One of Deleuze's Bergsonisms: Rossen Ventzislavov
One of Deleuze's Bergsonisms: Rossen Ventzislavov
One of Deleuze's Bergsonisms: Rossen Ventzislavov
Rossen Ventzislavov
Abstract
In this article I attempt to reveal some continuities between the antipsychoanalytic stance adopted by Gilles Deleuze in his later work and
Henri Bergsons early philosophy. On account of these continuities
I hope to provide a glimpse into what I believe is a century-old tangent
of philosophical resistance to the methods and theories of Freudian
psychoanalysis. In order to achieve this, I start with a brief meditation
on the challenges and benefits of cross-generational inheritance and
collaboration in philosophy. The purpose of this is twofold to explore
some general conditions for such collaboration and to tease out some
of the implications of these conditions for the substantive argument my
specific reading of Bergson via Deleuze occasions. I then expound on
Bergsons theory of duration and some of the uses to which Deleuze
puts it in the latter part of his career. In this I outline several fecund
similarities between Bergsons critique of associationism and Deleuzes
attack on Freud. Finally, I attempt a partial evaluation of Freudian
psychoanalysis from the joint, albeit naturally disjointed, perspective of
my primary sources.
Keywords: Bergson, Deleuze, Freud, anti-psychoanalysis
341
343
work and those preceding it, Deleuze can be said to employ Bergson by
means of quotation, trying to develop his ideas, or just using them as a
backdrop. Philosophical also because at this stage Deleuze seems eagerly
engaged with prior philosophy in general, with Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche,
Heidegger and many others. In the preface to Bergsonism, he boasts an
intimacy with the philosophers he has written about, the result of which
is, in Deleuzes words a child, which would be his [the philosopher
discussed] and which would at the same time be a monster (Deleuze
1988: 8). One of many proofs for the relevance of the metaphor lies
in the chain formed by Deleuzes treatment of Bergsons treatment of
Kants doctrine of the faculties.2 This could be looked upon as Deleuzes
formative period, when he gradually weaned himself away from earlier
philosophy and developed his own philosophical voice.
The second branch, the one that interests me here, is the interdisciplinary, inventive one, particularly as present in works like Anti-Oedipus,
A Thousand Plateaus and What is Philosophy? that is, in Deleuzes
collaborations with Guattari. These works are far less analytic, far less
philosophically correct. Here Deleuze unleashes a new Deleuzian
vernacular, with concepts uniquely his own. These are arguably also
the books whose influence has spread outside of philosophical discourse
(detectable in many contemporary architects writings, in the catalogue
of the Mille Plateaux record label, and so on). What makes them
Bergsonian is the attention they apportion to the method of intuition.
It is also here that Bergsons notions of multiplicity, virtuality and the
body are mobilised for a new purpose, new to both philosophers and, in
all probability, for philosophy in its totality. The innovation in question
is Deleuzes drawing out of the anti-psychoanalytic implications of Bergsons philosophy. As a Bergsonism, this is distinct from the historical
version manifest in the greater part of Deleuzes early work and from
the conceptual/creative one presented in his books on cinema. While
these other engagements with Bergson are just as valuable, and often
draw on the same sources, the anti-Oedipal Bergsonism I am concerned
with here is much less explored. My extraction of a new virtual dialogue
between Bergson and Deleuze on a new topic thus aims at making two
contributions first, to honour the two philosophers creative approach
to reading philosophy and, second, to carve out a place for a particular
Bergsonism which merits further attention.
345
347
349
351
repudiation of organic unity. Both the Ego and the body without organs
are now, never two minutes ago or tomorrow. Even though Deleuze
rarely writes of the body without organs in temporal terms, what he
writes has a recognisable parallel to Bergsonian duration. The body
without organs performs an ousting of the past, it makes a difference
from the past the way in Bergson pure duration involves the aforementioned upsurge of novelty at every stage. In one place, Deleuze explains
that the body without organs is what remains when we take everything
away (Deleuze and Guattari 1998: 151). Deleuze qualifies this suggestion by making an important distinction proper organisms perform
the connective syntheses of production while the body without organs
takes care of the disjunctive synthesis of recording (Deleuze and Guattari 1983: 12). The past is available to the body without organs through
aberrant paths of communication between non-communicating vessels,
transverse unities between elements that retain all their differences
within their own particular boundaries (Deleuze and Guattari 1983:
43). There is a record, but it is inconstant; the past is a body that continuously changes, the way in Bergson matter is subject to continuous
alteration. In the process of becoming which encompasses all of duration, space, and body for Bergson and Deleuze the present is the true
psychological existence, a present, as it were, untouched by the past except through the alterity of selective memory and an impetus for action.
Freud reserves the present for the Ego, the corrector of the past.
When he asserts that the Ego is the coherent organisation of mental
processes he admits the possibility of such organisation after the fact
(Freud 1999: 17). It is but a small step from here to the associationists
spatial model of consciousness. Space, for Bergson and even more
for Deleuze, is the stuff of conquest and regularity. Deleuze criticises
Freud severely for his letting the Ego supervene over the unconscious.
The symbolism of riders-whipping-horses, the present becoming an
excuse for past trauma, the layering of the psyche, presuppose a jump
between simultaneity and space. The memory of the past for Freud is
not selective, but solid; it does not call for action, but for retrograde
psychosis. The subdivisions of the psyche (Ego, Id, Ego Ideal, and so
on) line up in a strict hierarchy where everything follows neatly from
everything else. It is a theatre, a place rather than a time.
