Law and The Legal System
Law and The Legal System
Law and The Legal System
Samuel Mermin
Emeritus Professor of Law
University of Wisconsin
January 2009
SAMUEL MERMIN
Emeritus Professor of Law
University of Wisconsin
ALP
Published simultaneously in Canada
by Little, Brown & Compan)' (Canada) Limited
Chapter 1
Some General Observations
on Law and the Legal System
A.
1.
I. Tiller v. Atlantic Coast Line RR. Co., 318 U.S. 54. 5859 (1943).
2. Among those works suggesting a similar explanation of the "assumption or
risk" doctrine - or of a 5ubdoctTine, the "fellow ~eT\'ant rule" (under which the
employee was said to have impliedly assumed the risk of injury by a fellow employee's negligence) - aTe Lev}', The Law of the Commonwealth and Chief Justice
Shaw 178181 (1957); Bohlen. Voluntary Assumption of Risk. 20 Han'. L. Rev. 14.
31 (1906); Friedm;;m & I...."ldinsky. Social Change and the Law of Industrial Accidents,
67 Colum. L. Re\,. 50, 51-58 (196;). For opposing arguments see Pound, The Eco
nomic Interpretation of the Law of Torts. 53 Han'. L. Rev. 365. 373-380. 38~ (1940):
Burdick, Is Law the Expression of Class Selfishness? 25 HaT\'. L. Re\,. 349, 3543il
(1912).
3. See, e.g .. Bew \'. Travelers' Ins. Co .. 95 N.J.L. 533. 112 A. 859 (1921); Travelers'
Ins. Co. v. Peake. 82 Fla. 128.89 So. 418 (1921); Meredith v. Business Mens Accident
Assn .. 213 Mo. App. 688, 252 S.W. 976 (1923); Head v. New York Lie Ins. Co., 43
F.2d 517 (10th Cir. 1930).
4. Wells v. Kansas City Life Ins. Co .. 46 F. Supp. 754, 758 (D.N.D. 1942), alld.
133 F.2d 224 (8th Cir. 1943). For a summary of the development of the law in these
insurance cases, see Annot .. 45 A.L.R.2d 462 (1956).
5. Auerbach, Garrison. Hurst & Mermin. The Legal Process 85 (J96J). The
authors go on to say (at 85-86): "For instance, the fact of abundant land permitted
a legal policy of liberal disposition of the public domain; led to habits of waslefuJ-
A.
Yet, after all this has been said, it remains true that the "law"
blade of the lawsociety scissors must be reckoned with. Among other
ness, ultimately requiring legislation on conservation; and promoted an American
tendency to thumb one"s nose at Jegal authority (one could. if necessary. mo\"e on).
A difference in the availability of water, as between the arid western states and the
easlern Slales, correlates with clear differences in the legal doctrines governing the
use of water in the various Slates. Although the Supreme Court held in 1825 that
the federal admiralty and maritime jurisdiction extended only to tidewater, it over
ruled itself in 1851, recognizing explicitly that the effects of the invention of the
steamboat and seulement of the Mississippi \'a11e)' upon commerce on navigable
streams made it necessary that the federal jurisdiction apply to all na"igable \\'3lers.
Technological change iII such fields as printing and telegraph), produced new legal
problems. in areas of trademark and copyright, libel, and freedom of speech. Urban
ization. the coming of the automobilt-. mass production, meant new problems for
legal solution, and new doctrines in auto negligence law. legislation on health. safet)"
fair dealing, employer-employee relations, monopolies. and man)' other SUbjects.
Technological change also affected law enforcement: it made enforcement in some
ways more difficult (e.g., the auto provided a fast means of escape) but in m::my ways
easier (officials had not only fast transport and quick communication, but many
scientific weapons of crime detection)". For concise elaboration of the dependent
aspect of the role of law, see Hurst, The Growth of American Law 3-19 (1950).
6. The factor of "drifl and inertia," not as commonly noticed as the others
listed here, has been emphasized by Hurst. See, e.g., Hurst, Law and Social Process
in United States History 6375 (1960); Law and Social Order in the United States
6367, 206213 (1977).
7. Included in this "legal" world is the intellectual and charismatic force exerted by particular individuals - the "greats" among the judges, legislators. admin
istrators, and advocates.
8. This is the sort of thing that Roscoe Pound discussed (sometimes, I think,
in exaggerated fashion) in lenns of "the tenacity of a taught tradition," "received
ideals" of rightness and wrongness, and "recei\"ed techniques" of utilizing "principles"
to "bring about a body of logically interdependent precepts." See Pound, supra n.2.
9. For exposition of the point in the parenthesis, sec Chap. 4 herein under A.
The rest of the material in the paragraph reflects a familiar "cultural lag" idca:
The ability of new social forces to supplant existing legal rules is diminished by the
sticky persistence of the old rules, assisted by COUrls whose interpretations of com
mon law, statute, or constitution are initially shaped more by [he old order than
tbe new. Also, the mere attainment of a legal change - even one that is relarively
inelfectj\'e - has sometimes defused the social and political forces responsible for the
change. See Tushnet, Commentary. Perspectives On the Development of American
Law, 1977 Wis. L. Rev. 81, 102-105. And survival of some rules and traditions may
be due not to their acceptability to dominant social groups but to their relation to
other rules and traditions that do have such acceptability. Nelson, Legal History.
Ann. Survey Am. L 625, 639640 (19781974).
10. For realistic details on the striking impact of a number of Burger Court
rulings on personal rights (indigent misdemeanants' right to counsel; hearings with
procedural safeguards for alleged probation and parole violators; severe limits on
death penalty; limits on involuntary commitment of mentally ill; abortion rights).
see Choper, Judicial Review and the National Po1itical Process 108-122 (1980).
B. Functions of Law
B.
Functions of Law
Let me now explore one general aspect of this relation: What does law
do for people in our society - or, putting it in terms of what the legal
agencies are supposed to do or are trying to do (sometimes successfully),
what are the social functions of our law?
You probably think first about the dispute-settling function. We
do tend to think about the courts and their business of settling disputes. These may be disputes between private parties, or between a
private party and a government unit or official, or between different
government units or officials. Many government administrative agencies also engage in adjudicative dispute-settling. But it is worth remembering that private individuals functioning in the area of labor
arbitration and commercial arbitration already account for a larger
number of dispute settlements per year than do all the courts of the
nation. Here too, however, the courts playa role - they can be called
on to enforce the arbitration award, and sometimes to enforce an agreement to arbitra teo
Another function we tend to think of right away is maintaining
II. Thus. Friedman, A History of American Law (1973) has been laken to task
for its stated "jew of law (at 10) as a "mirror of society" or as "molded by economy
and society." For criticism based on the book's relative neglect of social factors other
than economic. of "autonomous" and "ideological" aspects of law, and of the recip-.
rocal effects of law on society, see Tushnet. supTa 0.9. See also book reviews by
Presser. 122 U. Pa. L. Rev. 217. 225228 (1973). and While. 59 Va. L. Rev. 1130.
1134-1135. 11381141 (1~73). The economic class emphasis in Horwitz. The Trans
formation of American Law, 17801860 (1977) has also been subjected to criticism
for too narrow or doctrinaire a view of legal history. See reviews by Reid, 55 Tex. L.
Re\,. 1307. 13101321 (1977); McClain. 68 Calif. L. Re\,. 382 (1980); Gilmore, 86 Yale
LJ- 788. 79379i (1977); Smith. 1977 Wis. L. Rev. 1253. 12631276; Bridwell. 53 Ind.
L.J. 449 (1978). The "ruling class domination" hypothesis is further criticized in
Hurst. Old and New Dimensions of Research In United States Legal History, 23
Am. J- Legal Hist. I. 14,19 (1979); Pound. Interpretations of Legal History. chap. 5
(1923).
12. E.g.. Tushnet, supra n.9 at 105; Pound, supra n.2 at 366.
13. Hurst. supra n.5 at 4, 9.
B. Functions of Law
planning, too, exemplified by zoning and other land use controls, COn
servation laws, and environmental protections. I think also - because
the legal machinery requires maintaining legal skills for its mainte
nance - of provisions governing the qualifications of lawyers, judges,
and other government officials for their respective vocations. There
are, moreover, measures that build into the system agencies to make
continuing assessments and proposals for improvement of the systeme.g., the state legislative councils and judicial councils, the commis
sioners on uniform state laws, the federal judicial conferences, and
the Administrative Conference of the United States.
In the Constitution can be seen another vital function of our law:
protection Of the citizen against excessive or unfair government power.
I refer mainly to the Bill of Rights - to such basic rights as freedom
of speech, press, and religion, the right 10 privacy and against unreason
able searches and seizure, the privilege against selfincrimination, the
right of jury trial for crime. Remember that the '"due process'" clause
has been construed by the courts to assure both fair procedure and
freedom frof1l arbitrariness in the substance of government require
ments. A standard of equality of treatment applies to the states through
the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment and is, to
some uncertain extent, applicable 10 the federal government through
the due process clause of the Fifth Amendment. Remember also that
included in the due process protection against both governments are
property rights, as well as life and liberty.
Our legal system is concerned, 100, with protecting people against
excessive or unfair private power. In addition 10 antitrust law protec
tion against private monopolistic power are a number of specialized
protections. For example, an employer's power is curbed by laws like
those compelling the payment of minimum wages, or prohibiting dis
crimination in employment, or compelling collective bargaining with
unions; a corporation's power in the sale of its securities is curbed by
SEC requirements. Analogous restrictions apply through a host of
regulatory laws and administrative commissions on both federal and
state levels.
Somewhat overlapping in function with these laws are some that
are aimed at assuring people an opportunity to enjoy the minimum
decencies of life by protecting their economic and health status. These
functions have been more prominent in the later history of our society.
I have in mind laws on unemployment insurance, social security, IIledicare, public housing, welfare, and anti poverty programs, as well as
older statutes like those on bankruptcy and garnishment. I would also
include measures for psychic health, by which I mean not only go\"eru
ment services for the poor who are mentally ill, but also measures
attempting to eliminate various external sources of psychic distress.
1.
B. Functions of Law
Thus. the judges are in effect saying: One ought not to have to
respond to damages here. because one ought not to have legal obliga.
tions that (I) strongly limit our basic ideal of individual freedom of
action (including our freedom to do nothing) by requiring affirmative
action in an emergency situation where it is not clear that the average
man would so act. especially in the absence of a known requirement to
do so; (2) are very difficult to administer because of the vagueness of
the rule and because of the difficulty arising from there being more
than one spectator On hand. i.e . which one has the duty? and if all
have. won't they get in each other's way? (3) apply in the kind of emer
gency situations where people tend to freeze Or panic. In short. the
judges are saying in this situation - and in others that could be
cited" - that it is unfair or too violative of other values to impose a legal
duty here. You may disagree with the reasoning. but you cannot say
the law is being indifferent to ethical or moral duties. In its concern
with standards of conduct. the law is honeycombed with "ought'" prop
ositions that purport to be rationally based. After all. the law is not
an end in itself; it is a means for the achievement of social ends. Even
the Sabbath. we are told. was made for man. not man for the Sabbath.
Perhaps you lend to think of a judge's decision as valuefree. i.e .
as flowing strictly and logically from the unequivocal requirements of
17. Even the duty toward truth may. in some circumstances, be rationally sacrificed in the light of other values. In criminal cases, concern for the defendant (who,
except in minor cases, is in peril of depTh'alion of his liberty) has led OUT law to
entitle the defendant to PUt the burden on the prosecution to prove its case beyond a
reasonable doubt, even when he and his lawyer know he is guilty; i.e., the defendant
is entitled to lie by pleading "nol guilty." And afler an acquittal, he cannot be
subjected to double jeopardy by re-prosecution for the same crime - even if overwhelming new evidence has been discovered manifesting his guilt and the perjury of
his testimony. He could be prosecuted for the separate crime of that perjury, but not
on the basis of any part of the testimony "that related to the elemenLs of the charge
on which the acquittal was obtained. And in the civil area, most jurisdictions pTO
hibit suits for libel, malicious prosecution, or similar forts where the foundation of
the suit is the al1eged commission of perjury by the [present] defendant in prior
litigation which led to a judgment against the present plaintiff. The values of finality
in litigation - and peJce for those released by a jUdgment from entoilment in j t arc in these instances thought to override the imere5t in finding the truth." Wolfram,
Client Perjury: The KUlak Commission and the Association of Trial Lawyers on
Lawyers, Lying Clients, and the Adversary System. 1980 Am. B. Foundation Research
J. 964, 976.
Another illustration involves the controverted question whether a lawyer should,
by disclosure to the court, breach his client's confidences about perjury committed
or to he committed by the client. The argument for nondisclosure has been: "If an
attorney were required (or. perhaps, even permitted) to reveal client perjury, this
would unduly chill the willingness of too many clients to confide in their attorneys
their knowledge of matters that, perhaps mistakenly, they might regard as embarrassing, illegal. dangerous, or irrelevant. Unless attorneys are able to assure their
clients that nothing they reveal to them will be used against their interesls, it is
feared that much [hal should be revealed will remain unknown to the lawyer." Id.
Further on this issue of lawyer disClosure, see Postscript herein at nn. 7679.
10
C.
Limits of Law
Given some such list of law's functions as I have set out - and other
lists could be compiled, shorter ?r longer, or couched in different categories 19 - an interesting question is, how far can these functions go?
What kinds of specific barriers have been encountered in the attempt
to fulfill these functions? What, in other words, are the major "limits
on effective legal action," to use the phrase of Roscoe Pound? By this
I don't mean legal limits like those set by the Constitution. I am concerned rather with the important nonlegal or practical limits that are
rooted, you might say, in the human condition - though I shall occasionally refer to the Constitution as well.
I.
Social Conditioning
One outer limit, of course, arises from an already mentioned fact: the
social conditioning of law. In other words, if basic socioeconomic conditions and interests have a shaping influence on the law, one cannot
18. Cohen, Ethical Systems and Legal Ideals
~2-~3
contrary and presently distinctly minority view is Dworkin's assertion thal ('''en in
"hard cases," there is a single correct or right answer deri,'abJe from legal principles
(rather than "policies"). including. in case of ambiguities or conflict of principle.
more ultimate principles underlying the olhers and the legal system as a wlH'!e.
See text of Chap. 4 herein at nn. ::?734.
19. Thus, Professor Hurst observes that within the limits of the ideal of "con
stitutionalism," Jaw's functions in American history were (1) embodying tht. "legili
mate monopoly of force" and claiming "as a corollary. the right to apprJ.ist' lil"
C.
Limits of Law
11
expect the law to turn around and completely transcend those conditions and interests_ No one. in a society with the kind of private property substructure that America now has. expects that Congress will in
the foreseeable future pass a National Communization of Property
Act destroying and replacing tha t substructure_
This is not to say that gradual legislative restrictions on private
property rights have not occurred and will not occur_ Some of these
occurrences I have mentioned in discussing the function of law_ They
have occurred in spite of the fact that legislators' economic interest is
generally viewed as closer to that of the "Establishment" than to the
classes that were principal beneficiaries of the legislation_ The same
can be said of the role played by. and prior backgrounds of. the judges.
Paul Freund reminded us in 1949 of Supreme Court justices who on
the bench departed from views held. or probably held. in their preCourt careers. 20 More recent exam pies also can be found. 21
Yet when all such cautionary qualifications have been made. it remains true that "the business of a legal system is to make the postulates
of a society work. It would be remarkable indeed if it could be so
worked as to secure their fundamental transformation ..... Thus one
aspect of the social conditioning limit on law is that basic change in
the socioeconomic structure is. to put it mildly. neither easily nor
legitimacy of all pri\'3te forms of power," (2) emphasizing "regular and rational
procedures," as well as "some level of rationality in the substance of public policy,"
(3) "aIIorat[ing] scarce economic resources . . . by taxing and by spending" and in
directly by "public borrowing and also by the standards by which it regulated
beha\'ior (as when by setting standards for marketing food. it required a cenain
leveJ of capital investment by food dealers):' Hurst, Legal Elements in United Slates
History, in Fleming & Bailyn, eds., Law in American History 36 (1971). Llewellyn
thought that the "law-jobs" consisted of: "cleaning up . . . grievances and disputes";
"channeling conduct .. _ 50 that, negatively grie\'ances and disputes are avoided,
and, positively. men's work is geared inw team-play"; tIre-channeling along new
Hnes"; "allocation of that say which in case of doubt or trouble is to go, and, , .
the procedures for making that sayan official and binding sa y"; "producing a net
organization and direction of the work of the whole group or society, and in a
fashion which unleashes incentive"; "building and using techniques and skills for
keeping the men and machinery of an the law-jobs on their jobs and up to the jobs."
Llewellvn, On the Good, the True, the BeaUliful in Law,9 U, Chi. L. Re\'. 224. 253
(1942); The Normative. the Legal, and Ihe Law Jobs, 49 Yale L.J. 1355. 13i3HOO
(1940). Summers and Howard recognize seven functions of law: helping w (1) pro
mote human health, inchJding a healthy environment, (2) reinforce the family and
protect private life, (3) keep community peace, (4) protect basic freedoms. (5) secure
equality of opportunity. (6) recognize and order private ownership, (7) exercise
surveillance and control over persons in poSitions of power. Summers &: Howard,
La ..... , Its Nature, Functions and Limits 440 (2d ed. 1972). See also Raz, The Authority
of Law 163179 (1979).
