giving up of other equally valid
goals. The Western option to become master and possessor of nature is
paid by the loss of other ways of relating with nature. This drawback
revalues the African legacy by construing non-technicalness as a pursuit of
a different purpose with its positive and negative sides.
The rehabilitating reading confirms that the way out of the African
dilemma is the divergent conception of evolution. Contrary to the
universalist and stage-producing-stage conception of evolution, divergence
implicates splits within the same unity such that the process, in the words of
Henri Bergson, splaying out like a sheaf, sunders, in proportion to their
simultaneous growth, terms which at first completed each other so well that
they coalesced (Bergson 1944: 130). This dissociation of the original unity
achieves particular outcomes, which are complementary rather than
hierarchical. The one outcome does not represent a higher stage, but a
divergent course with positive and negative attributes. In light of the
complementarity of the divergent courses, the human target should be less
the frenzied pursuit of one direction which is what Westernization is
forcibly accomplishing than the attempt to achieve a harmonious
development of human potentials by integrating the positive characters of
the divergent courses.
The relativization of the West, not its normativeness, opens the
African path to modernity. When the West is presented as the norm,
Africans are reduced to imitators, or to speak a more familiar language, to
dependency. When the West turns relative through a divergent conception,
it becomes an object of assessment, better still, of free choice. With the
intervention of choice, the instruction to copy the West gives way to
utilitarian questions: what can Africans learn from the West? What must
they reject? How can they integrate their borrowings into their continuity?
The identification with a rehabilitated past provides the detachment that
allows the deployment of such questions. Developing this type of pragmatic
relation with the West means the prior decolonization of the African mind,
which is neither more nor less than the recovery of freedom. The questions
are the very ones that Africans would have raised were they not colonized.
The normativeness of the West has far-reaching detrimental
implications. As imitators rather than creators, Africans become totally
dependent, and lose their ability to think and act in a steadfast, systematic,
and creative manner. A copy never reaches the perfection of the model, and
the copyist has less passion and commitment to execute the project. Since
42
Messay Kebede
imitators already accept their inferiority and do not strive to deliver their
own making, they fall short of being passionate and resolute about their
understanding. What they do is always very second-rate; it may even be
deliberately messed up out of the naughtiness that comes along when
grownups and old cultures stoop to the status of children undergoing a
process of domestication under Western tutorship.
No sooner do Africans decide to become imitators than they expose
themselves to faulty executions of the model. Since imitation is admission
of inferiority, the act by which copyists revere the model is the very act by
which they suppress their capacity, thereby putting themselves in the
position of committing mistakes. No other way exists to acquire the
requirements and the virtues of the model than to deviate by avoiding
repetition. You equal the model when you become creative or original, and
not when you imitate.
The essence of progress as defined correctly by Edward W. Blyden,
is the attainment of difference (Blyden 1967:76). All that is not unique,
original, is deficient because it owes its existence to a reduced ability.
When creativity takes the lead, the model loses its normative stand and
becomes an inspiration. The great difference between inspiration and
imitation is that imitation makes a person passive, subordinate; it is
lowering and debilitating. Not so with inspiration, which is an appeal to rise
to the same standard, if not to go higher. Inspiration is stimulating and
emboldening while imitation inculcates self-lowering and dependency.
This analysis sheds some light on the mystery of Africas apparent
inability to go forward. Though African societies adopt Western institutions
and values, none of these borrowings seem to function properly. One way
of explaining this stagnation is to suggest that imitation commits Africans
to failure. Externally, African societies appear to be doing all that is
necessary to modernize, but they do it as learners, apprentices who commit
mistakes. Unfortunately, these mistakes soon turn into internal blockages
that stand in the way of advancement. Just as undigested meal hampers our
body, so too the faulty imitation of the West leads to drawbacks that impede
the progress of modernization. Take the case of the state. On the
assumption that a strong and centralized state is necessary to implement
modernization, the conditions of dictatorship are put in place, which
conditions conflict with other admitted goals, such as democratization, and
prove tougher to remove later.
When the path of dependency is discarded, the attainment of selfreliance emerges as the sine qua non of modernization. According to the
basic belief of the modernization school, modernization occurs when
traditional values, beliefs, and ways of doing things give way to innovative
views and methods. In the words of Bert Hoselitz, in order to have
economic advancement, the practice of assigning economic role by
ascription, or according to status, must be replaced by the standard of
achievement (Hoselitz 1960: 19). The resurgence of innovative ability has
its prime condition in the practice of self-reliance.
43
44
Messay Kebede
the weak, so too the wretchedness of Africans is out to create a new sense
of the human person.
That this creative power exists is easily established if we pay attention
to the impossibility of reducing the mythical faculty to mere imagination.
Closely following the arguments of Bergson, I endorse the autonomous
existence of the myth-making function together with the empowering
purpose of the function, the understanding being that excessive valorization
of rationality results in the complete asphyxia of the power of the mind. The
basic error is to define myth in terms of knowledge, be it as false
knowledge or as construction. While ethnophilosophers change myth into a
different type of knowledge, that is, into a discrete epistemological
orientation, their opponents argue for the distinction between mythical
thinking and rational knowledge, and advocate the eradication of the
former. For V. Y. Mudimbe too, to the extent that myth is a construction of
the world, mythical thinking fulfills the function of knowledge, even if he
denies the objectivity of such knowledge.
Of all the theories exposing the involvement of ideological biases in
an epistemological orientation claiming to be objective, Marxism provides
clear-cut means to denounce the operations of false consciousness without
thereby espousing relativism. Provided that certain principles, such as,
materialism, scientific attitude, class position, are put to use, Karl Marx
believes in the possibility of discriminating between objective knowledge
and partisan or biased approaches. These principles guarantee that
we do not set out from what men say, imagine, conceive, nor
from men as narrated, thought of, imagined, conceived, in order
to arrive at men in the flesh. We set out from real, active men,
and on the basis of their real life-process we demonstrate the
development of the ideological reflexes and echoes of this lifeprocess (K. Marx and F. Engels 1965: 14).
Unlike Marx, Mudimbe has no provision for universalizing instances.
By reducing indiscriminately everything to construction, he deprives
himself of the opportunity of differentiating between ideology and objective
conceptions. His emancipated view of Africa is thus condemned to be an
invention confronting another invention. My argument does not criticize the
idea of invention; it simply points out that relativism clashes with
Mudimbes search for authentic Africa.
As for Marx, his attempt to shun ideological thinking altogether
betrays an objectivist commitment that treats mythical thinking as false
knowledge. His approach is totally deaf to the suggestion that the
involvement of invention does not necessarily entail the impossibility of
objective knowledge. If the role of myth is less to deform or conceal reality
than to provide galvanizing representations, the assumption that myth
complements reason becomes a legitimate statement. Instead of usurping
the role of reason, the function of mythical representations is to enclose
45
46
Messay Kebede
47
48
Messay Kebede
49
50
Messay Kebede
51
52
Messay Kebede
CHAPTER V
INTRODUCTION
Numbers play an important role in the day-to-day life of people in
almost all cultures of the world. But we know very little about the meaning
and use of numbers in local cultures. There remain too few detailed
accounts on the application of numbers in the context of culture study. Even
anthropologists, for whom every aspect of a culture is a gist for the mill,
seem to have disregarded the study of numbers. Reflecting on this fact,
Crump writes,
In anthropology, a faculty library will contain any number of
books applying the methods and insights of the discipline to
almost any category of human thought or behavior. At the same
time, the standard monograph, investigating in detail the daily
life of the population up on which it is based, may range equally
widely in the choice of the topics dealt with. To all this there is,
however, one exception: the use and understanding of numbers.
This subject, if not completely disregarded, is treated as no more
than marginal, even in cases where numerical factors dominate
the day-to-day life of the people being studied. (1990: vii)
It is, therefore, difficult to test effectively what purports to be a general
explanation of numbers. The study of numeration systems, symbolic
meanings of numbers, mystical beliefs and taboos about numbers, and
games having numerical contents are vast and virgin fields awaiting
investigation (Zaslavsky 1973). My objective is to deal with only one
aspect of numbers, that is, the application of the number nine in GujiOromo culture not as a counting number but as a number that has special
significance. In other words, I concentrate on the number nine entirely from
the point of view of its application, and not its being an abstract concept.
In Guji-Oromo culture, the number nine is associated with a critical
time, with a ghost, and with illness and death. This is clearly evident in
Guji-Oromo proverbs, in childrens games, and in the pregnancy and birth
of a ninth child. In this study, after providing an overview about GujiOromo, I will introduce what I may call riddles associated with the
number nine in their culture. I will then inquire why nine, among all other
numbers, is considered a special number. Finally, an attempt will be made
54
Taddese Beriso
55
activities and social roles are formally defined, both in terms of what is
permitted and what is forbidden. The ideal length of time in one rank is
eight years. In the past, the Gadaa system assumed military, economic,
legal and arbitrational responsibilities. In recent years, however, the
function of the Gadaa system in Guji has been reduced to ritual activities.
The Guji have a mixed economy of animal husbandry and crop
cultivation in a fertile land that stretches over a wide variety of altitudes.
They subsist mainly by growing grains such as barley, corn, and teff
(eragrostis ef), pulses and enset (musa ensete). But their real wealth
consists of cattle, sheep, goats, and horses. Emotions and pride are centered
in stock. People who do not own cattle are not considered to be proper Guji.
(Baxter 1991: 9). Cattle are important, not only for economic purposes, but
also for social and ritual life. The social status of a person among the Guji
finds its expression in the number of cattle owned. The owner of many
heads of cattle is a respected person. Cattle are ritually used for sacrificial
purposes.
With regard to religion, the Guji have developed a very complex set of
beliefs and practices. They believe in Waaqa heaven and in the existence
of durissa devil. They have Woyyu sacred shrines under which prayers
and sacrifices are made to Waaqa. They also believe in ritual power vested
on certain individuals and families, The Qaalluu supreme religious leader
and Abbaa Gadaa, who are respectively, considered as woyyu holy and
Warra Qallaca virile family, are among these individuals. Attached to
these are rituals and religious practices, such as oracle, sprit possession,
complex and varied divinations, and other traditional beliefs. But with the
introduction of the great religious and modern civilization, Guji traditional
beliefs are changing fast. There has been a mass conversion of Guji farmers
into Christianity (Protestantism in particular) and Islam specially, after the
1974 Ethiopian Socialist Revolution (Taddesse 1995).
The Guji consider their homeland to be the very ancestral cradle of the
Oromo culture. Indeed many scholars have now, on the bases of historical
linguistics, oral traditions and cultural data, concluded that the Oromo
originated in and around the areas currently inhabited by the Guji, Borana
and Arsi Oromo (Haberland 1963; Lewis 1966; Asmarom 1973). From
these areas, the Oromo launched their vast expansion in the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries on the basis of the Gadaa organization. It is only the
Borana and Guji who have kept alive the Gadaa system and the associated
ceremonies, with their relatively original features. In general, the traditional
order still functions, making the Guji-Borana area the spiritual and cultural
center of the Oromo .The riddles associated with number nine are other
cultural traditions retained in this area by the Guji-Oromo.
RIDDLES ASSOCIATED WITH THE NUMBER NINE
In Guji-Oromo culture, as in many cultures, there are taboos and
mystical belief about numbers. There are also numbers that have symbolic
56
Taddese Beriso
significance. For instance, there is a belief among the Guji-Oromo that the
counting of human beings and domestic animals will lead to their
destruction. To circumvent the taboo, they identify their livestock
individually by name. What was observed by (Asmarom 1973: 281) about
the Borana-Oromo is equally true for the Guji. According to him, each
animal is a unique creature with a different color, shape, pedigree, name,
and life history. Cattle are to the herdsman as books are to the academic.
The herdsman recalls not only how he acquired the animal, but often the
specific and emotionally tinged circumstances of acquisition.
For human beings too, counting is done indirectly. For example,
instead of saying I have eight children (from a wife) one may say, After
one more child I will celebrate sallii-falla. a ceremony held for the
pregnancy and birth of a ninth child (see below). The indirect counting of
human beings may have created confusion to official enumerators, and
contributed to the underestimation of the Guji population during census
counts. Besides this, there is a tradition of dual grouping of clans into
masculine four and feminine three; number four being a symbol for the
masculine principle, and three for the feminine principle (Haberland: 1963:
775).
Moreover, there are numbers that are associated with mystical belief
and the world-view of the Guji-Oromo. These include the number nine
itself (to be discussed later) and kumaa one thousand. Kumaa is generally
used in Guji to symbolize the highest number even though their counting
system extends far beyond this figure. Traditionally if two hundred heifers
gave birth to calves in two consecutive years, that is one hundred calves
each year, the owner would have the right of holding a kumaa gatee
discarding the 1000th ceremony. During this ceremony one of these heifers
would firmly be tied and taken to a forest where it would be left as an
offering to wild beasts. This was symbolically an indication that the man
had reached the ultimate level of herd development, for which he would be
widely known. The ceremony also indicates the desire of the Guji to keep a
large number of cattle. Besides this, it was a Guji tradition to require a
thousand heads of cattle for gumaa compensation for homicide although
the actual amount may not have exceeded one hundred.
There are also a number of dichotomies in Guji-Oromo culture, such
as even and odd numbers, right and left, male and female and up and down.
The former in each pair is associated with auspicious phenomena or events,
while the latter is associated with inauspicious phenomena. As a whole, all
odd numbers are bad, and things associated with them are considered
undesirable. To remove or control inauspicious events associated with
them, a Guji may engage in prayers and make sacrifices or he may postpone
the desired activity. And there are no riddles associated with these
dichotomies as such.
But there are instances, in Guji-Oromo culture, in which odd numbers
like nine are singled out and associated with different kinds of inauspicious
57
phenomena. The first riddle about number nine is one that associates it with
a critical time or moment. This is evident in the proverb,
Gaalie Sagali bulle
Kudhan bullu hindadhabu
The Guji share this proverb with the Borana-Oromo and most
probably with other pastoralists, such as the Garri and the Somali. In the
proverb, the number nine (or the ninth day) is considered as the most
critical time, which could bring about misfortune or death to the individual
or family concerned. Symbolically, it represents a time between life and
death. The proverb also indicates, ironically, the importance of patience and
the need for delaying present gratification for future satisfaction. In both
cases nine represents a critical moment that one has to pass through if one is
to be successful in life. A camel that has survived nine days (without
water?) is very strong!
The following is another Guji proverb that associates number nine
with a critical time or moment.
Haluun dhirra wagaaa sagalti bati.
What is one?
One is a finger/ a ring.
What is two?
Two are the teats of a goat and
one is a finger
58
Taddese Beriso
Sadi mali?
Sadi sunsuma aayya,
lama mucha ree, tokko kubba
what is three?
Three are Mums hearth stones;
two are teats of a goat, and one
is a finger
In this way, children are tested as to how fast and accurately they can
count all the numbers from one to ten, and all multiples of ten to one
hundred. All the numbers included in the game and the things associated
with each are recorded in Oromo as follows:
Tokko-kubba/kubbele
Lamma mucha ree
Saddi sunsuma aayya
Afur mucha sayya
Shan kubba harkka
Jahaa jabbii karaxaa
Torbaa bussa waka
Saddeet dhalla saree
Sagli lakkossa ekerra
Kudhan kuttata dula
Digdama bolla sadeqqa
Soddoma qabbido Soddaa
Afurtama kurnya afurii
Shantama wolaka dhibba
Jaattama kurna jahaa
Torbatama kurnyatorba
Saddetama dame kilxxuu
Sagalitama kurrya sagalii
Dhibba ganka lakkobisa
The counting game enables the children to learn a lot about their
culture and things in their environment by association. Such a game is
important in developing the childrens ability to speak and to sharpen their
mental capacity. The game also has educational value in passing tradition
from generation to generation. In general, it is one of the most efficient and
effective ways of teaching children in places where writing is not yet
developed.
In this game, it is interesting to note that the number nine is associated
with ghosts. The Guji do not believe in life after death, and, therefore, do
not worship ancestors. They do however, believe in the existence of ekerra,
a soul of dead person wandering in wilderness for a short period of time.
59
60
Taddese Beriso
61
62
Taddese Beriso
It was in relation to this view, that (Legesse 1973: 180) responded with the
polemical statement ,If the ethnographer fails to understand a particular
system of thought, he accuses his informants of magical thought, or of
pre-logical childlike mental operations, rather than admitting that his data
are inadequate and his understanding limited. From this, it is clear that
when some scholars fail to understand certain systems of thought of preindustrial societies, they blame their subjects either for having a pre-logical
thought or for borrowing them from the civilized West. This is an
ethnocentric approach which helps us neither to understand the cultures of
others nor to explain why people behave the way they do.
Marvin Harris (1974), a prominent American anthropologist, offers
solutions to a number of perplexing questions of why people behave the
way they do. He raised a number of riddles such as: Why do Hindus
worship cows? Why do Jews and Moslems refuse to eat pork? Why did so
many people in post-medieval Europe believe in witches? And why have
witches managed to stage such a successful comeback in todays popular
culture? Harris supplies some seemingly sensible, down-to-earth
explanations to these questions. He clearly demonstrates that no matter how
bizarre a peoples behavior may seem, it always stems from identifiable and
intelligible causes.
To explain different patterns of culture, he employed a cultural
materialism approach which is based on the premise that,
Human life is not merely random or capricious. Without this
assumption, the temptation to give up when confronted with a
stubbornly inscrutable custom or institution soon proves
irresistible. Over the years I have discovered that life styles
which others claimed were totally inscrutable actually had
definite and readily intelligible causes. The main reason why
these causes have been so long overlooked is that everyone is
convinced that only God knows the answer (Harris 1974: 2)
Harris argues that human behavior could be understood and
objectively explained no matter how irrational or bizarre it may seem at
first glance. But, he attempted to explain most culture forms and practices
from the point of view of practical utility or from a rationalist-materialist
point of view. He like those who adopt this theoretical position argues that
customs or institutions are not simply random practices, but are responses
to genuine needs in the life of a society. This is most frequently expressed
with statements that allude to cultural practices functions, or,
alternatively, as a part of a societys adaptation to environmental
circumstances (Barrett 1991: 78). Consequently, the task of interpreting a
custom involves searching for the function the practice serves within the
society or deciphering the role it plays in adjusting the society to its
environment.
63
64
Taddese Beriso
that nine is associated with a critical moment; and believed to bring about
misfortune, danger and death. Hence it is disliked. But at the same time,
nine is a marker of honor in Guji culture. It qualifies a family to hold a
major ritual and to attend, as a guest of honor, the sallii falla rituals of
others in their community, as mentioned earlier. My Borana friend also
informed me that when the Borana talk about tula saglan (sagali) the nine
wells of the Borana, they are talking about the deepest and the most
permanent wells that serve them throughout the dry seasons. The tula
saglan are not only economically significant but are also associated with a
special power, indicating the importance, or positive aspects, of the number
nine. Besides this, nine has a positive sense when a Borana says, saglan
Borana sagaltama garbba nine Borana to ninety slaves.