V. Oedipus Unravelling
The Freudian theatre is very aptly demystified by George Dimock
in his Anna and the Wolf-Man: Rewriting Freuds Case History
353
355
Notes
1. Update is here used in the sense of a restorers effort, while upgrade is
associated with the work of the inventor.
2. Kants doctrine of the faculties was apparently influenced by Leibnizs idea of
pre-established harmony. In his Kants Critical Philosophy Deleuze picks up
on Kants fascination with Leibnizian harmony and tries to show that Kants
enhancement of Leibnizs meaning has the limitation of allowing apriority to
suffocate the free accord of the faculties (cf. Deleuze 1993: 224). It is in no
way bizarre that a similar treatment of the same topic lurks behind Bergsons
exposition in Time and Free Will.
3. One emblematic mention of the unconscious in Bergson is found in his Matter
and Memory: And we have expressed how the cerebral lesion may effect this
weakening, without the necessity of supposing any sort of provision of memories
stored in the brain. What the injury really attacks are the sensory and motor
regions corresponding to this class of perception, and especially those adjuncts
through which they may be set in motion from within, so that memory, finding
nothing to catch hold of, ends by becoming practically powerless: now, in
psychology, powerlessness means unconsciousness (Bergson 1988: 176).
4. Deleuze and Guattaris attempt to reserve a genre slot for their contribution
to philosophy reads: RHIZOMATICS = SCHIZOANALYSIS = STRATOANALYSIS = PRAGMATICS = MICROPOLITICS. To this, a page later they
add POP ANALYSIS (Deleuze and Guattari 1998: 224).
5. May any omission of Guattaris name with reference to the two works not be
regarded by the reader as discounting Guattaris contribution, but as a matter of
mere brevity.
6. This operation is accomplished by associating the dream with the tale, The
Wolf and the Seven Kid-Goats (only six of which get eaten). We witness Freuds
reductive glee; we literally see multiplicity leave the wolves to take the shape of
goats that have absolutely nothing to do with the story. Seven wolves that are
only kid-goats. Six wolves: the seventh goat (the Wolf-Man himself) is hiding in
the clock. Five wolves: he might have seen his parents make love at five oclock,
and the roman numeral V is associated with the erotic spreading of a womans
legs. Three wolves: the parents may have made love three times. Two wolves:
the first coupling the child may have seen was the two parents more ferarum, or
perhaps even two dogs. One wolf: the wolf is the father, as we all knew from the
start. Zero wolves: he lost his tail, he is not just a castrater but also castrated.
Who is Freud trying to fool? (Deleuze and Guattari 1998: 28).
7. [I]t is at the highest point of this depersonalisation that someone can be
named, receives his or her family name or first name, acquires the most intense
discernibility in the instantaneous apprehension of the multiplicities belonging
to him or her, and to which he or she belongs (Deleuze and Guattari 1998: 35).
8. Whatever else these terms may signify, they point away from introspection
toward the interpersonal, away from psychoanalysis toward the broader social
and historical arena (Dimock 1995: 54).
357
9. With respect to the full range of human experience, a single dream at four
years of age and its latent content, a primal scene at one and a half, cannot
be presented as inexhaustibly meaningful without becoming narratologically
oppressive by virtue of what they exclude from consideration. Freuds
psychoanalytic drama leaves no room for, among other things, intersubjectivity
in the form of family history. The Wolf-Mans memoirs address, however
inadequately, the casualties of this exclusion (Dimock 1995: 59).
10. In Bergsons discussion of free will, we read: But the moments at which we thus
grasp ourselves are rare, and that is just why we are rarely free. The greater part
of the time we live outside ourselves, hardly perceiving anything of ourselves
but our own ghost, a colourless shadow which pure duration projects into
homogeneous space. Hence our life unfolds in space rather than in time; we
live for the external world rather than for ourselves; we speak rather than think;
we are acted rather than act ourselves (Bergson 2001: 231).
References
Ansell Pearson, Keith (2005) The Reality of the Virtual: Bergson and Deleuze,
MLN, 120:5, pp. 111227.
Bergson, Henri (1968) The Creative Mind, trans. Mabelle L. Andison. Westport,
CT: Greenwood Press, Publishers.
Bergson, Henri (1988) Matter and Memory, trans. Nancy Margaret Paul and
William Scott Palmer, New York: Zone Books.
Bergson, Henri (2001) Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of
Consciousness, trans. F. L. Pogson. New York: Dover.
Deleuze, Gilles (1988) Bergsonism, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam,
New York: Zone Books.
Deleuze, Gilles (1993) Kants Critical Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and
Barbara Habberjam, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, Gilles (1994) Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari (1983) Anti-Oedipus, trans. Robert Hurley, Mark
Seem and Helen R. Lane, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari (1998) A Thousand Plateaus, trans. Brian
Massumi, Minneapolis: Minnesota Press.
Dimock, George (1995) Anna and the Wolf-Man: Rewriting Freuds Case History,
Representations, 50 (Spring), pp. 5375.
Freud, Sigmund (1999) The Ego and the Id, in The Complete Works of Sigmund
Freud, trans. James Strachey, Anna Freud, Alix Strachey, Alan Tyson, ed. James
Strachey, Vol. XIX, London: Vintage.