20. Freund, On Understanding the Supreme Court 45-47 (1949). See also Croyle,
Industrial Accident Liabi1ity Policy of the Early Twentieth Century, 7 J. Legal Stud.
279 (1978).
21. See Chap. 4 herein. text at nn. 7482.
22. Laski, The State in Theory and Practice 177 (1935).
12
1.
2.
A second limit that comes quickly to mind is that the law dare not
get too far away from popular attitudes. habits. and ideals in the vari
ous situations that arise in everyday life (this necessity can also be
viewed as a form of social conditioning). A number of these habits.
attitudes. and ideals will be dealt with below.
a.
The significance of the role of racial or ethnic prejudice in our society needs no elaboration. 23 The difficulties we have encountered in
enforcing racial desegregation have stemmed largely from strongly en
trenched popular attitudes or habits on the part of substantial seg
ments of the population. It is possible - but far from easy - for the
law to help change those racial or ethnic attitudes. 1 shall comment
later on some basis for optimism 'in this respect.
b.
23. See generally. 12 Iml. Encyc. Soc. Sci. 439451; 13 id. at 277282 (1968).
C. Limits of Law
c.
13
14
I.
d.
Let me now expand on the role of the jury. The oft-noted observation that juries exert a moderating influence on the rigors of the
law seems accurate, though exaggerated. Elaborate studies by the University of Chicago Law School show that in about 17 percent of criminal cases, the jury acquitted when the judge (who had been asked by
the researchers to record his own attitude) would have convicted; and
in convictions in capital cases, the discretion whether to assess the
27. Furman \'. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (19i~). T\"\'o of the majority of fi\"e look the
absolUle position that the death penalty itself was "CTuel and unusual punishment."
The other three based their position on the arbitrary or discriminatory choice in
imposition of the penalty and its infrequent. hence nondelerrent, imposition.
28. The death penalty cases are treated in App. 2 herein at nn. ~40245.
29. Opinion polls on the subject have shown considerable fiuc!U3tion o\'er the
years. with a majoriry at the time of Fwman (ranging from about 50 to 5i%)
apparently supporting capital punishment for murder. Vidmar & Ellswonh. Public
Opinion and the Death Penally. 26 Stan. L. Rev. ]245. 1249-1250 (19i-:l). There are
discrepancies in percentage of support ",hen the questions are generJI. J!' Jgainst
when they pinpoint specific circumstances: and also when differenl subpop:daliom
aTe isolaled. Jd. at 1250-]255. Justice MarshaIrs concurrence in Funnan obs('rved
thJt the public is ill informed Jbout GlpilJJ punishment. and [hal if informed of ils
purposes and liabilities. a majoril), would fint! il immoral. -108 U.S. a[ 3o!.!. 363.
C.
Limits of Law
15
death penalty was exercised against the death penalty slightly more
by the jury than by the judge.'o
In recent years, the controversy over the jury's moderating, or in
deed "nullification," power in criminal cases has been most prominent
in connection with prosecutions for politically motivated crimes - e.g.,
those stemming from opposition to the Vietnam War. Defendants'
lawyers have asked judges to instruct juries that they have the power
to acquit when they have strong reasons (of conscience, let us say) to
depart from the law laid down by the other instructions. Current legal
opinion seems strongly against such a nullification instruction,3l
though in the early years of the Republic the jury was legally the final
arbiter of both the law and the facts." The Chicago research figures
previously cited suggest that the jury today in fact does exercise this
nullification power occasionally.'3 The researchers assert that "the jury
does not often consciously and explicitly" depart from the law."' One
reason may be that, in the oft.expressed view of Judge Jerome Frank,
juries often do not understand the instructions. a5
30. Ka]"en & Zeisel. The American Jury 56, 62, 436 (1966). The figures are reo
stated somewhat differently after "hung juries" (see id. at 57) are taken into account:
Concerning jury trials in aU criminal cases, the "jury is less lenient than the judge
in 3% of the cases and mOTe lenient than the judge in 19% of the cases. Thus, the
jury trials show on balance a net leniency of 16%" (at 59).
31. See Sparr and Hansen v. U.S., 156 U.S. 51 (1895); Leventhal, J. [or the
majority in U.S. v. Dougherty, 473 F.2d 1113, 11301137 (D.C. Cir. 19i2); St3te V.
McClanahan, 212 Kan. 208. 510 P.2d 153 (1973); Simson. Jury Nullification in the
American System: A Skeptical View, 54 Tex. L. Re\,. 488 (19i6); Christie, Lall..-ful
Departure From Legal Rules: "Jury Nullification" and Legitimated Disobedience.
62 Cali[. L. Re\,. 1289. 1~961305, esp. 13021305 (1974). See also Kadish & Kadish,
Discretion to Disobey 4572, esp. 6465 (1973).
For contrary views see Justice Gray's dissenting opinion in Spar!, supra at
110-177; Judge Bazelon's dis..<:.ent in Dougherly, supra at Il38-1144: Scheflin 8:
\'an Dyke, Jury N'uIJification: The Contours of a Contro\:ersy. 43 L. & Contemp.
Prob. 51 (1980); Sax, Conscience and Anarchy: The Prosecution of \\'ar Resistors.
57 Yale Rev. 481 (1968). Constitutional pro\'isions in Indiana and Maryland are
construed. \\.ithin certain limits. to gi\'e the jury the right in criminal cases to determine law as well as facts and thereby depart from instructions on the law if it
wishes to acquit. or to convict of a lesser offense. (See discussion in ScheHin &
"an Dyke, sup7'a at 79-85.)
32. See, e.g., Howe. Juries As Judges of Criminal Law, 52 Har\,. L. Rev. 582
(1939).
33. Kal\'en & Zeisel, supra n.30, point to a number of reasons, not envisaged in
the instructions, for jury \'erdicts disagreeing with whal the presiding judge's verdict
would ha\'e been. These include: unpopularity of the statute; and jury sentiments
concerning proper boundaries of self-defense, significance of the victim's own fauh,
the suffering already experienced by the defendant. or the se\'erity of the threatened
punishmenL. Mainly, the jury "yields to sentiment in the apparent process of reo
solving doubts as to evidence. The jury . .. is able to conduct its re\'olt from the
law within the etiquette of resolving issues of fact" (at 165).
34. Id. at 165.
35. Frank. Courts On Trial ll6-118. 130 (1950). His general attack on the jury
syslem (mainly in civil cases) is at 108-145. See also, on jury underslanding of the
instructions. Chap. 2 herein at nn. 173175.
16
I,
C.
Limits of Law
17
e.
like Kenneth Davis (id., 9: 19: 13; Davis, Discretionary Justice 188214 (1969 have
argued for fuller recognition of reviewabiJity. as well as (on the federal agency le'\'el,
at least) for greater use of prosecutorial policy statements, findings, and reasons in
making various kinds of prosecution decisions.
38. "Many persons whose conduct apparently violates the criminal law are not
arrested. In some instances this can be explained by the fact that there is no legis lath'e purpose (0 enforcing some statutes which are obsolete or drafted in o\'erly
general or ambiguous terms." There are other reasons, such as inadequacy of avail
able enforcement resources, or the use of non-arrest as a reward for information.
LaFave, Arrest 910 (1965). See id. at 6382, 492495; 2 Davis, supra n.37, 9:149:22;
Davis, Police Discretion (1975); Thomas & Fitch, The Exercise of Discretionary
18
I.
C.
Limits of Law
19
This rather pennissive attitude in the area of consensual sex conduct is a good ilIustration of a more encompassing attitude, strongly
held by large numbers of people and in even larger proportion among
young people_ I have in mind the drawing of a circle around certain
kinds of conduct as being "private" - conduct that the law should not
stick its nose into in order to promote one view of morality, or further
the defendant's own good, as distinguished from the purpose of protecting other people from hann_ John Stuart MilI expressed this quite
common attitude when he said in the first chapter of his essay "On
Liberty": "The object of this essay is to assert one simple principle,
as entitled to govern absolutely the dealings of society with the individual by way of compulsion and control. whether the means used be
political force in the fonn of legal penalties, or the moral coercion of
public opinion_ That principle is that ___ the only purpose for which
power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent hann to others_ His own good,
either physical or mental, or moral, is not a sufficient warrant:'43 (Crthe play, "Hair," Act I: "Kids, be free_ Be whatever you are, do whatever you want to do, just as long as you don't hurt anybody_")
Such a principle extends far beyond the field of sexual behavior.
On the basis of this principle, for instance, it could be argued that a
state could not compel a person to accept for his own good a life-preserving blood transfusion he did not want; Or compel mental health
treatment for the harmlessly insane; or compel participation in an air
raid drill, or the wearing of seatbelts by autoists and helmets by motorcyclists; or prohibit euthanasia, or attempted suicide; or prohibit gambling, prostitution, or personal use or consumption (or possession for
personal use or consumption) of alcohol, drugs (at least "soff' drugs,
such as marijuana), or obscene material; or prohibit abortions, particularly early ones_
These positions could be argued_ Whether such arguments would
or should succeed in all instances is another question_ The problem
is that the ambiguities and exceptions in Mill's "simple principle"
or menta] defects. or that the pregnancy resulLed from rape. incest, or other felonious
intercourse. Such a stature does not go far enough. in the light of the subsequent
Supreme Court decisions in Rot: v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, and Doe v. Bollon. 410 U.S.
]79 (19i3) im.'alidating the then typical restrictive laws against abortion. The Court
treated the decision to abort as a malleT of the woman's constitutional "pri\'ac)'"
right which she is free to exercise in the first trimester of pregnancy in consultation
with her physician. The Court did rule that the state may regulate abortion in the
second trimester in ways reasonably related to maternal health; and the state ma~'
go so far as to prohibit abortion after \'iability of the fetus, except where the abortion js necessary to preserve the mother's life or heahh.
43. Mill. Utilitarianism. Liberty and R. presentati\'e Government 72-73 (E\'eryman ed. 1910).
20
make its application anything but easy. For instance, what kind and
what quantity of "harm" to others will qualify? Looking at the differ
ences in the American Law Institute's treatment of various harms sug
gests that the Institute's application of the Mill principle has been
based upon judgment, prediction, and weighing of freedom against
other values rather than upon any self-evident inferences from the
"simple principle."" Indeed, Mill himself seemed aware of some of
the possible difficulties in applying the "harm" concept,.5 and recog
nized some actual exceptions to his principle, as did his critics. 4s Yet
44. In the case of homosexuality, the Institute had to consider the relevance of
psychological harm, i.e., distress, caused to the opponents of sexual freedom from
[~e mere knowledge that private homosexual conduct was occurring without legal
hmdrance. Furthermore, these opponents could argue (as Lord Devlin of England
has argued) that there is potentially a strong threat of social disintegration created
by removing criminal prohibitions from conduct beHeved by the average person to
be immoral and disgusting. Alternatively, in the case of fornication and adultery.
one might argue that these practices cause indiTect haTm to the institution of maTriage and the family. Under the previously quoted rhilosophy of the American Law
Institute, however, all these kinds of harms do not qualify - apparently because
they are not viewed as sufficiently probable and substantial enough to justify (I) the
invasion of human freedom and privacy invoI\'ed in criminaUy punishing private
consensual conduct, and (2) certain costs attendant upon atlempted enforcement.
But some other kinds of hann - even though invohing consent and occurring in
prhate - would qualify and thus faU in the realm of prohibition. For instance, the
ALI has not suggested that our long-standing and relati\'ely uncriticized prohibitions against assaults in . . .olving mu[Ual consent (induding sadomasochistic sex practices) should be removed from the books. Nor has it been willing to decriminalize
prostitution, genera]]y a consensual and pri,ale act.
45. Mill recognized that "the mischief which a person does to himself may
seriously affect, both through their sympathies and their interests. those nearly connected with him and, in a minor degree, society at large," and that a judgment had
to be made whether the conduct had produced "definite damage, or a definite risk
of damage. either to an individual or to the public:' Mill, supra n.43 at 137. 138.
Interestingly. he couJd not make up his mind ho''''' to decide the issue of whether a
legal system that did not punish fornication or gambling should punish the pimp
and the keeper of a public gambling house. Id. at 154-155.
46. A recent critical discussion of the Mill principle, Grey. The Legal Enrorce
ment of Morality 1-35 (ABA Commission on Undergraduate Education in Law and
[he Humanities, 1980), points to a few areas of Jaw where we now ha"e. and would
want to retain, penal sanctions against mere psychological harm, i.e., distress - and
argues that this undermines the Mill principle, construed as denigrating all such
alleged harm. See for further critical discussion, ReynoldS, The Enforcement of
Morals and the Rule of Law, II Ga. L. Rev. 1325 (1977); Golding. Philosophy of
Law 54-59 (1975); Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (1965); Hart, Law. Liberl), and
Morality (1963); Schwartz, Morals Offenses and the Model Penal Code, 63 Col urn. L.
Rev. 669. 6i5677 (1963).
In referring to Mi1l's own recognition or exceptions to his principle. I do not
mean ani)' his toleration of slate paternal intenention to protect children, the feeble
minded, and backward peoples. He thought the freedom to sell oneself inlo slavery
was properly restrained by law - because his principle was designed to presene
freedom of choice, and this purpose would be defealed by conduci precluuing
future use of that freedom. Mill, supra nAj at 157158. This category of exception
could be extended beyond slavery to situations in which the law cUTIails the freedom
of an individual to commil a serious injury against himself. such as suicide or maim-
C. Limits of Law
21
22
I.
C.
Limits of Law
23
1973 decisions),5. and laws against possession of obscene films, as applied to possession of films in the home, intended for viewing therein_ 5
32-39 (1978); Cox, The Role of the Supreme Court in American Government 1J3-1J4
(1976); Lusky, By What Right 15-17, 100 (1976). The companion case of Doe v.
Bolton, 410 U.s. 179 (1973) among other things held unconstitutional a state law
requiring (1) that aU abortions be performed only in certain accredited hospitals,
and that a hospital committee approve aU abortions contemplated by the hospital's
docwrs, (2) that two other doctors must first concur in the decision to abort, and
(3) that abortions be limited to the state's residents.
58. The case of Planned Parenthood of Mo. v_ Danforth. 428 U.S. 52 (1976) upheld state provisions that (1) defined viability of the fetus (in a provision restricting
abortions to those necessary for preserving the mother's life or health unless a
doctor's certification of non-Viability has been obtained) in terms of the stage of
fetal development when life may be continued indefinitely outside the womb by
natural or artificial support systems: (2) required that a woman prior to an abortion
during the first 12 weeks must certify in writing her consent to the procedure. and
that her consent is informed and freely given without coerdon; (3) required certain
record-keeping and reporting on the health facilities and physicians concerned,
irrespective of the pregnancy stage involved. But the court held unconstitutional,
provisions (I) requiring written consent of the spouse for abortion during the first
12 weeks unless a doctor certifies the abortion to be necessary to preserve the mother's
life; (2) requiring any person perfonning or inducing an abortion at any stage of
pregnancy to exercise, on pain of manslaughter penalty in case of the fetus's death,
the same professional skill, care, and diligence to preserve the fetus's health as required to preserve the health of a fetus intended to be born and not abOrLed; (3)
requiring. with respect to an abortion in the first 12 weeks of pregnancy of an unmarried woman under 18, the written consent of a parent or person in loco parentis.
unless a doctor certifies the abortion to be necessary to preserve the mother's life;
(4) prohibiting after the first 12 weeks of pregnancy an abortion technique whereby
the amniotic fluid is withdrawn and a saline or other fluid is inserted into the
amniotic sac.
However, in H.L. v. Matheson. 67 L. Ed, 2d 3BB (1981). the CoUrt upheld a st:lle
law requiring a doctor to "notify if possible" the parents of a minor upon whom
he was to perform an abortion - as applied to an unemancipated, unmarried fifteenyearold girl living with and dependent on her parents - even though the law did
not provide for a mandatory period of delay after such notification or a description
of what information the parents could supply the doctor, and allowed a pregn;;mt
minor to consent to other procedures without formal notice to her parents if she
carried the child to term.
Final1y. in Maher v. Roe. 432 U.S. 464 (1977), the Court ruled that a slate that
funded childbirth senjces for indigents could properly exclude indige11ls' 1Ion-llwrapeutic abortions /TOm public funding and could require. for medically necessary
abortions. the indigent woman's prior consent in writing and the state official's prior
authorization of payment. And even where the exclusion of public funding applied
to some medically necessary abortions (funding being restricted. under the most
extreme version of the federal "Hyde amendment," to cases where childbirth would
threaten the mother's life - thus eXc1uding abortions that threatened her physical
or mental health) the Court upheld the exclusion, in Harris \I. McRae. 448 U.S. 297
(1980).
See generally, Symposium on the Law and Politics of Abortion, 77 Mich. L. Rev.
1569 (1979); Dembitz, The Supreme Court and a Minor's AborLion Decision, 80
Colum. L. Rev. 1251 (1980): Goldstein, A Critique of the Abortion Funding Decisions:
On Private Rights in the Public Sector, 8 Hastings Const. L.Q. 313 (1981); Isaacs, Law
of Fenilit}' Regulation in U.S.: 1980 Review. 19 J. Fam. L. 65 (1980) (abortion,
contraception, and sterilization).
59. Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.S. 557 (1969).
24
I.
C.