The interpretation of the riddles associated with the number nine thus
calls for an in-depth analysis of the traditional Oromo concept of numbers,
and analysis of the patterns and relations in their culture. By assuming a
broader perspective than that of any of the participants and by discovering
how one institution fits another, anthropologists are able to perceive
connections and meanings that are not obvious to the members of a society
(Barrett 1991: 138-139).
To understand the Oromo concept of numbers in general, and to
interpret the riddles associated with number nine among the Guji Oromo in
particular, it is important to examine the underlying principle of the entire
traditional counting system of the Oromo on which there is hardly any
extensive study. Gemetchus (1993) attempt to analyze the meaning and
role of numbers in Oromo thought and culture is a pioneering work.
According to him and my Guji informants, in the traditional Oromo
counting system, there are only nine true counting numbers, lakkobssa
dhugga. These are the digital numbers one to nine. All the other numbers
are said to be a reproduction of this series and can be repeated infinitively.
This repetition is called mara, round, or return, and represents the zero
concept.
Kassam explained this cycle and its significance in Oromo culture as
follows:
there are therefore eight steps involved. Before another cycle
can begin, there is an intermediary, transition period, a sort of
void. This gap, which is empty but at the same time full, is
represented by number nine, standing for the zero concept. It
makes a critical turning point, in which the new cycle arises out
of the ashes of the old. These cycles vary
in complexity and
danger, but at each turn in the wheel of time, a certain amount of
evil overspills and is accumulated in the entire system, such that,
at certain point, in order for regeneration to take place, something
has to be cut off or sacrificed and disappear from the original
structure(1994: 36).
65
66
Taddese Beriso
the pollution they have entered into with the pregnancy of a ninth child,
whose birth is considered to be dangerous for the family and society at
large. The sacrifice of dulaca, an old cow, and malxuu are, therefore, held
as ritual means of averting dangers of the interstructural situation.
Inauspicious things are sometimes ritually transferred to animals that are
then slaughtered to create consistence out of inconsistency.
CONCLUSION
The importance of a theoretical approach in understanding a given
culture or practice is made clear in the discussion. Two theoretical
approaches are reflected in this study. One is ethnocentric and supremacist,
rooted in the theory of evolution/diffusion which assumes that preindustrial societies are primitive, simple and have pre-logical and
childlike mentality. Their thoughts and institutions are assumed to present
no challenge to the logical minds of Western scholars. If complex
institutions, such as the Oromo Gadda, are discovered in primitive
societies, it is understood that they are borrowed from civilized culture.
This theoretical approach, as represented, for example, in Haberland (1963)
is not only reductionist, but also unproductive, and inadequate in the face of
the staggeringly rich and complex human knowledge and experience.
The other theoretical approach is consistent with the development of
scientific tools that can help us minimize ethnocentric bias. Both
functionalist/ecological and symbolic/interpretive approaches come under
this category. The extent to which each of these approaches adequately
explains a certain issue depends on the issue itself, on the kind of
information obtained, and on socio-political interests, among others.
I cannot claim that I have found a completely satisfactory solution to
the riddles of the number nine. But I believe that the riddles cannot be
adequately comprehended by means of evolutionary or adaptation theories.
The interpretation of the riddles requires a good understanding of the
patterns and relations of the Guji culture, the traditional meanings, the use
of numbers in the Guji world view, and the latent underlying, form of
their custom/practice. The latent is that which is neither apparent on the
surface of things, nor a part of a conscious awareness of the members of the
society (Evans-Pritchard, 1962; 52; Barrett, 1991:42). In such a situation,
an interpretive/symbolic approach seems to provide a setting for a better
understanding of the riddles.
NOTES
1
67
hearth. They then twist their fingers and toes in turn to make a K sound
that would be carefully counted to determine the winning side.
4
In this game a person tries to make a member of a household laugh
using any means, while the other person desists from laughing.
5
This seems simply to indicate how big a kilxxuu tree is in terms of the
number of its branches.
6
See Bartels (1969) for a similar view among the Macha-Oromo.
7
The garayyu relationship in Guji is highly institutionalized and goes
far beyond a sexual liaison. A child born of this relationship belongs to the
legal spouse. The relationship thus helps to overcome problems arising
from male infertility.
8
Haririti is making a supplication while placing hands or ritual sticks
on the back of a sacrificial animal.
9
Since similar attitudes to number nine are found in Guji, Borana and
Konso, it is interesting to know how far this cultural value is found among
other Cushitic or other neighboring groups.
10
Asmarom (1973), Tessema (1986), and others have clearly
demonstrated that Gadaa is definitely an Oromo institution.
REFERENCES
Legesse, Asmarom. 1973. Gada: There Approaches to the Study of African
Society. New York: The Free Press.
Barrett, R. 1991. Culture and Conduct: An Excursion in Anthropology.
Second Edition. Belmont, Ca: Wadsworth Publishing.
Bartels, L. 1969.Birth Songs of the Macha Galla. In Ethnology 8 (4): 406422.
Baxter, P.T.W. 1991. Preface. In Joseph Van De Loo, Guji Oromo
Culture in Southern Ethiopia: Religious Capabilities in Rituals and
Songs. Berlin, pp .9-13
Crump, Thomas. 1990. The Anthropology of Numbers. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Evans-Pritchard, E.E. 1951. Kinship and Marriage among the Nuer.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
______.1962. Essays in Social Anthropology. New York: The Free Press.
Gemetchu Megerssa. 1993. Identity, Knowledge and the Colonizing
Structure. Unpublished Ph. D. Dissertation, University of London,
School of Oriental and African Studies.
Gennep, A. Van. 1960. The Rites of Passage. London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Haberland, E. 1963. Galla sud-Ethiopiens. Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer
Verlag.
Hallpike, C.R. 1972. The Konso of Ethiopia: A Study of the Values of a
Cushitic People. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harris, Marvin. 1974. Cows, Pigs, Wars and Witches: The Riddles of
Culture. New York: Vintage Books.
68
Taddese Beriso
CHAPTER VI
70
Charles C. Verharen
71
Both break down their topics into small parts and both rely on the light of
reason to guide their investigations. Both use reason to establish the
existence of God. Zara Yaqob goes so far as to claim that reason alone can
give us access to God scriptures including the Bible and Koran contain
much that is false in the light of reason. What is natural is what God
prescribes eating, procreation, monogamy, freedom, love. What is
unnatural is prescribed by man and propagated through scripture fasting,
abstention from sex, polygamy, slavery, hatred. All men, says Zara
Yaqob, are liars, and men write scriptures (Zara Yaqob in Sumner,
1976:13).
According to Claude Sumner, the discoverer of the Hatata, Zara
Yaqob goes so far as to excise key elements of Christian scripture through
his hatata the Holy Trinity, Jesus Christ, Incarnation, Redemption or
Resurrection, the Mother of Christ, the Church, liturgy or sacraments
(Sumner quoted in Messay, 1988:120). Zara Yaqob exemplifies a
philosophy of religion so corrosive that it matches 19th century European
and American deism like that of Thomas Jefferson.
Astoundingly, Messay claims that Zara Yaqob is not a philosopher.
With Sumner, Messay admires Zara Yaqob as an architect of unity
(Sumner quoted in Messay ibid.:78). He viewed all religions as
worshipping the same God. Like Descartes, he employs a method of doubt
that is resolved only through the light of reason. But unlike Descartes, Zara
Yaqob doubts in order to establish the authentic religion that brings
peace and love among men (Messay 1988: 84).
Messays dogmatism on his rejection of Zara Yaqob as a philosopher
is curious. Zara Yaqobs philosophy of religion is unique in the Ethiopia
of his time, to say nothing of the wider world. His originality has
precipitated Italian claims that the Hatata must have been written by an
Italian missionary because it is so uncharacteristic of conventional
Ethiopian thought of the 17th century (Sumner 1976: 61-275).
Messays claim follows from his definition of philosophy. The whole
point of Western philosophy, and most probably the essence of philosophy
in general is to explain and establish the possibility of scientific
knowledge (Messay, 1988:85). Messay does not single out Zara Yaqob
for exclusion. Banished from philosophy with him are Pascal and
Kierkegaard who refused to confront faith with science, who insisted that
religious belief is outside the purview of science (ibid.:86). Unlike these
philosophers, however, Zara Yaqob was not even aware of the existence
of a scientific knowledge (ibid.). Writing in 1988, Messay does not
address the claims of Paul Feyerabend (1975) and Thomas Kuhn (1970)
that science itself is grounded in faith the faith, for example, that science
is worth pursuing, that technology associated with science will not destroy
life on earth, and that one research program is more worth pursuing than
another.
The key to Messays rejection of Zara Yaqob as a philosopher lies in
his explanation as to why Zara Yaqob could not have developed a
72
Charles C. Verharen
73
tell a story determines the degree to which a nation controls its destiny
(ibid.:146).
Messays research in his Africas Quest for a Philosophy of
Decolonization is a search for a grounding myth, an ur-myth that will allow
the whole African continent to control its destiny. As we shall see in the
essays third section, Messay paints Leopold Senghors Negritude and
Cheikh Anta Diops Afrocentrism as myth-making efforts that must fail by
reason of their racializing characteristics. The African struggle against the
effects of colonization is difficult, in part because of the European
imposition of a cult of rationality on Africans. This cult, itself a myth,
imposed science as a standard of rationality and thereby robbed Africans of
their power to believe (ibid.:219). Senghor hoped to restore that power by
disparaging European rationality. Diops restoration claimed that black
Africa gave birth to European rationality.
Messay opposes myth to rationality. I have not found an explicit
definition of rationality in his research, but it is clear that the model of
rationality is science as a synthesis of experience and reasoning. Myth and
science live together in the modern world but they clash with one another.
Messay quotes Bergson: experience may indeed say that is false, and
reasoning [may say] that is absurd. Humanity only clings all the more to
that absurdity and that error (ibid.:213). Nevertheless, myth and rationality
cannot live without each other. Messay claims that rationality always
teams up with myth and that mythical thinking is coextensive with
rationality (ibid.:151). Nevertheless the two forces must achieve a delicate
balance: excessive valorization of rationality results in the complete
asphyxiation of the power of the mind. The myth-making function must
retain its autonomy to achieve its empowering purpose (ibid.: 212). What
I question is Messays separation of myth from rationality. In the next
section I propose a holistic definition of rationality that includes both
functions.
A CRITIQUE OF MESSAYS SEPARATION OF MYTH AND
RATIONALITY
Messays error is to separate myth and rationality. He goes so far as to
say that myth is not knowledge (ibid.:213). He invokes Kwasi Wiredus
support in claiming that even in the contemporary world, mythical
representations resist the impact of rationality (ibid.). Rather than defining
myth as the product of imagination disconnected from science, I regard it as
muthos, a likely story in the original Greek. We deploy our myths in this
sense when weve reached the limits of knowledge, when were not sure of
how to go on with what were doing, when we must go on regardless and
we must seize upon uncertain guidelines for our direction. Myth-making is
integral to rationality as its founding and guiding principles.
Under the influence of Bergson, Messay supposes that myth confers a
transcendent meaning on existence with the consequence that rationality is
74
Charles C. Verharen
75
76
Charles C. Verharen
77
78
Charles C. Verharen
assumptions that direct their connective efforts, are true in any sense of that
term. Relativity and heliocentrism merely satisfy rationalitys promptings in
greater degree. Both Einstein and Newton allow us to navigate the whole
universe with their theories. By this measure, scope, their theories are
superior to those of Kepler, Galileo and Ptolemy whose theories restricted
us to the local heavens or the earth. Nevertheless, Ptolemys assumptions
still serve as a foundation for modern celestial navigation.
Thomas Kuhns work showed how heliocentrism was more rational
than geocentrism (before our ability to detect celestial parallax) because of
its simplicity, its use of fewer symbols to cover planetary, lunar, and
perceived solar motion. Confronted with a failure to find experimental
confirmation of one of his theories, Einstein affirmed his support for his
theory because of its simplicity, economy, or beauty (subsequent
experiments proved him correct). Newtonian mechanics are still accurate
for purposes of space ballistics, but Einsteins relativity is more accurate for
greater velocities and masses.
Consider the likely story that malaria is caused by bad air (the
etymology of mal-aria). Such a story might be as practical as a theory of
bacterial transmission by the anopheles mosquito. Draining a swamp to get
rid of the bad air would stop malaria. But the anopheles theory unfolds into
a greater range of experience more accurately. The likely story that malaria
is caused by bad air comes to a full stop rather quickly. Pursuit of the
detailed nature of bad air would be as fruitless as the quest for the
caloric, the mysterious cause of heat propagation.
Perhaps the most important measure of the rationality of a likely story
is whether the story encodes instructions for knowing how to go on, in
Wittgensteins felicitous phrase. A theory that enfolds itself in other
theories, that advances a tradition, that provokes us to call itself into
question, is a fruitful or stimulating theory.
Even the measures of rationality can themselves be called into
question through metatheoretical investigation. Consistency is one of the
bedrock postulates of rationality. Do I contradict myself? I contain
multitudes! This phrase may be a fine poetic sentiment. But noncontradiction has achieved the status as one of the laws of thought for
Wiredu (1996), and it is enshrined as a theory of truth. Nevertheless,
quantum mechanics has called forth quantum logic, a multi-valued logic
used to address Heisenbergs uncertainty principle. Einsteins destruction of
our common sense notions of the fixity of mass, length and time does not
compare to quantum mechanics assault on consistency as a primary root of
rationality. The principle is so intuitively self-evident: To reason is to
connect. Let us not imagine that what we have claimed to be connected is in
the same sense and at the same time disconnected.
What hope have we, then, of separating rational from irrational myths?
Purely mythological symbol systems yield low rates of connectivity
even within highly rational systems like science. The symbol gravity, for
example, has taken on quite different life forms in the history of modern
79
80
Charles C. Verharen
81
given a point outside a straight line, only one line can be drawn through that
point parallel to the straight line is better than its competitors. Why not
assume Lobachevskis infinite number of parallel lines? Or Riemanns null
set of parallel lines? One cannot prove that a life with science in its current
technological expressions is better than a life without science. If one valued
survival over manipulation of the environment, and one could prove that the
contemporary expressions of science will terminate life on earth as we
know it, one could prove that a life without science is far better than a life
with science.
Do we have a choice in the matter of such foundational myths?
Previously, no. Natural selection dictated our choices. After 9/11 we should
be clear that a small group can exercise enormous destructive power. In a
few years the development of biological and chemical weapons of mass
destruction may allow small groups to terminate human life altogether. For
the first time in history, humans can now exercise a choice about whether
we should choose to keep on choosing or to commit speciescide. To that
end, we need a full complement of philosophies to stimulate our
imaginations about what life is and how we should live it.
MESSAYS PROPOSALS FOR PHILOSOPHY IN AFRICA NOW
Messays review of Africana philosophy in Africas Quest for a
Philosophy of Decolonization is comprehensive and incisive. His critique
covers a full spectrum, from Marcien Towas dismissal of attempts to look
for that philosophy in Africa herself, to Senghor and Diops discovery of
that philosophy in Africa and Africa alone. He resists Towas claim that an
assuredly pre-existing African philosophy need not be recovered for the
simple reason that it was utterly worthless (Messay 2004:88). He is
sensitive to Mudimbes contention that scholarship on Africa to date has
produced only an invention of Africa, one that has mythical rather than
rational qualities (ibid.: 20). Messay recognizes that philosophical research
cannot reproduce original African philosophies that might contain the seeds
of African renewal. He applauds Hountondjis insistence that an
ethnophilosophy that serves merely anthropological purposes is useless
for the purposes of decolonization (ibid.: 87). In this vein he finds Nkrumah
and Nyereres discoveries of an original African socialism to be instruments
for African political leaders successful recolonization of Africa with
oligarchy parading as socialism (ibid.: 162-169).
Messay singles out Orukas demand for a transition from
ethnophilosophy to sage philosophy as particularly problematic (ibid.:
91-94). The critical function of the latter attempts to save philosophy from
becoming a disguised version of anthropology but in the process accepts the
idea that philosophical sages are exceptions to the mythical norm of
primitive African thought. Sage philosophy cannot generate a myth
capable of decolonizing Africa.
82
Charles C. Verharen
FROM ETHNOPHILOSOPHY
ETHIOPIA
TO
SAGE
PHILOSOPHY
83
IN
84
Charles C. Verharen
85
86
Charles C. Verharen
the second section of the essay is tentative at best. The best outcome of sage
philosophy research team dialogues would show that alternative models to
my proposal of rationality are required. An example of such a model
emerging from African culture is the ancient Egyptian postulation of a
multi-valued logic, as described by Eric Hornung in his Conceptions of God
in Ancient Egypt: The One and the Many (see also Hornung 1982). My
brief sketch assumes that the principle of non-contradiction is clear and
compelling. Hornungs research suggests that the ancient Egyptian
understanding of the principle is at once more complex and more practical
than our own.
What is the compelling motive for pursuing sage philosophy in
Ethiopia? One reason is to test Diops hypothesis of cultural transmission
from ancient Egypt to other parts of Africa and its converse. A second
reason springs from the fact that culture is preserved not only by means of
language but also by philosophy. Cultures are being lost at the same rate as
languages. Globalization may reduce the worlds 6,000 or so languages to
2,000 within fifty years. Wiredu proposes retaining cultures philosophical
cores even while contemporary science and technology transform their
accidental features (cited in Messay 2004:116). To discover a cultures
deepest foundations through sage philosophy increases the chance of
cultural survival.
A third reason for pursuing sage philosophy in Ethiopia lies in the fact
that a philosophy is a work of art in the senses of both practical and fine
art. A culture survives in part through the execution of its philosophical
guidelines; a cultures philosophy is part of its proven technology for
survival. And philosophies, by reason of their high degrees of
generalization and expression through minimalist sets of symbols, are
beautiful by reason of their economy and simplicity. A fourth reason to
keep these philosophical works of art alive is to discover the collective past
of humanity, and to stimulate further creativity in the worlds collective
philosophy. A fifth reason is the longest stretch to hope to find a
galvanizing myth with filiations throughout a large number of African
cultures (Verharen 1998). My tentative hypothesis is that ancient Egyptian
holism may be widely reflected across Africa.
Where in Africa will Messays galvanizing myth come from? Messay
headed in the right direction by singling out Cheikh Anta Diop for
attention. However, by focusing on Diops claim that black Africans built
the pyramids, Messay missed Diops deeper message for African
unification. Diop holds that ancient Egypt is the key to a future African
renaissance in the same way that Greece was critical to the European
renaissance (Diop 1991; see Verharen 2006: 1997a). Debate continues to
rage over Diops argument that ancient Egyptian philosophy launched
Greek philosophy. But Diops galvanizing myth for African unity looks
back to take the past in the manner of Ghanas Sankofa bird the point of
looking back is to create the future. Africas historical impact on Europe
through Greece is irrelevant to her constitution of the future. Diops vision
87
88
Charles C. Verharen
89
90
Charles C. Verharen
91
SECTION III
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
CHAPTER VII
96
Taddese Lencho
Seeri mumme, Seeri sare! (literally laws for men, laws even for dogs)
(Legesse 2006: 201). I was told that even the animals seem to have
understood this gesture from humans and they return the favor. The cattle in
Borana spend the nights outside, unattended in the presence of hyenas and
foxes. I asked the elders how it is that the hyenas and foxes did not molest
their animals. I received a most astonishing answer. It turned out the wild
animals are also taken care of and therefore do not molest their domestic
animals. The Borana have laws for the order in which the animals of the
wild drink from their wells and I was told that the animals knew these laws.
