Frodeman (2003) - Geo-Logic
Frodeman (2003) - Geo-Logic
Frodeman (2003) - Geo-Logic
GEO-LOGIC
BREAKING GROUND BETWEEN
PHILOSOPHY AND THE EARTH SCIENCES
ROBERT FRODEMAN
Published by
State University of New York Press, Albany
2003 State University of New York
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever
without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval
system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic,
electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or
otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher.
2002030205
For De
CONTENTS
Preface / ix
Acknowledgments / xi
Chapter 1. Introduction / 1
Chapter 2. Acid Mine Philosophy / 19
Chapter 3. Corrosive Effects: Environmental Ethics
and the Metaphysics of Acid Mine Drainage / 37
Chapter 4. The Places of Science:
The Heavens, the Lab, the Field, and the Screen / 59
Chapter 5. Earth Stories / 77
Chapter 6. The Philosophy of (Field) Science / 95
Chapter 7. Being and Geologic Time:
The Meeting of Metaphysics and Politics / 117
Chapter 8. Science and the Public Self / 135
Chapter 9. Conclusion / 155
Notes / 161
Index / 181
vii
PREFACE
Geo-Logic is an essay in environmental philosophy. It approaches its subject through a curiously neglected field: the philosophy of geology. Philosophy and geology (or the Earth sciences) can
each make crucial contributions to contemporary environmental concerns, but neither discipline will fulfill its potential until it refashions
itself by engaging the other. Geo-Logic seeks to redraw the boundaries between the two fields, humanizing geology and bringing philosophy into the field.
I approach these issues from the perspective of training in both
philosophy (a Ph.D.) and geology (a masters). This combination has
also been leavened by experience in public policy. My time spent as a
consultant with the U.S. Geological Survey has served as a check on
both the conceptual rigor of my claims and their relevance to current
debates concerning the role of science in society. Finally, my participation in a number of educational experiments (the Grand Canyon
Semesters I & II; the Southwest Earth Studies Program; and currently, the Global Climate Change and Society Program, New Directions in the Earth Sciences and the Humanities, and the Flatirons
Outdoor Classroom Project) has provided me with opportunities to
test these ideas in the field.1
I have written Geo-Logic with four audiences in mind: the philosophic community; Earth scientists in academia and government; researchers and actors in political science and public policy; and
interested members of the public. A central thesis of this work is that,
in working on todays environmental problems, we must draw upon
the combined skills of all these perspectives. Geo-Logic offers philosophers examples of how to relate environmental philosophy to science,
public policy, and real-world problems. It shows earth/environmental
scientists what is epistemologically distinctive about their work and
ix
Preface
how to respond to the cultural dynamics that are pulling them into
the public sphere. It also suggests how workers in the public sphere
can use the insights of the sciences and the humanities to better address the needs of communities. Finally, this book hopes to attract a
readership among those members of the general public who are concerned with environmental matters. Geo-Logic thus continues the
work in Earth Matters in seeking to create interdisciplinary communities for addressing our environmental problems.2
Geo-Logic has a website: http://geologic.colorado.edu. The website has figures and photographs illustrating each of the chapters.
It also has links to sites concerned with questions of environmental
philosophy, the Earth sciences, science policy, and interdisciplinary
approaches to knowledge. Throughout this book, citings marked
GL:CH1 refer to the website, where illustrations are organized on
a chapter by chapter basis.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
xi
1
INTRODUCTION
I.
I live in Colorado, in the shade of the Rocky Mountains, at a
mile in elevation. And I sleep each night on an ancient ocean bottom. Six-foot-wide clams once filter-fed here; ammonites, curled in
their spiral shells, sailed through the water column; and plesiosaurs, carnivorous underwater reptiles, paddled the murky
depths of an inland ocean that extended from the Gulf of Mexico to
the Arctic. Just south of here you can find ancient shorelines where
dinosaurs traveled in herds: the sandstone ridges containing the
footprints of their passage and the bones of their dead survive to
tell the tale. Far to the west a string of volcanoes once rumbled: the
ash from those eruptions turns our dirt roads into a tire-grabbing
gumbo after a rain (GL:CH1).