Limits of Law
25
26
who did have the capacity to control himself and appreciate the
wrongfulness of his conduct. Any such similar treatment would
arouse a widely shared sense of injustice. Even a dog, Holmes reminded
us, distinguishes between being kicked and being stumbled over.
The proposed reform encounters, therefore, one of law's powerful
limits and is unlikely to receive any near future acceptance.
Much the same point is illustrated by the limits on the possibility
of extending "strict liability" in criminal law. This needs a little explanation. The typical crime involves a certain culpable mental element,
as for instance the intent to kill, the intent to take away another's
property without his consent, or carelessness that is gross enough (in
relation to the circumstances known by defendant) to amount to
criminal negligence. The typical tort, too, involves culpability or fault,
as for instance the intent to assault, the intent to defame, or negligence
(by which is meant the failure to abide by the standard of conduct
which would have been followed by a "reasonable man" in the circumstances involved).
In the tort field there have developed some areas of "strict liability," i.e., liability without fault. One example is the workmen's compensation system under which the worker injured on the job files his
claim with an administrative agency and collects compensation on the
basis of a governmentally prescribed schedule of benefits. He does not
have to assert the employer's negligence, or his own freedom from
contributory negligence. The financial structure varies, but a common
system is for the compensation payments to be made by the insurance
company with which the employer has insured himself. Another illustration of strict liability in tort is the field of "products liability."
Suppose you were personally injured in an auto accident because your
steering wheel had a defect which was unknown to you and which
was there when the car left the factory. If you can prove these facts to
the satisfaction of the jury, then under the developing law of recent
years you would be able to recover damages from the manufacturer
without proving negligence on his part.
In neither of these tort fields has there been very strong criticism
of the fact that liability was being imposed in the absence of fault.
We have, in recent decades, been increasingly sympathetic to the injured worker and injured consumer; the negligence standard in both
fields has not worked out satisfactorily for plaintiffs; the employer and
manufacturer defendants are in a better position to shoulder the loss,
and can protect themselves by insurance. Moreover, under the strict
66. See PackeT, The Limits of the Criminal Sanction 62-69. 131]35 (1968):
Kadish, The Decline of Innocence. 26 Cambridge L.J. 273. 283 (1968). For a summary
survey of the problems posed by the insanity reform proposals. sec Monahan.
Abolish the Insanity Defense?- NOl Yel. 26 Rutgers L. Re\". 719 (19i3).
C.
Limits of Law
27
liability standard they are not going to jail and are free from the
stigma of a criminal conviction. "It's only money" they are paying out,
in insurance premiums, and the added costs can probably be reflected
in their selling prices.
There are similar practical reasons for the growing success of the
movement for "no-fault" auto accident insurance - under which at
least certain economic losses from accidents (medical expenses, "loss of
work income) would be recovered under the victim's own insurance
policy, regardless of who was at fault. A mounting concern over the
difficulties, delays, and inequities of the prevailing "fault" system has
made people receptive to such an alternative system (of which there
are many varieties) that promises to be cheaper and to make recoveries
more rapid and certain. 57 There are even proposals now to extend the
no-fault insurance approach beyond automobiles, i.e., to accidents
involvi ng other products and services as well. 5
The situation is quite different when you are dealing with strict
criminal liability. Criminal liability without fault has existed on the
outer edge of criminal law but it has been a slightly growing edge,
with a tendency of the laws to extend beyond such standard categories
as food and drugs, liquor, conservation, and traffic regulation. 5 ' The
sense of injustice that I earlier described with respect to the insanity
defense operates here too, and is mirrored in the call by scholars for
a halt to the spread of strict criminal liability, and in the willingness
of courts to reject the idea that imprisonment can ever be imposed on
a strict liability basis, and in the forthright position of the American
Law Institute that: "Crime does and should mean condemnation and
no court should have to pass that judgment unless it can declare that
the defendant's act was wrong. This is too fundamental to be com
promised. The law goes far enough if it permits the imposition of a
monetary penalty in cases where strict liability has been imposed. "70
67. ABA Special Commission on Automobile Insurance Legislation, Automobile
NoFau1t Insurance (1978); Epsl.ein. Automobile No-Fault Pl:Jns: A Second Look al
First Principles, 13 Creighwn L. Rev. 769 (1980); O'Connell. The Injury Industry
(1971); I'\ew York Insurance Depanment (report to Go\'ernor Rockefeller), Automobile Insurance . . . for Whose Benefit? (1970): U.S. Depanmenl of Transportation, Molor Vehicle Crash Losses and Their Compensation in the United Slates
(I971); Kimbal1. AUIOmtrbiie Accident Compensation Systems-Objectives and Per
speClives, 1967 U. III. L.F. 370.
6B. See O'Connell, Ending Insult to Injury: Nofault Insurance [or Product~
and Services (1975); O'Connel1. The Lawsuit Lotlery: Only the Lawyers ''''in (19i9).
69. See ALI Model Penal Code. Commentary at 141]45 (Tent. Draft 1\"0. 4.
1955); Saltzman, Strict Criminal Liability and the United States Constitulion: Suh
sLamive Criminal Law Due Process, 24 \Vayne L. Rev. 1571 (197B); Note, 75 Colum.
L. Rev. 1517 (1975).
70. ALI. supra n.69 at 140. See scholars cited therein after the quot:J.lion; see
also Commonwealth v, Koczwara, 397 POl. 575. 155 A.2d 825 (1959); Morisetre v. U.S.,
342 U.S. 216 (1952).
28
I.
h.
C.
Limits of Law
29
3.
I come now to a third type of limit - one which is set by human frail
ties in moments of grea t stress.
1. For example. the law tends to deal rather leniently with some
kinds of criminal conduct that are impelled by a sense of overwhelming necessity. You have no doubt heard of the famous American
criminal case involving the lifeboat. adrift on rough seas. that was
leaking and so overcrowded that the first mate thought it imperative
to throw some people overboard in order to lighten the load and
thereby save the lives of others. rather than lose the lives of all. This
was a case in about mid-nineteenth century. in a lower federal court.'.
The ship William Brown with 65 passengers and a crew of 17 had hit
an iceberg off Newfoundland. About half the passengers went down
with the ship. And so perhaps did a noble maritime tradition: While
the facts are not altogether clear. it seems that the captain and crew
got out first. At least we know that all of them. together with the other
half of the passengers. managed to get into a "long boat" and a "jolly
boat." In the long boat. where the relevant action occurred. there were
9 crew members and 32 passengers. Acting pursuant to the first mate's
orders to spare the women and not part husband from wife. the crew
threw over most of the male adults. Next morning the long boat was
sighted by a ship. and all on board were saved.
73. I Corbin. Contracts 2 (1963).
74. Prosser. Handbook of the Law of Torts 6 (4th ed. 1972).
75. U.S. v. Holmes. 26 F. Cas. 360 (No. 15.383) (C.C.E.D. Pa. 1812). Further on
the Holmes situation. see Cahn, The Moral Decision 61-71 (1955); Hicks, Human
Jettison (1927).
80
I.
C. Limits of Law
31
the high seas.'. There too, because of compassion for human frailties
in situations of overwhelming stress, the letter of the law was moder
ated: A death sentence was commuted by the Crown to six months.?S
There have been cannibalism cases in this country, not all of
which were immortalized in court opinions. One involved the Donner
party, trapped by early snow in what is now known as the Donner Pass
in the high Sierras. Some survivors of the disaster fed on the bodies of
some of the dead, as Bernard De Voto has vividly described. s Murder
and subsequent cannibalism by a Utah gold hunter, Frank Packer, in
Colorado in 1873 drew a sentence of hanging by Judge Gerry in
1883 - of which Gene Fowler contributes a memorable vignette:
Although Judge Gerry delivered what was considered the most eloquent
hanging speech in Western court history, an apocryphal sentence is the
one that persists, and by which this scholarly gentleman'S name still
lives..
Larry Dolan, who had a grudge against Packer, attended every
session of the trial. Between times, Larry filled himself to the larynx
and nO[ to separate man and wife? Should Holmes's order h3\"e been different if the
passengers included chiJdren, a dying man, male and female prisoners being transported to a place of execution. a world-famous male scientist or top political leader
or Olympic record-holder? Is there a "natural law" principle (and if so, should the
criminal law follow it here) that under no circumstances shall an "jnnocem" life be
deliberately taken in order that another, or enn a gTeater number. shall live? Should
the kind of situation in the Holmes case be viewed as governed by the practices
applicable in a "state of nature," i.e., outside the bounds of organized society. on
the theory of Holmes's lawyer th'll "[a}1I became their own 13wgi'\ers. . . . E'\'ery
man on board had a right to make law with his own right hand"!
78. Regina v. Dudley and Stephens. 14 Q.B. 273. 15 Cox Crim. Cas. 624 (1881).
FOUT seamen were in an open boat on the high seas, 1600 miles from the Cape of
Good Hope, having had to abandon a yacht in a storm. After drifting fOT eighteen
days. and after seven days without food and six days without water. two of them
agreed, with the third dissenting, that the fourth seaman - a youth of seventeen or
eighteen who Jay helpless, extremely weakened by famine and the drinking of se3waler-should be killed fOT sustenance the next day if help hadn't ~et arrind. And
kill him they did, next day. All thrt'C' of them fed on hi~ body for four days befort'
being picked up by a passing vessel. The two ringleaders were prosecuted for
murder. The jury found that probably all would ha\'e died ..... ithin the four da)'s
had not the three men fed on the bod)": that probabl)' the youth would ha'\'e died
first anyway. The jury Jeft it to the court to determine whether it was murder. The
judge so held, rejecting the idea that "necessity" could justify taking an innocent
human life. He referred to the "awful danger of admitting the principle which has
been contended (or:' "\\'ho is (0 be the judge of this sort of necessit)"? B)' whJ.t
measure is the' comparative value of lives 10 bl' measuTcd?" For more detail on this
case see Mallin. In \\'3rm Blood: Some Historical and Procedural Aspects of Regina
v. Dudley and Stephens. 34 U. Chi. L. Re\". 387 (1967).
79. Further on lht" type of situation presented in this English case, see Mc
(196~):
FuUpr, The Ca5t' of the Spduncean Explorers. 62 Har'\". L. Rp\". 616 (1949)
(imaginary case and opinions).
SO. D('\"oto. The Year of Decision: ]846, 3t 38638i (19-13). Cannibalism follo\\"
ing an Andes plane crash i~ described in Read. AliH' (l9iI).
lI2
I cannot resist telling one more tale, of the same macabre genre.
The whaleship Essex was rammed and sunk in the Pacific in 1820 by
an enormous whale, and this incident became the climax of Herman
Melville's Moby Dick. What happened after the sinking-which
Melvillf! did not write about - was this: Of the three lifeboats that
were launched, one was lost; on the other two, after lengthy ordeals
of storm and famine, cannibalism was practised on the bodies of a few
who had died. On one boat the men were also driven to kill one of
their number, after drawing lots. The victim was the cabin boy, a
nephew of the master of the Essex, Captain Pollard, who was in the
same lifeboat. "There is a Nantucket legend that when a reporter
from the mainland came out to the island to interview [Captain
Pollard] on his last birthday, the reporter closed the interview with
the personal remark that he was distantly related to one of the Essex'
crew. 'You remember him, of course: he added. 'Remember him: the
old man cackled. 'Hell, son, I et him!' "82
There was apparently no prosecution in this case. "'-'here prosecution did occur in the other cases mentioned, we have seen that the
courts typically refused to recognize a "necessity" defense as such, but
punishment tended to be lenient. "The law falters and averts her face
and sheathes her own sword when pronouncing judgment upon creatures of flesh and blood thus goaded by the Furies."aa (Yes, that was
Cardozo again.) Judge Gerry's treatment of Frank Packer does not fit
this description, but not all the facts of the case are clear; and further
data presented by Gene Fowler might suggest that the multiple killings
were unnecessary and connected with a robbery motive.
Though the states today would rarely be found recognizing a
necessity defense where the defendant had taken an innocent, human
life <as distinct from, say, theft or destruction of another's property),
81. Fowler, Timber Line 37 (1933). Afler reversal and a second ('om'lCllon,
Packer received a life sentence, and was p.udoned after ]8 years. Id., al 38.
82. Whipple, ThreeMonth Ordeal in Open Boats. Life, No\'. 10. 195~, 31 ]56.
83. Hall, ed., supTa n.75 at 390.
C. Limits of Law
33
the American Law Institute's Model Penal Code is willing to go further by recognizing for all crimes a "choice of evils" provision_ This
recognizes as a defense the. defendant's belief in the necessity of his
conduct where "the harm or evil sought to be avoided by [the defendant'S) conduct is greater than that sought to be prevented by the law
defining the offense charged," unless this defense would be inconsistent
with a legislative purpose appearing elsewhere in the state's statutes. 54
2. Related to this necessity defense is a classic defense in terms of
"duress" or coercion. The Model Penal Code, for instance, recognizes
this defense where there was coercion against the defendant by use or
threatened use of unlawful force against the person - force which a
person of reasonable firmness in his situation would have been unable
to resist. 85
3. Some other related situations: You are doubtless familiar with
the fact that some rather frequently occurring stressful circumstances
will mitigate an intentional killing so as to prevent its classification as
"murder." If the circumstances amount to "self-defense," there is a
complete defense to the alleged crime. If the defendant were not acting
in self-defense but his intentional killing can be shown to have been
done "in the heat of passion" and upon "sufficient provocation," then
under many homicide statutes these stressful circumstances would
mitigate the crime from murder to "voluntary manslaughter."
4. A highly stressful situation of still a different sort is that of
euthanasia Or mercy-killing - involving, for example, the terminal
cancer patient who is in great pain which caimot be relieved by drugs
(or can be relieved only by a fatal dosage) and which impels the defendant to commit euthanasia. Here the letter of the law is still against
the act, through a legislative prohibition either against murder or
against assisting a suicide. But the letter of the law is being moderated
by leniency in the administration of the law. There have been anum
ber of cases in which a jury acquittal was based upon a defense in terms
of temporary insanity, or a defense that the conduct of the defendant
had not actually caused the death. You may remember the muchpublicized English trial of Dr. John Bodkin Adams a good many years
ago, skillfully described in Sybille Bedford's book.B. The defense was
in terms of causation - i.e., that his conduct had not caused the death.
The reason why the jury was able to acquit on that ground was that
the judge's instruction said: If the administration of the drug by the
doctor merely had the effect of hastening the death so that it occurred
84. ALI Model Penal Code 3.02 (Proposed Official Draft 1962): id., Com
mentary at 510 (fent. Draft No.8, 1958).
85. ALI Model Penal Code 2.09 (Proposed Official Draft 1962): id., Com
mentary at 216 (fent. Draft No. 10. 1960).
86. Bedford, The Trial or Dr. Adams (1958).
lI4
I.
C.
Limits of Law
35
56
I.
C.
Limits of Law
57
38
inability to get too far out of line with public attitudes. At the close of
. this section on limits of law. I shall have more to say. by way of summary. on the law's capacity to effectively change people's attitudes and
behavior_
Returning then to the main point for which the euthanasia cases
have been used here - the limits put by stressful situations upon the
law's effectiveness - you may well ask: Well. then. why doesn't the
law openly recognize a right of mercy-killing? Why does it cling to the
principle that a defendant's worthy motives may be considered in
mitigation of penalty but not as a complete defense? Apparently for
the same reason that it does not condone the other types of conduct
under stress that I have already noted: the fact that great practical
difficulties and dangers would arise from even such a limited recognition of the right to kill.
4.
C. Limits of Law
39
40
I.
C.
Limits of Law
41
5.
"Internal" Disputes
I move to another category, but it is not wholly a separate one. It involves in part the kind of practical considerations already treated in
the previous category, together with privacy considerations also involved in an earlier category. I am thinking of the situations involving
the internal affairs of nonprofit associations, like families, fraternal
societies, religious groups, and unions.
101. See Weinrib. The Case For A DUly 10 Rescue, 90 Yale L ..J. 217 (1980): NOles.
47 Ind. L.J. 321 (1972). 55 id .. 551 (1980): Franklin. Vermonl Requires Rescue: A
Comment, 25 Stan. L. Re\', 51 (1973); Prosser. supra n.73 at 310-343.
102. Zepeda v. Zeped., 41 III. App. 2d 240. 190 N.E.2d 849 (1963), c<rl. denied,
379 U.S. 945 (1963). See also Williams v. Slale, 18 N.Y.2d 481, 223 KE.2d 343 (1966):
l'\ote. 66 Colum. L. Rev. 127 (1966). Compare a 197i Illinois case recognizing a
child's claim against a doctor and hospital for preconception negligence: i.e .. a
negligent blood transfusion [0 the child's mother over seven years before conception
had caused memal and physical impairments of the child, apparent at birth.
Renslow \', Mennonite Hosp .. 67 Ill. 2d 348. 367 r..;.E.2d 1250 (1977). discussed in
NOle. 48 U. Colo. L. R,,. 62 (1977).
103. Rieck v. Medical Protective Co., 64 Wis. 2d 514. 219 N.\V.2d 242. 245 (1974).
This was a parents' action against the clinic and obstelrician for negligelltly failing
to ascertain the mother'S pregnancy in time to permit abonion,
42
I.
You can see why the law in these situations tends to stay its hand.