How did the Borana manage to inaugurate such laws and institutions?
Is it the result of strong constitutional tradition they have developed for
centuries? Or is it a product of their rich tradition of popular participation in
their assemblies? Or is it perhaps because the Borana have refused to
recognize the right to hold land as private property? They regard land as the
wife of the sky. Neither the sky nor the earth is appropriable. I wish to
explore the causes of the effectiveness of their institutions and laws. I also
wish to explore how the Borana managed to preserve their institutions not
only from the invasions of neighboring peoples but also from internal
degeneration.
While reading Rousseaus Social Contract, particularly his
championing of popular democracy, I became interested in what Rousseau
had to say about popular democracy in light of the fact that the Borana had
been practicing their version of popular democracy for more than 350 years
of recorded history. The practice of popular democracy in Borana preceded
the birth of Rousseau by a hundred years. Rousseau appealed to the ancients
to find evidence for his theories and rued the fact that his brand of
democracy was no longer practiced among the moderns of his time. He
was quite unaware that his version of popular democracy was being
practiced during his time but very far from the Europe.
In what follows, I hope to accomplish two objectives. First, to find
similarities between some of Rousseaus political theories and the political
tradition of a pastoralist community in Southern Ethiopia and Northern
Kenya. 1 Second, to show that Rousseaus theories, though usually
considered to be too ideal and quixotic to be of any practical utility deserve
our attention.
This essay intends to encourage future researchers to explore Oromo
democracy. The essay does not attempt to foster respectability for Oromo
democracy by association with a more illustrious philosopher of
democracy. There are affinities between Rousseaus political theories and
the political practices of the Borana, where a unique African democracy is
97
still alive and well albeit threatened from all sides by authoritarian
practices. These affinities are coincidental, of course, but they are
interesting because the Borana have been practicing their unique brand of
democracy for 350 years of recorded history. The actual duration of Borana
democracy cannot be assessed, given present methodologies. .
For lack of time and space, I am going to focus in this paper on
Rousseaus theories of the general will, popular sovereignty, and the role of
the legislator. I juxtapose his theories with the practices of traditional
democracy among the Oromos of present day Ethiopia and Northern Kenya.
INTRODUCTION TO OROMO POLITY
Borana land is located in Southern Ethiopia and Northern Kenya. The
Borana are ethnically part of the greater Oromo people, who are the largest
ethnic group in Ethiopia. The people, the Borana, still practice the Gadaa
system (Helland 1996: 137). The Borana are by tradition herders but of late
because of persistent drought in the area, some of them have taken up
irrigated agriculture and cultivate maize, vegetables and fruits (Dahl 1996:
164). The most striking feature of the Borana is neither their pastoralist
lifestyle nor their adaptation to agriculture in recent times, but their
participatory culture of democracy. In describing their political system,
Marco Bassi wrote:
Borana polity, of which gada is only one component, may
certainly be considered a democracy, if democracy is strictly
taken in its classic meaning of government of the people, by the
people, for the people. (Bassi 1996: 159).
Members of the polity participate in the juridical and legislative
efforts, a sure sign of its democratic nature with regard to division of
powers and universal suffrage. It is a form of government that works in
small and unstratified societies. There are three principal institutions in
Borana political organization. They are the national assembly (Gumi), the
generational organization (Gada) and the dual organization (Qallu)
(Legesse 2006: 97).
The national assembly the Gumi (meaning the multitude) is the
most important institution. It is made up of many councilors, assemblies
drawn from different sections of the Gadaa institution as well as ordinary
citizens who have the ability to express their thoughts on matters of national
concern and interest to travel to the site where the assembly is held (Ibid.).
The one assembly that has survived to this day is the Gumi Gayo in Borana,
southern Ethiopia, named after a famous well in the area. It is interesting to
note that the Gumi broke up into regional assemblies during the great
Oromo migration of the 16th Century and assemblies were held by different
splinter communities in places like Malka Bollo (around Awash River) and
in another place called Tule in Central and Western Ethiopia (Legesse 2006:
98
Taddese Lencho
99). As distance and the large number of people involved became too
unwieldy, the people created their own prototype assemblies so as not to
lose the original spirit of such assemblies i.e., popular democracy.
The other institution is the Gadaa (which is more like the government
that enforces the laws passed by the Gumi). Gadaa is a generational
organization. In the words of Legesse, in the Gadaa system, all
generations take turns in assuming the authority and responsibility to
perform domestic labor, take part in wars, lead their people, make laws,
mediate or adjudicate conflicts, and during their partial retirement, sit in
judgment of the ruling gada class, give legislative leadership to their people
and end the life cycle in a sacred state (Legesse 2006: 128). For Legesse,
Gadaa is an effective method of distributing authority and responsibility
across the whole life course and helps the Borana society in attaining
intergenerational equity and separation of powers on a sequential scale
(Legesse 2006: 128).
In the Gadaa system, every one has a role appropriate to his age.
Every one passes through generation grades: Dabballe I (childhood), Junior
Gamme II (the age of looking after livestock), Senior Gamme III (the age of
initiation and the period during which the boys elect their six leaders to
practice political leadership), Cusa IV (apprentice warriors), Raba V (the
age of warriors), Gadaa VI (the age of assumption of political power)
(Legesse 2006: 124-125).
The leader of the Gadaa class in power is known as the Abbaa Gadaa
or Abbaa Bokku (father of the Gadaa or Father of the Scepter). He is
democratically elected (see Appendix for Abba Gadaas of Borana since
1659). The Gadaa class remains in power for eight years. They assume
power at a designated place called Nura and designated time, a transfer of
power from one Gadaa class to another is effected in ceremony known as
balli-wal-irra fudhani or the transfer of ostrich feathers a symbol of
authority (see Appendix) (Legesse 2006: 125).
After the six grades mentioned above, there are four grades (VII to X),
collectively known as Yuba. These are periods of partial retirement from
active political leadership. The members continue to play some roles but
their activities are greatly restricted. They are not actively involved in the
day-to-day political government but they play an important role during the
national assembly conventions (Legesse 2006: 126).
The third institution the Qallu is a ritual institution representing the
two great societal halves of the Borana nation. The Qallu are hereditary and
hold office for life. They are empowered to oversee the election of Gadaa
leaders but they and their kin are barred from holding such office (the
Oromo version of separation of state and religion). They are not allowed to
bear arms or shed blood (Legesse 2006: 101), for men who communicate
with God have no business carrying arms or shedding blood.
In Borana political system, participation is built into and permeates
the whole system. The Gumi, as indicated before, personifies the
culmination of a societal culture that puts a premium upon participation.
99
100
Taddese Lencho
101
102
Taddese Lencho
This passage from the state of nature to the civil state produces
quite a remarkable change in man, or it substitutes justice for
instinct in his behavior, and gives his actions a moral quality they
previously lacked. Only then, when the voice of duty replaces
physical impulse and right replaces appetite, does man, who had
hitherto taken only himself into account, find himself forced to
act upon other principles and to consult his reason before
listening to his inclinations he ought constantly to bless the
happy moment that pulled him away from it forever and which
transformed from a stupid, limited animal into an intelligent
being and a man (ibid. 151).
Rousseaus homo politicus is not the individual who wishes to be left
alone, as in the case of Locke or Mill. He rather prefers a society in which
participation in the political process is indispensable. The happiness of the
community must be given precedence over that of the individual. The
freedom and security derived from a communal life based on participation
and equality is more meaningful than the right of the individual. Selfgovernment based on participation of the members is the key to Rousseaus
community.
If one is to make sense of Rousseaus political philosophy as a guide
for practical politics (not to get blood out of a stone, as Plamenatz says),3
one must seek ways of rescuing his theories from disuse, and even worse,
abuse.
Rousseau, we should remember, writes about legislation in two senses.
The first sense in which he uses is the original social contract that creates
the state. In this Rousseau simply reiterates the famous principle of contract
that a contract is a law as between the parties that have signed up to it
(pacta sunt servanda). His famous remark that those who disobey the
general will should be forced to be free is in that context not as draconian as
it appears at first sight.
The second sense is what, in Rousseaus words, gives it [the social
compact] movement and will (Rousseau 160). I am interested in the
second type of legislation: the form it might take when taken on the ground.
For the first one, I can only repeat what Gloucester in Shakespeares King
Lear says of his bastard son: I cannot wish the fault undone, the issue of
it being so proper. As far as I am concerned, the birth of states is
immaterial as long as they turn out well, and it does not really matter how
proper the birth of states was if they turned out bad.
Plamenatz writes It is certainly a good rule to take the theory you are
studying seriously; but that need not involve trying to get blood out of a
stone. Do what you like with it, you will get no pearls of political wisdom
out of it (Plamenatz 1963: 394)
103
104
Taddese Lencho
105
reminded at the beginning of the assembly that the assembly is not a place
for clever disputation and sophistry. Attempts to pull rank or resorts to selfpraise are discouraged. According to Legesse, the presiding Gadaa officer
starts the assembly by saying the following:
Dubbin dubbi Gumi Gayooti
Our talk is that of Gumi Gayo
Dubbin dubbi Gumiiti
Our talk is the affair of the multitudes
Dubbi qorumman dubbatani mit
This is not the place for clever talk
Warri qaro qarumman laf keyyadha
Clever people! Leave cleverness behind.
Fula tun, fula wan adaa dubbatan male
This is the place for discourse on custom
Fula qarumman dubbatani miti
It is not the place for clever talk
An hayyu, an qaro, an duressa wabeeka jedhani
Some [people] may want to brag: I am knowledgeable, I am clever, I
am rich and so on;
Dubbi akkas akka hin jiranne
Such talk is not allowed here
Dubbi kara adaati
[our] talk is [about] the path of custom;
nam ada chaqasa!
Listen to those who speak of custom! (Ibid. 213, with authors
modifications)
These appeals to the Convention to refrain from provocative and
rancorous language are deliberately intended to calm down passions so that
consensus would be possible. The signal that a consensus is about to be
reached is sent by the father of laws, who presides over the meetings,
when he is ready to formulate a decision that might be acceptable to most of
the participants. If that is acceptable to the rest, he asks members if they are
ready to reach a consensus. If the assembled multitude overwhelmingly
responds with Peace! Peace! Peace! it means that there is a meeting of
minds. If not, the debate continues until a consensus is reached (Ibid. 213-
106
Taddese Lencho
14). It does not mean that dissenters are not allowed to voice their dissent,
but pressures are applied upon dissenters by chanting Bless! Bless! Bless!
and these rituals usually end up in the submission of the dissenters (ibid.).
Now that the procedures of Gumi Gayo are outlined, the differences
between Gumi as an expression of popular democracy and the standards
laid down by Rousseau should become clearer.
First of all, the Gumi is not just a legislative body. It is also involved
in an adjudication of outstanding conflicts not settled by other bodies of
Borana political system. Rousseau famously proscribed the involvement of
a sovereign body in adjudication of particular cases because to him, the
sovereign body loses its general character when entangling itself in
particular issues and cases.
Secondly, the Gumi, although it starts its proceedings with all the
citizens of Borana, its later deliberations are dominated by Gadaa
councilors. The early (so-called pre-Gumi) proceedings may meet
Rousseaus stringent standards but the later stages may violate his
injunctions against surrender of any legislative authority to a representative
body.
Are Gumis proceedings any worse for that? Not at all. These
communities have gone as far as they could go in giving their people a
voice in the legislative process. When everyone around them succumbed to
various forms of autocratic governments, they followed a unique political
system which accepted the natural goodness of an ordinary citizen and took
his views into account. If the type of laws they have passed over the years is
anything to go by, it is fair to conclude that the quality of their laws is in
large measure the product of the wide-ranging discussions they
incorporated into their law making process.
I have described the Gumi Gayo as an example of Rousseaus popular
democracy in Borana (it is certainly the supreme body on pan-Borana
matters). According to the Borana political tradition, what the Gumi
decides cannot be reversed by any other assembly (Legesse 1973: 93). But
it must be remembered that there are several other assemblies which make
binding decisions concerning virtually all spheres of life (Bassi 1996: 153).
These assemblies involve different groups depending on the nature of issues
and they make decisions such as money and cattle collections for collective
investments or for assisting the needy, arrangements on management and
use of natural resources and juridical proceedings (ibid.). The decisions
taken during an assembly can only involve the members of the community
concerned with that specific assembly and all binding decisions are reached
through consensus (ibid. 153-54). It is this political phenomenon of the
Borana that led Marco Bassi to refer to the Oromo society as una societa
assembleare or a society of assemblies (in Legesse 2006: 215).
ROUSSEAUS LEGISLATOR AND BORANA LEGISLATORS
Several political philosophers have cast doubt about the ability of the
107
average citizen in matters political. Plato was led to a rule by philosopherkings in part because of his ambivalence about the ability of the people to
govern themselves (Hacker 2006: 323). Even Rousseau, the great champion
of the natural goodness of the average citizen, could not resist a
condescending statement at times: How will a blind multitude, which often
does not know what it wants (since it rarely knows what is good for it),
carry out on its own an enterprise as great and as difficult as a system of
legislation? (Rousseau 1987: 162)
For Rousseau, the general will, the source of laws, inheres in the
people but in the apt expression of Andrew Hacker at the collective
unconscious (Hacker was instructively employing Freudian language to
make sense of Rousseau) (Hacker 2006: 323). This collective unconscious
needs an articulator- whom Rousseau calls legislator.
By what oracular powers the legislator unlocks and reads the general
will, Rousseau does not say. He attributes it to near mystical powers of the
legislator. Gods would be needed to give men laws, he says. Nonetheless,
the position of the legislator in Rousseaus political system is not as exalted
as the position of philosopher-kings in Plato, for example. Rousseaus
legislator is a person with a power to compel without violence and
persuade without convincing.(ibid. 164)
The office of the legislator says Rousseau, is neither magistracy
nor sovereignty (Ibid. 163). In another memorable passage, Rousseau says
he who has command over the laws [the legislator] must not have
command over men (ibid.). Rousseau insisted that the legislator must not
be entangled in the government of the people because he feared that the
legislator so involved would use his office to perpetuate injustices and
allow his private opinions to taint the sanctity of his work.(ibid.).
The legislator draws up the laws and will have no business getting the
law passed. He who frames the laws, says Rousseau does not or should
not have any legislative right.(ibid. 164) The populace cannot, even if it
wanted to, deprive itself of this incommunicable right, because according to
the fundamental compact, only the general will obligates private individuals
and there can never be any assurance that a private will is in conformity
with the general will until it has been submitted to the free vote of the
people.(ibid.).
In order to ensure that the legislator remains detached from
government over men, Rousseau would be content to have the legislator
abdicate his office (as Lycurgus was said to have done) or even come from
a foreign country as was the custom in ancient Greek towns and the
Republics of modern Italy and Geneva.(see ibid. 163-164)
It is not altogether clear in Rousseaus philosophy at what point the
legislator should stop and let the people decide because the legislator must
communicate the laws he has drawn to the people (or assembly of people).
At what point is the legislator going too far? Rousseau wants his legislator
to master the arts of persuasion, blend fact with fiction, reason and emotion,
science and myth (Hacker 2006: 325). It is unclear how the legislator who
108
Taddese Lencho
employs these tricks would remain faithful to the general will, granted
that the latter can be known. In a romantic like Rousseau, however, that
kind of ambiguous language may be excused. Rousseau was seeking to
achieve rational legislation and at the same time leave ultimate power in the
hands of the people (ibid.). We can cavil endlessly about the possibilities of
that but it is at this point unnecessary.
Let us now come to the traditional polity and examine the role of
Borana legislators (obviously that is not the word they use). The Gumi
Gayo, being an assembly of a large number of people, requires a
management by individuals who possess knowledge of the laws, rituals,
history, chronology and time reckoning (Legesse 2006: 211). A tradition
has been developed, therefore, to seek the advice of men of knowledge.
Rousseau mentions Lycurgus as a paragon of legislators in history, and
among the Borana, there have been renowned legislators of similar stature.
According to Legesse, one such legislator active in the 50s and 60s is a
man of knowledge named Arero Rammata, who was said to have the entire
Gadaa chronology three hundred and sixty years of history stored in his
mind (ibid. 131). A mathematician named M. Ascher used Rammatas
knowledge to examine the nature of mathematical concepts and techniques
of reckoning in non-Western communities and archaeo-astronomers, B. M.
Lynch and L. Doyle used Rammatas extensive knowledge to confirm that
the Borana calendar is based on a clear understanding of lunar motion.
Rousseau says that the legislator is in every respect an
extraordinary man in the state and Rammata meets that profile. Rousseau
also says that if a great prince is a rare man, a great legislator is even rarer.
Legesse cites two well-known legislators from Oromo history: Dawwe
Gobbo (of Borana) and Makko Billi of Macha (western Oromia) (ibid.
209). These two men were credited with formulating the fundamental laws
that stood the test of time, such as the Gadaa system itself.
An interesting feature of the Borana political organization is that the
Yuba class becomes most active during the Gumi Gayo conventions at a
time of their life when they retire from active political leadership in Gadaa
(ibid. 99). Because of the enormous knowledge they accumulate in their
previous leadership, their influence in directing the Gumi convention and in
formulating the right kind of laws is undeniable. Rousseau, it must be
remembered, wanted his legislators to follow the example of Lycurgus:
resign from office to occupy a more exalted position of a legislator. In the
Borana political system, that philosophy seems to be built into the system.
That said, the similarities of legislators as Rousseau imagined them in
his Social Contract and as the Borana view theirs must not be carried too
far. First of all, the legislators in the Borana political tradition are involved
in the law-making process of the Gumi assembly (there is no way of going
around it) although they are involved as individual citizens or members of
the multitude. In his insistence that those who frame the laws shall have no
dominion over men, Rousseau might consider that as going too far. Borana
legislators are retired from Gadaa (Government) leadership and not from
109
110
Taddese Lencho
111
112
Taddese Lencho
Name of Abba
Gada
Abbu Lakhu
Abbayyi Babbo
Alle Kura
Wayyu Uru
5
6
Morrowwa
Abbayye
Gobba Alla
Dawwe Gobbo
Jarso Iddo
Wale Wacchu
10
Sora Dhaddacha
11
12
Dhaddacha
Wayyu
Halakke Doyyo
13
Guyo Gedo
14
Madhu
Boru
Dadoye
Dhaddacha Oda
Morrowa
Bule
Dhaddacha
Liban Wata
15
16
17
Period
No.