Stand at the rim of the Grand Canyon and let your eye fall upon
the Supai Formation, a brick-red, sparsely vegetated set of cliffs over
five hundred feet thick. The Supai is made up of cross-bedded sandstones, red shales, and lenses of limestone. In the geologists eye,
these kiln-dry cliffs become near-shore mudflats baking under a tropical sun, crisscrossed by lazy, meandering rivers. Nor are such wonders limited to exotic locales. Go to Chicago and watch the Cubs play
at Wrigley. While sitting in the bleachers, consider: eighteen thousand years ago what is now Wrigley Field lay beneath a sheet of ice
two miles thick. This is geologydisciplined visions of past worlds
drawn from the rocky palimpsest of the Earth.
This is also geology: not far from my home, in the offices of the
United States Geological Survey in Lakewood, Colorado, teams of
Earth scientists analyze data to help lawmakers and communities
address questions of environmental policy. USGS scientists research
the likelihood of natural hazards: when will the Mississippi River
Geo-Logic
seek out a new channel, abandoning the port of New Orleans? How
will the next major earthquake affect Los Angeles or the San Francisco Bay Area? Other scientists investigate energy or mineral resources, questions of water quality and quantity, and global climate
change. Will declining mineral or energy reserves force the United
States into questionable foreign policy decisions? How much longer
will farmers in the High Plains be able to draw upon the Ogallala
aquifer? This is geology in the public interest, traversing the boundaries between science and politics.
Finally, this too is geology: it is June 1997, the first summer of
the Southwest Earth Studies Program. Ten undergraduates, half
each in the sciences and the humanities, have come to study acid
mine drainage in Colorados San Juan Mountains. The drainage from
abandoned mines is the American Wests greatest single water quality problem. We attend a three-day conference on acid mine drainage
that claims to make a special effort to speak to the concerns of local
citizens. But the first two days of the conference are anything but
community-orientedwe are inundated in graphs and statistics. Day
3, consisting of a field trip to old mine sites and damaged streams,
consists of more of the same. We watch as the scientists place instruments into pools of rust-colored water, generating numbers expressed
in obscure codes. The students look dubious. One turns to his friend
and comments: It just looks like sin up here.
Geopoetry, geopolitics, and geotheology are three loci of our relation to the Earth. Each of these sites disrupt the categories that
have governed western culture since the birth of the modern age. Accepting the disciplinary boundaries of the academy, we proceed by
ontological dogmaassuming that science, politics, economics, religion, and aesthetics are essentially discrete activities that can be
examined in isolation from one another.1
The divergence between this parsing of knowledge and the challenges we face is becoming visible everywhere, but it is especially evident within geology. A complex set of forcespopulation growth,
shifting cultural consciousness, advances in science and technology,
and ever more pressing environmental issueshave made geology
a prime site for the challenging of our accustomed categories of
thought. Defying categories, geologic insights today often function
simultaneously as scientific statements, political truths, and poetic
and metaphysical incantations.
Geo-Logic explores this disruption of the categories of our intellectual and institutional lives. It is an ontological investigation with
practical import. The problems facing society today require us to
Introduction
Geo-Logic
II.
Geo-Logic does not only aim to redefine the conceptual space of
the Earth sciences. This argument also seeks to redirect the humanities by bringing philosophy and the humanities into the field.
To see the opportunity facing us, consider Kai N. Lees Compass
and Gyroscope.4 Lee is concerned with helping society develop the
Introduction
skills and institutions needed to reconcile economic growth, environmental justice, and ecological sustainability. Framing his discussion in terms of the close of the age of Columbus and the recognition
of natural limits to societys activities, Lees argument relies upon
the metaphors of compass and gyroscope. His compass highlights
the role of the sciences in providing us with reliable knowledge
about the environmental effects of public policy decisions. His gyroscope emphasizes how democratic institutions stabilize society by
limiting conflicts within the confines of open political debate. For
Lee, the compass of science and the gyroscope of democratic debate
are the two navigational aids we need to chart an environmentally
sustainable future.
We must, however, add a missing third term to this debate
philosophy, or more generally, the disciplines of the humanities.5 Lee
rightly emphasizes the fundamental roles of science and democratic
debate in mapping a sustainable future. But without the decisive
contributions of the humanities our other efforts will be abortive. We
can see why by revisiting Lees metaphors. A compass can provide us
with a sense of orientation; but it cannot tell us what our direction
should be. Similarly, for open political debate to create the gyroscopic balance needed for societal stability, it must be supplemented
by the inculcation of public virtues. The humanities provide a context for understanding the facts of science, and order and deepen
public conversation through their hard-won wisdom.