Not only are there constitutional restraints to worry about.'"' but a
court's inquiry into, and interpretation of. a group's rules and prac
tices "may lead it into what Professor Chafee has called the 'dismal
swamp: the area of its activity concerning which only the group can
speak with competence."'' The difficulties encountered when the
court tries to provide appropriate remedies must also not be dis
counted. The family is a good example here since some family disputes
are obviously not appropriate for resolution by a court.'G The wife
who complains, for instance, that her husband no longer exhibits
affection, can hardly get a court to order her husband to exhibit affec
tion, or even get a court to order her wayward husband to live under
the same roof. The same goes for certain other family disputes - e.g.,
the proper schooling and upbringing of children.'7
This is not to say that "internal"' affairs of institutional groups are
immune from legal intervention. "Thus, although we must respect the
autonomy of the family, intervention against child abuse is nonetheless
essential. And although we delegate great power to labor unions, we
impose upon them obligations of fair representation . . . ."'.8 As for
churches, the Supreme Court in dealing with church propert), disputes
arising out of church schisms once counseled deference to the judgment
104. For instance, the First Amendment's clauses on religious freedom and
church-state separation represent a barrier to governmem inten'ention in the religious affairs of church institutions. And. "(s]ince the First Amendment and due
process clauses appear to guarantee to individuals the right to associate freely, . . .
intervention might be challenged on constitutional grounds as an interference with
the protected sphere within which groups are free to act as thq' wish. and. in
particular, to choose their own members." I\;ore, 76 Han', L. Re\.. 983, 990-991 (1963).
105. [d. at 99I.
106. For discussion of state intrusion in family affairs. see Note, 26 Stan. L. Rev.
1383 (1974).
107. For example, in }959 the Supreme Court of Alabama considered a case in
which a father was seeking a court injunction to restrain his wife, with whom he was
living, from sending their child to a public rather than a parochial schoo1. The
court decided that it should not interfere at all. It pointed out that the case did
not involve a question concerning custody of the child, incident 10 a separation or
divorce, "but simply whether a court of equity should sellie a difference of opinion
between parents as La what is best for their minor chHd when the parents and the
child are all living together as a family group." "It seems to us," said the court, that
"if we should ho!d that equity has jurisdiction in this case, such holding will open
wide the gales for settlement in equity of all sorts and \"arielies of intimate family
disputes concerning the upbringing of children. The absence of cases dealing with
the question indicates a reluctance of the courts to assume jurisdiction in di!<Oputes
arising out of the intimate family circle. It does not take much imagination to
envision the extent to which explosive differences of opinion between parentl' as to
the proper upbringing of their children would be brought into court for attempted
solution . .. . Considerations of policy and expediency forbid a resort 10 injunctive
relief in such a case: Kilgrow '"- Kilgrow, 268 Ala. 475. 479,108 So. 2d 885, 888 (1959).
108. Tribe, Seven P]uralisl Fallacies: In Defense of the Adversary Process - A
Reply to Justice Rehnquist, 33 U. Miami L. Rc\. 43, 49 (19i8).
C. Limirs of Law
43
44
6.
Now finally let me suggest another broad limit on what the law can
accomplish: the limit that is imposed by the relative dearth of reli
able scientific knowledge.
Reliable knowledge is of course important to legislators. adminis
trators. or judges since they are interested in ascertaining the probable
consequences of their enactments or decisions. Knowledge of this kind
is notoriously limited.
What about the kind of scientific knowledge that would enable
the fact finder in a dispute to accurately reconstruct the happenings
that gave rise to the dispute? We are here dealing with what Max
Radin once called one of the two "pennanent problems of the law"
(the other pennanent problem being the detennination. and the pub
lic's prophesying the determination. of the "just" decision).II" Jerome
Frank. in his popular book COUTts on TTial (1950). vigorously demon
strated the many pitfalls that lie in the path of the fact finder. among
them the uncertainty surrounding the credibility of witnesses. The
law would like to have a surefire method of testing the truth of a wit
ness's testimony; but lie-detector (polygraph) evidence is generally
inadmissible in court. partly because of unreliability. In this instance,
112. It has been urged that the solution for the present failures of narcotics
enforcement is not simply abo1ition of punishment but a system of distribution that
uses doctors to c1.ispense controlled d05CS to addicts while also attempting cures.
requires recordkeeping. and prohibits distribution through other cbanJleJs. Olhers
suggest that the present ineffective prohibitions against marijuana might be
replaced by a system permiuing sales through licensed dealers under a control
system similar to that for liquor. The 1972 Report of the National Commission on
Marijuana and Drug Abuse took a middle ground on marijuana: Production and
distribution of the drug. as well as possession with intent to distribute com
mercial1y. would remain criminal; but personal use. and possession incident thereto.
would be- decriminalized. Further on the varieties or 3\'ailable legislative and judicial
techniques. see the final section of this chapter.
113. Radin. The Permanent Problems of the Law, 15 Cornell L.Q. 1 (19::!9).
C.
Limits of Law
45
though, the main reason for inadmissibility may be not inherent unreliability but the fear that the trier of facts, whether judge or jury,
will tend to give an infallibility to the evidence that it does not
deserve. 1H
Still, in very recent years, some courts have moved in the direction
of admissibility of polygraph evidence, particularly when the tests were
taken "upon stipulation of the parties" ;'15 and some have started admitting (what had previously also been inadmissible) evidence obtained
by hypnosis. 11S Other new techniques of scientific evidence have caused
considerable movement in the field: "Neutron activation analysis,
sound spectrometry (voiceprints), psycholinguistics, atomic absorption,
remote electromagnetic sensing, and bitemark comparisons are but a
sample of the kinds of scientific evidence inundating the courts."l17
Change has worked in the opposite direction, too; there are cases in
which "[slome well-accepted scientific techniques, such as radar and
certain drug-testing procedures, have been challenged successfully."lls
The legal approach to admissibility of evidence in general has
been that any "relevant" conclusions should be admissible, in the absence of factors like "dangers of prejudicing or misleading the jury,
and undue consumption of time"; and this approach, according to
Professor IIIcCormick, should be applied to scientific evidence as well,
when the conclusions are "supported by a qualified expert witness."11.
While some courts have taken this approach, the most popular standard, announced in 1923, makes admissibility of scientific evidence
more difficult: The scientific principle or discovery from which an
experts testimony is deduced "must be sufficiently established to have
gained general acceptance in the particular field in which it belongs."12o
The many problems encountered in applying this standard have provoked strong criticisms, and suggestions for alternative approaches 12] 114. McCormick on Evidence. 207 (2d ed. 1972).
115. See Giane11i. The Admissibility oC No\'el Scientific E\'idence: Frye v. United
Siales, a Half-Century Later. SO Colum. L. Rev. 1197, 1199 n.S (19S0); Notes, 14
Akron L. Rev. 133 (19S0); 73 Colum. L. Rev. 1120 (1973).
116. Gianelli. supra nJ 15; MCLaughlan. Hypnosis in Its Role and Current Ad
missibility in the Criminal Law, 17 Willamette LJ. 665 (1981); Diamond. Inherent
Problems in the Use of Pre-Trial Hypnosis on a Prospecti\'e \OVitness, 68 Calif. L.
Rev. 313 (l9S0); Natl. L.J .. June 2, 19S0, at I. col. 4.
117. Gianelli. id. at 119S.
liS. 1d. at 1199 nn. 9 8: 10.
119. McCormick on Evidence. 203 at 491 (2d ed. 1972). The Federal Rules of
Evidence, effective in 1975 and adopted in many slate jurisdictions. dec1are reJe,'anl
e\'idence to be admissible (except as otherwise provided by the Rules. Federal Con
stitution or statute. or Supreme Court rules) and define rele\'ant evidence as
"evidence haying any tendency to make the existence of any fact [hat is of conse
quence to [he determination of the action more probable or less probable than it
would be without the evidence" (Rules 401, 402).
120. Frye v. U.S .. 293 F. 1013. 1014 (D.C. Cir. 1923).
121. See Gianelli, supTa n.l15; Note, 40 Ohio St. L.J. 757 (1979). It is not yet
46
C.
Limits of Law
47
48
I.
chiatrist is on the other side (generally each side does have such an
expert). Most expert or scientific evidence brought before the law falls,
like psychiatric evidence, somewhere between the two extremes indio
cated.
This is true, for instance, of the opinion poll evidence referred
to in connection with the Repouille euthanasia case. It is also true of
the social psychologist evidence that figured in the 1954 Brown v.
Board of Education school desegregation decision of the Supreme
Court. 1 7 Because that decision is often referred to - and (I think)
erroneously - as being based on sociological evidence, some space
will be given here to its explication.
The courtroom testimony by psychologists for the plaintiff school
children in the Brown case centered around some "doll tests." Sixteen
black children - ages six to nine - had been asked these questions
about the drawings of a white doll and a black doll, identical except
for skin color: (a) Show me the doll you like best, or that you would
like to play with (10 chose the white doll); (b) Show me the doll that
looks bad (II chose the black doll, I chose the white doll, the remain
ing 4 were silent); (c) Show me the nice doll (9 chose the white).
The witness-stand interpretation of these answers by psychologist
Kenneth Clark for the plaintiffs was that the black child accepts a
"negative stereotype" about himself.
However, Edmond Cahn has argued with considerable force that
the questions asked were ambiguous. The child might select what he
"likes," or "likes to play with," or the "nice" doll, on the basis of what
he is accustomed to; and most dolls are white. "Bad" might have been
interpreted similarly, i.e., as not a customary type of doll (or might
have been considered as the doll who had been naughty and hence
more fun to play with and rebuke; or might have been treated as
referring to the remaining dolls, by process of elimination, after the
preceding question had been answered).'""
Again, psychologist Clark's interpretation could be disputed when
he described as an "evasion of reality" the children's answers to the
last of the following questions: (d) Give me the doll that looks like a
white child (16 picked the white doll); (e) Give me the doll that looks
like a colored child (16 picked the black doll); (f) Give me the doll that
looks like you (7 picked the white doll). Cahn here again points to
ambiguities: "looks like you" in what respect? The child might not
have been thinking of color but of other likenesses - i.e., since the)'
found the white dolls "nice," perhaps it was this niceness they were
identifying with, not the color.
127. 317 U.S. 483 (1951).
J28. Cahn, A Dangerous Myth in the Schoo1 Segregation Cases. 30 ::'\.r.u.L. Rev,
150 (1955).
C.
Limits of Law
49
There are other difficulties. Not only was the sampling not shown
to be adequate, but the tests did not purport to isolate the effect of
school segregation on the children's answers. Indeed, another study by
Kenneth Clark had shown that black children's preference for white
dolls decreased as their ages went from four years to seven years, yet
these latter years are those of school attendance. l " And still another
Clark study had shown northern black children even more pronounced
in their preference for the white doll- apparently tending to refute
the notion that school segregation causes this preference. lS
Thus the psychological evidence presented in the Brown case was
not strong. Remember, however, that the Supreme Court opinion did
not rely on or even cite this evidence. Neither did it refer to a lengthy
appendix to plaintiff's Supreme Court brief, entitled "The Effects of
Segregation and the Consequences of Desegregation: A Social Science
Statement," signed by more than thirty leading scholars, including
sociologists, anthropologists, psychologists, and psychiatrists. What it
did cite in its now famous footnote II were several articles and books
(most of which had been included in the authorities cited in the above
appendix) dealing with the opinions of social scientists on the effects
of school segregation. These seemed not to be cited as the basis of the
Court decision but rather as corroboration. That is, after stating that
school segregation had a detrimental effect on school children, and
after quoting the finding of the Kansas court (in one of the four cases
being heard together by the Supreme Court) to the same effect, the
Court stated, "Whatever may have been the extent of psychological
knowledge at the time of Plessy v. Ferguson,l", this finding is amply
supported by modern authority." And footnote II was appended to
this statement.
Cahn made a further argument, namely that the use of social sci
ence evidence in these cases was dangerous. However appropriate such
evidence might be in cases of socioeconomic regulation, he asserted, it
should not be the basis for determining the scope of our "fundamental"
rights, such as equal protection of the laws. These rights, he argued,
should not depend on whatever happens to be current fad among social
scientists; future social scientists may have illiberal, "racist" notions.
But note that while there is some conflict in the standards applicable
to admissibility of scientific evidence, the following seems roughly true:
(I) Scientific evidence, whether the case involves economic regulation
or civil liberties, cannot be kept out - if relevant to the issues, pre129. Garfinke-l. Social Science Evidence and the School Segregation Cases, 21
Pol. 37 (1959).
130. ld. For an absorbing personal account of \\'itness Clark and the doll tests
see Kluger. Simple Justice 317321. 353-356 (1975).
131. 163 U.S. 537 (1896).
J.
50
I.
132. Levin & Hawley. Foreword to the Symposium. 42 Law & Con temp. Prob ..
No.3, 1.3 (1978). They went on to say thaI "much of the social science research [hat
has been the far too narrow focus of the social. political and legal justificalion~ for
desegregation has used inadequate methodologies. inappropriatt" samples. "arying
definitions oC critical variables such as desegregation or student Ollte-omes and
reached contradictory or ambiguous conclusions."
C. Limits of Law
51
52
C.
Limirs of Law
53
scientists are with us for good, and are going to remain in the very
midst of government . . . . Judges may and should become acquainted
with the various non-legal disciplines. But because of the variety of
these disciplines, and of the variety of their judicial tasks, they will
always remain intelligent laymen, as far as these disciplines are concerned. And intelligent lay control . . . seems the best defense against
the tyranny of experts. . . . "1<,
54
C. Limits of Law
55
56
C.
Limits of Law
57
353.
154. See on this, id. aL 354 el seq.
58
The Courts
a. Structure
I'll begin with the structure of the court system, and largely confine myself on this point to the state courts, since the structure of the
federal court system will be developed in Chapter 2.
Each state has a triple.layered hierarchy of courts. On the bottom
are those dealing with the petty cases in which small monetary amounts
or minor criminal penalties are involved. In a non urban area, the judge
of such a court is likely to be called a justice of the peace, and his job
might be only a part-time one. In the cities he is likely to be called a
magistrate or a judge and might be attached to a specialized court like
police court, traffic court, or small claims court. These petty or "inferior" courts are generally not "courts of record"; they make no detailed
record of the proceedings beyond the identification of parties, lawyers,
and disposition of the case. The procedure may be rather informal. The
losing party may appeal to the next level of court, but not through
what we usually mean by appeal, since typically a completely new trial
is involved rather than appellate review of the record made in the
lower court (there will usually have been no such record there).
This next level of court would be known as a "trial court of general jurisdiction," authorized to hear civil and criminal cases generally.
Unlike the petty court, it is a court of record; its procedure is quite
formal; it is not confined to, and indeed is usually prevented from
entertaining, the pett), cases. It is called perhaps most often a "district"
court or "circuit' court, though in some places it has such other names
as "superior court" or "court of common pleas." (New York State
creates a special confusion by calling it the "supreme court" - which
elsewhere of course means the highest appellate court - and recognizing both this trial part of its supreme court and an appellate part which
is an intermediate court, the final appeals court being called the New
59
60
I.
b.
Turning from the structure of the courts to aspects of their functioning, I'll confine myself to five such matters, though perforce dealing
with them sketchily: (I) court delay, (2) selection and tenure of judges,
(3) the limited role of the court itself in the disposition of litigation,
(4) access to courts and other modes of dispute resolution, and (5) the
courts' new administrative involvement in reforming public institutions.
(I)
Court Delay
61
62
I.
D.
63
169. The pretrial conference between the judge and the opposing lawyers has
long been viewed as salutary. It is a preview of the case that helps clarify and
simplify the issues. And it has been thought to shorten the trial and facilitate a
.settlement of the case without trial. The latter two effects are now subject to some
doubt. as a result of empirical studies. The larger cases, in particular, resist settlement in spite of pretrial. Trials were found to be no shorter because of pretrial, yet
the conferences do absorb an appreciable amount of the judge's time~ so these would
seem to be a nCg:ltive _contribution toward solving the problem of delay. To be
weighed against this is the improved quality of the trial where there had been a
pretrial conference - apparently because the conference had improved the lav.ryer's
understanding of problems to be met and methods to be followed. Also to be
pondered is the fact (hat plaintiff's recoveries were found to be higher when there
had been a pretrial. After these facts had been revealed by (he Columbia Project
for Effecth'e Justice in a study which had been requested by Chief Justice Weintraub of New Jersey. (he New Jersey Supreme Court changed its rule reqUiring
pretrial conferences in personal injury suits. and made the conference optional in
auto accident cases. See. in support of this paragraph. Rosenberg. 'supra n.15G at
4951. For a federal judge's call for strengthening pretrial procedures. see Peckham.
The Federal Judge 35 a Case Manager: The New Role in Guiding a Case from Filing
to Disposition, 69 Calif. L. Rev. 770 (1981).
.
170. In such a trial. instead of e\'idence being admitted on both the liability
issue and the damage issue. there is no evidence admitted on damages until after
there has been a detennination of liability. This can save considerable time (some
say about 20% of total trial time. some say "substantially less"), because (1) juries
in personal injury suits bring in verdicts of no liabiliq' about 40% oC the time, and
(2) even after a verdict of liability. the split. trial system might sa\'e time that would
normally be spent on evidence of damages, since in some cases the defendanr
chooses to settle after the liability verdict - i.e., no evidence is taken on damages.
And here. as in the case of the pretrial conference technique. studies showed an
unexpected substantive effect of the procedural change. This time the effect was to
fa\'or the defendant - i.e . in split trials, there were substamially more \'erdicts of
nonliabiliry (probably because of the absence of the emotional impact on the jury,
on the liability issue. than one might expect from e\'idence on damage suffered by
the pJaintill). Rosenberg, supra n.156 al 46-49.