Period
24
Name of Abba
Gada
Madha Boru
16591667
16671674
16741682
16821690
16901698
16981705
17061714
17141722
17221730
17301737
17371745
17451753
17531761
17611768
17681776
17761783
1783-
25
Liban Jilo
1845-1852
26
1852-1860
27
Jaldessa Guyo
Debbasa
Doyyo Jilo
28
Haro Adi
1868-1876
29
Dida Bittata
1876-1883
30
1885-1891
31
Guyyo Boru
Ingule
Liban Jaldessa
32
Adi Doyyo
1899-1906
33
Boru Galma
1906-1913
34
Liban Kuse
1913-1921
35
Arero Gedo
1921-1929
36
Bule Dabbasa
1929-1936
37
Aga Adi
1936-1944
38
Guyyo Boru
1944-1952
39
Madha Galma
1952-1960
40
Jaldessa Liban
1960-1968
1837-1845
1860-1868
1891-1899
113
1790
179141
Gobba Bule
1968-1976
1798
19
Boru Madha
179842
Jilo Aga
1976-1984
1806
20
Ingule Halakhe 180643
Boru Guyyo
1984-1992
1814
21
Saqo
181444
Galma Madha 1992-2000
Dhaddacha
1821
22
Jilo Niencho
182145
Liban Jaldessa 2000-2008
1829
23
Sokhore Anna
18291837
Source: Asmarom Legesse, Oromo Democracy, Appendix I, p. 267
18
Wayyu Ralle
SECTION IV
PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION
CHAPTER VIII
For at least the last four decades Africanists have been engaged in a
lively scholarly discourse centered on the questions of why and how world
religions expanded at the expense of African indigenous religions. 1 The
explanations rely mostly on two models of conversion. The first, promoted
by Robin Horton, assumes African conversion to world or missionary
religions was the result of Africas widening political, economic, and
cultural frontiers which followed the continents contact with and
integration into the modern world. According to this view, the Africans
expanded sociocultural interactions required an enlarged cosmology and
revised morality that the universalistic doctrines of the world religions
offered. Conversion resulted from Africans moving out of their hitherto
insulated homogenous communities (microcosm), where local spirits
controlled events, to an expanded world (macrocosm) under the reign of a
supreme deity. In this sense, conversion is the result of the Africans choice
of a different cosmology in which missionaries served only as facilitators in
accelerating changes that were already underway (Horton 1971; Horton
1975).
The second model, enunciated by Humphrey Fisher, criticizes
Hortons model for placing too much emphasis on the adaptive capacity of
indigenous religious thought and underestimating the role of external
agencies, thus ignoring the fact that the broader worldview of the
missionary religions creates its own juggernaut that allows religious
conversion to proceed under its own momentum (Fisher 1985). His
alternative model conceptualizes conversion as a three-stage process in
which Africans first quarantined outside religions, then mixed their
former belief system with the new, and finally initiated reforms to purge
religious practices that were found to be inconsistent with the basic tenets
118
Ezekiel Gebissa
of their new faith (Fisher 1973). Other opponents of Horton fault his theory
as too deterministic, due to its emphasis on a predictable unidirectional
religious change (Ikenga-Metuh 1987), and as too intellectualistic, due to its
neglect of political and socioeconomic influences on conversion that
materially affect the convert (Ifeka-Moller 1974; Comaroff 1985). Still
others stress that African societies have in fact always been aware of a
High God whom they invoked when occasions demanded (Mbiti 1980;
Idowu 1973; Idowu 1967).
In assessing conversion later scholars favor giving priority to the
Africans own experience at the local level their goals, motivations, and
strategies to better understand patterns of religious change rather than
overemphasizing the macrocosmic context. Lamin Sanneh, for instance,
contends that from the Africans religious perspective conversion to a world
religion signifies very little or no change at all (Sanneh 2003). John Peel
argues that studies of religious conversion ought to investigate not just how
Africans became Christian but also how Christianity became African (Peel
2000). Other studies of conversion focus on religious diversification and
multi-causality of conversion (Ikenga-Metuh 1987).
In Ethiopia, the scholarly literature on religious change seemed
unaffected by the contemporaneous debate in the rest of Africa, providing
descriptive accounts of conversion from indigenous faith traditions to the
monotheistic world religions (Trimingham, 1952; Tamrat 1972; Crummey
1970; Arn 1978; Kaplan 1984). A review of the literature on the subject by
Steven Kaplan acknowledges that the studies on conversion are largely
descriptions of the main actors, motives, patterns, and impact of incentives
in the conversion process rather than causal explanations (Kaplan 2004). In
recent years, however, several anthropologists have raised critical questions
concerning patterns of conversion and the political economy and
sociocultural contexts of conversion. These studies view the encounter
between indigenous and missionary religions as a transformative space
where the beliefs and practices of the advocate and potential convert
intermesh and potentially where a hybrid that incorporates elements of both
cultures emerges and evolves. This is shown in several studies exploring the
conversion of the Sidama to evangelical Christianity (Hamer 2002),
processes of religious syncretism in southern Ethiopia (Braukmper 1992),
stages of conversion and resistance to conversion among the KambbaataHadiiyya (Rnne 1997), and reexamination of Emperor Ezanas conversion
to Christianity (Kaplan 1982).
This paper examines the dynamic and complex process of conversion
of the Macca Oromo of Wallaga, Western Ethiopia, to Protestant
Christianity with a goal of exploring the meaning of conversion of a people
who had an indigenous religion with a complex theology and elaborate
rituals. My explanation of the meaning of conversion among the Macca
Oromo builds on a perspective first enunciated by Lambert Bartels, the
pioneer scholar of Oromo religion. Based on his study of the Macca Oromo,
he concluded that,
119
120
Ezekiel Gebissa
121
122
Ezekiel Gebissa
123
(Eide 2000: 75). The same is true for all the other Oromo religious concepts
Onesimos employed in translating scriptures.
Nearly all of the indigenous Protestant missionaries who were
involved in evangelizing (sharing the joy of the new revelation) the Oromo
were in one way or another connected to Onesimos (Eide 2000: 51). Their
ventures would not have succeeded, to the degree they did, without the
scripture in the Oromo language. This was particularly true for the first
successful missionary venture to Oromoland undertaken by an Orthodox
clergyman named Gebre Ewostatewos, who learned the Oromo language
from Onesimos Nesib specifically to read scriptures, and an Oromo named
Daniel Dabala. On arrival in Naqamtee in 1898, the seat of the governor of
Wallaga at the time, they met Fitawrari Dibaba, a provincial governor who
was perhaps looking for a priest for an Orthodox church he had built in his
capital of Boji Karkarrro, west of Naqamtee. The governor was nominally
an Orthodox Christian, having been forced to embrace that faith by
Emperor Menelik, but in practice, like many of his contemporaries, he had
continued to practice the Oromo religion (Gidada & Crummey 1972:105).
The meeting with Gebre Ewostatewos, who arrived equipped with an
Oromo New Testament, was a turning point. Gustav Arn describes the
encounter as follows:
Gebre-Ewostatewos now produced his books in Oromo, read
some portions from the New Testament and sang some hymns,
for he had a beautiful voice. Dibaba marveled. He never
imagined that it would be possible to use his own native language
for sacred scriptures and Christian poetry. Excited, he offered the
priest from Hamasen instant employment. Dejazmach GebreEgziabher consented, remarking that the clergy form Gojam
would never permit the Oromo Holy Scriptures to be read in
Naqamt Mariam (Arn 1978: 395-96).
It is clear that the delivery of the message in vernacular Oromo was
determinant in grabbing Dibabas attention. It was equally critical for the
evangelization endeavors of the Oromo students of Gebre Ewostatewos and
Daniel Dabala. Following in the footsteps of these pioneers, for instance,
Samuel Danki and Boru Siba successfully led the effort to evangelize the
Oromo in the villages of All Ambalto and Siban respectively and
conducted general literacy work along with their evangelistic activities
(Arn 1978: 401-03; Gurmessa 2009: 152-153). Given that Onesimos made
use of Oromo religious concepts to convey the meanings of relevant
Christian categories, it would be difficult to assume that the Oromo who
responded positively to these advocates entreaties were imagining that they
were being asked to abandon their Oromo religion. They were able to
adhere to the new faith without conviction and without affiliation. In
practice, this means that people attend mission schools taking Bible lessons,
124
Ezekiel Gebissa
but they go back to their old religious practices and never feel any
obligation to become church members.
The vernacular Bible was the single most important factor in the
activities of another group of Oromo evangelical missionaries: Oromo freed
slaves who attended the Swedish Evangelical Mission (SEM) schools in
Massawa and Imkulu on the Red Sea coast and Oromo traders who learned
the gospel from Onesimos. Among these, Gebre Yesus Bambe in
Naqamtee, Habte Mariam Kassa in Sadi in Qellem (western Wallaga), and
Ayele Yimer in Boji and later in Sadi, carried out evangelistic endeavors in
Oromoland. Onesimos and Aster preached in Naqamtee and Nejo between
1904 and 1905. Between 1903 and 1911, Feben and Ayele Yimer carried on
the work of evangelizing in Boji which Daniel Dabala had started. They
also worked in Qellem from 1911 to 1919, carrying on the evangelistic
work that Habte Mariam Kassa earlier began in Sadi in Sayyo (Arn 1978;
412-430; Gurmessa 2009: 152-156). In all of these cases, the use of the
vernacular looms large as the main catalyst for the eventual conversion of
the majority of the Oromo in Wallaga (Eide 2000: 74).
Indigenous evangelists who learned the message in the Oromo
language from the evangelists who followed the pioneers in turn proclaimed
the gospel in areas around Naqamtee, Nejo, Boji, Sayyo, Mendi and Chalia
in central Wallaga, and taught the people there how to read the Bible in the
vernacular. The evangelization that was started by the Oromo evangelists
brought forth converts such as Shuramo Yadessa, son of the governor of
Sadi in Sayyo, who was instrumental in preaching the gospel in Mendi. He
taught the gospel to Hunde Gutama, Irana Sarda, and Kenea Tesgera all of
whom, in turn, traveled and preached with the same purpose throughout the
villages between Mendi, Chalia and surrounding areas (Lundgren 1953:
144). Their success owes much to the appeal of the message in the
vernacular as the testimony of Mathewos Chibsa, an early convert from
Mendi, attests. He told his story to Eide as follows:
When I was young my only ambition was to become an Amhara
[alternatively Orthodox Christian]. But then I came across the
Oromo Bible. Realizing that God talked to me in my own
language, surprised me with joy, and changed my ambition
completely. From now on my sole desire was to learn the word of
God to bring it forth to my people (Eide 2000: 74).
Dibabas experience occurred at the beginning and Mathewos case at
the end of the period of this chapter respectively. These and the other cases
demonstrate that the Oromo Bible unleashed chain-reaction evangelism in
which the Macca Oromo took to reading scriptures in their own language,
rejoiced in the experience, and then resolved to share it with their kinfolk.
Overall, it is important to note three things here. First, the translation was
done entirely by Oromo converts with the missionaries logistical
assistance. Second, the gospel message was brought to the Oromo by
125
In the end, though, translation only makes the message accessible. The
content of the message may be accepted or rejected. As Bartels had noted
the Oromo showed a remarkable tendency to remain true to their own
conception of God, Waaqa, even as they adopted a new religion. At the
point of the encounter, in any case, conversion can only mean adhesion to
126
Ezekiel Gebissa
the new faith, despite the enthusiasm for the gospel in the vernacular. The
warm reaction could be to the Oromo text itself rather than the gospel
content. The next section deals with how the Oromo interpreted and
responded to the content of the message.
INTERPRETATION AND MUTUAL VALIDATION
When European Protestant missionaries arrived in the Horn of Africa
in the nineteenth century to reach the Oromo with the gospel, the Protestant
and Macca Oromo religious traditions had a surprising number of key
religious ideas that were similar. In this regard, I argue, following John
Thorntons analysis of the encounter between Africans and European
missionaries, that the Macca Oromo embraced Christian religious ideas and
practices that they found compatible within the Oromo religion and
resolved through mutual validation those they found to be different. Both
the Oromo and the European missionaries had similar cosmologies in that
both conceived the universe as being a two-tiered continuum: this world,
the material world which is accessible to anyone, and the other world,
which is invisible and accessible only to a few gifted individuals. The
worlds are basically separate, but were intimately interconnected. The
other world is primarily the abode of the divine, but also inhabited by
deities, spirits and souls of the dead from this world. It is also superior
and controls events in this world (Bartels 1983: 46-47; de Salviac 2005:
155-156; Aguilar 2005: 57-60; Megerssa 2005: 76).
Even the creation myths each side believed about how the universe
came into existence were more or less the same. Bartels (1983:355) states
that for the Oromo creation begins with the element of water. According to
the Borana version of Oromo creation myth, in the beginning, there was
water. This primeval water, called Walaabuu or Bishaan Ganamaa, was
divided into the Bishaan Gubbaa (Water of Above) and Bishaan Goodaa
(Water of Below). This was a fundamental conception of the universe
before it was shaped into the physical space comprising the celestial and
terrestrial realms commonly known as heaven and earth, which the Oromo
refer to as qolloo (lit. covering), and dachii (land) respectively (Megerssa
1993). Cosmologically, the conception is replicated in the realm of Waaqa,
known as Bayyanacha Waaqa (The Repose of God) or Fulaa Waaq (The
Dwelling of God), and the realm of humans, also known variously as uuma
(creation), adunya (world), and lafa (earth). The fundamental difference
between the two places is the absence of duality in the realm of Waaqa,
which is also known as Iddo Dhugaa (The Place of Truth), and its presence
in the realm of humans. The absence of duality, such as truth and falsehood
or life and death, in Waaqas realm denotes wholeness or perfection, and
their presence in the realm of humans denotes confusion, conflict, and
suffering. The realm of Waaqa is therefore a place of delight to which the
Oromo assign only noble intellectual happiness as contrasted with bodily
127
128
Ezekiel Gebissa
129
their own language, and delighted with the beautiful doctrine that
it contained, the listeners expressed highly their astonishment.
But of course, they said, among themselves, he is right, that is
well there the precepts of Waaqa taught by our forefathers. (de
Salviac 2005: 158).
The nature of the encounter with Protestant missionaries was more or
less the same, as Dibabas story demonstrates (cf. p. 146). Here the
illustrative aspect of the story is not just the ingenuity of the missionary, but
the response of the Oromo. What transpired is a negotiated construction of
reality in which the missionary validation of the Oromos belief and the
Oromos acceptance of the missionarys version in the context of their own
religious tradition occurred.
The exchange between the missionary and the Oromo illustrates the
two themes of this paper: first, hearing the new message in their own
language from an Oromo evangelist caused the Oromo to become open to
new religious ideas; and second, the Oromo accommodated the evangelical
faith because its principles comported well with the religious ideas of their
ancestors. The acceptance of the book nevertheless need not imply that the
Oromo standardized their revelation but that they came to view evangelical
Christianity as a new form of their old indigenous religion. This was the
point of departure in Oromo conversion to evangelical Christianity where
they began creatively to formulate a theology linking the indigenous and the
universal faiths, so that, to use Okorochas words describing a similar
situation in Igbo conversion, what is desired in the old is realized in the
new, and . . . a dynamic equilibrium is maintained within a new and unified
whole in spite of inevitable tensions (Okorocha 1987: 31).
On their part, the missionaries decided not to contradict the local ideas
of God. As they did particularly among other peoples that had a single
name for that deity and whose creative and sustaining acts resembled the
attributes of the Christian God, they adopted the Oromo Waaqa as a creator
of human life and of the cosmos. This was more than a useful translating
device. It meant that the God of the Ancestors of the Oromo came to be
identified with God the Father of Jesus Christ.
JESUS THROUGH THE PRISM OF OROMO RELIGION
Thus far, I have maintained that in the process of conversion the
Macca Oromo tended to reinterpret religious categories of the Protestant
faith in their own cultural and religious frameworks. This position faces an
immediate difficulty when it encounters the widely-held belief that the
concept of Jesus as the only son of God is nonexistent within indigenous
religious conceptions (Mbiti 1972: 51). Articulating the foreignness of
Jesus in the African experience, Enyi Ben Udoh (1988: 92) says: It is as
though Africans are saying: God we know; ancestors we acknowledge; but
who are you for us, Jesus Christ? However, the notion that contextual
130
Ezekiel Gebissa
131
132
Ezekiel Gebissa
133
134
Ezekiel Gebissa
135
136
Ezekiel Gebissa
SECTION V
PHILOSOPHY AND WOMEN
CHAPTER IX
140
Gail M. Presbey
141
pride. Both Kwasi Wiredu and Paulin Hountondji wrote books in the
seventies and eighties that pointed out irrational aspects of African practices
and beliefs, suggesting that some old values were outdated and had to go.
While many had popularly interpreted the authors as saying the past should
be forgotten, these scholars have each taken pains to clarify that they think
studying African traditional thought is worthwhile and important. As
Wiredu cautions, however, studies of traditional African philosophy should
not just be expository and clarifying, but also reconstructive, evaluating
our heritage in order to build up on it: (Decolonization 17). Hountondji
explains, The real issue is not whether African philosophy exists, but what
use Africans today decide, in full lucidity and responsibility, to make of
their traditions of thought (Intellectual 88). So we can consider that a
project like Sumners, one of not just championing texts of the past as
relics, but of analyzing texts and evaluating them, would be a worthy
project within the field of African philosophy.
While Sumner excels in certain forms of analysis of texts, he has not
focused on whether the wisdom put forward in the texts has a relationship
to political and social power. Feminist criticism offers a source of
hesitations about the wisdom traditions of Africa. Several of Sumners
texts are pious treatises that advocate a Christian life. Certainly the
Ethiopian wisdom tradition, as is the case with so many other wisdom
traditions, whether Egyptian, Biblical, or otherwise, provides excellent
examples of virtuous conduct regarding, for example, compassion toward
others, selfless hard work, truthfulness, humility, perseverance in the right,
thrift, and generosity. One who lived by its maxims would in many ways
live a virtuous life by most standards. However, it would be a mistake to
accept a tradition because of its authority without subjecting it to scrutiny
and evaluation.
We can easily understand the potential ambivalence of a contemporary
Ethiopian woman toward the wisdom tradition when we consider her role in
the institution that has fostered and transmitted it, the Ethiopian Orthodox
Church. On the one hand, she is likely to be a frequent participant in the
many long religious ceremonies of her Church. If living in a rural area, she
may still seek advice from the male rural elders advice steeped in this
very wisdom tradition regarding how she should live her life, including
her sex life with her husband, complete with reference to proverbs and
tradition; a recent Oromo play by Fayyisaa Yaadasaa entitled Guulaa Bulaa
illustrates this point. On the other hand, she is not allowed, despite her
piety, to play any leading role in the Ethiopian Orthodox Church and, as we
shall see, the traditional wisdom consulted by the elders regards her nature
as weak or wicked. Accordingly, her place in society is rigidly delineated.
