Affordance Gibson PDF
Affordance Gibson PDF
Affordance Gibson PDF
0021-8308 82.50
The concept of affordance is one of the most controversial and debated features
of James J. Gibsons ecological approach to perception. With this concept
Gibson offers a new approach to a knotty problem in perception theory;
namely, the problem of accounting for meaning in perceptual experience. The
controversial nature of the affordance concept stems largely from the fact
of its growing out of an approach to perception that is a significant departure
from standard formulations. The aims of this paper are two-fold. The first
is to provide a detailed analysis of the concept of affordance, and in the
process to draw out some of its implicit theoretical claims concerning the
nature of perception. This analysis will be presented in the first part of the
paper. Exploration of the implicit assumptions of the affordance concept will
reveal the underlying intentional character of the ecological approach to
perception.
The second aim of the paper is to consider the applicability of the affordance
concept to features of the human world whose meanings are sociocultural in
origin. As will be clear shortly, affordances seem most plausibly applied to
features of the environment that have species-specificor transcultural significance. However, the concept of affordance has sometimes been applied to
features that have significance only within a particular sociocultural context.
These applications have been a source of some debate. I will argue that this
extension of the affordance concept is warranted once affordances are carefully
grounded in an intentional analysis of perception. Moreover, the resolution of
this controversy will provide the basis for maintaining the broad and
fundamental character of affordances in perceptual experience. Toward these
ends, we will examine in parts two and three of the paper some issues concerning
intentionality in perception and its relationship to Gibsons ecological theory of
perception.
There is a need to study the perception of surfaces with a realistic attitude as well as a
phenomenological attitude. (Gibson, 1979b, p. I 12)
Affordances defined
Gibson (1979a) defines affordances most directly in the following way: The
affordances of the environment are what it ofers the animal, what it provides
or furnishes, either for good or ill (p. I 2 7 ) . The affordances of a given place
in the environment establish for an individual what actions are possible there
and what the consequences of those actions are. For example, a surface of
support at approximately knee height to the individual affords sitting on. A seat
is a feature of the environment specifiable in terms of properties of the object
(i.e., it has a particular mass, height, and width); but its parameters as an
affordance are delimited with reference to a specific individual of a particular
weight, leg length, and girth. As a result, what constitutes a seat (or affords
sitting-on) will vary among individuals with significantly different body scaling.
The relative nature of seat affordances can be illustrated by the fact that a
surface perceived as a seat by a young child may not be perceived as such by an
adult. Specifically, a foot stool may be perceived as a seat by a child and not by
an adult as a function ofleg length, and a cardboard box may be perceived as a
potential seat by a child but not by an adult because of their differences in
weight.
Affordances, then, are properties of the environment taken with reference to
an individual. As such, they have both objective and subjective qualities.
They are objective in the sense that they are facts of the environment;
what constitutes, e.g., a seat, depends on the physical characteristics of an
object .
Harry H 4 t
What [an environmental feature] affords the observer is determined by its material substance and
its shape, size, rigidity, motion, etc. What it means and what it is are not separate, as we have been
led to believe. And the observer who perceives the substance and the surface of anything has
thereby perceived what it affords. (Gibson, 1972, p. 410)
region that analyses ofanimal and environment mutually share. That is, some
of the most psychologically significant phenomena are relational in nature.
The hallmark of an entity with a relational quality is that its specification
implies a second entity. Many of an animals structural and behavioral
characteristics have this quality of pointing beyond themselves to implicate
particular characteristics of the environment. For example, the sensory
sensitivities of an animal bracket some types of physical energy in the
environment, among the variety ofenergies that can be identified, as well as the
range of energy within those categories to which the animal is responsive. So
humans, like all terrestrial animals, are sensitive to electromagnetic radiation,
and humans in particular, (and unlike, e.g., some insects) are responsive only to
wavelengths between approximately 400 and 700 nanometers. Thus, a
description of human visual sensitivities implies a specification of some portion
of the total environment, and conversely that particular portion of the
electromagnetic spectrum has significance because of its relation to human
vision. That is, both factors are relationally specified. The same analysis can be
performed for other aspects of the animals structure, such as other receptor
sensitivities.
Likewise, the behavioral capacities of an animal co-implicate particular
characteristics of the environment. For example, the behavior ofgrasping in an
animal means that detached objects are potentially significant features of the
environment (if, that is, the object is smaller than the handspan). Further,
sitting co-implies places that afford sitting-on, striding co-implies places that
can be stepped across or stepped up onto, and so on. Each ofthese actions is only
possible with respect to environmental features which permit them, and these
particular features are significant in relation to these actions, i.e., each factor is
re1ationally specified.