In short. "there is no acceptable evidence that any remedy [for delay] so far
devised has been efficacious to any substantial extent. Only a few of the new measures
ha\'e worked e\'en to a modest extent, and some of them have been positively
counter-producth'e on the efficiency scale. More important, many of them ha\'e had
unsuspected side effects i'1 changing the outcome of appreciable numbers of Jaw
suils. A major lesson of this chronicle is that progress in coping with the old problem
of court deJay wjIJ have to come from marshalling relief measures in groups. not
from a one-injection miracle cure. There is no such panOlcca." Id. at 55.
For an esS<l)' by the Direclor of the Federal Judicial Center on research related
64
1.
But the delay problem in the criminal case is not so much the
civil case problem of speeding up the court process between the time
the initial papers are filed and the time the case is disposed of. Rather,
one of the chief problems is how more time can be spent on the minor
criminal cases that now may receive a minute or less of time per case
in the assembIy.line treatment of defendants who have pleaded guilty.
An expansion in the number of minor criminal court' judges seems
imperative. It has been further suggested that some load can be re
moved from the criminal courts by (I) removing criminal penalties
from some types of offenses and substituting other approaches such as
civil monetary penalties; and (2) expansion of "medical, psychiatric
and other treatment facilities so as to reduce by cure the volume of
persons processed through the criminal courts because of addiction
to alcohol or drugs:' 17 '
Finally. what can be done about congestion and delay in the
appellate courts? Among the many suggestions that have been made.
let me select a few for brief discussion. First is increasing the number
of appellate judges. This could take the form of enlarging the highest
court and/or creating or enlarging an intermediate appellate court
(which most states still do not have). There are some limits here. Thus
it has been observed that in California. "the number of intermediate
appellate courts has been increased from three to five, and there has
been an even greater increase in the number of judges sitting on those
courts. To push the California development a few steps further, suppose that there were ten or fifteen intermediate appellate courts in
that state ten years hence. In such circumstances, what were once
authoritative appellate tribunals, subject to occasional review by the
Supreme Court of California. would have been converted into a judi
cial Tower of Babel. The proliferation of utterances could divest any
one of these courts of significant authority."l7'
Another suggestion is to make some classes of cases not appealable
at all. or reviewable only at the discretion of the appellate court. This
device is now used in some states with intermediate appellate courts
when the appeal to the highest court, for at least some classes of cases,
is precluded or else left discretionary with that court. But extending
this. in states with no intermediate appellate courts, to cases of appeal
to delay and other aspects of judicial administration, see Le\'in, Research in Judicial
AdminiSlration: The Federal Experience. 26 N.Y.L. Sch. L. Rev. 237 (1981).
171. Barren. Criminal Justice: The Problem of Mass Production. in Jones. ed .
supra n.l56 at 121123.
172. Hazard, Afler the Trial Court - The Realities of Appellate Re\'iew. in
Jones. ed., supTa n.I56 at 81. Set' also Rosenberg. Contemporary Litigation in the
United States, in Jones. ed .. Leg:I1 Institutions Today: English and American Approaches Compared 171175 (1977).
65
from the trial court to the highest state coun, is going further than we
presently seem prepared to go. It is not that the Constitution requires
at least one appeal; it does not. But I think both the public and the
profession do want a system of at least one appeaJ.17S An additional
objection centers around criteria for the class of case that would be
excluded from appeal. If, for instance, the criterion were on the basis
of how much money was at stake in the lawsuit, or on the particular
subject matter involved (e.g., auto accidents), this might be attacked
on the grounds that (I) importance of the legal points to be appealed
has no necessary relation to money involved or subject matter, and
(2) the criterion might be unconstitutionally discriminatory, denying
to those excluded the "equal protection of the laws:
One further device presently used to cope with appellate conges
tion is the omission or attenuation of one or more of the usual steps
in case disposition. Thus, a preliminary screening procedure may reo
suit in a "summary disposition (without briefs and argument); judges
may vote on some cases without a prior discussion; they may exclude
or limit the opportunity for oral argument; they may issue decisions
with no supporting opinions or only brief memorandum opmlOns.
Such devices raise serious questions about the quality of appellate
justice. 1H
At least some of the reasons '75 for court overload are likely to
persist, and so are the techniques of coping with the problem, not all
of which have been canvassed above.17 6
173. See Hazard. supra at 83. In the federal system, there is such all appeal as of
right to the coun of appeals. and the bulk of the Supreme Court's review is discretionary. 1':onetheless the caseJoad of the Supreme Court is so great that proposal~
ha\'e been made for a new National Coun of Appeals to screen cases for which
Supreme Court review is sought. See Stern &: Gressman, Supreme Coun Praclice.
1.16 (5th ed. 1978) and the articles cited therein for and against the proposal. and
Chap. 2 below between nn. 48 & 51.
174. Sec Rosenberg. supra n.172 at 175: Carrington, Crowded Dockets and the
Courts of Appeal. 82 Han. L. Re'. 542. 558561; 569574 (1969). Almost a lhird of
the cases in the (edenl appellate cOUrls are presently being decided without the
opportunity for oral argument, and approximately the same percentage are delivered without opinion." Marcus, supra n.159 at 118. See also ABA Task Force on
Appellate Procedure, Efficiency and Justice in Appeals: Methods and Selt-cled MJterials (1977) (Joose-Ieaf); Reynolds &: Richman, An Evaluation of Limiled PubliC:llion in the COUT! of Appeals: The Price of Reform. 48 U. Chi. L. Rev. 573 (1981);
McCree, Bureaucratic Justice: An Early Warning. 129 U. Pa. L. Rev. 777 (1981).
175. Marcus. supra n.174. argues that the reasons for judicial o\'erload include
sociological factors such as the decline in traditional modes of social control and the
growth of rights consciousness. legislative and judicial expansion of access to the
courts. and economic incentives such as the award of attorneys' fees" (at 128). For a
less confident treatment of reasons, see Ca.rring1on, supra at 543-547.
176. See for further approaches to appel1Jte court congestion. Wasby. Marvell &
Aikman, Volume and Delay in State Appellate Courts (1979); Rosenberg. Carrington &: Meador. Justice on Appeal (19i6); Symposium. Federal Appellate Jus1ice in an
Era of Growing Demand, 59 Cornell L. Re\". 571 (19i4); Carrington. supra n.17:I.
66
(2)
67
first of all, substantial opinion that the selection process does not pay
primary attention to professional quality of the judges. Moreover, the
public is thought not to cast an intelligent vote, in view of its limited
knowledge of legal matters and of the qualifications of candidates. It
is further argued that while in office the elected judge is more prone
to allow improper political considerations to influence his judicial
judgment, and as election time nears, feels the need to take time away
from his judicial duties for campaigning or political fencemending.
However, the elective system continues to have strong adherents,
particularly among political scientists. They generally prefer the direct
popular control associated with elections, to the indirect popular con
troIs involved in gubernatorial appointments and the increased private
bar influence119 under the Missouri Plan. Their studies of alternatives
like the Missouri Plan are claimed to show that" . . . selection systems
themselves have little impact in guaranteeing that selection procedures
will be free from partisan or interest group politics, or that decidedly.
superior judges will be selected for office."180 Thus, studies are cited
for the proposition that educational qualifications of state trial and
appellate judges selected under various plans (appointed by governor
or legislature, or selected under the l'vlissouri Plan, or elected in parti
san or nonpartisan elections) did not vary much with the type of
plan;'.' nOr did "the evidence . . . establish a close link between
judicial selection and judges' voting.''.2 As for reduction of political
partisanship, "[e]ven in Missouri plan states, the selection commissions
which submit lists of judicial candidates for gubernatorial considera
tion are usually dominated by members of the Chief Executive's party.
Hence the Governor is ordinarily able to name one of his fellow parti.
sans to the bench.''.3 In addition, the political scientists tend to object
to the denigration of political considerations. They point out that a
Missouri. If the governor rejects the name, or if the approved candidate fails in the
election, the procedure is follO\\o'ed over again. Under both plans. the solo elections
ha\'e been generally successful. Abraham, Justices and Presidents 1314 (1974).
179. The opportunity for greater bar influence is not always fulfilled. See Glick.
The Promise and the Performance of the Missouri Plan: Judicial Selection In the
Fifly Slales, 32 U. Miami L. Rev. 509, 536537, 539540 (1978).
180. [d. al 539.
181. Adamany &: Dubois, supra n.l77 at 773. An interesting sidelight on :.he
significance of educational qualifications and other measures of achinemem is
furnished by the responses of state trial judges, both new and experienced. to
queries on the desirablt attributes of a judge. They rated as low in importance
such qualities as high law school record; high earnings in law practice; acti\ity in
civic, community. or professional affairs; or past honorable political aClivity. The)"
rated the following as. having the highest imporlance: moral courage, decisiveness.
reputation for fairness and uprighmess, patience, good health, and consideration for
olhers. Rosenberg, The Qualities of Justices - Are They Strainable? 44 Tex. L Rev.
1063, 10661072 (1966).
]82. Glick, supra n.179 at 534. See id. at 53]539.
183. Adamany & Dubois, supTa n.I77 at 774. See also Glick. supra n.179 at
521523.
68
I.
D.
69
but some actually corrupt federal judges. The most celebrated instance
was that of Judge Manton of the Second Circuit Court of Appeals,
who in 1939 was convicted of selling justice. It was he who argued,
ingeniously and ingenuously, in his appeal to the Supreme Court, that
"it serves no public policy for a high judicial officer to be convicted of
a judicial crime. It tends to destroy the confidence of the people in
the courts."l.S And it was he of whom Thomas Reed Powell observed
that he was "the finest judge that money could buy" But as Hurst puts
it, "over the years the Instances in which even a substantial charge of
corruption was raised against federal judges were trifling." And "when
all the state causes ct!/ebres were added together their total, like that
in the federal courts, was trifling," though there was as yet no compre
hensive study of corruption in the state judiciary.l.7
In addition to being criminally prosecuted for his derelictions, a
judge may of course be removed from office. But the process for federal
judges, and generally for state judges, is the cumbersome one of im
peachment by the legislature. In recent years there has been much
debate over the possibility of removal by other means, including exer
tion of pressure for resignation, through the medium of a judicial
commission. In the federal sphere, the commentators have clashed over
whether legislative impeachment is constitutionally the exclusive
method of removal, and whether it is so even for misbehavior other
than the constitutionally specified "high crimes and misdemeanors: ' .'
Persistent complaints about judicial neglect of duties, favoritism,
drunkenness, arrogantly high.handed courtroom behavior, and the like
have led the states, starting in the early 1960s, to adopt nonimpeach
ment plans for control of judicial misconduct: Investigatory agencies
can recommend sanctions, from censure up to removal, to a high state
court or a special courts commission for final action. ' .' Debate on the
186. Borkin. The Corrupt Judge 23 (1962).
187. HurSl, The Growth of American Law 142 (1950).
188. See e.g., Kaufman, The Essence of Judicial Independence. 80 Colum. L. Rev.
671 (1980); Kaufman. Chilling Judicial Independence. 88 Yale L.J. 681 (1979); Berger.
Impeachment of Judges and Good Behavior Tenure. 79 Yale L.J. 1475 (1970);
Kurland, The Constitution and the Tenure of Federal Judges: Some Notes From
HiSlory. 36 U. Chi. L. Rev. 665 (1969); S'olz. Disciplining Federal Judges: Is 1m
peachmen' Hopeless? 57 Calif. L. Rev. 659 (1969).
189. Penn, More States Monitor Members of Judiciary for Improper Conduct.
Wall Sl. J" Aug. 25. 1980, at 1. The California Commission on Judicial Performance,
composed of lawyers, judges. and lay citizens, was created in 1960 by a state constitutional amendment to investigate judges suspected of incompetence or misconduct
and to recommend removal. if appropriate. In 1979 there was a televised and otherwise publicized Commission hearing on whether some jUdges of the California
Supreme Court had purposely delayed the court's issuance of a controversial decision
(on constitulionalily of a law making a prison term mandatory for anyone using a
gun while committing a felony) until after the election. in order not to jeopardize
the election chances of then Chief Justice Rose Bird. Under the California system,
Governor Brown's prior appointment of Ms. Bird was subject 10 voter appro\"al at
70
I.
(3)
the general election. The story of the controversy and the judicial testimony at the
hearing. with its revealing details of decision making procedure by a leading state
appeIlate COUTt, are presented in Stolz, Judging Judges (1981).
190. The Judicial Councils Reform and Judicial Conduct and Disability Act of
1980 (94 Stat. 2035 (1980), 28 U.S.C. 372(c): for committee reports, see 4 U.S. Code
Cong. & Ad. News 4315 et seq. (1980 authorized anyone to lodge a complaint with the
clerk of the court of appeals of the circuit alleging that a federal judge or magistrate
"has engaged in conduct prejudicial to the effective and expeditious administration
of the business of the courts" or "is unable to discharge aU the duties of office by
reason of mental or physical disability." A special committee of circuit and district
judges investigates, with power of subpoena, and affords the judge or magistrate a
full opportunity to be heard; then it reports to the judicial coundl of the circuit.
The lauer, in turn (after conducting any additional investigation it finds necessary)
may choose among several alternatives, including: (1) requesting, after certifying a
judge'S disability, that the President appoint an additional judge (a previously
existing remedy under 28 U.S.C. 372(b)); (2) Tequesting the judge to voluntaril)"
retire; (3) ordering that for a specified period, no further cases be assigned to the
judge; (4) issuing a censure or reprimand, either private or public; (5) following such
other action as is deemed appropriate - but in no circumstances is a judge who was
appointed to hold office during good behayior to be "remo\ed" from office.
The judicial council is also authorized to refer the complaint to the Judicial
Conference of the United Slales. It must so refer if the council determines that Ihe
conduct might be grounds for impeach men I under the Constirution or "in the in
terest of justice is not amenable to resolution by the judicial council." The Judicial
Conference (or a standing committee thereof appointed by the Chief Justice) can
further investigate, with subpoena powers, and can choose among the above altern~
tives open to the council, or if it determines that impeachment is appropriate, shall
transmit the proceedings and detennination to the House of Representatives. The
Court of Claims, Court of Customs and Patent Appea]s, and Customs Court (now
the Court of Internationa] Trade) aTe required to establish comparable procedures.
191. HUTst, The Functions of Courts in the United States, 1950-]980, ]5 L. 8:
Socy. Rev. 401, 428-435 (19801981).
i92. A study of Michigan auto accidents showed the following: Of 86,100 cases
71
72
I.
(4)
196. In state courts, appell:ite court judgments were "probably always much
less than one percent of the total cases disposed of in all reporting trial COUTIS"
(the lauer includes uncontested judgments as we]]. more precise figures on a. comprehensh"e scale being unavailable). In federal courts in recent years. Crom cidl
"contested judgments" of trial courts there has been a 20 to 24% rate oC appeal: in
criminal cases the rale has been higher, perhaps largely because of the free legal
sen'ices provided for indigents. The appeal made a difference in only a minorit)'
of the cases. In those stale court appeals that could be had as or right. the re\'ersal
rate in the last few decades has been about 37% (and 50% for appeals heard at rhe
appellare court's discretion). Appeals to federal courts of appeals in the same period
have been about half as successful as in stale appeals taken as of right. And "gi\'en
the broad discretionary control of the U.S. Supreme Court o\'er its review docket.
and the peculiarly difficuIr issues usually brought 10 it. nol surprisingly ils rale of
re\'ersal consislentIy ran far higher. . , . Thus in 1956 the Supreme COllf( rnersed
in 61.1 percent of the cases it decided. in 1964 in 69.7 percent. and in 1974 in 59.S
percenL" Hurst, supra n.l91 at 4~442S. See al!'o Chap. 4 herein at n.25.
197. See the discussion in Chap. 2 under B6.
198. See Poslscript herein at n.lO.
199. [d. at nn. 1113.2223.
200. [d. at nn. 1416.
201. [d. at nn. 1820.
73
74
I.
75
76
court, and reorganization of large indusuial and railroad corporations."9 Finally, the pragmatic point is made"that judicial relief may
be a catalyst; it may, as, "in the civil rights fi\!ld", help to "mobilize
political action whose legislative consequeni:~s far transcended anything that judges were equipped to compel."220
The controversy is sure to continue. In Judge Friendly's words,
"the risk of confrontation between a court, generally a federal court,
and a financially hard-pressed city or state is fearsome, although perhaps inescapable." 201
2.
The Legislatures
77
225. In the stales, in contrast to Congress, not every bill is first referred to a
standing committee. When a congressional committee does receive a biB, the committee can kill it by simply not reporting it out. Most federal bills die in that
way. though in a rare case Congress forces a bilI out of committee. In some states.
however, the committee must report out each bill, favorably or unfavorably. ld. at
2021. State committees often report the bill in modified form, but not as often as
in Congress. ld. at 25. On the federal as opposed to the staLe level, all reported bills
are scheduled for Boor consideration. ld. at 2829. While few bills reported by
congressional committees lose on the Hoor (though they are often amended). many
state bills do not enjoy such success; and the rules in a particular state may discourage amendments. Id. at 30-31.