Viewing her obvious attachment to her Church and its wisdom tradition, an
outside critic is likely to speak of brainwashing or subtle manipulation by
the dominant ideology. If she herself should become critical, she would be
faced with the dilemma of Yentl of the Isaac Bashevis Singer novel (and the
subtext of the Streisand film): can a woman love the wisdom embodied in
142
Gail M. Presbey
her religious tradition while refusing to accept the subservient role that
same wisdom assigns her?
Sumner has defined wisdom as the sum-total of things worth knowing
(Classical 8). In the case of the Ethiopian wisdom tradition, as with other
traditions, I contend that some of what calls itself wisdom is not wisdom
at all, but an unfair and inaccurate denigration of women. Descriptions put
forward as neutral, factual accounts of womens nature and behavior are
often sexist perspectives that flourish in a patriarchal society. Certain
passages cannot stand up to rational scrutiny, whether Cartesian or
figurative, since they are based on biased accounts written from a male
point of view. It is therefore important when studying or promoting a
wisdom tradition to encourage a critical attitude, and reject narrow-minded
chauvinism when it shows itself in however holy a guise.
How has Sumner approached the rather problematic wisdom about
women in Ethiopian sapential tradition? One of Sumners Geez
translations, The life and Maxims of Skendes, is an ample source of
wisdom about women. As a young student, Skendes was scandalized by
the wise philosophers saying that all women are prostitutes. In disbelief,
Skendes decides to test the truth of the maxim by trying it out on his
mother. He conceals his identity and finds that, indeed, his own mother is
willing to accept money to sleep with him for one night. While his mother
had first vehemently refused the offer when her maid conveyed the
message, she was later wooed by the maids account of the handsomeness
of her suitor. He spends the night with her, kissing her breasts, but going no
further. Because of his experiments success, he concludes that the
philosophers maxim is true (Classical 168-73).
However, the story goes on to convey both a tragedy and Skendes
later success in life. In the morning the mother questions her companion,
asking with concern if he were not pleased with her. Skendes then explains,
I am your son. Upon the news, his mother runs out and hangs herself.
Skendes, surprised at what has happened, blames his tongue and its
utterance for the death of his mother, and so sentences himself to a life of
silence. But his silence only intrigues others, and when the Emperor finds
out that even under pain of death, Skendes will not say a word, Skendes is
newly esteemed as a wise man, and the Emperor asks to receive counsel
from him on all important matters. The rest of the book is the record of
Skendes wisdom on a myriad of topics, including his insights regarding
women.
From a critical viewpoint, and certainly from a feminist viewpoint,
Skendes actions are morally problematic. Firstly, Skendes attempt at
empirical verification of the maxim falls prey to the fallacy of hasty
conclusion. He very subjectively decides that a test on one person, his
mother, is all that is needed; perhaps because he egoistically believes that
his mother would be least susceptible to such temptation. He therefore
concludes that if she were to succumb, all other women would as well. Why
does he consider one example to be enough? It could be that Skendes
143
knows that men might be prone to negative valuations of women, but stop
short from condemning all women, because of the esteem in which they
hold their mothers. Showing that ones own mother is as weak or fallen as
all other women makes judgments against women complete and universal.
Skendes experiment could also belie the assumption that all women act
similarly, denying the independent agency of women.
Secondly, missing from the experiment is any sensitivity to the double
standard to which men and women are often held regarding sexual issues. Is
the maxim regarding prostitutes, in the sense of those charging money for
sexual services, limited to all women, because it is known that there are
some men who will not accept money to have sex with a woman? To
charge that all women and all men are prostitutes would not make sense,
because mens moral worth in society is not routinely tested by whether
they will resist offers of money to sleep with women. The economic
background is missing as well. Women more often than men find
themselves in financial straits, especially in male-dominated economies.
This contextual factor would help explain why they would be more likely to
accept pressure to have sex for money, and less likely to have the spare cash
needed to encourage men to sleep with them for money.
Perhaps the moral distinction present in the contemporary West
between a licentious woman and a prostitute (who has sex with men for
money) is not made in the Geez story. Sumner notes that the word
zamawyat used in the maxim all women are prostitutes is used in the
Ethiopian Bible to refer to all morally forbidden libidinous acts, including
fornication and adultery (Skendes 233). Indeed in the story Skendes mother
seems to be more motivated by the handsomeness of her suitor, and is at
first offended by the idea that she should accept money. Nevertheless she
dose not refuse the money. It seems clear that Skendes mother is not being
condemned with all women for her love of easy money but rather for her
uncontrolled lust for handsome men. However, even understood in the
sense of lust, there is still a double standard. Do we think that men as a
whole are easily able to refuse the sexual advances of beautiful women? If
not, shall we say, All men are prostitutes as well as women?
While Skendes notes that all women have uncontrollable sexual
desires, Sumner notes that Skendes nevertheless has pity on women, since
they were given this desire by God as part of their nature, in order to ensure
the continuance of reproduction (Classical 176, 189). Why then does
Skendes not note that males are also given a libidinous nature by God in
order to ensure their participation in reproduction? Sumner points out the
influence of the earlier Greek and Arabic texts, which argue that since birth
is such a painful experience, a woman would not otherwise return to her
husband after she experienced the pain and anxiety of delivery, unless she
were driven by inordinate desire (Skendes 94). It stands to reason that since
men do not have to overcome such antipathy, a milder desire would suffice
as impetus for their cooperation. The Ethiopian text of Life and Maxims of
Skendes, perhaps influenced by its Arabic forbearer, puts the woman in the
144
Gail M. Presbey
145
146
Gail M. Presbey
147
148
Gail M. Presbey
reasoning that women reach the nubile age quicker and subsequently age
faster, it may be that the slight biological differences in this area cannot
justify such a wide age difference. More likely, social practices determine
this age gap (Classical 277). It is Sumners own appraisal that only Zera
Yacob holds the position that men and women are equal.
We can, however, say that the reason these two authors praise women
and marriage so much is that they were social critics of their times. In
addition to rebelling against the religious sectarianism that was then
prevalent, they also spoke out against the popular views and derogatory
treatment regarding women, especially found in the monastic tradition.
Samuel Wolde-Yohannes notes that while the sapential tradition has
permeated Ethiopian culture, the critical evaluations of Zera Yacob and
Walda Heywat found no popular following in Ethiopia (319-21). Perhaps
these two authors posed a threat to the religious power-that-be. Sumner
suggests as much in an interview with an enthusiastic Marxist, who was
scanning Ethiopian history looking for positive role models for their new
Marxist government. The reporter sees Zera Yacob as one who criticized
the Church and the ruling class, who opposed the feudalist system, and
denounced the exploitation of the people by the Church (Yacob 2).
Sumner finds negative views of women in his book, Oromo Wisdom
Literature, Vol. 1: Proverbs. Sumner found sixteen Oromo proverbs on the
topic of women, and almost all are wholly negative. It is said that a woman
cannot manage the household, let alone public affairs: only one proverb,
out of the sixteen devoted to woman, admits, as a concession to male
superiority, that it may be advantageous to have a woman in the house
(Oromo 327). This one positive reference is to the companionship that a
wife can provide. However, the category of woman is not alone in being
represented one-sidedly by proverbs. Sumner notes that while there are fifty
Oromo proverbs for vice, there are only eight for virtue. Likewise,
there is only one proverb on reality, while fifteen are on appearance; one
proverb on moderation, while thirteen on excess, etc. Does this context
ameliorate the seeming one-sided negativity of the proverbs on women?
Sumner says of these one-sided cases, That dose not mean that the idea of
the contrary is unknown, but only that proverbs that would make up an axis
of reference for the opposite notion either were not collected or were never
formulated the opposite, although being well known, did not become the
subject of a proverb (Oromo 292-93). The question is why not?
By examining closely related literature from a vastly different
perspective, Yeshi H. Mariam raises further questions about the worth of
wisdom. Her M.A. thesis analyzes the Amharic-language proverbs
regarding women, thus complementing Sumners collection of Oromo
proverbs. Whereas Oromo speaking-people make up about 40% of
Ethiopias population, Amharic-speaking people make up about 30% of the
population. But Mariams, analysis much unlike Sumners, is based on
poststructural theory. Noting definitions by Firth, for example, who calls
proverbs a jewel of truth, and, an outspoken piece of wisdom, she is
149
concerned that such expressions are seen to connote the idea of the
objectivity of truth. Instead, she focuses on proverbs role of telling others
what to do. Mariam suggests that proverbs do not represent the view points
of the entire society, but instead articulate the interests of the dominant
group. Particularly, proverbs on women are based on the views of the
dominant group in patriarchal societies. Proverbs reinforce the patriarchal
system through indoctrinating the minds of the people and normalizing
patriarchal views (Mariam, Critical 5-7). Discourse, including proverbs,
is linked to techniques of control. Institutions wield their power through
processes of definition and exclusion. They reach to the unconscious mind
and emotional life of the subjects they seek to govern. This approach draws
heavily on Foucault, who noted that while discourses power relations may
find their expressions at the institutional level, power at the localized level
is nevertheless crucial. We could therefore say that proverbs ability to
influence men (and women) regarding their attitude toward women plays
just as crucial a role in oppression as the institutional structures that
suppress women. In fact, power relations are not always obvious; instead
they are masked. They affect desire, so that ones oppression is not always
obvious. Language and socio-cultural codes are slowly legitimized, until
they are seen as normal (Critical 17-19).
For Foucault, truth and power are mutually produced. Each society
has its regime of truth, its general politics of truth: that is, the types of
disclosure which it accepts and makes functions as true (qtd. in Critical
19). This clearly goes against the proverbs own representations as
expressions of self-evident truths. Mariam explains that poststructural
theory shows that language does not just represent reality. It distorts reality
through its implicit ideology. Meaning is constructed; presenting itself as a
transparent medium, language disguises its function as a meaning
constituting system. There is no determinism in this view of language, for
it is possible to reconstruct those meanings that are not compatible with
the structures in which we live. In other words, dominant discourse is not
the only discourse (Critical 12-15). Since statements and beliefs are
historically bound, they may change (Critical 16). Therefore negative
proverbs regarding women are not inevitable, but can be challenged by a
new social reality, made obsolete, or replaced by new ones.
Mariam raises the question, do proverbs reinforce the existing
patriarchal system in Ethiopia? According to her observations, in
contemporary Ethiopian society, women for the most part find their lives
limited and constrained. Mens work consists of soldiering, plowing, and
mercantile affairs, while women labor in all other categories, including
agricultural work, reproduction and raising of children, and work in the
home. Women are subjected to circumcision and early marriage. Across
Ethiopia women are considered a source of contamination of men unless
they perform cleansing rituals after childbirth, menstruation, and sexual
intercourse (Social 59). Mariam suggests that in her society, the
150
Gail M. Presbey
151
152
Gail M. Presbey
men are awarded exclusive land rights because in many communities the
legends surrounding the founding of the community regard men as those
who first found and tamed the land on which the group settled. There are
also stories in which women, when entrusted with jobs like tending cattle,
acted irresponsibly, thus justifying the exclusive male ownership of cattle.
Adagala therefore concludes that more fundamental than the division of
labor by sex, and thus management of natural resources by sex, there exists
the division of the ownership of natural resources by sex (55-57, 71).
In addition to the study of Adagala, Adefioye Oyesakins study on
Yoruba proverbs on women show that the wisdom tradition sees women as
agents of indiscipline and the source of most moral problems in the
society. Such studies suggest that if society is morally deteriorating, it must
be due to the weak links of the moral order the women. However, it is
doubtful that the many problems facing Nigeria today military rule, abuse
of human rights, bribery, and corruption can be traced to the actions of
women denounced in their proverbs.
Amba Oduyoye has done a study of Asante proverbs on women
showing that the proverbs put forward the idea that all actions of note and
merit are done by men. Her study is complemented by the findings of Safro
Kwame, who says that Akan proverbs express the view that all women are
equally unfaithful, bad, or even worthless. This conception of women as
greedy parasites, as put forward in the proverbs, is inconsistent with most
Akans conceptions of their mothers who are obviously women (261).
Although Kwame insists on the universality of womens subjugation, he
admits that such subjugation can take different forms, according to specific
historical and social conditions (264). Therefore, one could still make
meaningful distinctions, as Mernissi suggested, between Christian and
Islamic forms of womens oppression. Different social conditions could
also lead to different strategies for improving womens lives.
Florence Dolphyne of Ghana argues that the priorities of Western
feminist movements and African womens movements are not the same.
Whereas Westerners think African priorities should be the eradication of
polygamy and female circumcision, Dolphyne thinks development in
general, literacy skills, and economic well-being for women should be the
highest priority; if these priorities are met, problems of polygamy and
female circumcision will take care of themselves (Dolphyne). Likewise,
Marie Pauline Eboh of Nigeria explains that black womanists, who are
unlike white feminists, know that men are central to their lives, as
husbands, brothers, and sons. African women are not apprehensive of
wifehood and motherhood. The success of African womanism derives
from the discovered awareness by women of their indispensability to the
male, Eboh explains. This assurance of indispensability then serves as an
anchor for their liberating actions (211).
Leonard Harris describes studies in the implicit or commonly held
values of societies as necessary steps before change can be contemplated.
Philosophical anthropologys value lies in its driving presuppositional-state
153
154
Gail M. Presbey
155
156
Gail M. Presbey
______. 1991. Source of All Evil: African Proverbs and Sayings on Women.
Nairobi: Phoenix.
Stout, Jeffrey. 1998. Ethics after Babel. New York: Beacon.
Sumner, Claude. 1994. Classical Ethiopian Philosophy. Addis Ababa:
Commercial Printing P. 1985. Los angles: Adey.
______. 1974. Ethiopian Philosophy Vol. I: The Book of the Wise
Philosophers. Addis Ababa: Central Printing P.
______. 1981. Ethiopian Philosophy Vol. IV: The Life and Maxims of
Skendes. Addis Ababa: Commercial Printing P.
______. 1978. Ethiopian Philosophy Vo. III: The Treatise of Zera Yacob
and Walda Heywat. Addis Ababa: Commercial Printing P.
______. 1995. Oromo Wisdom Literature, Vol. I: Proverbs, Collection and
Analysis. Addis Ababa: Gudian Tumsa Foundation.
______. 1991. Problems of an African Philosophy. Books for Life. (eds).
Negussay Ayele and Claude Sumner. Addis Ababa: Relief and
Rehabilitation Commission, 44-71.
______. 1978. Seminar on African Philosophy, Addis Ababa University.
1-3 December 1976. Abba Salama 9, 104-52.
______. 1986. The Source of African Philosophy: The Ethiopian
Philosophy of Man. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner.
Volume IV on Ethiopian Philosophy Comes out. Ethiopian Herald 37.1
(4 June 1981): 1, 5.
Wiredu, Kwasi. 1995. Conceptual Decolonization in African Philosophy.
Ibadan: Hope Publications.
Wolde-Yohannes, Samuel. 1994-95. Western Philosophical Tradition and
Ethiopian Sapential Tradition. Ethiopian Review of Cultures:
Religious Studies in Ethiopia and Eritrea, a Symposium. (Special
Issue), 317-26.
Yadassa, Fayyisaa. 1996. Guulaa Bulaa. Oromo Play performed in Addis
Ababa. 24 March.
Zera Yacobs Philosophy of Protest. Ethiopian Herald. 21 Nov. 1976: 2,
5.
SECTION VI
SAGE PHILOSOPHY
CHAPTER X
160
Tenna Dewo
Particularly at this moment in time when millions are longing for peace, but
when the modern mechanisms of keeping peace do not seem to meet the
needs of the people, it is imperative to explore the roots that peace has in
the traditional values of indigenous societies. In this light, this paper
explores what peace means for the Oromo both at the individual and
societal levels, what goal it has for them, what moral values underlie it, and
the mechanisms by which the Oromo make, restore, keep and promote
peace. The last section of the article ventures into a critical assessment of
the applicability of Oromo conception of peace and its mechanisms of
peacemaking to twenty-first century situations.
CONCEPTUAL AND THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK
According to Royce Anderson, as noted in his article A Definition of
Peace, peace is a condition of having a well-lived life (Anderson 2004:
103). Since not all who seek and need it attain a well-lived life, clearly
peace is a value-laden concept denoting a desirable way in which people
live together harmoniously. Louis P. Pojman, for example, states, We want
to live a meaningful, fulfilled life as individuals, and we want to live
together in a prosperous, flourishing Community (Pojman 2005: xi). A. C.
Grayling adds, Almost everyone wants to live a life that is satisfying and
fulfilling, in which there is achievement and pleasure, and which has the
respect of people whose respect is worth having (Grayling ibid). The
nagging question that deserves answer for these influential philosophers is
how should we live our lives?
Since all humans aspire to have a well-lived life, peace is the common
need for all. As Grayling again observes, it is impossible to be truly happy
when people around you are not; for our natural sympathies make the
happiness of others a part of our own (ibid.). It is conceivable that one can
be happy while others are suffering from war and violence, terror and fear,
poverty and hunger of different scales. However, peace in the true sense of
the word may not be maintained in a society where wealth and opportunity
are unfairly distributed (ibid.: 248).
In such a context, one denies to others the peace that he/she wants for
him/herself. Grayling tersely asks, which would you prefer: Machine-gun
fire in the next street, fear, danger or warmth in winter, holidays in
summer, a good job, hope, enjoyment? If the answer is obvious, why should
the peace and prosperity alternative be yours alone (ibid.: 258)?
The implication of Graylings question is clear. No rational human
being should expect an island of peace and serenity in a sea of want and
deprivation. Even though no one has preferred war and violence to peace,
war and violence have been the tragic realities of human existence. Why
has humanity that needs peace more than anything else lacked the power to
put an end to events that violate peace? Responding to Graylings invitation
to provide a philosophical foundation of how humans can pursue a well-
161
lived life, this article maintains that the Oromo traditional concept of peace
can provide practical solutions to the perennial problems that disturb peace.
Philosophers are not unanimous concerning the application of
tradition, regarded as that body of practice and belief which is socially
transmitted from the past into a context of modernity, which is defined as
the rational and scientific views, beliefs, knowledge and life of the present
(Craig 1998: 445). Traditionalists seem to advise humanity to embrace the
past without any critical concern and are thus accused of being so
engrossed with the past that they have little care for the present and the
future (Tripathi 2003: 15). They contend that tradition or the past has the
authority to guide the present, because it contains the rules of conduct for
personal and social life, the duties and responsibilities of person in different
walks and stages of life (ibid: 16). In contrast, the very idea of tradition is
an anathema to the anti-traditionalists. They dismiss the authority of the
past or tradition in favor of the present. According to Karl Popper, a
prevalent modern attitude to the past holds that I am not interested in
tradition, I want to judge everything on its own merit quite
independently of any tradition with my own brain, not with the brains
other people lived long ago (Craig ibid.).
The either this or that option does not present realistic choices. The
traditionalists position is unsound, because tradition might have been
stuffed with bias and prejudice, irrational and non-rational beliefs,
superstitious and mythical imagination. The uncritical, wholesale adoption
of tradition can hamper development and threaten the well-being of life.
Tripathi comments, in spite of its stabilizing role in social life,
unquestioned acceptance of customary morality has had many negative
effects on the growth of human life and human personality (ibid.: 116). If
we recognize tradition as it is, we may not only lose sight of both its merits
and demerits but also consideration of the realities of the present.