Many characteristics of an animal do not have this relational quality. Most
neurophysiological features, as well as hypothetical mental operations, can be
described without simultaneously implicating features of the environment. For
example, biochemical characteristics of cell receptors sites or hippocampal
functioning, on the one hand, or the functional characteristics of hypothesized
memory processes, on the other hand, can be considered independently of
environmental conditions. Therefore, only some aspects of an animals
functioning can be characterized as relational, and these relational processes
should be the particular province of psychology, (or at least an ecologically
oriented psychology), as opposed to neurophysiology or cognitive science,
respectively .
It can be seen then that specification of certain structural and behavioral
characteristics of an animal implicates and delimits that portion of the total
environment comprising the animals (or the species) econiche. These characteristics of an animal have a relational or transactional quality in that they
imply a second entity; they point to the surround, and together both sides
Harry H g t
7
explanation proved to be very fruitful and perhaps sufficient as well. The
fruitfulness and, more particularly, the sufficiency of mechanical explanations
for biological phenomena may be another matter.
Classically in the Aristotleian framework, causal categories were invoked,
in part, to contribute to our understanding of a things nature. For Aristotle,
the explanation ofsome occurrence is attributable to: ( I ) the material character
of the features involved (material cause), ( 2 ) their structural character (formal
cause), (3) their origins (efficient causality), and (4) their immanent or
teleological character (final cause; see Grene, 1963).These categories, and
those of formal and final causality in particular, emphasize the distinctiveness
of natural things. In contrast, it is characteristic of post-Renaissance science
to apply mechanistic explanation to all entities regardless of their nature.
Mechanistic causal explanation, often in combination with materialism, seeks
to reduce the diversity of natural things to a common mode of description,
if not a common level of analysis. Thus, Newton offers a grand theory of
physics applying mechanistic explanation to events in the heavens as well
as on earth; in the same vein, Locke and those who follow broadly in his
approach propose a Newtonian analysis of mind. The Lockean model has
profoundly affected psychological analysis to the present day. Behaviorism, and
its contemporary versions, e.g., information-processing, are transpositions
of this approach to observable actions and inferred mental operations,
respectively .
One might argue, however, that in order to understand the cause of some
event, it is necessary to take into account the distinctive nature of the entities
involved. Otherwise, all entities are treated identically, and their substantive
differences are ignored. This is not a problem if a reductive, materialistic
approach to all phenomena is adopted. If, however, one minimally distinguishes between physical (closed) and living (open) systems, the nature of
the entity in question needs to figure quite prominently in a causal analysis. We
may need to adopt a broader view of causality (although not necessarily the
above classical categories in particular) precisely because the specific qualities
ofliving systems, and their relationship with their surround, are fundamental to
an adequate explanation of psychological phenomena.
In what way is a causal analysis in a relational view different from that in a
dualistic approach? Let us consider two differences, and then apply this
discussion to our consideration of the affordance concept.
I ) As applied to psychology, a dualistic approach suggests that events stop
and start in a discontinuous series ofjerks (Dewey, 1896).The animal, in effect,
is in a state of relative stasis until some environmental occurrence stimulates or
goads it into activity. This admittedly sketchy account also applies to many socalled active models of perception and cognition that employ schema as a
central concept. With few exceptions (e.g. Neisser, 1976), environmental
occurrences are seen as initiating psychological activity. I n this view, the causal
Harry Hdt
9
higher-order, relational factors, such as behavior settings and affordances,
which may be in fact the more valuable explanatory constructs.
2 ) In addition to the on-going nature of the transactions within the animalenvironment system, causal influences are reciprocal, with the impetus of
fluctuations in the on-going behavior stream having its source in the
environment facet OT in the individual facet of the transaction; and this
reciprocal exchange is cumulative in its effects.
Considering the environmental side of the exchange first, occurrences or
features of the environment can lead td the initiation of a series of subsequent
transactions, as in the case of a telephone ringing in my home, and its
transactional aftermath. As with this example, most instances ofenvironmental
conditions initiating a subsequent series of transactions are likely to be intrusive
in nature (e.g., an unexpected sound or sight in the perceptual field). Further, it
is possible that the impact of particular environmental conditions is not
immediate, but rather becomes manifested sometime after the individual has
been exposed to them (e.g., the effects of some conditions in the home on child
development, Wachs and Gruen, 1982). In addition, environmental conditions
may have a somewhat pervasive influence, even though we may not always be
able to isolate their impact at some specific moment in time. Instead, their
impact may reflect the prevailing conditions confronting the individual over a
continuing period oftime. One example ofthis view ofthe environment in terms
of prevailing conditions, rather than as temporally discrete stimulus inputs, can
be found in adaptation-level theory (Helson, 1964).In this important work,
prevailing setting conditions are seen as establishing a perceptual-cognitive
frame of reference for the individuals on-going transactions with the environment. (For an excellent application of this approach, see Wohlwill and Kohn,
973.)