226. Wahlke. Organization and Procedure, in Heard, ed., State Legislatures in
American Politics 131132, 133-137 (1966). FuUer reporting would not only tend to
make legislators act more responsibly and intelligently but would help courts in
interpreting statUles. You will find, in reading Chapter 3, that a statute's "legislative
history" (e.g., the various drafts of the bil1. the committee hearings. the committee
reports, what was said on the Hoor) when available often plays a significant role
in its interpretation. Accordingly, the role of legislative history is much more important in interpreting federal statutes, since Congressional reporting is excellent.
2Z7. Citizens' Conference on State Legislatures, The Sometime Governments
(1971).
228. "Today legislatures are more likely to meet annually than biennially.
They spend more time in session than before. Professional staff has increased.
Research agencies nearly everywhere are larger, many of the standing committees
have assistance. and leaders in more than haJf {he states have full-lime staff support.
Facilities are better. Salaries are higher. Procedures have become more efficient and
more public. Electronic data processing, in one form or another, is widespread.
Legislative office is more attractive and larger numbers of able individuals are
willing [0 make personal sacrifices in order to serve. Probably more than other
American public institutions, state legislatures have recently undergone, significant
change." Rosenthal. supra n.224 at 2-3.
78
D.
79
supra applies on the federal level as well. There is more openness aboUl campaign
funding under [he Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971. as amended, which also
limits honoraria for appearances, speeches, and articles (see .2 V.S.c. 431.455):
there was, as a result of the 1977 Ethics Resolutions of both Houses. disclosure not
only of member finances but also of the receipt of gifts of $100 or more, and a limit
on outside earnings. Under the Ethics in Government Act of 1978, amended in 1979
(92 Stat. 1824; 93 Stat. 37) members of Congress are included. along with other
Officials including the President, Supreme Court Justices, and presidential nominees
and candidates for federal office, in the requirement of annual public financial disclosure reports (see 2 U.S.c. 70J 709; and analysis of the 1981 financial disclosures
made by members of Congress. in 39 Cong. Q. 1677 (1981). The occasions when votes
in Congress must be recorded have been increased; most committee meetings have
been opened to the public, with members' votes recorded and made public. Proposals for additional openness include leJe\-ising Congress and closing loopholes
in the Federal Regulation of Lobbying ACL See Bullock. Congress in the Sunshine,
in Rieselbach, supra n.229 at 209221. Bullock notes (at 216-220) that increased
openness may have had some unintended consequences. such as making members
less willing to compromise their positions; causing more deJ3y in decisionmaking
in committees and on the Ooor; introducing a conservative bias. both because
delay supports the status quo, and because heeding constituent preferences more
c]ose]y may mean more conservative voting on some issues like civil liberties or
abortion funding; and turning lobbyists' interests towards influencing staff members
instead of Congress members.
233. Dodd &: Schou, Congress and the Administrath'e State 124-129, 326-328
(1979); Huntington, Congressional Responses to the Twentieth Century. in Truman,
ed., The Congress and America's Future 18-22 (1965).
234. Huntington, supra at 15.
235. Hurst, Law and Social Order in the United States 97)05 (19i7). For the
states. see id. at 8297.
236. Id. al 112-122. This includes taxing and spending for the deb IS, defense,
and general welfare of the United States; borro\\'ing money; and contrOlling the
coin and currency. For the stales. see id. at 105-112.
237. Id. at 122132. 153154_ See also Note, 70 Han'. L. Re\". 6il (195i); Auerbach et aI., supra n.5 at 606623 (1961).
80
3.
I.
I confine myself here to the President and the sources and nature of
his power. The primary definition of his position is Article II of the
Constitution. Its listing of powers is less extensive than Article I's
enumeration of Congress's powers: "The executive power" is vested
in him, and he is to "take care that the laws be faithfully executed."
A few more provisions add some specificity: He has military power
as "Commanderinchief'; he has veto power over congressional bills;""
"he may require the opinion, in writing, of the principal officer in each
of the executive departments, upon any subject relating to the duties
of their respective offices"; he "shall have power to grant reprieves and
pardons for offenses against the United States, except in cases of im
peachment"; he has the power to make treaties with the concurrence
of twothirds of the Senators present; and he can, with the concurrence
of a Senate majoritY...make ce.rtai'L :tpDDintmen,rs." He also is obliged
to "from time to time give to the Congress information of the state of
the Union, and recommend to their consideration such measures as
he shall judge necessary and expedient."24<l
The other source of presidential power is statutory. When Con
gress has authorized a President to do certain things, "his authority is
at its maximum," Justice Jackson once said, because "it includes all
that he possesses in his own right plus all that Congress can delegate."
When he acts "in absence of either a congressional grant or denial of
authority, he can only rely upon his own independent powers." By
so relying he may undertake a course of action that, according to a
238. Under Article I. VII, d. 2, this veto can be overridden by two-thirds \'ote
of each house; if a bill after passage by both houses is presented to [he President
and not returned by him "within len days (Sundays excepted) ... the same shall
be a Jaw in like manner as if he had signed it, unless [this being the "pocket veto"
provisionJ the Congress by their adjournment pre\'em its return, in which case it
shall nOI be a Jaw." That is. where Congress adjourns within the ten-day period,
the President may eft'ecth'e1'y sign the bill within that period. but if he does not it
Wi~1
no
come law. See Edwards v. U.S., 286 U.S. 482 (1932).
~hese are "ambassadors. other public ministers and consuls. judges of the
Sup
e Court. and all other officers of the United States whose appointmelils are
not herein otherwise provided for, and which shall be established by law; but the
Congress may by Jaw vest the appointment of such inferior officers. as they think
proper, in the President alone, in the courts of law, or in the heads of departments."
And he has "power to fil) up a1l vacancies that may happen during the recess of
the Senate. by granting commissions which shal) expire at the end of the nexl
session."
240. In addition. "he may on extraordinary occasions, convene both Houses. or
either of them, and in case of disagreement bel\\'een them with respect to the time
of adjournment. he may adjourn them to such time as he sha1l think proper: he
shan receive ambassadors and other public ministers"; and "shall commission all
the officers of the United Slales." He is to be "removed from office on impeJchment
for and conviction of treason, bribery, or other high crimes and misdemeanors."
81
Jackwn, J., concurring in Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343
635637 (1952).
Dodd & Scholl, supTa n.233 at 3 (1979).
ld. at 43-44.
On this and the preceding paragraph. see id. at 34.
82
4.
83
the first place, in order to execute or administer the law laid down by
the legislature, a department or agency may be authorized by the
legislature to exercise a lawmaking function (i.e., issue rules and regu
lations, with the force of law, that implement the statute) - as, for
instance, when the Treasury Department issues tax regulations, or
the SEC issues rules regarding the sale of securities. The regulations
are issued after notice of a so-called "notice and comment" hearing247
on the proposed regulations. Unlike a court hearing, this hearing is
more like that of a legislative committee, during which written and
often oral comment is received, but there is no crossexamination, and
no detailed findings of fact and conclusions of law are made by the
issuing agency. Statutes for particular federal agencies, however, have
sometimes imposed some or all of the characteristics of a trial-type
hearing upon rulemaking. 2' 8
So too, both forms of agencies may exercise a kind of judicial
function. In the first form of agency, consider the office of a district
attorney: The prosecutor has to make some judgments that migh t be
called "adjudicative," such as whether criminal proceedings should be
brought, or whether the nature of the case, the condition of the office
workload, and other factors justify substituting a lesser charge in reo
turn for a guilty plea to that charge. The police, too, are constantly
making instant adjudications when they determine whether the facts
justify making an arrest. A Veterans Administration or a Social Security office adjudicates claims for pensions, though usually informally.
But it is the second form of agency - the "administrative agency" that we are prone to recognize as more clearly exercising a judicial
function. This seems to be because of the hearings held prior to adjudication of, let us say, whether an FTC cease-anddesist order, or an
NLRB unfair labor practice order, should issue. These hearings in
many respects resemble the hearings in civil court proceedings. Often
called "quasijudicial" agencies, therefore, these administrative agen
cies are distinguished from ordinary executive departments. (But the
dividing line is somewhat blurred: There are some executive depart
ments, too, e.g., the federal Department of Agriculture, Commerce, or
Interior, in which constituent bureaus hold rather formal adjudicative
hearings as well as making more informal adjudications.)2'> The
question of whether there is a constitutional right to a full, or an
almost full, court like hearing before the making of adjudications of
particular individual rights (as distinct from the making of general
247. See 4 of the Administrative Procedure Act, 5 U.S.c. 553.
248. See 1 Davis Administrative Law Treatise, chap. 6, esp. 6.J. 6.9 (211d ed.
1978).
2-19. Sec Vcrkuil. A Study of Informal Adjudication Procedures. 43 U. Chi. L.
Rev. n9, 757-796 (1976).
",
84
I.
250. Friendly. Some Kind of Hearing. 123 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1267. 1!!73 (1975). See
2 Davis, Administrative Law Treatise. chaps. 1013 (2d ed. 1979).
251. On administrative sanctions, see Hazen. Administrative Enforcement: An
Evaluation of the SEC's Use of Injunctions and Other Enforcement Mcthods, 31
Hastings L..J. 427 (1979); Diver, The Assessment and Mitigation of Civil Money
Penalties By Federal Administrative Agencies. 79 Colum. L. Rev. 1435 (1979); Note,
73 Nw. V.L. Rev, 957 (1978); Lawrence'. Judicial Re\'iew of Variable Ci .... il Money
Penahies. 46 U. Cin. L. Rev. 373 (1977); Thomforde, Negotiating Administrative
Seulements In SEC Broker-Dealer Disciplinary Proceedings. 52 N.Y.U.L. Rev. 237
(1977): Thomforde, Controlling Administrati ....e Sanctions. 74 Mich. L. Re\'. 709
(1976); No.e. II Wake ForeS! L. Rev. 83 (1975); E. Gellhorn. Adverse Publici'y By
Administrative Agencies, 86 Harv. L. Rev. 1380 (19;3); W. Gellhorn. Aurninislralh'e
Prescription and Imposition of Penalties. 1970 Wash. U.L.Q. 265: McKay, Sanctions
In MOLion: The Administrative Process. 49 Iowa L. Rev. 411 (1961).
252. Sec ] Davis, supra n.250 al 1.3.
85
heavier burden than do the courts. In a given recent year, the federal
district courts will have handled several thousand cases, but the federal
agencies will have handled ten times as many, counting only those
involving an oral hearing and verbatim transcript. If federal informal
adjudications were counted, the annual number would run into the
hundreds of millions and perhaps billions. And remember that the
average state may have more than a hundred agencies with powers to
adjudicate or issue rules (or both) with the force of law."">
4. It is not hard to see the advantages of lawmaking and enforce
ment by agencies. The legislature has neither the time nor the expertise
to handle the detailed requirements of regulatory schemes for a myriad
of ever-changing industrial and nonindustrial problem areas, and to
provide the continuous, dayto-day supervision that may be needed.
Could the legislature meet the lawmaking aspect of the problem
by regulating in general rather than detailed terms? Of course, it
sometimes does this. But it is an unsatisfactory technique: (a) it is
unsatisfactory to the industry or other subject of the regulation because the vagueness gives unsatisfactory notice, and indeed would
sometimes be unconstitutional on this account; (b) it, at any rate,
tends to maximize the amount of litigation over the meaning of the
standard.
As to the enforcement aspect of the problem, could the legislature
leave it to the district attorney, or to aggrieved individuals, rather than
administrative agencies, to bring cOurt enforcement suits? Again, of
course, it sometimes does this. But it foregoes certain advantages of
administrative agency adjudications and agency enforcement suits in
court. The advantages here would be: quantitatively greater enforcement as a result of continuous supervision; qualitatively better
enforcement because of the development of a uniform enforcement
policy and because of specialized knowledge on the part of the plaintiff
enforcers.
But while this expertise of the agencies is important, you should
beware of attempts to exaggerate its extent and its value. Top members
of administrative commissions and boards are not always experts in
the field involved; and though there are experts on the staff, they are
not always expert in the precise area of the agency's field (e.g., a power
commission concerned with water power problems may have to hire
an engineer whose expertise in water problems is acquired after rather
than before the hiring). Moreover. agency experts, like other personnel
of bureaucratic organizations. tend to become congealed and conservative in their positions. Federal Judge Wyzanski once put it this way:
253. In supporl of this paragraph, sec Davis. Adminislralh"e Law Text 4 (3d ed.
1972).
86
1.
5.
The Public
Only two aspects of the influence of the public on law will be touched
on here: (a) the role of public opinion, and (b) public participation
in governmental processes.
a. Public Opinion
Consider first a well-known passage from Justice Cardozo about
the role of public opinion or public values in the shaping of a judicial
decision: "When the legislature has spoken. and declared one interest
superior to another. the judge must subordinate his personal or subjective estimate of value to the estimate thus declared . . . . Even
when the legislature has not spoken. he is to regulate his estimate of
values by objective rather than subjective standards. by the thought
and will of the community rather than by his own idiosyncrasies of
conduct and belief."256 What is not so often noted is the subsequent
passage in which Cardozo observes that when the objective and sub
jective standards differ. there is no authoritative declaration or defini
tion of the difference to help the judge. He will "have no standard of
value available except his own"; '"the objective will for him be merged
251. U.S. v. United Shoe Mach. Corp . llO F. Supp. 295. !46 (D. Mass. 1953).
255. Schwartz, Legal Reslriction of Competition in the Regulaled Industries:
An Abdication o Judicial Responsibility. 67 Han:. L. Re\,. 436, 47'2 (1951). See
generally Freedman, Expertise and [he Administrative Process. 28 Ad. L. Rn. 363
(1976).
256. Cardozo. The Growth of the Law 95 (1921).
87
88
I.
D.
89
b.
Public Participation
The other legal aspect of the public that I want to say something
about is the relatively recent phenomenon described as "public par
ticipation." Of course the phenomenon is not wholly new; but by
reviewing developments over the last couple of decades or so, one
sees a rather steady expansion of the public's right to participate in
government processes. In the field of elections, statutes and decisions
268. See Chap. 5 herein under Cl.
269. See Choper. Judicial Review and the National Political Process 165166
(1980).
270. People v. Anderson. 6 Cal. 3d 6~8, 493 P.2d 880 (1972).
2il. "OnT the years a series of carefully structured studies. surveys ami polls.
as well as assorted grab-bag questionnaire arrangements ascertaining the ,'je,,s of
gTOUpS of questionable representatives. all ha\'e probed and examined the attitudcs,
of Americans toward ci\,j} liberlies. Apparently without exception, these studies
record profound antiliberalism latent throughout our society." Choper. supra n.~69
at ]63, quoting from Krislov, The Supreme Courl and Political Freedom (1968) and
citing lli~cussion at 39-53 of the latter. Other sources are cited in Choper"s discus~ion
at 163164.
90
I.
have worked substantially to overcome barriers to voting and to participation by would-be candidates.' 72 Direct participation in government administration was called for by the Economic Opportunity Act
of 1964 with its "community action" boards and its requirement of
"maximum feasible participation." Analogous provisions were in
other antipoverty, housing, health, and education legislation of the
1960s.273 In addition, the 1972 Federal Advisory Committee Act
authorized and controlled the agency practice of using committees of
unpaid representatives of particular interests in the community as
sounding boards ~or policy development;'" and a trend has developed
in the states for inclusion of public representatives on state licensing
boards.' ro As distinguished from participation in administration,
opportunity to be heard administratively received a big boost in the
1960s and early 1970s, both when the individuals or groups involved
were the specific object of adverse government action,27. and when
the} simply wished to participate in an agency proceeding that might
adversely affect their interest - a participation that Congress was in
some instances willing to subsidize?77 Three recent (though attenuated) forms of participation or opportunity to be heard administratively should also be mentioned: (I) making use of an "ombudsman"
(official receiver of public complaints about the action or inaction of
government officials) - a European technique that has been making
very slow headway in American state and local governments;7. (2)
seizing the opportunity afforded by the "freedom of information" type
of statute to obtain information from government files - a statute
enacted by many states, and by Congress in 1966 (and strengthened in
1974);'79 (3) utilizing the "sunshine" or "open meeting" laws (throwing
open to the public most of the meetings of most public bodies) enacted
in all the states, and by Congress in 1977.2.0
272. Mermin, Participation in Governmental Processes. in Pennock &: Chapman.
eds., Participation in Politics 136-137 (1975).
273. [d. al 137138.
274. See 86 Stat. 770 (1972), 5 U.S.C., App. I; Perritt Ie Wilkinson. Open Ad
visory Committees and the Political Process: The Federal Advisory Commillee Act
Afler Two Years, 63 Geo. L.J. 725 (1975); Markham. The Fede",1 Ad,isory Commit
tee Act. 35 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 557 (1974). Some agenc), statutes have provided speciflcall~'
for representation from the general public as well as from industry. Also the Ad
visory Committee Act provided for open committee meetings with some exceptions
that Congress in the Sunshine An (5 U.S.C. 552b) amended, making them the same
exceptions provided in the latter Act.
275. See N. Y. Times, Feb. 20, 19i7, E, at6.
276. Mermin, supra n.272 at 138140; Friendly, Some Kind or Hearing, 123
U. Pa. L. Rev. 1267 (1975); Mashaw, The Supreme Court's Due Process Calculus
For Administrative Adjudication . .. :' 44 U. Chi. L. Rev. 28 (1976).
2:77. Mermin, supra n.272 at 140143; Gellhorn et at, supra n.211 at 6346i4.