On the other hand, the uncritical acceptance of the anti-traditionalists
position may deprive us of the vital qualities entailed in tradition. This is
particularly harmful to societies such as Ethiopia in which traditional values
and systems are not a dead fact, but lived experience that is sacred and
always meaningful. In fact, tradition is a life that the majority in traditional
societies still live and the rigid demarcation between the tradition of the
past and the life of the present is only imaginary. The past is in the present,
in its good or bad, relevant or irrelevant, form. As Grayling noted, seeing
into the past is a necessity for seeing the present and the future more
clearly (Grayling 2005: 33).
Therefore, traditional beliefs and values should not be accepted or
rejected as a whole. Instead, they should be critically examined in order to
disentangle the pertinent and good from the obsolete and bad contents in the
best philosophical tradition of examining the validity of every belief to see
which is good and which is spurious (ibid: 248) with a goal of liberating,
freeing us from prejudice, self-deceptive notions and half truths (Pojman
2000: 2). The purpose is not to prescribe the past as the remedy for present
162
Tenna Dewo
163
Peace to animals
Peace to the wild beasts
O, God listen to us, we pray to you
Make us live in peace, we know that you can do it
O, God you are the only Father we have
Protect us from evil, protect everything from evil
We do not want to do evil to anyone, protect us from
those who intend to do it to us
Save us from the spears, swords, and fires of war
We do not want to set fire to anyone, help us keeping
away from those who want to set it to us
Help us in our effort to do away with evil
O, God, peace matters most to us, keep away from us all
those anti-peace forces
O, Father, give us your light that leads us to sustainable peace
(Authors interview with elders in West Shawa 2005.)
That the Oromo pray for the peace of everything, even for such things
as stone, water, and air, shows that in Oromo cosmology everything is
interconnected through a myriad of webs and threads. Human beings are
related not only to fellow humans but also to nature, and even to the
spiritual power believed to be supernatural. Lambert Bartels writes the
remark of his assistant, Gemetchu Megerssa, who says, when Oromo pray
for peace, there are not two but three parties. The third party is Waaqa
with whom peace is made, too, and through whom people make peace with
each other (Bartels 1983: 252). But in the light of the above prayer, the
parties are not only three but more.
If any one of the parties is not in peace, according to the Oromo, it is
unlikely that the other parties can enjoy it. Humans cannot enjoy peace
while nature suffers turmoil. The Oromo strongly believe that making peace
with nature is as essential as being at peace with oneself and with other
human beings. Being at peace with God is an incomparable experience, and
one can be at peace with God only if he/she is in peace with everything else
in nature. Thus for the Oromo peace is holistic, it is the harmonious
relationship among all the parties involved.
Prayers for peace are made not only in groups but also separately or
individually. They ought to be made particularly in the morning and
evening, before meals, and during special occasions such as holidays,
weddings and mediations. In the morning, for example, the Oromo pray;
O, Waaqa, God you made us spend the night in peace; make us also spend
the day in peace (ibid 291). In the evening, shortly before going to bed,
they say, O, Waaqa God you made us spend this day in peace. Give us a
lasting peace (Megerssa 1994). When a meal is served, they pray, O, God
here is food; make us have it in peace. Bless it for us, so that it satiates us.
We thank you for your boundless generosity (authors interview in West
Shawa 2005).
164
Tenna Dewo
165
strife, violent acts and behaviors, arrogant and aggressive attitudes, unfair
and abusive treatments, are all threats to peace.
In traditional Oromo worldviews, therefore, any human action or
behavior that is harmful to the flourishing of human life is contrary to
peace. One may lose peace and experience evil because of ones own deeds,
because of the actions of others or due to conditions beyond ones capacity
to control. Personal peace is threatened when someone does to another
individual, to society, to God or even to self, something that he/she knows
is proscribed by custom or even personal conviction. This is self-inflicted
evil. Poor living conditions, as the Oromo believe, sap the basis of
individual peace. This is evident in Borana elders rhetorical question,
What does peace really mean, for a person who is forced to go to bed with
an empty belly because of poverty? (Authors interview with Jaatanii
Diida in Borana 2005.) In this sense, a person or a community that suffers
perpetually from injustice because of lack of good governance cannot have
peace. This is another caused evil.
From this follows the notion that the Oromo perceive peace to have
internal and external dimensions. Internal peace is the expression of the
harmonious relations of the different units of the community. It includes
personal peace, which is a state of an individual experience in which a
person does not have physical, mental, social, spiritual or legal troubles or
is not in conflict with himself. Such states are achieved as a person obeys
his/her inner feelings that are governed by his/her moral principles. In the
belief of the Oromo, a person who is at peace with him/herself is likely to
live in peace with others. If a person is not at peace with him/herself, then
he/she is likely to do evil to them individuals, society and Waaqa. Thus
the Oromo always strive for the peace of one and of all. If every member of
a given community has peaceful life within himself, then the community
very likely will enjoy peace.
This belief is, fostered by Gadaa values that teach the Oromo not to be
violent towards one another, but instead cultivate a sense of caring, sharing
and valuing one another. The Gadaa system and the institution of
Qaalluu writes Lambert Bartels, essentially form a ritual system stressing
the basic principles of internal peace and cooperation (Bartels cited in M.
Basisi 1994: 25) among the Oromo. Gadaa Officials, Qaalluu ritual
leaders, and Oromo elders teach that the Oromo people should not break
the peace among them. Aggression should be directed against [non-Oromo]
outsiders, (Hultin ibid.: 78) not against ones community. In prayers and
166
Tenna Dewo
blessings elders are very often heard saying, O, God, make our peace
everlasting. Bless our harmony which is our source of strength and beauty.
Do not divide us. Make us stand and remain together when we stand
together being shoulder to shoulder anti-peace forces get frustrated and
those who love peace get encouraged (authors interview with Dagaagaa
Cuucee, West Shawa: 2005).
In the traditional context, thus, individual Oromos are expected to
behave and act towards one another and towards others according to a
commitment to the value of peace. The Borana Oromo in particular give
special emphasis to the maintenance and promotion of internal harmony or
peace among the members of their own community. They maintain that
peace is the supreme value for which every person should persistently strive
(Bulcha 1996: 51). Witnessing this Johan Helland says, The maintenance
of internal peace is a strongly expressed ideal in Borana public life
(Helland 1994: 140). The same point is underscored by another scholar,
Mekuria Bulcha, who cites Baxter in this regard, Between Boran there
should be peace and gentleness, violence even angry violence between
Boran is a sin (Bulcha op. cit.: 51). That means, In everyday personal
interaction, Borana men are expected to treat each others physical and
psychological integrity by not using violence or insults to each other
(Dahl 1996: 175). In these manners, the Borana Oromo endeavor to reduce
the possibility of a conflict of serious nature.
While internal peace emphasizes personal peace and peace within the
Oromo community, external peace refers to the peaceful or healthy relation
that the Oromo have, make or establish with other, non-Oromo,
communities. In the relationship that they establish with non-Oromo ethnic
groups, the Oromo prefer friendship, cooperation and tolerance to enmity,
mutual exclusion and intolerance. Many scholars and researchers of
sociology, anthropology, history, religion, politics, etc. with the exception
of some Abyssinian writers assert that the Oromo do not act with arrogance
and violence, aggression and confrontation. The principle of tolerance and
peaceful coexistence is inherent in their culture and values (Bassi 1965: 65).
Intensive interviews conducted by the author in 2005 with Oromo
elders in various parts of Oromia reveal that the Oromo notions of peace
and tolerance emanate from their conceptualization of human differences
and oneness. The following is the authors summary: Difference is regarded
as a matter of fact, and hence it should be recognized, valued, or respected.
Even though human beings have differences, according to Oromo
traditional belief, they all have sprung from a single source. The Oromo
maintain that all humans are the children of the same father Waaqa or God.
As descendents of the same God, all people are distant siblings, even
though spatio-temporal differences have made them appear strangers to one
another. The Oromo traditional perception of human difference, in essence,
is the same as the difference between identical twins, that is, the difference
within the same human family. Because this kind of difference is one of
diversity within unity, the fact that difference exists is not a source of
167
conflict. Both unity and diversity become bases for conflict when humans
abuse them (authors interview with Caalaa Sori 2005). Oromo elders
observe that ideally, therefore, there has to be a reasonable balance sought
between human differences and their unity. There is a possibility of
exaggerating one and underestimating the other when the human mind is
infested with bias and prejudice, ignorance and arrogance, greed and lust. In
the Oromo Gadaa system human differences (whether social or natural,
mental or physical, shape or color, wealth or knowledge, etc.) are not
characterized by the difference of superiors and inferiors, but rather by
those between social equals and friends. Oromos treat non-Oromo persons
not only as equals but also as brothers and sisters. 3 If people treat one
another as brothers and sisters, peace will prevail. We Oromo as many of
them very often say,
do not want to ill-treat others, because we do not want also to be
unfairly treated by others. It is our duty to fairly treat others if we
need others to treat us fairly. Why ill-treatment if we recognize
what they want us to recognize for them, and if they recognize
what we want them to recognize for us? Ill-treatment does not
exist in the language of our Gadaa. We want everything to
remain in peace. (authors interview with Caala Sori ibid.).
An apparent reason for treating non-Oromo fairly is the expectation of
reciprocal treatment by others. The more concrete reason is the moral
obligation sanctioned by religion. In view of their indigenous religion,
treating a brother or sister (who is considered a child of Waaqa) unfairly is
an offence against God. In Oromo traditional belief, being human alone is
reason enough for treating another human being morally. Throughout their
history, the Oromo have welcomed and assimilated people who settled
among them. As observed by some researchers the Oromo have developed
the culture in which every right and privilege an Oromo enjoyed is granted
to outsiders who dwell among the Oromo. Oromo law forbids a distinction
between biological and social descent when adoption takes place.4
168
Tenna Dewo
169
170
Tenna Dewo
with praise and blessings, and the new group takes over with blessings and
good wishes. No confusion, curse or blame are involved, nor is violence
employed in the process of the transfer of power. Using any means for
seizing power other than peaceful means does not exist in the nature of the
Gadaa. Even an exchange of unhealthy language is forbidden legally,
religiously and morally (ibid: 219-220).
In the Oromo Gadaa system, as Lambert Bartels observed quite
sometime ago, power emanates from the people, and if those to whom it is
entrusted fail in their responsibility, it can be withdrawn. This is the Oromo
version of government by the people (Legesse 2000: 126). If power
belongs to the people and if these people have the right to bring down those
who abuse their responsibilities, then the society enjoys good governance,
which is a necessary condition for peace to flourish. Though the power of
relieving officials of their duties is a crucial safeguard against the abuse of
power, such a practice may not even be necessary since officials terms are
limited. In the traditional Oromo system of government, the entrenchment
of power is virtually impossible since the class that has been in office for
eight years does not intend to stay in power beyond its term (ibid: 114-116).
The Rule of Law as Guarantor of Peace
Gadaa is a law-making system, creating laws that clearly define what
ought to be done, and what ought not to be done. Marco Bassi says the
Oromo have traditional norms and laws recognized by everybody as
binding (Bassi 1965:65). Every member of the community, according to
the Gadaa notion of law, is expected to know what her/his rights are to
exercise and what her /his duties are to perform. Laws, in the context of the
Gadaa system, are made not with the intention of restricting the freedom of
people, but, as Legesse observed, to meet some of the great challenges that
confronted them in history (ibid: 259). The maintenance of peace is one
such challenge. For the Oromo the law is the strongest tool for the
maintenance and promotion of peaceful life.
Laws are made in the general interest and with the consent of the
society. Once every eight years the assembly of Gumii Gaayyoo of the
Borana, Meebookku of Guji and the Caffee of Macca and Tuulamaa
Oromo are convened. These assemblies are higher political bodies that
stand above all other institutions (Legesse 2000: 33). All the members of
the Gadaa class as representatives of the society actively participate in
these institutions. According to Legesses observation, the assembly sits as
a law making body, revises existing laws, and proclaims new laws (ibid).
They are the laws that according to Gufu Oba provided the requisite social
and political order which enabled them to move in and live with each other
in peace (Oba 1996:118).
For the Oromo the rule of law is the decisive parameter of peace. They
believe that when laws rule all men, the possibility for the prevalence of
peace is high, but when men rule, peace loses ground. The major source of
171
172
Tenna Dewo
173
174
Tenna Dewo
175
176
Tenna Dewo
177
mechanisms to make its people work for and live in peace. The egalitarian
ethos, communal solidarity, democratic governance structure, separation of
powers, and civility in political deliberations are elements of the Gadaa
system that allow people to be in control of their destiny and thus promote
peace for the well-being of the collective (Levine 2007: 51).
Respect for Peace as a Mechanism of Peacemaking
In the Oromo world view, peace will develop and prevail if life
conditions and environments are free of violence, strife and antagonisms.
One necessary condition for that, according to their belief, is good
governance and justice. Peace requires good administration. In the Gadaa
system, as we have noted, power belongs to the people and is transferred
peacefully to the legitimate age-set that rules on behalf of and is
accountable to the people. Under ideal circumstances, Oromo laws are
made by the peoples representatives in ways that promote the interest of
the people. The rule of law is a cardinal principle that governs politics and
administration. The society upholds the values of caring and sharing and
fights back against harmful and unethical acts and behaviors. These
desirable moral and democratic values diminish the development of a
political environment that fosters violence. Viewed from this angle Gadaa
is a democratic system that promotes peace and social harmony.
In the Oromo thought system, human actions are born and flow from
the human mind. The idea of peace or violence is conceived in the minds of
individuals and then spills over to social life and relations. People
practically behave, according to what they think about peace or violence. A
person who has respect for peace is inclined to act in favor of peace and a
person who has little respect for peace, according to Oromo conviction, acts
more in favor of violence. In either case, the individuals disposition is not
an innate condition, but a learned behavior. Gadaa officials thus endeavor
to teach people to guard their minds from being polluted by evil thoughts
and wicked ideas. In fact, the framework of predetermined actions given to
age sets and classes in the Gadaa system implants the notions of peace,
which are explained through demonstration and then take form in the mind.
The assumption is that a person with a mind guided by Gadaa moral
principles and egalitarian ethos is likely to act positively towards peace and
harmony.
Traditional Peacemaking Mechanisms and the Modern Legal System
The Oromo indigenous conflict resolution mechanism has an
important role in restoring peace that has been disturbed by conflict or
violence. Conflict is intrinsically harmful, destructive, and expensive
socially. The goal of conflict resolution, in the Oromo context, is the
reconciliation of the parties engaged in conflict. In a broader sense, it not
only aims to remove ill feelings between the reconciled parties, but also to
178
Tenna Dewo
179
with reference to the already existing value system. Conflicts arise mainly
when the value system that creates harmony is violated. Thus, when
resolution is made the individuals are reconciled not only with each other
but also with the value system of the society that they had violated. In this
sense, the Oromo traditional way of settling conflicts deals with conflict in
more profound and complete ways than the modern court system. Quite
startlingly, the Oromo faith in the effectiveness of the traditional way of
making peace, which is normally associated with the Gadaa system, was
the preferred means even among Christian converts as recently as the 1970s
(ibid: 253-254).
Professional Duty vis--vis Social Responsibility
In the modern conflict resolution mechanism in general and Ethiopian
state courts in particular, legal activities and procedures that may not be
clear and transparent to the parties of the conflict are pursued strictly as
matters of professional routine. Judges and attorneys are motivated by the
desire to get something done or to win a case for someone at any cost. The
pursuit of truth and resolution of conflict are not the prime objectives of
those who practice the law. This makes the court mechanism susceptible to
abuse, opening the way for doing what is morally objectionable, such as
rushing justice or winning on false premises, rather than what is morally
indispensable, such as seeking truth and upholding the law. Where the
greater good of society is not the ultimate goal, justice may be denied to one
who deserves it and given to one who ought to pay the price for violating it.
Then justice itself, in the sense of administering deserved punishment and
reward, loses its meaning.
In the Oromo traditional method of conflict resolution, mediation is
neither a profession nor a means for earning a living. It is the extraordinary
social responsibility that comes with being a member of a given group. No
compensation is paid or received for participating in resolving conflicts.
The mediators render this social service motivated by good will and the
desire to apply principles and conform to social expectations. It is thus
assumed that they treat the case presented to them in good faith and to the
best of their knowledge. What matters for them is the unconditional
resolution of the conflict and the greater good of their society.
Moreover, the possibility that exposes the mediators to corruption is
very limited. Even if there is an opportunity to resolve a conflict unfairly,
the demand for transparency in the mechanism militates against corruption.
The main reason why the Oromo indigenous conflict resolution mechanism
is incorruptible is the care with which mediators are selected and the oath
they take in the name of Waaqa to resolve the conflict in good faith. Elders
with rich experience in mediation very often say, We mediate mainly not
for this or that person, but for the truth and for our soul. Doing good or bad
in such matters is ultimately for or against oneself. To the best of our
knowledge, we do what is good and right mainly for our conscience or soul
180
Tenna Dewo
181
182
Tenna Dewo
the Oromo peacemaking mechanism. Despite the weak points, the Oromo
traditional conflict resolution mechanism, jaarsumma, immensely
contributes to the maintenance and building of peace.
CONCLUSION
This paper has shown that not everything of traditional nature must be
considered as useless and irrelevant and not everything of modern
development should be believed as morally desirable and solution-offering.
Both must be considered in terms of what problems they solve, and
consequently to what extent they make life worth living.
The second important lesson to be learned from this inquiry pertains to
the concept of peace in general. There has been fierce struggle between
peace and war. It is still ongoing. And yet no one knows whether peace or
war wins the battle at the end of the day. The mystery however, is that it is
man who makes both war and peace, and it is again man who suffers from
the destructive effects of war or enjoys the fruits of peace.
Let us put these questions as an invitation for further exploration of
peace and war. If both peace and war are the work of human beings, then
why is war so hated? Why is peace universally most sacred, cherished and
respected? Why then, is peace, which has the support of billions, not able to
win victory over war, which is despised by billions? What is the invisible
force that inspires war? Why is peace that is most desired to triumph over
unwanted war pursued with less vigor and determination?
REFERENCES
Aguilar, Mario. 1996. Keeping the Peace of the Waso Boorana In P. T.
W. Baxter, Jan Hultin, Alesandro Triulzi (eds.), Being and Becoming
Oromo: Historical and Anthropological Inquiries. Uppsala: Nordiska
Afrikainsitutet.
Anderson, Royce. 2004. A Definition of Peace. Peace and Conflict:
Journal of Peace Psychology 10: 2, 101-116.
Bartels, Lambert. 1983. Oromo Religion: Myth and Rites of the Western
Oromo of Ethiopia An Attempt
to Understand. Berlin: Dietrich
Reiner Veralg.
______. 1994. Pilgrimage to a Holy Tree. In D. Brokensha (ed.), A River
of Blessings: Essays in Honor of Paul Baxter. Syracuse: Maxwell
School of Citizenship and Public Affairs.