Second, and perhaps more commonly, the stream ofbehavior is redirected or
shunted by intentional acts on the part of the individual. In these cases, the
individual engages particular features of the environment in the course of some
activity. And significantly, through many of these acts, the individual can
modify the environment, e.g., by manipulating objects, by affecting others
around him, by constructing tools, or by building shelters. These environmental modifications, in turn, transform the surround, which may influence the
individual, and so on in a reciprocal manner (Shotter, 1983).As a result, the
individual may take an active role in fashioning his environment in important
ways. These on-going reciprocal exchanges form an essential part of the
individuals psychosocial history and, consequently, serve as the foundation
from which subsequent development proceeds. The reciprocal nature of social
interaction in particular has been receiving considerable attention, particularly
in the area of child development.
To summarize, in a relational view of environment-animal interaction, the
standard causal analysis may have only limited applicability. A mechanistic
10
Harry Hcfi
Our own body is in the world as the heart is in the organism: it keeps the visible spectacle constantly
alive, it breathes life into it and sustains it inwardly, and with it forms a system. (Merleau-Ponty,
1963. P. 03)
I1
I2
Harv HeJ
likewise, specific motor actions (excluding perhaps certain simple reflexes) are
probably not programmed in the nervous system to be expressed without the
presence of situational factors that play a direct role in establishing their
particular form (Turvey, 1977).
An intentional act is situated with respect to two factors: the functional
characteristics of the environment confronting the individual, (i.e., its affordances), and the physical characteristics of the individuals body, (e.g., bodyscaling). The affordances of the setting are, in a sense, the ecological resources
for behavior. The physical characteristics of the body establish what can be
performed (i.e., what the individual can do) as a function of such things as
length of reach and stride, breadth of grasp, strength, etc. In combination, the
affordances of the environment and the characteristics of the body constrain the
range of intentional acts that can be expressed.
To take an example, sitting down is an intentional act with two situational
facets: perceiving a surface ofsupport that affords sitting and simultaneously an
awareness of ones relevant body dimensions. These two factors jointly create
the possibility for the expression of this intention and determine its particular
form. The act ofsitting down has little meaning as a pure motor representation;
it is only meaningful as a situated act.
Both Merleau-Ponty and Gibson emphasize that perceiving simultaneously
entails an awareness ofboth the environment and the body. Just as affordances
are perceived properties of the environment, our body is also phenomenally
present as we move around and engage the world. While the object or event
receiving our attention at a particular time stands out in relief as a figure
against the background of the rest of the environmental array,
ones own body is the third term, always tacitly understood, in the figure-background structure,
and every figure stands out against the double horizon of external and bodily space. (MerleauPonty, 1963; p. 101)
Gibson (1g7ga) makes a similar point about these two facets of perceptual
experience:
The optical information lo specify the self, including the head, body, arms and hands, accompanies
the optical information to specify the environment. The two sources ofinformation coexist . . ..The
supposedly separate realms of the subjective and objective are actually only poles of attention.
(p. I 16). . .. The continuous act of perceiving involves the coperceiving of the self. (p. 240)
It is suggested then that both the environment and the body are aspects ofthe
perceptual field, and moreover, that goal-directed actions are realized in
relation to these two factors. The body, in particular, is an instrument or tool
through which intentional acts that are directed toward environmental objects
are expressed. That is, the body needs to be viewed not merely as a set of
physical dimensions, but more deeply as a vehicle for being in the world.
Affordances reconsidered
Adopting the intentional approach to the body suggested in the foregoing
invites a modification of our earlier definition of affordances. Instead of solely
specifying an affordance relative to the size of some relevant body feature,
perhaps we should couch this specification in relation to the body as it
participates in a particular goal-directed act. That is to say, an affordance is
perceived in relation to some intentional act, not only in relation to the bodys
physical dimensions. So, for example, whether that object before me affords
grasping must be assessed relative to an intentional act (i.e., grasping), and not
only with respect to hand size, although this remains an essential factor.
This point may seem to entail a relatively minor definitional revision, but it
has significant consequences by broadening considerably the possibilities of
what can count as an affordance. If affordance is defined relative to the
intentions of the individual, instead ofonly relative to body-size considerations,
we can attribute functional meaning to any environmental feature that is
implicated in an intentional, goal-directed behavior.