278. Mermin, id" references at 156, n.52.
279. GeIIhorn et al .. supra n.211 at 579624.
280. [d. at 628634.
91
6,
282. Mcrmin. id. at 147-148; Rosenthal. Lawyer and Client: Who's ]n Charge?
(1974). See also Ch,p. 5 herein, text at nn. 6871.
283. Mermin, supra n.272 at 148149.
92
I.
a.
93
94
95
included; and a plan had to be developed for e\'aluating the regulation after
issuance).
Agencies were ordered to establish criteria, induding effect on competition,
burdensomeness, and relation to other programs and agencies. for identifying which
regulations were "significant." The criteria for determining which of the significant
regulations required a "regulatory analysis" had to ensure that such analyses were
perfonned for all regulations resulting in "an annual effect on the economy of $100
million or more," or "a major increase in costs or price for indi'\:idual industries,
levels of go . . ernment Or geographic regions"; and had to permit such analyses to be
performed at the agency head's discretion, for any proposed regulation. Agencies
had to periodically review existing regulations to determine whether their standards
were achieVing the policy goals of the Executive Order. Among the exemptions ,,ere
regulations issued on a formal triallype hearing record (the usual regulation is not).
President Carter also established a Regulatory Analysis Review Group (RARG)
to rniew the analyses accompanying proposed regulations, and a Regulatory Coun
cil, composed both of executive departments and independent regulatory agencies.
The Council coordinated and dealt with problems of o'Verlapping, duplicating, and
conflicting regulations. It also pUblished a Calendar of Federal Regulations 10 give
an oveniew of the most important federal regulatory acthities under dnelopmenl.
The Administ1"3li\c Conference o( the United Siaies issued a guide to assist the
agencies. 43 }'ed. Reg. 36.112 (1978).
295. Rosenthal. Executh'e Order on Regulation Boosts OMB's Power, Legal
Times of Washington. March 16. 1981. at 14. It is Exec. Order No. 12.291. Feb. 17.
19B1. 46 Fed. Reg. 13,193 (19B1).
296. \-Vhen I say "substantial \\"ay" I am referring lO the definition of "major
rule," which repeats the Carter Order's conditions for mandatory regulatory analysis
(see the reference supra n.294 to annual effect on the economy and major increase
in cost or prices) and adds the following concem: significant adverse effects on
competition, employment. investment, producti\ity. inno\ation. or on the ability
of United States based emerpris{'s 10 compete with foreign,based enterprises in
domeslic or export markets.
96
D.
97
98
I.
99
I.
100
While the OMB has had some coordinating effect, the tendency
of the independen t agencies is to follow the clearance proced ure less
fully than the executive bureaus have. Congress, in the creation of
particular agencies, has sometimes called for direct submission of
budgetary and substantive requests and comments to Congress TlO later
than the submission to OMB; and bills have been introduced to free
all independent agencies from the OMBs prior coordination process. 30S
This refusal of Congress to give up control introduces the subject of
the next section.
b.
101
102
I.
317. Ellwood & Thurber. supm at 267. Presidential "deferrals" during 1976
1980 have had a success rate per year ranging from 63 10 99% with a median in the
upper 90s; but "rescissions" haye been less successful. ranging (rom 0 to 80'."';, per
year: 0 for one year; and 4%. 37%. 46%. and 80% for the olher four. [d. at ~65.
318. See references supra n.237.
103
104
105
courfs reason was that the publicity might prejudice the expected
criminal trials. Its judgment was affirmed on a different ground: True,
"presidential conversations are presumptively privileged," to ensure
"that the President and those upon whom he directly relies in the
performance of his duties could continue to work under a general
assurance that their deliberations would remain confidential." The
presumption "can be defeated only by a strong showing of need by
another institution of government:' But here the subpoenaed evidence
was not "demonstrably critical to the responsible fulfillment of the
Committees functions." Since creation of the Senate Committee, the
House Judiciary Committee had begun its impeachment inquiry and
already possessed copies of each of the five subpoenaed tapes; and the
Presi dent had publicly released transcripts, wi th partial deletions, of
each of the tapes in question, and had transmitted the originals of four
of the tapes to the district COUTt in response to a grand jury subpoena."
b) The litigation involving the grand jury subpoena and a later
subpoena after the grand jury indictment does not squarely reflect a
Congress-President conflict, but is relevant to such conflicts because the
litigation ended in the Supreme Court and revealed that Court's attitude on executive privilege. In spite of Nixon's claim of executive
privilege, District Judge Sirica ordered the President to produce the
tapes and papers for the grand jury and was affirmed by the court of
appeals_32; At this point, Nixon changed his tactics. Claiming he would
no longer submit the issue to the COUTtS, he agreed to let the court have
only those of the nine tapes which Senator Stennis of Georgia (a conservative, friendly to the idea of executive privilege) thought should
be delivered, and he would not turn over any subpoenaed papers.
He instructed the Special Prosecutor not to seek court aid for production of evidence withheld under claim of executive privilege. On Cox's
refusal, Nixon dismissed him. This "evoked a public reaction which
[Nixon's] chief aide later described as a 'fire storm: Within seventytwo hours the President changed his mind and promised to comply
with the decree. A bit later, a new Special Prosecutor [Leon JaworSki]
- d. _ ., "3')8
.
was appomte
After the grand jury had returned an indictment, Jaworski obtained a further subpoena to Nixon. from the district court,s whose
judgment was appea~ed to the court of appeals. By a special by-passing
jurisdiction depends upon [he existence of a statute giving jurisdiction (or the
type of case im"oh-ed. No such statute for this type of case was found to exist.
326. Sen a,. Selec, Comm. ". Nixon. 498 F.2d 725.730.731.732 (D.C. CiT. 1973).
affirming 370 F. Supp. 521 (D.D.C. 1974). See Cox. The Role of the Supreme Court
in American Government 26-~7 n.4 (19i6).
327, Nixon v. Sirica. 487 F.2d 700 (D.C. Cir. 1973). affirming 360 F. Supp. 1
(D.D.C. 1973).
328. Cox. 5up,-a n.326 at 8.
329. U.S. v. Mitchell et al .. 377 F. Supp. 1326 (D.D.C. 1974).
106
I.
330. U.S. Y. Nixon, 418 U.S. 683, 706. 713 (19i4). The Court outlined guidelines
for the district COUrl'S in camera inspection of the subpoenaed materials. The COUft
made other rulings. induding the point that the Attorney General's statutoT)'
powers to conduct go\'ernrnenl criminal litigation and to appoint subordinate
officers authorized his issuance of a regulation with the' force of law that did the
foUo\'oing: It appointed the Special Prosecutor, giying him a special independence
with explicit power to contest the claim of executive pri,:i1ege, and assuring him.
pursuant to assurances from the President. that the laller would not remove him
from his duties- except for "extraordinary improprieties" and after [he Presidenr"s
consulting and finding an approving consensus in the Majorily and Minority
Leaders and Chairmen and ranking Minority Members of the House and Senate
Judiciary Commitlees. The Court further found. inLer alia. that the conrroycl"sy was
"justiciable" (see Chap. 2 herein under B6) despite the fact that it was bel ween a
subordinate and superior officer of the executive branch. In 1978 Congress itself
enacted, as part of the Ethics in Government Act. a special prosecutor statute to be
in effect [or five years. 5 U.S.c. 591-598. See Ci\"ilel~i. Post"'atergale Legislation
in Retrospect, 34 SW. L.J. 1043, 1052-1056 (1981).
331. See generally on execuri\'e pri\ilege. Berger, EXeculjYe Pri\'ilege (1974):
Cox, Executive Privilege. 122 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1383 (197..f); Symposium. LlnilC'd Slales \'.
Nixon. 22 U.CLA. L. Rev. 4 (19,4); Note, 76 Colum. L. Rey. 142 (19,6); U.S. v.
Reynolds, 345 U.S. I (1952).
Nixon, 22 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 4 (19i4); Note, 76 Colum. L. Rev. H2 .19i6): U.S. v.
News 2316 ct seq. (1973).
D.
107
into hostilities, or into situations where imminent involvement in hostilities is clearly indicated by the circumstances, and to the continued
use of such forces in hostilities or in such situations."333 The purpose
of the National Emergencies Act of 1976."34 according to the Senate
Committee Report, was "to tenninate, as of 2 years from the date of
enactment, powers and authorities possessed by the Executive as a
result of existing states of national emergency, and to establish authority for the declaration of future emergencies in a manner which will
clearly define the powers of the President and provide for regular
Congressional review. "335
My exploration of the interrelations between Congress and the
President is now completed.330 Certainly not all such interrelations have
been identified or developed in detail."3; but at least some major ones
have been broached.
333. In rough summary: When the President unilaterally decides to send United
States mi1ilary forces "into hostilities or into situations where involvement in
hostilities is clearly indicated by the arcumstances," he must within 48 hOUTS repan
10 Congress concerning the circumstances. justification, and estimated duration of
the inYoi\'ement. and must periodically report thereafter during its continuance. He
must temlinale the use of armed forces within 60 days from the date required for
the repon or date of the actual report, whichever is earlier (with possible extension
of another 30 days) unless Congress declares war or othen.. ise Votes appro\'al or is
unable to meet because of a:rmed attack on the United States. Any time that United
States armed forces are engaged in external hostilities without a declaration of war,
Congress can direct their removal by concurrent resolution. The Resolution states
that it gives the President no powers he did not ha..e before; nor is it "intended to
alter the constitutional authority of the CongTess or of the President or the
provisions of existing treaties." For Professor Charles Black's views of the Resolution
as "a series of puzzHng repugnancies and contradictions." see Black, The Working
Balance of the American Political Departments, I Hastings Const. L.Q. 13, 18 n.21
(1974).
334.90 Slat. 1255,50 U.S.C. 160I, 1621, 1622, 1631, 1641. 1651. For committee
reports see, 3 U.S. Code Congo & Ad. News 2288 el seq. (1976). See also the International Emergency Economic Powers Act. 91 Stat. 1626 (19i7), 50 U.S.C_ 1701-1706
and committee reports in 3 U.S. Code Congo & Ad_ News 4540 et seq. (1977).
335. S. Rep. No. 94116B, 94lh Cong., 2d Sess. I (1976). Provisions of law conferring emergency powers were to be effective (1) only when the President speCifically
declared a national emergency, and (2) only in accordance with the Act. In declaring
an emergency he must specify the legal provisions under which he or other officers
will act There are prm-isions for termination of emergencies; for presidential and
executj\'e agency maintenance of a file and index of emergency Orders and regulations and transmittal of such Orders and regulations to CongTess; for presidential
reports to Congress of expenditures attributable to the emergency; and for repeal
or continuation of various emergency and other statutory provisions.
336. For a good general treatment of the subject see Fisher, The ConstilUtion
Between Friends - Congress, The President and the Law (1978).
337. Thus, for instance, the ability of Congress to intrude on the executjve is
enhanced by court interpretation of the Constitution's "speech and debate clause"
(Art. I, 6, declaring with respect to members of Congress that "for any speech or
debate in either House. they shall not be questioned in any other place"). In 1971
Senator Gra,;el of Alaska at a public meeting of his Senate Subcornmillee on
Buildings and Grounds read extensively from the goyernrnent's confidential "Pentagon Papers" on the Vietnam War and made all 47 volumes part of the public
108
I.
c.
This topic encompasses two major areas I wish to explore: (I) One
is the pronounced trend in recent years towards legislative cutting
down of the administrative bureaucracy. through "deregulation" or
through the process of "oversight"' of administrative agencies and their
rules and regulations. including the use of a "Iegislative veto." (2) The
other is the further cluster of "separation of powers" issues that arise
over the legislative creation of an agency that not only "administers"
or "executes" but also has powers partly judicial and partly legislative.
(I)
record. Also, his aide negotiated with Beacon Press for publication of lht' documents
in book form. In Gravel,', U.S .. 409 U.S. 606 (19i~) the Court ruled that [he speech
and debate clause extended only' to "legislali\"(,' acts," and hence would protect the
Senalor and his aide from grand JUTy questioning about e\'enls at the 5ubcomminee
meeting. but would nOI prolect Ihem from questioning concerning arrangements (or
pri\'3te publication of the papers. 1\or was there in the laller type of inquiry any
general "Iegislarh'e immunit),,, stemming from a nonconstitutional source. The
COUf[ cautioned thar the speech or debate clause "does not privilege either Senator
or aide to violate an otherwise \'alid criminal la\\' in preparing for or implementing
legislative acts." On the latter point, see U.S. \'. Brewster, 408 U.S. 501 (1972).
338. For 3 sampling of the growing literamre on deregulation, see S)mposium,
Managing the Transition to Deregulation. 44 Law & Contemp. Prob. 1 (1981);
Gellhorn. Deregulation: Delight or Delusion: 24 Sl. Louis V.L.]. 469 (1980): ABA
Commission on Law and the Economy, Federal Regulation: Roads to Reform
(1979); Breyer & Stewart. Administrative La\\' and Regul3lory Policy 135-1~8 (1979):
Breyer, Analyzing Regulatory Failure: Mismatches, Less ReSlrictin:' Altcrnalj,'es. and
Reform. 92 Han. L. Re\". 549 (1979); CoJ]oquium" The Deregulation of Industry. 51
Ind. L.J. 682 (1976); Stewart, The Reformation of Adminislratiye L:m", 88 Hap".
L. Re\". 1667. 16891693 (19;5).
D.
109
the process more efficient.". In the same year the Regulatory Flexibil
ity Act, primarily pushed by small business, stated as its purpose that
agencies should "fit regulatory and informational requirements to the
scale of the businesses, organizations and governmental jurisdictions
subject to regulation." Agencies when giving notice of a proposed rule
were to submit an "initial regulatory flexibility analysis," giving the
rule's objectives; its impact on small entities; identification of all fed
eral rules which may duplicate, overlap, or conflict; and description of
"significant alternatives" to the rule that minimize any.significant impact of the rule on small entities. The final rule was to be accompanied
by a "final regulatory flexibility analysis" showing agency reactions to
comments on the initial analysis and why any significant alternatives
were rejected." o Moreover, by approximately July I, 1981, each agency
was to publish in the Federal Register a plan for periodic review of
agency rules having significant impact on a substantial number of small
entities - in order to determine whether rules should be changed or
rescinded in order to minimize the impact on small entities.' U
"Sunset" legislation which, we have seen, has been popular in the
states, has been promoted on the federal level, but thus far not success
fully since the financial and administrative problem for Congress is far
greater than for the states. The major federal sunset bill, introduced
in 1977, had mandated congressional committee review of most government programs every ten years as a condition to possible renewal. But
the substitute agreed on by the Rules Committee in September, 1980
would not require the review of any programs; the committees would
choose which, if any, programs would be reviewed, subject to approval
by the appropriate House. This easing of review requirements was a
result of the awareness of the members of Congress of the potentially
enormous workload for committees, as well as the disruption, delay,
or paralysis of agency programs that would result unless sunset reviews
were undertaken at a measured pace.S<'
339. 94 Sial. 281~ (1980), 44 U.S.C. 3501.3520. See commillee reporls in 5 U.S.
Code Congo &: Ad. News 6241 et seq.
340. 94 Sial. 1164 (1980). It adds chap. 6 (60161~) 10 Tille 5, U.S. Code. For
committee repoTlS see, 4 U.S. Code Cong. &: Ad. News 2788 el seq. (1980). The
requirements as to flexibility analysis are inapplicable if the agency head certifies in
the Federal Register that the rule will not have a significant economic impact on
small entities, succinctly explains the reasons, and also provides such certification
and explanation to the Chief Counsel for Advocacy, Small Business Administration.
341. There are further prOVisions concerning the agency's review of its rules;
concerning restriction of judicial revie\\'; and concerning the power of the Chief
Counsel for Advocacy, Small Business Administration, to monitor compliance with
this law by the agency and to appear in court to present views on the effect of a
rule on small entities, in any federal suit to review a rule. The said Chief Counsel
discusses the Act in Stewart, The New Regulatory Flexibility Act, 67 A.B.A.]. 66
(1981).
34~. See Congo Q., Sept. 6, 1980, at 2645. The ABA Commission on Law and the
Economy had recommended that Congress delegate to the President the authorit), to
llO
I.
3. Carter, who had backed a broad sunset bill, had also backed the
core of a measure or measures that (a) would have required agencies to
execute a "regulatory analysis" for any proposed major rule - i.e., a
preliminary analysis discussing the need, the alternatives, and the po
tential consequences, and a final analysis (after allowing time for public
comment and debate); (b) would have required periodic review of rules
and programs, and a biannual "'regulatory agenda" from the agencies,
outlining the major rules contemplated for the coming year; and
(c) would have provided more public funds to encourage public par
ticipation in agency proceedings. Three other provisions proved so
controversial that passage of the whole program was prevented;"" a
similar program described earlier, however, which Carter had estab
lished by Executive Order, continued until revoked by the Reagan
Executive Order previously discussed. 3 "
4. Often overlooked in discussion of legislative oversight of the
agencies is the authority of Congress's watchdog, the General Accounting Office, headed by the Comptroller General. Concerned not only
with seeing that public funds are not spent for unauthorized purposes,
he is also specifically authorized by Section 204(a) of the Legislative
Reorganization Act as amended in 1974 to "'review and evaluate the
designate which agencies or regulatory functions were to be re\'iewed. A good
example of negative sentiment on federal sunset is the follo\\"ing from a 1976
Brookings Institution study called "Are Government Organizations Immortal"':
"Imagine the paralysis, the sense of suspended animation that would overtake
agencies. their clients. and their beneficiaries as expiration dales approached. Think
of trying to do business and plan for the future under such conditions. \'isualize rhe
dilatory tactics of interests that, having lost an immediate battle over federal inter
vention, strove to delay implementation until the automatic reopening of the
struggle rolled around. And finally consider the crush and confusion of legislatures
as they tried in each session both to dispose of current business and to renegotiate
the accumulating body of prior settlements. Time limits would soon be abandoned
or ignored. Organizations would be routinely and uncritically renewed. Things
would soon revert to their present state."