Bassi, Marco. 1994. Gada as an Integrative Factor of Political
Organization. In D. Brokensha (ed.), A River of Blessings: Essays in
Honor of Paul Baxter. Syracuse: Maxwell School of Citizenship and
Public Affairs.
______. 1996. Powers Ambiguity or the Political Significance of Gada.
In P. T. Baxter, et. al (eds.), Being and Becoming Oromo: Historical
and Anthropological Inquiries. Uppsala: Nordiska
Afrikainstitutet.
183
184
Tenna Dewo
CHAPTER XI
186
Charles C. Verharen
most famous text that supports this assumption is the letter from the
Pharaoh Neferkare to his vizier, Harkhuf. Harkhuf was on a voyage from
Egypt to the extreme south and he reported to his Pharaoh Neferkare that he
found a Twa (formerly called pygmy) in these southern regions. The
Pharaoh issued an urgent reply to Harkhufs report: You have said in this
dispatch of yours that you have brought a Twa of the gods dances from the
land of the horizon-dwellersCome north to the residence at once! Hurry
and bring with you this Twa whom you brought from the land of the
horizon-dwellers, live, hale, and healthy, for the dances of the god, to
gladden the heart, to delight the heart of King Neferkare who lives forever!
(quoted in Asante and Abarry 1996: 451).
This exchange reveals that the Egyptians had the technology for
coastal voyaging on the Red Sea. It is possible that the ancient Ethiopian
Empire of Axum very likely started not only in the Ethiopian highlands but
also on the shores of the Red Sea at Adulis in the first millennium BCE
(Casson 1989). Coincidentally, Adulis was the port through which Meroe
exported its produce (Reader 1997: 204). Archaeologists have dated the
ancient temple of the Axumite culture at Yeha in northern Ethiopia only to
around 500 BCE. It should be noted, however, that very little
archaeological work has been done to establish a time frame here by reason
of the Italian/Ethiopian conflict which dates back to the birth of
archaeology as an academic discipline. Internecine strife between Ethiopia
and Eritrea after the Italians had been removed from the scene continued to
keep the area inaccessible to scholars. The Axumite Empire straddled the
present border between Ethiopia and Eritrea.
The fourth reason for comparing Oromo and ancient Egypt is the
recurrent hypothesis, most forcefully advocated by the Senegalese scholar
Cheikh Anta Diop, that ancient Egypt exerted a strong cultural influence on
more southerly Africa. This hypothesis begs examination in the region
immediately south of Egypt Oromia. Diops research compared Egyptian
and West African cultures at a far distance from Egypt. His claims about
language affiliations between the ancient Egyptian language and his native
Wolof are sketchy at best (1991/1981). African research institutions such as
his own IFAN and Cheikh Anta Diop University in Dakar have had little
incentive and no research funds to pursue his research hypothesis since his
death. The most significant book showing deep affinities between ancient
Egypt and other African cultures, Egypt in Africa (Celenko 1996), is a
relatively recent production and it has so far generated few successors.
Comparing ancient Egyptian and East African cultures would be a means to
test Diops hypothesis.
These four reasons admittedly are highly generalized yet they still
furnish an intriguing, attractive rationale for conducting comparative
research on ancient Egyptian and other African cultures. More specific
reasons for comparing Oromo thought with ancient Egyptian are fourfold.
First, the ontological and ethical analogues between the two cultures are so
strong as not to be coincidental consequently a hypothesis of cultural
187
188
Charles C. Verharen
Kebede does not advert to the fact that Negritude presents a false image of
Africans (Kebede 2004: 219 220).
Kebede holds that Diops virtue is to help Africans feel good about
themselves because their ancestors created the pyramids (ibid. 219). Kebede
does not begin to grasp Diops real virtue. Diop believed that the Egyptians
were African and that Africans can claim the pyramids as part of their
cultural heritage. But that fact is immaterial to Diops Sankofa view of
Egyptian culture: Look back and take it! What is important about Egypt is
not the past, but rather what use Africans can make of ancient Egyptian
culture in the present. The Sankofa bird, an Akan symbol from Ghana,
looks back over its shoulder in order to recapture its history to plan for the
future. Diop believed that the ancient Egyptians laid the foundations for
rationality and science in the Mediterranean basin. In his words, by
renewing ties with Egypt we soon discover an historical perspective of five
thousand years that makes possible the diachronic study, on our land, of all
the scientific disciplines that we are trying to integrate into modern African
thought (1993: 4).
Thus, this paper searches for analogues between ancient Egyptian
thought and traditional Oromo thought in Ethiopia. I am particularly
interested in determining whether there may be an homologous philosophy
shared by many African cultures. What has become of ancient Egyptian
philosophy in Africa over time? Has it been extinguished, like ancient
Egyptian culture itself? Or has it been transformed into other African
variations readily accessible to those who keep their eyes open to the real
Africa, not the Africa of myth and distorted history? And what influence
might other parts of Africa have had on ancient Egypt?
Striking parallels between ancient Egyptian and Oromo thought may
be explained by cultural diffusion from ancient Egypt to todays Ethiopia
region. But the opposite must be considered as well. Some scholars argue
that Oromo culture derives from an earlier Cushitic culture that stretched
from present day Ethiopia to ancient Egypt to ancient India three thousand
years ago, with connections to ancient Egyptian culture (Megerssa 1995:
11-12; Kassam 1995: 10). Since ancient Egyptian thought may be dated
back some 5000 years due to specialized methods of record-keeping,
diffusion from the Cushites to the Egyptians is at present difficult to
investigate using current methodologies. The papers scope cannot consider
these wider questions. Its principal purpose is to furnish good reasons for
initiating a comparative research program on ancient Egyptian and Oromo
philosophy.
My interest in traditional Oromo philosophy started while on
sabbatical in Ethiopia at Addis Ababa University doing research on
Kebedes program for decolonization of Africa. My motive was to start a
research program on traditional Ethiopian philosophy. One of my
colleagues, Bekele Gutema, an Oromo who is keenly interested in Oromo
philosophy, introduced me to Gemetchu Megerssa, an Oromo and a social
anthropologist who wrote his dissertation on Oromo world view. I was
189
190
Charles C. Verharen
191
192
Charles C. Verharen
philosophies push that principle to the limit by collapsing the creator and
the creation into a single existent. Ancient Egyptian philosophy is more
extreme on this point than Oromo philosophy under Megerssas
interpretation. The Nun, the primordial chaotic water of the Egyptians, has
no originating principle other than itself. Like the hydrogen atoms
comprising the Big Bang of contemporary cosmology, the Nun
transforms itself into a highly organized universe organized around the sun.
However, the universe collapses back into the Nun to start the cycle all over
again, as The ancient Egyptian Book of the Dead states in Spell 175, i. e.,
while life shall continue for millions on millions of years, a life-time of
millions of years, in the end the Nun will destroy all that I have made; the
earth shall return to the Abyss, to the surging flood, as in its original state
(Faulkner 2005: 201). The Egyptian model follows the same dynamic as a
contemporary cosmological model that collapses the universe back into
itself to start another Big Bang by reason of gravitational force (Hornung
2001/1999). The Oromo model as interpreted by Megerssa postulates a
creative force outside of Walaabu, the primordial water. Megerssa insists
on the unknowable and irreducible nature of the creator of the universe in
the Oromo tradition.
Nonetheless, these distinctions between Oromo and ancient Egyptian
philosophy are vanishingly small in the face of their distance from dualist
or pluralist philosophies. Scholars like Martin Bernal (1989) who trace the
origins of ancient Greek philosophy to ancient Egypt pass over the radical
division between the two schools of thought. Against Egyptian holism,
Plato postulates an ontology of irreducible principles: at one extreme, the
form as perfect, non-physical patterns, and at other a chaotic physical
universe. A divine craftsman organizes the universe as we know it out of
chaos using the forms of a divine blueprint.
To look beyond the Mediterranean basin, Hindu philosophy espouses a
nominal holism in claiming that all reality reduces to a single principle,
Brahman. The manifest plurality of the universe as we experience it is
explained away as an illusion, maya. Hinduism achieves its holism only At
the cost of denying the reality of our manifest experience. However, Taoism
in East Asia and Spinoza in Europe show that the holistic philosophy is not
unique to Africa (Rhadakrishnan and Moore, 1967 and Chan, 1969). An
investigation into Oromo and ancient Egyptian ethics can suggest that the
ontological similarities of these philosophies may not be accidental.
OROMO ETHICS
Megerssa defines Waaqa as the Totality of Nature (1993: 139).
Every philosophy that conflates the creator and the created faces the
problem of explaining evil in the universe (Verharen 1998). Evil can take
two forms natural disasters that cause human suffering and suffering that
humans inflict on themselves. Megerssa claims that the Oromo explain the
first kind of evil as intrinsic to nature. As expression of the totality of
193
nature, such disasters are manifestations of Gods best efforts to keep the
universe together. Hence the Oromo accept the conditions imposed on
them by Waaqa; they regard natural disasters as events which occur for
the good of the whole (ibid). The point of nature is the harmony of the
whole which transcends the parts (ibid). Whatever happens is an
expression of the Totality of Nature, Universal Nature, and must therefore
be right (Ibid).
Evil caused by humans in the universe arises from human incapacity
to act in harmony with the cosmic whole, in as much as it is only man
who fails to act in accordance with the natural laws set down by Waaqa
(Ibid., 140). Humans can choose between good and evil since they have a
natural capacity to tell the two apart. Waaqa in the form of Universal
Nature has made humans into moral agent[s] as conscious
participant[s] in the natural process of the universe (Ibid.).
Morality flows out of the nature of the universe, the totality of which
is God himself. Ontology, the study of what exists, axiology, the study of
what is valuable, are inseparable for the Oromo. Human laws must be
derived from natural laws. In Megerssas words, thelaws made by man
thus act as a social control, preventing evil deeds from overwhelming the
harmony of the cosmic whole (Ibid.). The Oromo characterize the totality
of nature in an anthropomorphic way. Human sins against natures harmony
release the anger of the Totality of Nature (Ibid.).
The concept of harmony is key to understanding Oromo ethics. It is
also the foundation of ancient Egyptian ethics in the principle of maat as I
shall discuss more fully at the conclusion of this section on ethics. The
Oromo parallel to maat is found in the concept of nagaa or peace and
harmony. Nagaa is achieved by following safuu or the moral code. The
moral code dictates the proper order for biological and social development,
which is termed finna. The concept of finna or fidnaa is given a biological
exposition in Megerssas interview of Dabassa Guyyo, an Oromo oral
historian and philosopher.
Oromo ethics are grounded in the biological concept of growth and
guddina. The metaphor of growth extends to the development of social
groups. The general path of biological development and human growth
follows an order called finna. That order may be good or bad.
Guddina literally means an increase in what is given, as in the
growth of hair or tree. Growth following the harmony or order of the
Totality of Nature leads to well-being or gabbina. The root meaning of
gabbina is growing fat. This is an apt metaphor for groups whose food
supplies are dependent on the weathers vagaries. The more general sense
of the word indicates biological growth or human development in accord
with greatest potential. An organism, including human organisms, in a state
of well-being grows naturally to express its nature. This natural growth is
called ballina. The organism growing in accord with its environment is said
to be in a state of harmony or badhaadhaa. Badhaadhaa is defined as a
state of having gabbina, guddina, and ballina favored by conditions such
194
Charles C. Verharen
as peace and all other conditions necessary for the well-being of life
(Megerssa, personal communication, 2007). Badhaadhaa includes both
individual organisms and societies whose people, property, custom and law
are so complete that they increase themselves (Ibid.).
Organisms in harmony with their environments naturally reproduce
themselves through acts of replication called hormaata. Such organisms
grow through a repetition of rounds, called dagaaga, that change the state
of the organism or society while still preserving its identity. Dagaaga
literally means a rams horn. The metaphor of the spiral growth of the
horn captures its identity in difference. Organisms or societies that
successfully pass through the six stages have the power to transmit
themselves into new territories in a process called daga-horaa. (Megerssa
1993: 121).
What is true for organisms is also true for human societies. Groups
that find exemplary means for living in harmony with the Totality of Nature
become such powerful examples of the will of Waaqa that other groups
rush to imitate them. The laws, seera, and customs, aadaa, of such groups
flow directly from the harmony of nature (Ibid. 122).
The totality of the seven steps is called finna in the Oromo language.
The word may derive from the root fin which means embryo in the Arsi
dialect of Oromo (Megerssa, personnal communication, June 14, 2007).
Finna may be both good and bad. Expressions of the seven steps of growth
which are out of harmony with the Totality of Nature are in an evil state of
finna. Megerssas informant, Dabassa Guyyo, insists that contemporary
Oromo peoples exist in an evil (hamtu in Oromo) state of finna because
their economic, political, and cultural subjection to the Amhara minorities
of Ethiopia (Ibid., 127).
That Oromo concept of safuu determines whether a finna is good or
evil. Finna specifies the concept of order or development, and safuu
dictates the quality of that order. In Megerssas words safuu provides the
moral and ethical code according to which events, whether at personal,
social or cosmic level take place (Megerssa 1993, 138). Waaqa generates
the ethical code and propagates it through ayyaana. Living according to the
code of safuu is the only means to a full and happy life (Ibid.).
The measure of an individual or societys ability to live according to
the code of safuu is found in the Oromo concept of nagaa, which is defined
literally as peace but carries extended meanings such as harmony,
order, balance, justice (Dewo 2008). Organisms are at peace with
their environments and one another when they contribute to mutual
flourishing. Societies must possess both an internal and external harmony
with respect to their environments and their neighbors (Kelbessa 2005). The
Oromo Gadaa system (the traditional socio-political structure of the Oromo
based on generation sets) aims at sustaining peace through its extensive
conflict resolution mechanism such as the jaarsummaa, a council of elders
that focuses on mediation (Dewo 2008, 159-162; Legesse 2001, 1973).
195
196
Charles C. Verharen
began in the centuries before Christ. Its many schools have in common the
view that a specialized kind of knowledge is required to understand the
nature of life and the universe in order to achieve salvation (King 2003).
One of the most important Gnostics was Valentinus who was born and
educated in Egypt in the second century C. E. Unlike most other Gnostic
figures, Valentinus subscribed to a monistic philosophy. The Gospel of
Truth, usually ascribed to Valentinus, pictures God as pleroma, the fullness
and unity of true existence, or as a bythos a depth out of which all existence
arises. God is shrouded in mystery and can only be known through his
creation. God as pleroma or bythos creates the universe through emanation.
Any sense of a separation between God and his creation derives from
human ignorance. Salvation is achieved through returning to the one an
act achieved by coming to knowledge of oneself as one with God.
Valentinus left Alexandria in Egypt for Rome where he was said to be
a candidate for bishop of Rome. Accounts differ as to whether he refused
the position or was not elected. His philosophy is very much at odds with
dualistic Christian philosophy. Valentinus heresy faded with the
overpowering success of orthodox Christianity in the Mediterranean
basin, and was completely obliterated with the Muslim conquest of North
Africa (Rudolph 1983).
As monistic, Valentinus version of Gnosticism is unique. However, as
a holistic philosophy, it is directly analogous to ancient Egyptian and by
extension to Oromo philosophy as well. However, scholarship on
Gnosticism in general and Valentinus in particular does not carefully
address the hypothesis that Valentinus belief may be grounded in ancient
Egyptian philosophy. A recent review of the critical scholarship on
Gnosticism acknowledges that he was born in Egypt in the second century
C. E., but the review makes no effort to connect his thought with ancient
Egyptian thought (King 2003). Although older researchers viewed
Gnosticism as arising as a Christian heresy, scholarly consensus now
indicates that the movement predated Christianity. The most often cited
origins are Greek, Jewish, Persian and Indian. Very few scholars cite
ancient Egyptian thought as an inspiration for Gnosticism. An exception is
the 19th century scholar Emile Amelineau (1887) who argues that ancient
Egyptian thought is a primary influence not only on Gnosticism but also on
Platos Timaeus.
Valentinus is not alone in failing to attract comparative research
between his philosophy and that of ancient Egypt. A later and more
heralded philosopher, Plotinus, also born in Egypt but in the third century
C. E., produced a monistic philosophy that has come to be called neoPlatonic. Certainly Plotinus wrote in Greek, but the basic tenet of his
philosophy is monistic, quite unlike that of Plato. While Plato insists upon a
rigid demarcation between spirit and matter, Plotinus holds that the
universe emanates from God in the same fashion as light proceeds from
the sun (Gerson 1996). Unlike Plato, Plotinus follows the tradition of the
pre-Socratic philosophers who argue for a monistic philosophy that has its
197
198
Charles C. Verharen
rather than coincidence, then this research program would make a strong
case for further comparative work in East and West Africa.
The practical objective of this research program is to discover a
philosophy that can rescue Africa and the world from imminent catastrophe.
We now confront the bankruptcy (Amiri Barakas term) of world
philosophies that can no longer serve as inspirations for how we should live
as a global community, intent on passing life on to our childrens children.
The global threats to life we now face result in part from the failures of
world-historical philosophies and religions to find the meaning of life in life
itself. Powerful, contemporary versions of the religions of The Book
Judaism, Christianity, and Islam present life as a test rather than an end in
itself, but space does not allow careful consideration of whether these
contemporary versions are faithful to their progenitors. Hinduism regards
life an illusion. Buddhism advocates transcending desire- a defining
characteristic of life to stop suffering.
In the spirit of looking for Messay Kebedes inspiring myth out of
Africa, let us consider for the future the common message from both the
ancient Egyptians and the Oromo (Verharen 2008). Both advocate a
philosophy of holism, the conflation of ontology and axiology. That holism
underpins the famous democracy of the Oromo Gadaa system as well as the
Oromo respect for the environment and its inhabitants. Workineh
Kelbessas (2005) research on the rehabilitation of indigenous
environmental ethics in Africa demonstrates the practical consequences of
Oromo holism. Maulana Karengas (2003) research on Maatian ethical
responsibilities to strangers, women, and ecosystems illustrates the
revolutionary character of ancient Egyptian thought for its time and for
our own. The philosophical principles of maat and nagaa have
demonstrated their practical force over long periods of time. Maat was the
controlling element of ancient Egyptian philosophy for three thousand
years. Nagaas longevity is a matter for further research, but its force is as
old as Oromia. Whether it may equal maats longevity is a key question for
this research program. What is beyond dispute is that together the
philosophies of maat and nagaa promise an African model for passing life
on to future generations in these perilous times.
REFERENCES
Amelineau, Emile. 1887. Essai sur le Gnosticisme Egyptien, ses
Developments et son Origine Egyptienne. Paris: Annales du Musee
Guimet. Vol. xiv.
Asante, Molefi and Abarry, Abu, eds. 1996. African Intellectual Heritage:
A Book of Sources. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
Assman, Jan. 1998. Mosses the Egyptian: The Memory of Egypt in Western
Monotheism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bartels, Lambert. 1983. Oromo Religion: Myths and Rites of Western
Ethiopia, An Attempt to Understand. Berlin: Dietrich Reimer Verlag.