Consider the following example: Can one justifiably say that a typewriter
affords typing? If affordances are limited to body-scaled objects, this claim
makes little sense and may seem to be an unreasonable application of the
affordance concept. Even though the design of a typewriter keyboard is scaled
to the hand, the act of typing goes beyond mere manipulation of keys. It is a
structured act both linguistically (in terms of language expression) and
motorically (in that a particular manipulation of the machines parts is
critical). At the same time, when viewed as a structured act, typing can be seen
as a goal-directed or intentional, situated behavior. The act of typing is realized
through the body in conjunction with a machine configured in a particular
way. Within the domain ofthis situated act, the typewriter affords a specific action,
namely, typing. From an intentional perspective, then, the typewriter takes on
functional meaning, that is, an affordance, within the context of this goaldirected activity.
We might then reconsider affordances as the functional significances of
environmental objects taken relative to what an individual can do with respect
to them. Knowing how to do something necessarily implicates( I ) the structural
characteristics of the objects utilized in the performance of the action and ( 2 )
the structural characteristics of the body that engages those objects. In other
words, knowing how to do something is situated knowledge.
Is the couching of affordances in an intentional framework consistent with
Gibsons theoretical approach? It clearly is appropriate to do so in that the
action-oriented definition of the concept of affordances suggests an intentional
perspective. In contrast to an emphasis solely on their body-scaled characteristics, an intentional view ofaffordances may be more in keeping with Gibsons
concern with the environments possibilities for action. Indeed, body-scalingper
se suggests little, if anything, about action.
Harry Hgt
When we say that an animal exists, that it has a world, or that it belongs to a world, we do not mean
that i t has a perception or objective consciousness of that world. The situation . . . is not entirely
articulate and determinate. . . i t presents only a practical significance; it asks only for bodily
recognition; it is experienced as an open situation, and requires the animals movements, just
as the first notes of a melody require a certain kind of resolution . . . (p, 78)
In other words, the perceived meaning of the situation arises from the
interaction ofthe environments functional possibilities and the intentions of the
individual, that is, from its place in a situated, intentional act. Its functional
significance is relationally determined.
This claim requires additional explication, and for this purpose let us
consider Deweys (1896) treatment of perceived meaning in his classic critique
of the reflex-arc concept in psychology. He argues in this analysis that the
perceived meaning of an environmental object emerges from a continuous,
transactional interchange between the individual and the environment. This
point becomes clearer when it is recognized that often the meaning or value of
an object changes with experience and with intention. Let us first consider the
case of the modification of object meaning as a function of experience. T o use
Deweys example, at one moment a candle flame may appear attractive to a
child, who accordingly reaches out to it, but at a later moment, after the child is
burned, the candle appears aversive. How can we understand this state of
affairs?
The initially perceived quality of attractiveness is not solely inherent in the
object (i.e., as a thing-in-itself), otherwise how could this quality change with
experience? Nor is it held subjectively by the child independent of the object;
the object cannot be construed in any way by the child. Its possible meanings are
constrained by the objects physical properties (e.g., its light and warmth).
Instead, the attractive quality arises out of the relationship between the object
and the child at a particular time. The naive child visually inspects the candle
(perhaps we might say, adopts an aesthetic attitude toward it) and in the
context of this intentional action, the candle appears attractive. This positive,
perceived quality encourages haptic exploration (i.e., it appears to afford
16
Harry H$t
Again, the perceived meaning of the object does not reside solely with the
object or the person, but it derives from the intentional relationship between the
two, which includes the history of their interaction. The quality of the initial
experience is reconstituted through the course of interaction with the object.
Viewing environment-behavior interaction as being continuous as well as
cumulative, as discussed above, the meanings of environmental features
naturally become transformed over time (Shotter, 1983).
The claim that the functional significances of environmental features emerge
from the relationship between the object and an individuals actions can
perhaps be more simply and clearly illustrated by the observation that the
perceived affordance of an object also changes as a function of intention. A
lighted candle not only affords pain, ifyou touch its flame, but more positively,
it also affords illuminating a dark place as well as heating a liquid such as water.
Which of these latter two dispositional qualities is realized in experience depends
on the individuals behavioral goals or intentions at a particular time. The
illuminating quality of a flame emerges from intentions concerning the lighting
of a setting; and its heating quality arises out of intentions such as the desire to
boil water. Both properties inhere in the object; a candle gives off both light and
heat. Which one of these properties is functionally significant and is experienced
at a particular time depends on the intentional character of the perceivers
actions at that time. (We will return to the issue of the multiple affordances of an
object .)