The humanities makeor at least, could makedecisive contributions to both science and society. Scientists do science; it is not
the task of scientistsat least, it is not their primary responsibilityto provide an epistemological and political analysis of what
they have uncovered, or an account of the metaphysical implications of their work. Understanding how lab results or computer
models play out in the endlessly complex, open-ended world we live
in is (or should be) the work of philosophers, historians, and social
critics. Philosophy in particular is well suited for uniting the insights of science with economic, political, ethical, aesthetic, and
religious perspectives.
A similar point applies to the gyroscope of political debate. A
stable democracy requires a populace that is educated in democratic virtuesopen-mindedness, respect for evidential reasoning,
and a commitment to pluralismand that appreciates the metaphysical intuitions of different individuals. Statecraft requires
soulscraft: the traditional concern of the humanities with the cultivation of the soulwhat the Germans call Bildung, the moral and
Geo-Logic
Introduction
ever more artful tools. But rather than more instruments, the challenges we face require reflection and a patient commitment to conversation. Science concerns itself with facts rather than meanings;
and (despite the libertarian biases of our culture) democratic debate must be tempered by the wisdom embodied within the humanities. We will grapple effectively with the challenges we
faceenvironmental or otherwiseonly by marrying the wisdom
of the humanities to the insights of science and the deliberations of
democratic debate.
III.
As they are currently constituted, the humanities are ill-prepared to play a substantial role in society. A passage at the beginning of Kants Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals (1785) puts
the problem in a historical light:
All industries, crafts, and arts have gained by the division of
labor, viz., one man does not do everything, but each confines himself to a certain kind of work that is distinguished
from all other kinds by the treatment it requires, so that the
work may be done with the highest perfection and the greatest ease. Where work is not so distinguished and divided,
where everyone is a jack of all trades, there industry remains sunk in the greatest barbarism. Whether or not pure
philosophy in all its parts requires its own special man
might well be in itself a subject worthy of consideration.
Would not the whole of this learned industry be better off if
those who are accustomed, as the public taste demands, to
purvey a mixture of the empirical and the rational in all
sorts of proportions unknown even to themselves and who
style themselves independent thinkers, while giving the
name of hair-splitters to those who apply themselves to the
purely rational part, were to be given warning about pursuing simultaneously two jobs which are quite different in
their technique, and each of which perhaps requires a special talent that when combined with the other talent produces nothing but bungling?8
Kant expresses the vision that has dominated our intellectual labors
since the mid-nineteenth century: Knowledge, including philosophic
Geo-Logic
Introduction
These answers point toward matters that are both true and important, but they do little to address the question of why society should
support professors to engage in recondite research on Wordsworth
or Kant.
This question can be answered, for the societal challenges we
face today are fundamentally humanistic in character, involving
questions of history, beauty, personal identity, the sacred, the emplotting of scientific insights, and our response to the inevitable
limits of knowledge and planning. Is nature, for instance, best
understood as merely the raw material of our manufacturing
processes? Are there reasons other than prudence for restraining
our constantly expanding consumer lifestyle? And how do we balance the imperatives of expertise and democracy? The humanities
have shown a laudable concern with such questions: the problems
we face are profound, and nuanced reflection is absolutely necessary. But the humanities are guilty of not complementing these investigations with an account of their pertinence to our common
lives. Philosophy is, by its very nature, an exercise in abstraction.
This fact should be praised rather than apologized for; the skill of
discerning the significant quality within a thousand details lies at
the heart of thinking. But even as it embraces the most far-flung
abstraction, philosophy must simultaneously retain a regard for the
personal or social forces that animate it.
At least since Descartess Discourse (1637), philosophy has
prided itself on examining every presumption and prejudice; but
both within and outside the academy we find an unquestioned consensus: philosophers spend their time teaching and writing in the
university. Whether coming from the analytic or continental school
of philosophy, philosophers perform the same set of tasks: introducing nonmajors to subjects such as ethics, and training majors in the
traditional disciplinary domains such as logic, the philosophy of science, and political philosophy. Most of these philosophy majors will
move on to other fields, often the law, but for those who go on to
graduate school, their future is laid out before them: they will
become the next generations professors of philosophy.