199
Baxter, Paul and Kassam, Aneesa. 2005. Performing the Soodduu Ritual:
Introduction to the Special Issue of the Journal Oromo Studies in
Memory of Father Lambert Bartels, Journal of Oromo Studies 12:
1&2, 1-20.
Bernal, Martin. 1989. Black Athena: The Afro-Asiatic Roots of Classical
Civilization (The Foundation of Ancient Greece 1785- 1985). Vol.1.
New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Casson, Lionel. 1989. The Periplus Maris Erythraei. Princton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Celenko, Theodore. ed. 1996. Egypt in Africa. Bloomington, IN: University
of Indiana.
Chan, Wing-Tsit, trans. 1969. A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Dewo, Tenna. 2008. The Concept of Peace in the Oromo Gadaa System:
Its Mechanisms and Moral Dimension. Journal of Oromo Studies 15:
1 (March), 139-179.
Diamond, Jared. 1997. Guns, Germs and Steel: The Fates of Human
Societies. New York: Norton.
Diop, Cheik Anta. 1991/1981. Civilization or Barbarism: An Authentic
Anthropology. Trans. Ya-Lengi Meema. Chicago: Lawrence Hill.
Fanon, Frantz. 1963. This Africa to Come. Toward the African Revolution:
Political Essays. Trans. H. Chevalier. New York: Grove 177-190.
Faulkner, Raymond. O., trans. 2005/1972. Ancient Egyptian Book of the
Dead. New York: Barnes and Noble.
Gerson, Lloyd P., ed. 1996. The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gutema, Bekele. 2004. Introducing Intercultural Philosophy, EJOSSAH:
Ethiopian Journal of the Social Sciences and Humanities 2: 2,
(December), 29-49.
Hassen, Mohammed. 1990. The Oromo of Ethiopia: A History 1570- 1860.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hornung, Erik. 2001/1999. The Secret Lore of Egypt: Its Impact on the
West. D. Lorton, trans. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
______. 1990/1982. Conceptions of God in Ancient Egypt: The One and the
Many. Trans. J. Baines. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
______. 1982/1971. The Valley of the Kings: Horizon of Eternity. Trans. D.
Warburton. New York: Timken.
Jalata, Asafa. 2002. Fighting Against the Injustice of the State and
Globalization: Comparing the African American and Oromo
Movements. NY: Palgrave
Jonas, Hans. 1967. Delimitation of the Gnostic Phenomenon Typological
and Historical, in Le Origini dello Gnosticismo Colloquio di Messina
13-18 Aprile 1966, pp. 90-108. Ed. Ugo Bianchi. SHR XII. Leiden: E.
J. Brill.
Karenga, Maulana. 2003. Maat: The Moral Ideal in Ancient Egypt. New
York and Oxford: Routledge.
200
Charles C. Verharen
201
CHAPTER XII
204
Teodros Kiros
205
206
Teodros Kiros
Rather, the expectations are that (1) the person is going to make an effort to
be precise, because her intention is to be just, and (2) that her eyes are just,
or that she prays that they would be. (1) and (2) are the requirements; the
rest is left to moral imagination.
She cuts the pies, and it turns out that all the pieces appear to be equal,
and when the guests arrive, they randomly pick the pieces, and appear to be
satisfied. What we have here is a display of justice in the Aristotelian sense,
in which justice is defined as an activity that is guided by a measure of
equality, and equality itself is manifest in the attempt at being fair to
everyone in this case, an attempt to be fair to the guests, without their ever
knowing that they are being worked on. They judge the event as illuminated
by justice, and as uplifting.
Generalizing to a higher level, what we can say is that any economic
form must be guided with justice and that all the commodities that human
beings should want must be distributed with such a standard, the standard
of justice as fairness. Given justice as fairness, commodity A can be
distributed between persons B and C, in such an equitable way that B and C
share commodity A by getting the same amount at any time, any place and
for a good reason.
III
Compassion is another feature of Maat; indeed, it is one of the
cardinal moral forms for the new moral economy that I am theorizing here.
Compassion is to moral economy as greed is to capitalism. One cannot
imagine capitalism without the salient principle of greed, and similarly, one
cannot imagine moral economy without the original principle of
compassion. The modern world, being what it is, is divided by class, race,
gender, ethnicity and groups. Out of these divisions, it is class division
which is the most decisive, as it is also the one that seems to be so natural
that we cannot surmount the pain and agony that it produces. In a classdivided world, compassion is the least present, since there is no compelling
reason for individuals to be compassionate if they are not naturally so, or so
inclined. In such cases, though, compassion could be learned, either by
example or directly through teaching.
An example may elucidate the place of compassion in moral economy.
It is summer, and exhaustingly hot. People that you encounter are hottempered too. Everybody is on the edge, including you. You happen to be a
coffee-lover, so there you are standing behind a long line of people to get
your fix. The heat has made you impatient, and you are ready to explode on
anything around you. You are naturally generous, but not this day. Shortly
before you leave the coffee shop, a homeless person smiles at you and tries
to talk to you, hoping that you will understand the purpose of the
conversation. Of course you understand, but you ignore him and walk by.
But then something bothers you, and you came back to the coffee shop and
generously give the man what he wanted. You are proud of yourself,
207
because you have done what generosity demands, that you control your
temper and perform the morally correct action. Surely, you say to yourself,
it was not easy, but you did it.
Now you wonder what all this means, and why you did it. The answer
is obvious. Indeed, it is because you are really a compassionate human
being. You had no obligation to pay attention to that person. He is not
related to you, he is not an ex-friend that fortune turned against, nor did you
do it so as to be a media-hero. Your action is morally worthy only because
you have internalized compassion. To you compassion comes quite
naturally. It is part of your moral frame. Any repeated action becomes a
habit. So compassionate action comes habitually to you. You rarely fight it.
Rather, you exuberantly let it lead your way, as it eventually did on that hot
and difficult day. But even on that day you conquered the temptation of
doubt, and excessive self-love, by the moral force of compassion. That is
why you corrected yourself when you were briefly but powerfully tempted
by forgetfulness, and returned to do the morally right thing.
Compassion is morally compelling when it is extended to a total other,
who has nothing to do with our lives, beyond awaiting our moral attention.
It is much easier to be compassionate towards a loved one, a friend, a
relative and even an acquaintance; harder is the task when the subject is a
real other, such as that person by the coffee shop. In order for any action to
be morally worthy, the motive must be pure, and the purity is measured by
the quality and quantity of the compassion that is extended to any needy
human being, uncontaminated by external motives, such as love, friendship,
acquaintance and relation. It is in this particular way that I am arguing that
compassion serves Maat.
IV
Tolerance is another crucial feature of Moral Economy. In fact, it
could easily be argued that it is an indispensable organizing principle,
which works in tandem with loving kindness. Just as we cannot love a
person except illusorily without respecting her, so we cannot live with
one another without tolerating each others needs, habits, likes and dislikes.
In the economic sphere tolerance is subtly pertinent. We cannot readily
sense its inner working unless we pay attention to its musings at the
workplace, as we interact with one another as managers and workers.
Consider the following example to underscore the point. There is this
worker who does things in ways that many people find annoying. She
customarily comes late to work; she procrastinates; she spreads papers, cans
and food stuffs all around her; sometimes she cannot even find herself
amidst the dirt, the pile and the dust. Yet, and this is the point, whatever
tasks she performs are carried out as flawlessly as is humanly possible. Her
supervisor has agonized over what to do with her and has often
contemplated firing her. Mollified by the elegance of her work and his
loving-kindness towards her, he decides to keep her. He has promised
208
Teodros Kiros
209
210
Teodros Kiros
CONTRIBUTORS
Bekele Gutema, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Addis Ababa
University, Addis Ababa, Ethiopia
Charles C. Verharen, Professor of Philosophy, Howard University,
Washington, D.C., USA
Daniel Smith (), Associate Professor of Philosophy at Addis Ababa
University until his untimely death in January 2012
Ezkiel Gebissa, Associate Professor of History, Kettering University,
Flint, Michigan, USA
Gail M. Presbey, Professor of Philosophy, University of Detroit
Mercy, Detroit, Michigan, USA
Messay Kebede, Professor of Philosophy, University of Dayton,
Dayton, Ohio, USA
Taddesse Berisso, Associate Professor of Social Anthropology, Addis
Ababa University, Addis Ababa, Ethiopia
Taddesse Lencho, Lecturer, Faculty of Law, Addis Ababa University,
Addis Ababa, Ethiopia
Tenna Dewo, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Addis Ababa
University, Addis Ababa, Ethiopia
Teodros Kiros, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Department of
Liberal Arts, Berklee College of Music, Boston, USA
INDEX
A
D
Darwin, 75, 77
decolonization, 37, 41, 50, 72, 8182, 187-188
deconstruction, 27, 40, 51
democracy, v, 3-4, 14, 27, 30-33,
48, 90, 95-98, 100-101, 104,
106, 109-113, 159, 162, 183,
198, 200-201
Derrida, Jacques, 29, 33
Descartes, ix-xi, 12, 70-71, 79, 140
Dewo, Tenna., 199
Diamond, Jared, 199
Diop, Cheik Anta, 89, 199
Du Bois, W.E.B., 9, 14
Dussel, H, 33
E
Einstein, 13, 76-79
Engels, Friedrich, 52
episteme, 50
ethics, iii, 1-2, 12, 33, 90, 153-156,
184, 197, 200-201, 209
Ethiopia, i-iii, vii-xii, 2-3, 14, 1718, 29-32, 54, 67-72, 83-90, 9697, 103, 111, 118, 122, 133-136,
139-140, 145, 148-156, 159,
161, 176, 180, 182-188, 194,
198-201, 211
ethnophilosophy, 3, 37, 47, 50, 8184
Eurocentrism, 17, 23, 49, 201
Evans-Pritchard, E.E, 67
F
Fanon, Frantz, 199
Faulkner, Raymond, 199, 209
Feminist criticism, 141
Foucault, M, 33
214
Index
G
Gadaa, iv-v, 2, 4, 14, 54-55, 61,
65-67, 96-99, 103-111, 130,
135, 159, 165-179, 194-195,
198-199
Gebissa, Ezkiel, 1, 4, 211
Geez, 70, 139, 142-144
Gemetchu Megerssa, 3, 4, 67, 70,
83, 84, 131, 163, 167, 175, 185,
188, 200
gnosticism, 70, 87
Guji, iii, v, 3, 53-68, 170
Gumi, 14, 97-98, 103-110
Gutema, Bekele, 1-iii, v, 1-2, 28,
89, 188-189, 199, 211
H
Hallen, Barry, 27
Habermas, J., 33
Haile Selassie, 17, 18, 27
Harding, Sandra., 154
Hassen, Mohammed, 134, 199
Hatata, xi, 70, 71
Hegel, Georg, Wilhelm, Friedrich,
52
Heidegger, 12, 14
Historically Black Colleges and
Universities, 2, 9
historicity, 3, 40, 43, 49
Hornung, Erik, 4, 89, 199
Horton, 117, 119, 120, 122, 130,
134
Houngnikpo, Mathurin, 27
Hountondji, P, 27, 33
I
imagination, 12, 13, 14, 44, 69, 72,
73, 74, 76, 161, 190, 197, 205
Irele, Abiola, 28
J
N
jaarssummaa, 173
Jesus, 71, 121, 129-133, 136, 203
Index
Negritude, 51, 70, 73, 83, 187
Newton, 13, 77, 79
Nietzsche, 3, 46, 47, 52
Nubia, 185, 200
number nine, 3, 53, 55, 56, 57, 58,
59, 60, 63, 64, 65, 66, 67
Nun, 76, 87, 191, 192
O
OConnor, David B, 200
ontology, 12, 80, 85, 189-192, 198
Oromo, perssim
Oruka, Henry, Odera, xii, 30, 70,
83, 89, 90, 155, 200
P
Pascal, 52, 71
peace, ix, 4-5, 14, 71, 80, 147, 159182, 193-195
Presbey, Gail, iv-v, xiii, 4, 155,
211
Protestant, 52, 118-123, 126-129,
132-134
Punt, 84, 185
215
Q
Qaalluu, 54-55, 112, 165
Qallu, 14, 97-98, 103
S
safuu, 4, 128, 175, 193-195
216
Index
Z
Zara Yaqob, 27-28, 70-71, 90
Zaslavsky, Claudia, 68
Zitelmann, Thomas, 91, 136, 201
218
Publications
*****************************************************************
CULTURAL HERITAGE AND CONTEMPORARY CHANGE
Series I. Culture and Values
I.1 Research on Culture and Values: Intersection of Universities, Churches
and Nations. George F. McLean, ed. ISBN 0819173533 (paper);
081917352-5 (cloth).
I.2 The Knowledge of Values: A Methodological Introduction to the Study
of Values; A. Lopez Quintas, ed. ISBN 081917419x (paper);
0819174181 (cloth).
219
I.3 Reading Philosophy for the XXIst Century. George F. McLean, ed.
ISBN 0819174157 (paper); 0819174149 (cloth).
I.4 Relations Between Cultures. John A. Kromkowski, ed. ISBN
1565180089 (paper); 1565180097 (cloth).
I.5 Urbanization and Values. John A. Kromkowski, ed. ISBN 1565180100
(paper); 1565180119 (cloth).
I.6 The Place of the Person in Social Life. Paul Peachey and John A. Kromkowski, eds. ISBN 1565180127 (paper); 156518013-5 (cloth).
I.7 Abrahamic Faiths, Ethnicity and Ethnic Conflicts. Paul Peachey, George
F. McLean and John A. Kromkowski, eds. ISBN 1565181042
(paper).
I.8 Ancient Western Philosophy: The Hellenic Emergence. George F.
McLean and Patrick J. Aspell, eds. ISBN 156518100X (paper).
I.9 Medieval Western Philosophy: The European Emergence. Patrick J.
Aspell, ed. ISBN 1565180941 (paper).
I.10 The Ethical Implications of Unity and the Divine in Nicholas of Cusa.
David L. De Leonardis. ISBN 1565181123 (paper).
I.11 Ethics at the Crossroads: 1.Normative Ethics and Objective Reason.
George F. McLean, ed. ISBN 1565180224 (paper).
I.12 Ethics at the Crossroads: 2.Personalist Ethics and Human Subjectivity.
George F. McLean, ed. ISBN 1565180240 (paper).
I.13 The Emancipative Theory of Jrgen Habermas and Metaphysics.
Robert Badillo. ISBN 1565180429 (paper); 1565180437 (cloth).
I.14 The Deficient Cause of Moral Evil According to Thomas Aquinas.
Edward Cook. ISBN 1565180704 (paper).
I.15 Human Love: Its Meaning and Scope, a Phenomenology of Gift and
Encounter. Alfonso Lopez Quintas. ISBN 1565180747 (paper).
I.16 Civil Society and Social Reconstruction. George F. McLean, ed. ISBN
1565180860 (paper).
I.17 Ways to God, Personal and Social at the Turn of Millennia: The Iqbal
Lecture, Lahore. George F. McLean. ISBN 1565181239 (paper).
I.18 The Role of the Sublime in Kants Moral Metaphysics. John R.
Goodreau. ISBN 1565181247 (paper).
I.19 Philosophical Challenges and Opportunities of Globalization. Oliva
Blanchette, Tomonobu Imamichi and George F. McLean, eds. ISBN
1565181298 (paper).
I.20 Faith, Reason and Philosophy: Lectures at The al-Azhar, Qom,
Tehran, Lahore and Beijing; Appendix: The Encyclical Letter: Fides
et Ratio. George F. McLean. ISBN 156518130 (paper).
I.21 Religion and the Relation between Civilizations: Lectures on
Cooperation between Islamic and Christian Cultures in a Global
Horizon. George F. McLean. ISBN 1565181522 (paper).
I.22 Freedom, Cultural Traditions and Progress: Philosophy in Civil
Society and Nation Building, Tashkent Lectures, 1999. George F.
McLean. ISBN 1565181514 (paper).
220
Publications
221
222
Publications
223
IIA.15 Islam and Its Quest for Peace: Jihad, Justice and Education.
Mustafa Kyl. ISBN 1565181808 (paper).
IIA.16 Islamic Thought on the Existence of God: Contributions and
Contrasts with Contemporary Western Philosophy of Religion. Cafer
S. Yaran. ISBN 1565181921 (paper).
IIA.17 Hermeneutics, Faith, and Relations between Cultures: Lectures in
Qom, Iran. George F. McLean. ISBN 1565181913 (paper).
IIA.18 Change and Essence: Dialectical Relations between Change and
Continuity in the Turkish Intellectual Tradition. Sinasi Gunduz and
Cafer S. Yaran, eds. ISBN 1565182227 (paper).
IIA. 19 Understanding Other Religions: Al-Biruni and Gadamers Fusion
of Horizons. Kemal Ataman. ISBN 9781565182523 (paper).
Series III. Asian Philosophical Studies
III.1 Man and Nature: Chinese Philosophical Studies, I. Tang Yi-jie, Li
Zhen, eds. ISBN 0819174130 (paper); 0819174122 (cloth).
III.2 Chinese Foundations for Moral Education and Character Development: Chinese Philosophical Studies, II. Tran van Doan, ed. ISBN
1565180321 (paper); 156518033X (cloth).
III.3 Confucianism, Buddhism, Taoism, Christianity and Chinese Culture:
Chinese Philosophical Studies, III. Tang Yijie. ISBN 1565180348
(paper); 156518035-6 (cloth).
III.4 Morality, Metaphysics and Chinese Culture (Metaphysics, Culture and
Morality, I). Vincent Shen and Tran van Doan, eds. ISBN
1565180275 (paper); 156518026-7 (cloth).
III.5 Tradition, Harmony and Transcendence. George F. McLean. ISBN
1565180313 (paper); 156518030-5 (cloth).
III.6 Psychology, Phenomenology and Chinese Philosophy: Chinese
Philosophical Studies, VI. Vincent Shen, Richard Knowles and Tran
Van Doan, eds. ISBN 1565180453 (paper); 1565180445 (cloth).
III.7 Values in Philippine Culture and Education: Philippine Philosophical
Studies, I. Manuel B. Dy, Jr., ed. ISBN 1565180412 (paper);
156518040-2 (cloth).
III.7A The Human Person and Society: Chinese Philosophical Studies,
VIIA. Zhu Dasheng, Jin Xiping and George F. McLean, eds. ISBN
1565180887.
III.8 The Filipino Mind: Philippine Philosophical Studies II. Leonardo N.
Mercado. ISBN 156518064X (paper); 156518063-1 (cloth).
III.9 Philosophy of Science and Education: Chinese Philosophical Studies
IX. Vincent Shen and Tran Van Doan, eds. ISBN 1565180763
(paper); 156518075-5 (cloth).
III.10 Chinese Cultural Traditions and Modernization: Chinese
Philosophical Studies, X. Wang Miaoyang, Yu Xuanmeng and
George F. McLean, eds. ISBN 1565180682 (paper).
224
Publications
225
226
Publications
227
228
Publications
229
230
Publications
231
232
Publications
233