The apparently mentalistic tone of this intentional analysis may seem at odds
with Gibsons consistent criticism of mentalistic accounts of psychological
processes. If such a characterization of this analysis was appropriate, then
indeed it would be inconsistent with the thrust of Gibsons theory. But such a
reading is not necessary, and certainly is not desirable. As we have seen, an
intentional approach is generally consistent with Gibsons ecological view.
18
Harry Hejl
19
a . Perceptual learning that accompanies maturation and other sources of physical change
Some of the affordances of the environment are discovered as the individual
changes physically through maturation. Changes, for example, in height or
strength, permit new actions in the environment. The individual can perform
actions that were previously not possible. Conversely, in the case of aging or
significant changes in motor ability due to accident or disease, the individual
can no longer perform certain actions. The physical state of the body and motor
proficiency (and the accompanying awareness of these body factors) are one set
of factors that establish what one can do, that is, what intentional acts are
possible.
In turn, (as argued earlier), intentional possibilities invest the world with
functional meaning. For example, when the child develops the motor abilities to
grasp small objects and to make controlled arm movements, objects such as
pencils, pens, and crayons take on new functional significance; namely, they
afford marking, scribbling, drawing, etc. The discovery of new affordances is
made possible by the maturational change, and more deeply by enhancement
of the intentional repertoire.
Loss of function, or of intentional possibilities, through aging, disease, or
accident also results in changes in the possibility of realizing particular
affordances. For example, in the case ofsome disabilities, stairs may no longer
afford locomotion, but instead signify an obstacle. As the intentional capacities
of an individual change, the affordances of the environment change concurrently.
20
H a r y Hgt
Putting this passage in the terms of the present discussion, it would seem that
the affordances of features at the loading dock site were different for adults
and children. Moreover, Muchow noted that the site was probably experienced
differently by children of the various ages observed. In particular, the fence
and the slope were perceived as affording different activities at successive age
levels:
21
The child of two to three yean old frequently apprehends fence and slope as areas ofindependence,
as a means of affording a temporary, pleasurableseparation from the mother standing on the other
side of the rails. Children ofkindergarten age use the fence as something on which to sit and balance
themselves, whereas six- to eight-year-olds use i t as a gymnastic device. For the three- to four-yearold the slope is something to be apprehended in awe and curiosity as a field ofdanger. Somewhat
older children try to master this danger zone by sliding down it on their seats. (Werner, 1948,
PP. 387-3881
22
Harry Hdt
object, that same cutting-with object will be perceived as affording pryingwith. If the intention is to tighten a screw, this same object may afford that
particular action. In each of these cases, the various affordances of the object
arise from a relationship between a particular intentional goal and the
properties of an environmental object, as discussed at length above.
Typically, an environmental object offers a variety of potential affordances,
one (or more) of which is realized in conjunction with a particular intentional
act. The multiple affordance possibilities of an object highlight a crucial
distinction between potential and actualized afordances, a distinction that has its
counterpart in potential and actualized intentional acts. At any given time, the
individual is perceiving-utilizing only a subset of the potential affordances of an
object. In addition to the potential affordances of a single object, more generally
the individual is experiencing few of the affordance possibilities in the total
environment a t any particular time. The remaining environmental affordances
exist as possibilities to be realized in relation to the individuals intentions.
Following Turvey, Shaw, Reed, and Mace (1981),we can distinguish
between dispositional and occurrent properties of objects. Dispositional
properties refer to a things potentialities -to what can happen. As such they
are to be distinguished from occurrent properties, the properties that a thing is
currently exhibiting (p. 261). The dispositional properties of objects considered at a behavioral level are their functional possibilities-what an animal
can potentially do with them or in relation to them. These properties can be
specified as environmental potentialities, apart from their occurrence or
realization, but in relation to some animal (see below). Accordingly, functional
possibilities, or potential affordances, like any dispositional (e.g., the solubility
ofsodium chloride) ,are real properties ofobjects or substances. The ecological
approach. . . focuses on real possibility; for it takes possibility to be an
ontological category (Turvey, et al., 1981,p. 262).Thus, the environment for a
particular perceiver can be considered to consist of permanent possibilities
for perceptual-motor experience. We will pursue this issue further in the next
and concluding section.
