Ruth Levitas Utopia
Ruth Levitas Utopia
Ruth Levitas Utopia
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Utopian
Studies.
http://www.jstor.org
So her next five chapters examine the views about Utopia held byMarx
and Engels, Mannheim and Sorel, Bloch, Morris, and Marcuse. Each chap
ter focuses on Utopia's function of social transformation. Each presents
further elements that constitute themeaning of Utopia for this tradition: for
instances, Levitas explores the linked concepts of "dreams," "desire," and
she examines the idea of "abstract" versus "concrete" Utopias;
"hope";
and she asks about estrangement and itsovercoming for each thinker.Each
chapter also criticizes the thinkers: for instance, most pay insufficient
attention to form. Finally, each is a valuable interpretive enterprise on its
own. She re-evaluates Marx and Engels, arguing that they object not to the
Book Reviews
221
Utopians socialists' images of the future but to their ideas about the
transition to that future. She provides a clear catalogue of criticisms of
Mannheim's work on ideology and Utopia (and of Ricoeur's neo-Mann
heimian approach); she also notes how Mannheim and Sorel, ideological
opposites, are linked by their inabilities to integrate reason and passion, the
dichotomy on which somany of their core ideas are built. Merely to present
Bloch's Utopian ideas in English is a signal contribution; and Levitas also
proposes a novel interpretation of Morris's News from Nowhere and an
imaginative synthesis of Marcuse's evolving ideas about Utopia.
Levitas's penultimate chapter returns to Anglo-American definitions,
focusing on the strong scholarly work of the past decade or so, inwhich,
nonetheless, Utopia's definition remains sharply contested and problematic.
The final chapter explicitly pulls together the definitional issues from earlier
chapters in the book and tries to resolve them. How should students of
Utopia deal with the variety of definitions of Utopia and the historical vari
ability of Utopias? Is Utopia to be defined in terms of farm, function, or
content?Must itbe a possible world? Can arcadian, millennial, or cockaigne
like visions be considered Utopias? Is there a Utopian impulse or propensity?
Is Utopia currently in decline? Amidst these and other questions about the
content of any definition of Utopia, Levitas iswisely self-conscious about
the function and goal of defining Utopia. She settles on an analytic
definition (not a descriptive or normative one) that is consciously broad (in
order to allow for historical variability as well as to encourage scholarly
diversity), that tries to integrate reason and passions, and that does not
prejudge on ideological grounds any Utopias, Utopian scholarship, or active
pursuit of a Utopian vision: Utopias express "the desire for a better way of
living" and "being" (8, 191).
Just as a brief review can only indicate how Levitas weaves together all
the book's concerns to produce and enrich her definition, so too itsdifficul
ties or ambiguities can only be touched on. For those who wish clear and dis
tinctdefinitions that definitively demarcate the ins from the outs, Levitas's
last chapter will disappoint. But I think she has shown well the failure of
definitions that carefully delimit Utopia; so she ison the right track in seek
ing a broad definition. Whether "desire" suffices is less clear tome. On the
one hand, desire seems too broad, including as itdoes almost every particu
lar feeling of dissatisfaction each individual has; on the other hand, it seems
too narrow, downplaying reason too much and ignoring the dreaming and
play, the complex logic and intricately-articulated ideals, that can go into
creating an extensively-described model society.
Beyond its central critique and its definitional proposal, the book has
many strengths. Its approach to the problem of definition?to seek an ana
lyticaldefinition through a sociology-of-knowledge analysis of scholars and
activists who attempted to define Utopia?is unusual, and provides a novel
angle on the topic. So does Levitas's concern with social change, and her
insistence?when talking of human needs, for instance?that human char
acteristics are socially constructed. She is attuned to feminist concerns,
222 UTOPIAN
STUDIES
briefly but incisively noting that those who contrast Bellamy and Morris
ignore their shared overlooking of the development of women and the status
of children, issues on which Gilman stands in contrast to both men (109).
She does not limit the Utopias she considers to the usual litany fromMore to
the present, but includes Utopias of theNew Right and of the neo-Marxist
left (i.e., Bloch, Marcuse). Finally, even when the concepts are complex, she
writes with clarity and grace. In sum, Levitas has written a strong and signif
icant book, a far-ranging, insightful, and incisive exploration of the concept
of Utopia.
Peter Stilllman
Vassar College
and London,
England: MIT
Press,
1988.