For some discussion of sunset legislation see Price, Sunset Legislation in the
Uniled Stales. 30 BayloT L. Re\,. 401 (1978): Note. 11 U. Mich. J.L. Ref. 269 (1978):
Vidas. The Sun Also Sets: A Model For Sunset Implementation. 26 Am. U.L Rev.
1169 (1977).
343. First was the "Bumpers amendment" that would haye given greater scope
to court review of regulations by removing the presumption of ...alidily that has
attached to regulations; see O'Reilly, Deference Makes A Difference: A Stud)" of
Impacts of the Bumpers judicial Review Amendment, 49 U. Cin. L. Re\". 739 (1980);
second was a pro\'ision for a "Iegislath'e veto" of regulations by vote of one House
(later weakened by requirjn~ a vote of both Houses, with power in the President to
velo the congressional veto); and third was a provision that the rulemaking process
be of a "hybrid" form, so that instead of the legislative-type hearing in which com
menls (written, and nOl always oral) on proposed rules are received. interested parties
would have not only the right of oral presentalion but also. in certain circumstances,
the right of cross-examination of other panicip:lOtS. See Congo Q., Dec. 13, 1980.
aL 3576.
344. See discussion of both Orders under D6a above.
III
112
I.
113
or a committee) is said to be as permissible as the delegation of legislative power to the executive or administrative agency in the basic
regulatory provisions of the statute; the courts are liberal today in the
matter of "standards:' (See p. 119 below.) (c) The President's veto power
on legislation is not by.passed. As explained above, this is not a case
of legislation. Moreover. the President did approve the original law
specifying the condition.
No Supreme Court decision has thus far resolved the constitutional
issue.
Aside from the constitutional objections, critics have pointed to a
number of practical difficulties. One is the delay of administrative
action - which can stretch out far beyond the specified 60 or 90 days
when a House disapproves the proposed rule and the agency then revises and negotiates and revises again. Congressional disapproval might
be of only part of a rule or program: How would that affect other
related rules; and when would the agency's subsequent, modified rule
be so similar to the disapproved rule as to come within its ban? The
veto enormously expands the workload for Congress (perhaps mainly
for its stall). Unlike an administrative rule, which is issued with the
Administrative Procedure Act safeguards assuring opportunity for full
input into the decision through hearings. the decision by one House
or a committee has no such safeguards; it would be a "low visibility"
decision in which intensive lobbying or log-rolling may be more determinative than merit. There may be other, unintended impacts on
administrative agencies and administrative law. s5 '
6. Still other important techniques of congressional oversight
should be catalogued here briefly. Congress. as we know, has a role in
appointments to agencies. Substantive policy may be affected through
the control of Congress over the size of appropriations - for the agenpart of Congress. Currin v. Wal1ace, 306 U.S. I (1939); U.S. ", Rock Ro)'al Co-op,
30i U.S. 533 (1939). The Court said in Currin thal there was no delegation. "Here
it is Congress that exercises its legislative authority in making the regulation
[through the Secretary] and in prescribing the conditions of its application. The
required fa\'orable ,'ote upon the referendum is one of these conditions." (at 16).
352. The prestige of an agency as a responsible, aUlOnomous body rna)" be
diminished, and recruiting capable people may be more difficult. Agencies may be
induced to rely less on rulemaking than on adjudication to announce rather new
policies - which contrasts with Wh'H is generally thought to be a salutary oppnsite
trend in agency practice. Judicial re,riew of regulations' may become narrower:
A courl may conclude that failure of a house or comminee to disapprove within
the specified period signifies that the regulation had been ratified as being statutorily
authorized {see Fredericks ". Kreps, 578 F.2d 555, 563 (5th Cir. 19i8). For examples
of some of the practical difficulties mentioned in the texl above, see Bruff &:
Gellhorn, supra n.347.
Critics have suggested alternatives to the velO: Bliss, supra n.298 at 64465 J;
Kaiser, Congressional Action to Overturn Agency Rules: Alternatives to the "Legisla
tive Velo," 32 Ad. L. Rc\". 66i (1980).
I14
cys work generally, or for particular programs. Quite apart from its
enactment of sunset provisions, Congress may put a short expiration
date on a statute, e.g., a year, so that hearings can be held annually on
whether agency policies are to be approved through reenactment. Still
other channels by which Congress keeps informed about what is happening in the agencies include: committee investigations; a statutory
requirement of regular agency reports; committee hearings on appropriations and other matters within the committees jurisdiction; the
required publication in the Federal Register of agency rules and regulations; and a watchdog committee that might be established over all
the operations of a particular agency (a state may have a committee
for watching all agency rules and regulations). Moreover, the existence
in both Houses of the standing ("subject matter") committees, appropriations committees, and committees on government operations means
that each agency has at least six committees - plus subcommitteeswhich, while perhaps not watchdog committees, are capable of keeping
in close contact with, and influencing, the agency's operations.'"
Whether or not they are on such committees, members of Congress
(acting usually in behalf of constituents) are known to intercede with
and put pressure on the agencies.'" All this accountability, however,
does not necessarily result in efficient "oversight." Senator Ribicoff in
1976 lamented the "fragmentation' of responsibility and the "chronic
absence of coordination and cooperation between committees'- The
"standing committees do not coordinate their oversight with either
the Government Operations Committees or the Appropriations Committees on a systematic basis."'55
7. Finally, you should realize that there is more than just "oversight" in the interaction between legislature and agency. Agencies
may develop a close relation of mutual assistance with particular legis
lative committees or members. This includes - in spite of the funneling of agency legislative requests through the Office of Management
and Budget - direct legislativeagency contacts over content and drafting of proposed legislation. Scholars have observed that "the norms of
legislative committees often differ from those of appropriations [committees]; the former often attempt to expand an agencys jurisdiction
and view an agency as a partner rather than an adversary, whereas in
353. See GeJIhorn et aI., supra n.21 I at 108.
354. ld. at 112-114. Recall the "due process" and Administrative Procedure Act
barriers to "ex parte" contacts in formal proceedings. See supra n.302. And see
GeHond, Judicial Limitation of Congressional Influence on Administrath"e Agencies,
73 N ...... U.L. Rev. 931 (1978); Parnell. Congressional Interference in Agency Enforce-
103-116.
115
Nor should we forget that the legislature plays a vital role before
there is any administrative agency to "oversee." That is, it is the legis.
lature that brings the administrative agency into being, by a statute
describing (among other things) its composition, functions, and powers.
It is the legislature that determines whether the agency is to hold
hearings and exercise the judicial power to adjudicate disputes,
whether it is to have the power to issue rules and regulations with the
force of law, make investigations and inspections, issue subpoenas, and
bring enforcement suits in court.
Among the questions thus raised, I wish briefly to discuss four
separation of powers issues.
(a) When an agency is vested with judicial power, can it be ob
jected that the legislature has transgressed the constitutional separation
of powers by giving an agency what the constitution contemplates for
courts? Generally, the answer nowadays is no. To sustain this objection,
said the Supreme Court in 1940, "would be to turn back the clock on
at least i half century of administrative law."357 The reasons that administrative law has developed in this direction are probably (I) the
courts are aware of the impossible burden that would be placed on the
courts themselves if the agencies could not help in shouldering the ad
judicative burden (recall the statistics in my earlier discussion of the
functioning of administrative agencies); (2) the courts are aware that
the typical agency adjudication is not the final word - it is subject to
court review. Still, there are a few maverick decisions in state courts
finding, some decades ago, that agency adjudication violates the separation of powers principle under the state constitution. s5
(b) Even if exercise of a judicial function by a noncourt is permissible, does it not become impermissible when the legislature allows
356. Dodd & Schott. supra n.233 at 225.
357. Sunshine Anthracite Coal Co. v. Adkins. 310 U.S. 381 (1940). See also
NLRB v. Jones & Laughlin Steel Corp .. 301 U.S. 1 (1937): Union Bridge Co. v. U.S ..
204 U.S. 3&1 (1907); Brown, Administrative Commissions and the Judicial Power. 19
Minn. L. Re,. 261 (1935).
358. A New Mexico court so held in 1957 with respect to the Workmen's
Compensation Commission (Slale v. Mechem, 63 N.M. 250, 3]6 P.2:d 1069 (195i, and
a New Hampshire court so held Wilh respect to a proposed administrative' agency
system fOT adjudicating auto accident cases (In re Opinion of the Justices. 87 N.H.
492. 179 A. 344 (1933.
116
1.
II7
118
365. Auerbach. Some Thoughts on the Hector Memorandum. 1960 'Vis. L. Re\,.
183, 186. See also Auerbach. Should Administrative Agencies Perform Adjudicatory
Functions? 1959 Wis. L. Rev. 95; Cary. Why I Oppose the Divorce of the Judicial
Function From Federal Regulatory Agencies. 51 A.B.A.]. 33 (1965).
!Wi6. The Supreme Court has recognized the wisdom of allowing federal agencies
to assess the relative merits of announcing an innovative principle in an adjudicatory
proceeding as against a rulemaking proceeding, and to make a reasonable choice
between the two procedures. See Gellhorn eL al.. supra 0.211 at 211-248; Shapiro.
The Choice of RuJemaking or Adjudication in the Development of Adminis[f::lti\'e
Policy, 78 Harv. L. Rev. 92 (1965): SEC v. Chenery Corp., 332 U.S. 194 (1947):
NLRB v. Ben Aerospace Co., 416 U.S. 267 (1971).
119
367. The HeClor memorandum was published as Problems of the CAB and the
Independent Regulatory Commissions. in 69 Yale L.J. 931 (1960). Minow's position,
originally in the form of a May 31, 1963 letter to President Kennedy. appears in
Suggestions for Impro\,ements of the Administrati,"e Process. 15 Ad. L. Re\". 146
(1963). Elman's position appears in his A Modest Proposal for Radical ReoTDl, 56
A.B.A.J. 1045 (1970). William L. Cary. former SEC chairman. after leaving the SEC
took specific issue with both Minow and HeClor in his article cited in n.365 supra
and in his later book. Politics and the RegulalOry Agencies (1967).
368. Panama Refining Co. v. Ryan. 293 U.S. 388 (1935); Schecter Poultry Corp. v.
U.S .. 295 U.S. 495 (1935).
369. See Davis, supra n.248, chap. 2.
370. See dissents in American Textile Mfrs. Inst. v. Donovan. 69 L. Ed. 2d. 185
(J9131). and in Arizona v. California, 373 U.S. 546 (1963); Barber, The Constitution
and the DeJegation of Legislative Power (1975); Wright Oudge Skelly Wrighl),
Beyond Discretionary Justice, 81 YaJe L.J. 575 (19i2); Lowi, The End of Liberalism
297299 (1969); Merrill, Standards - A Safeguard For the Exercise of Delegated
Power. 47 Neb. L. Re\". 469 (1968).
371. See 1 Coopel', Slate Administrative Law, chap. 3, esp, 7980, 8485, 8790
(1965); GeBhorn et aI., supra n.2l1 at 8183.
120
d.
121
122
379. The leading case is Universal Carner. Corp. v. NLRB. 310 U.S. 474 (1951).
See generally, Davis. Administrative Law Treatise. chap. 29 (1958) and forthcoming
corresponding chapler of second edition; Davis, supra 0.253, chap. 29.
123
124
125
126
fore did not come under the Act, went into federal court for an injunc
tion to restrain the Board from holding the hearing. The Supreme
Court has said that a "long.settled rule of judicial administration"
should be applied to this situation, the rule of "exhaustion of administrative remedies." The Board having initiated an administrative proceeding, it was the company's duty to exhaust this remedy before
going to the court. 389 The exhaustion rule has been riddled with
exceptions by some courts - typically where wholly non-factual determinations are involved - but the basic rule does illustrate a court
deference to the agency. The court wishes to gain the benefit of agency
expertise before it concerns itself with the problem.
3. Analogous to the exhaustion rule is that of "primary jurisdiction." Here, unlike the situation in an exhaustion case, no administrative proceeding has been or is about to be commenced. The case has
been brought in court and at least one of the issues is an issue that an
administrative agency has special competence and adequate authority
to handle (and no statute has given exclusive authority to either court
or agency), so the court says the agency should have priority on the
issue. The court either dismisses the suit or retains the case on its
docket to await the agency action.3OO
4. One other illustration of court deference to the agency is the
law applicable to "mandamus." Mandamus is a court remedy, one of
whose uses is to command an official to perform a public duty. The
remedy is qualified, to minimize interference with the functioning of
officials. Thus, courts may say that the remedy is available to command
the exercise of only "ministerial" (nondiscretionary) duties. or to
compel an officer to perform a discretionary duty. but not to compel
him to exercise his discretion in a particular way. True. exceptions
are sometimes recognized where an officia)"s exercise of discretion has
been "arbitrary," and indeed alternative remedies like injunction may
avoid the limits on the mandamus remedy, but mandamus doctrine
does reflect a concern by courts for the prerogatives of a sister agency
of government. 391
e.
127
128
129
.1..
130
I.
31
441.
D.
131
132
I.
405. International News Serv. v. Associated Press, 248 U.S. 215. 262-267 (1918).
More recently, an important study. after pointing to some limits on the Jegisl:uin
and administrative process paralleling those on the mUTts, nonetheless finds a substantia] difference in degree. It concludes that on certain issues of social poliCY,
"the judicial process is a poor (onnal for the weighing of altern::ui\'es and the
calculation of costs," the anticipation of primary and secondary "consequences,"
the necessary "oversight" that is associated with a legislath'ely creative adminisl1'''live agency. the exercise of a broad-based, informed insight unconfined by th(' walls
of a particular piece of litigation. See Horowitz. The Courts and Social Policy.
chap. 7 (1977).
406. See Peck. The Role of Courts and Legislatures in the Reform or Tort
Law, 48 Minn_ L. Rev. 265. 270-285 (1963). See also Bodenheimer. Power, Law and
133
134
I.
135
M. Hart has put it. the exceptions that CongTess may make to the
Court's appellate jurisdiction must not be such as would "destroy the
essential role of the Supreme Court in the constitutional plan."414
The Constitution. in other words. is not to be read as authorizing its
own destruction. Thirdly. there is some authority for invalidating
statutes on the gTound that their purpose or motive is to undo or
obstruct. judicial protection of constitutional rights.4I5
Fortifying these arguments are certain practical considerations:
If the lower federal courts or the state courts were left with final
authority on the issues being withdrawn from the Supreme Court's
appellate jurisdiction. a wellnigh intolerable situation arises: incon
sistency among these courts in interpreting the Constitution (with
perhaps some unanimity created by some courts' treating as precedent
the very Supreme Court decision that had led to the congressional with
drawal of jurisdiction). "The federal system," as Professor Herbert
Wechsler has said. "needs federal courts and the judicial institution
needs an organ of supreme authority.""6
Besides congressional regulation of federal court jurisdiction. there
is another weapon that CongTess might try to use - but again, I think,
not a potent one. I refer to congressional control over the size of the
Supreme Court (the Constitution being silent on the number of Jus
tices). The Court originally had six Justices. and at various times had
seven and ten. but has had nine since 1869. President Roosevelt's
famous "court packing" plan of 1937 (call it "court enlargement" if
you would have favored the plan) differed from the earlier legislation
changing the size of the Court because it was more clearly aimed at
overcoming existing attitudes of the Court on constitutional issues.
The reasons initially given were largely in terms of the volume of
work. but these reasons were soon demolished by a letter from Chief
Justice Hughes and Justices Van de Vanter and Brandeis to the chair
man of the Senate Judiciary Committee. The real reasons seemed to
most lawyers - even some New Dealers - to make the proposed legis.
lation violative of the spirit if not the letter of the Constitution. This
apparent breaking with the spirit of constitutional provisions safe
414. Hart. The Power of Congress to Limit the Jurisdiction of Federal Courts.
66 Han'. L. Re\', 1362,136':' (1953). See also Berger, Congress \'. The Supreme Courl
285296 (1969); BaloT. Mishkin. Shapiro &: Wechsler, Federal CoUTts and Federal
S}Slem 360365 (2d ed. 1973).
4J5. For recent discussion of the problem, including limits on McCardle. see
Sager. Foreward: Constitutional Limitations on Congress' Authority to Regulate the
Jurisdiction of the Federal Courts, 94 Harv. L. Rev. 17 (1981). See Taylor, Limiting
Federa.l Jurisdiction: The Unconstitutiona.Jity of Current Legislative Proposals. 65
Jud. 198 (1981): NOlo.:ak et al.. supra n.222 at 41-48. FOT some pro and con discussions
of the recent bills see Symposium. 65 Jud. 177 (1981).
416. Wechsler, The Courts and the ConsLitulion. 65 Colum. L. Re\,. 1001. 100G1007 (1965).
11I6
I.
7.
D.
137
138
I.