23
Whereas Gibson stresses the critical role played by the perceivers actions in
the perceptual process, specifically in the pick up of invariants in the ambient
array, he is wary to promote more fully the pragmatic or intentional role of
action in perceptual experience. The reasons for this are all too obvious. Gibson
wants to avoid the appearance of introducing mentalistic concepts into his
account of perceiving so that he cannot be read as advocating a mentalistic or
dualistic approach, or an enrichment theory (Gibson and Gibson, 1955).
Accordingly, he seems to limit his discussion of the perceivers role in the
perceiving process, particularly (but not solely) through the language that he
employs.
Noble feels that Gibson has unjustifiably drawn away from the pragmatic
and intentional character of his own position, and
that Gibsons neglect of the pragmatist tradition. . . has meant a lack of access to nonmcntulistic
concepts ofthe organisms role in the creation ofits experience. Notions such as intentionality, for
apsychologisf, belong to motivation, and for Gibson, I suspect, that would be classed as part ofthe
baggage for mentalism and put to one side. (pp. 7-71; emphasis added)
Noble contends, and I concur, that one can adopt an intentional approach to
perceiving, and with it acknowledge more fully the individuals participation in
24
Harry H g t
the perceiving process, without necessarily falling into the camp of mentalism
(also see Ben-Zeev, 1984).Gibson could have articulated more explicitly this
facet of his theory without being overly concerned about this latter possibility
(but not the possibility of being misinterpreted). Indeed, in the preceding
section of this paper I tried to develop the intentionality in Gibsons theory,
while attempting to remain faithful to the nonrnentalistic commitment of his
position. Moreover, it is only by explicating the intentional strain in Gibsons
ecological theory that the apparent tension can be resolved between the
independence and the relational claims concerning affordances.
Before demonstrating why this contradiction is more apparent than real, let
us first consider this intentional approach more broadly. If one is inclined to
assimilate all psychological concepts to a dualistic framework, then intentionality will seem to refer to a mental process. This assimilative tendency toward
dualism is commonplace in perceptual analyses; indeed Gibsons theory has
often been misread or failed to be understood because it does not fit into a
dualistic framework (Heft, I 980, I 982; Wilcox and Katz, I 98 I ). But intentional
approaches to perception are typically viewed by their proponents as offering
an alternative to dualism, and more particularly, as an alternative to the two
manifestations of dualistic thinking in psychological theory: behaviorism and
mentalism. Commenting on Merleau-Pontys intentional analysis of behavior,
Wild (1963)states:
Human behavior is neither a series of blind reactions to external stimuli, nor the projection of
acts which are motivated by the pure ideas of a disembodied, worldless mind. It is neither
exclusively subjective nor exclusively objective, but a dialetical interchange between man and
world, which cannot be adequately expressed in traditional causal terms. . .. It is out of this
dialectical interchange that human meanings emerge. These meanings are neither passively
assimilated from an external, cosmic order that is already fixed and established, as the realists have
imagined nor constructed dc nouo by a creative mind, as the idealists have supposed. (pp. xiv-xv)
25
And
But, actually, an affordance is neither an objective property nor a subjective property; or it is both if
you like. An affordance cuts across the dichotomy ofsubjective-objective and helps us to undentand
its inadequacy. It is equally a fact ofthe environment and a fact ofbehavior. I t is both physical and
psychical, yet neither. (Gibson, 1g7ga, p. 29)
How then does this alternative approach, reflected in the affordance concept,
allow us to reconcile the tension between the independence and relational
claims? In the ecological approach, the environment for an individual is
delimited relationally in terms of what is potentially significant, in a functional
or an intentional sense, for that individual, such as what the potential
affordance properties of the environment are for a particular individual. As
suggested above, a n emphasis on the individuals potential for activity, i.e., the
character and range of her intentional repertoire, specifies particular environmental features with respect to which these actions are situated. Although
these environmental features are relationally specified, they can be considered
to exist independently of the perceiver in at least two (related) respects.
First, as argued above, affordances can be viewed as dispositional properties
of environmental features taken at a behavioral level of analysis; and viewed in
this manner, affordances can be appropriately considered to inhere in
environmental features. That is, the affordance properties that an object can
take on are constrained by the physical characteristicsofthe object. Affordances
are not imposed on objects by perceivers mental processes. Second, and
importantly, as a property of an object, an affordance is carried by the
information in the ambient array. Thus, an affordance like any other object
property specified by information in the ambient array, is always there to be
perceived.6 For these reasons, Gibson (1979a) is justified in stating:
The affordance ofsomething does nof change as the need of the observer changes. The observer may
or may not perceive or attend 10 the affordance, according to his needs, but the affordance, being
invariant, is always there to be perceived. An affordance is not bestowed upon an object by a need of
an observer and his act of perceiving it. The object offers what i t does because it is the object it is.
(PP. 138-1391
26
Harry Heft
certain affordances that are compatible with these intentional acts. Needs
control the perception ofaffordances (selectiveattention) and also initiate acts
(Gibson, 1975, p. 411).Thus, among the affordance possibilities of the
environment, which are ontologically real, some affordances will be realized in
the course of the individuals interaction with the environment.
As the foregoing considerations indicate, by bringing out the intentional
quality of Gibsons theory, the apparent contradiction between the independent and relational nature of affordances is resolvable. An emphasis on the
pragmatic and intentional character of perceiving allows one to claim that the
functional significances of objects are to be specified relative to an individual
perceiver, while at the same time preserving the independent status of object
meaning (i.e., direct realism). Further, it can be seen from the foregoing
analysis that this tension grows out of a tendency to view perceptual processes
from a dualistic perspective, in which relational concepts such as affordances,
are inappropriately viewed as either objective, and independent of perceivers, OY
subjective, and dependent on perceivers.
CONCLUDING COMMENTS
Harry H e j
Department of Psychology
Denison University
,Granville
OH43023
27
NOTES
To simplify the discussion, I will focus primarily on vision throughout the paper.
Turvey and Shaw (1979;also see Shaw and Turvey, 1981)discuss the compatibility
relations between environment and animal in terms of affordances and their complement, on the animal side of the ledger, eJectivities. Their emphasis on an animals
potential for action and its relationship to affordances is broadly similar to the
intentional analysis presented in this paper. Although the Shaw-Turvey approach
influenced my thinking in a general manner, I chose to develop the present form
of intentional analysis, rather than follow their lead for several reasons; most
notably because this intentional approach seemed more readily to offer an avenue to the
problem of perceiving the culturally-based meaning of environmental features (see
below).
This perceptual knowledge does not include a n understanding of how the postal
system works (Noble, 1981).Such understanding is of an abstract, cognitive nature in
that it entails at least a rudimentary knowledge of the workings of this institution. One
can know that a particular environmental object affords the mailing of correspondence,
without an understanding of what happens after the envelope disappears down the
chute.
* For a preliminary discussion of the role of affordances in the development of
environmental knowing in children, see Heft and Wohlwill (1987).
See Noble (198I ) for a suggested resolution of this contradiction by drawing on the
work of G. H. Mead.
Shotter (1983)is critical of Gibsons theory on similar grounds as Noble (198I ) ,
arguing that Gibsons account lacks an intentional analysis ofthe perceivers activities in
perceiving processes. Toward this end Shotter presents a stimulating application of
Giddens ( I 979) concept of structuration to individual-environment transactions
(whereas Giddens is primarily concerned with social structures). While I agree that the
intentional aspects of perceiving need to be articulated in Gibsons ecological theory, I
contend (as I believe Noble does) that this aspect of perceiving is already implicit in
Gibsons account (see above and subsequent comments in this section). Shotter fails to
recognize this.
28
Harry HeJ
REFERENCES
BARKER,R.G.
(I
Press.
BARKER,
R.G., and WRIGHT,H.F. (1951).One boys day. New York: Harper and
Row.
GIBSON,
J.J. (1967).New reasons for realism. Synthese, 17, 162-1 72.
29
GIBSON,
J.J. (1972).The affordances of the environment (previously unpublished manuscript). In E. Reed and R. Jones (eds.), Reasons f o r realism:
Selected essays ofJames 3. Gibson. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum (pp. 408-410).
GIBSON,
J.J. (1974).The theory of proprioception and its relation to volition:
An attempt at classification (previously unpublished manuscript). In E.
Reed and R. Jones (eds.), Reasonsf o r realism: Selected essays o f James 3. Gibson.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum (pp. 385-392).
GIBSON,J.J. ( 1975). Affordances and behavior (previously unpublished
manuscript). In E. Reed and R. Jones (eds.), Reasonsf o r realism: Selectedessays
ofJames J. Gibson. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum (pp. 4 1 e 4I I ).
GIBSON,J.J. (1979a). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston:
Houghton-Mifflin.
GIBSON,
J.J. (1979b). What is involved in surface perception? (previously
unpublished manuscript). In E. Reed and R. Jones (eds.), Reasonsf o r realism:
Selected essays ofJames J . Gibson. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum (pp. 1 0 6 - 1 I 2 ) .
GIBSON,
J.J., and GIBSON,
E.J. ( 1955).Perceptual learning: Differentiation or
enrichment? Psychological Review, 62, 32-4 I .
GIDDENS,
A. ( I 979). Central problem in social theory. London: Macmillan.
GLOTZBACH,
P.A. and HEFT, H. (1982).Ecological and phenomenological
approaches to perception. Nous, 16, 108-1 2 I .
GRENE,
M. ( I 963). A portrait ofdristotle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
HALLFORD,
W. ( I 984). Sizing-up the world: The body as a referent in a sizejudgment task. Doctoral dissertation. Ohio State University, Columbus,
OH.
HEFT,H. ( 1980).What Heil is missing in Gibson. Journal f o r the Theory of Social
Behavior, 10 187-193.
HEFT,H. ( 1982).Incommensurability and the omission in Gibsons theory.
Journal f o r the Theory of Social Behavior, 12, 345-347.
HEFT, H. (in press). Affordances of childrens environments: A functional
approach to environmental description. Childrens Environments Quarterly.
HEFT,H. and WOHLWILL,
J.F. (1987).Environmental cognition in children. In
D. Stokols and I. Altman (eds.), Handbook of environmental psychology. New
York: John Wiley (pp. 175-203).
HELSON,
H. Adaptation-level theory. New York: Harper, I 964.
KOHLER,W. ( 1925). The mentality of apes. New York: Harcourt, Brace and
World.
MARK,L.S. ( I 987).Eyeheight-scaled information about affordances: A study of
sitting and stair climbing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
and Performance, 13,3617370.
MERLEAU-PONTY,
M. ( I 963). The phenomenology ofperception. ( C .Smith, Trans.)
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Original work published I 945).
MUCHOW,
M. and MUCHOW,
H.H. (1935).D e r Lebensraum des Grosstadtkindes.
Hamburg: M. Riegel.
30
Harry Heft
NEISSER,
U. (1976). Cognition and reality. San Francisco: Freeman.
NOBLE,
W.G. ( 198I ) . Gibsonian theory and the pragmatist perspective. Journal
f o r the Theory of Social Behavior, I I , 65-85.
REED,E., andJONES, R. ( I 981). Is perception blind?: A reply to Heil. Journal for
the Theory of Social Behavior, I I , 87-9 I .
REED,E. andJoNEs, R. (eds.) (1982).Reasonsforrealism: SelectedessaysofJamesJ.
Gibson. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
SCHIFF,W. (1965).The perception of impending collision: A study of visually
directed avoidant behavior. Psychological Monographs. 79, (Whole no. 604).
SHAW,R.S. and TURVEY,
M.T. (1981).Coalitions as models for ecosystems: A
realist perspective on perceptual organization. In M. Kubovy and J.R.
Pomerantz (eds.), Perceptual organization. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum (pp. 343415).
SHOTTER,J. (1983). Duality of structure and intentionality in an
ecological psychology. Journal f o r the Theory of Social Behavior, 13, 19-43.
TURVEY,
M.T. (1977). Preliminaries to a theory of action with reference to
vision. In R.S. Shaw and J. Bransford (eds.), Perceiving, acting, and knowing.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum (pp. 2 I 1-265).
TURVEY,
M.T. and SHAW,R.S. (1979). The primacy of perceiving: An
ecological reformulation of perception for understanding memory. In L.G.
Nilsson (ed.), Perspectives on memory research. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
TURVEY,
M.T., SHAW,R.S., REED,E.S. and MACE,W.M. (1981).Ecological
laws of perceiving and acting: In reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn. Cognition, 9,
237-304.
WACHS,T.D. and GRUEN,G.D. ( I 982). Early experience and human development.
New York: Plenum Press.
WARREN,
W.H. (1984). Perceiving affordances: Visual guidance of stair
climbing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Performance and Perception,
10,683-703.
WARREN,
W.H., and WHANG,S. (1987).Visual guidance of walking through
apertures: Body-scaled information for affordances. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 13, 37 1-383.
WERNER,
H. ( I 948). Comparative psychology of mental development. New York:
International Universities Press.
WILCOX,
S. and KATZ,S. ( 1981).What Gibson isnt missing after all: A reply to
Heil. Journal f o r the Theory of Social Behavior, I I , 3 I 3-3 I 7.
WILD,J. ( 1963). Foreword to M. Merleau-Ponty, The structure of behavior (A.L.
Fisher, Trans.). Boston: Beacon Press. (Original work published 1942).
WOHLWILL,
J.F. ( I 985). Martha Muchow and the life-space of the urban child.
Human Development, 28, 200-209.
WOHLWILL,
J.F. and KOHN,I. ( 1973). The environment as experienced by the
migrant: An adaptation-level view. Representative Research in Social Psychology,
4,135-164.