In addition to teaching, contemporary philosophers engage in
research that issues in the production of articles and books. With the
exception of a few textbooks, philosophical writings consist of professional productions written for experts in the various philosophical
subfields of specialization. As for writings meant to reach the populace, whether the general public or those in other parts of the knowledge industry, very few philosophers make the attempt. Books like
10
Geo-Logic
Alasdair MacIntyres After Virtue are exceptions that prove the rule.
Such works are viewed by academics, when they are considered at
all, as a sign of a lack of philosophical seriousness.
The upshot of these efforts is a discipline that produces work of
great intellectual quality and little relevance to the larger world. It
does not seem to have occurred to many within either philosophy or
society that philosophers could be doing something other than explaining books and writing scholarly articles within the academy.
But is this the onlyor bestway to do philosophy? Or can philosophers, as philosophers, participate in the political sphere, work in
government or business, build a cabin, or go on a hike? That is, can
we not merely apply the insights of philosophy to these activities,
but engage in these activities as philosophy? Is philosophy necessarily tied to logos in the sense of words, as Aristotle claimed in understanding truth as a function of language, residing in the truth or
falsity of statements about the world? Or might there be a form of
logos and truth that is incarnate, an embodied philosophy through
which one enacts philosophy within the community or the natural
world? Could there be a philosophyand by extension, a humanitiesthat, without becoming superficially pragmatic, takes on the
juxtaposition of Aristotle and climate change, or semiotic theory and
geologic fieldwork, in order to see what the effects are on both?
Geo-Logic treats philosophy (and by extension, the humanities)
as a practice as well as a linguistic activity. Practice is here meant
in the Buddhist sensethat wisdom cannot be wisdom if it only consists of a set of propositions. Wisdom must also be embodied, manifesting itself personally and socially in a daily performance. Indeed,
until philosophy becomes a practice we can have little confidence in
a philosophers conclusions. Practicing philosophy means something
more than applying the established insights of philosophy to our
lives; we must approach philosophy as a yogaa disciplined and embodied way of being in the world that in turn influences our philosophical propositions. The point is not to dismiss philosophys
discursive element, but to view the linguistic and the embodied, engaged aspects of philosophy as complementary. In this view of philosophy, philosophers would spend roughly equal amounts of time
out in the field and in teaching and writing. The preamble of
thought, the transition through which it passes from the unconscious to the conscious, is action.10
Consider the way that Buddhism and Hinduism treat these
questions. For all their differences (e.g., on the nature of the self,
Introduction
11
God, and the cosmos) Buddhist practice and Hindu yogic techniques
share a vision largely missing from Western philosophy: both emphasize the unity of our physical and contemplative lives and the
practical and embodied nature of wisdom. Buddhism eschews speculation for an insistence upon the lived aspects of wisdom. The Japanese tradition of Buddhism especially focuses on the relation to
everyday life through a set of do or Ways. Skills such as archery,
flower arrangement, tea making, and fencing are all treated as occasions for gaining insight. Zen koans are based upon the belief that
reason is an inadequate vehicle for expressing truth: a koan can be
solved only through inspiration or action. Possibly the most rigorous
of the Ways is judo, which trains the entire body rather than focusing on a particular technique. But even household activities such as
washing the dishes and sweeping the floor are occasions for insight.
If a Zen student is sufficiently alive, he can practice the Way in the
simplest activities of daily life.11
Similarly, yoga is a five-thousand-year-old Indian philosophicalreligious system designed to unite the body, mind, and spirit. Like
the word religion, yoga means to tie or bind together: yoga is
Sanskrit for yoke or union. Westerners think of yoga in terms of
its physical aspect, hatha yoga, in which adepts practice a set of
asanas or postures. Within the Hindu tradition, however, physical
training and meditation are two aspects of one process. Traditional
yoga emphasizes an eightfold system of spiritual development including ethical disciplines (yama and niyama, restraints and observances), postures, breathing exercises, control of the senses,
concentration, meditation, and absorption.
To suggest that Western philosophy, and more generally the
humanities, be treated as a yoga implies that the theoretical and
the practical be yoked in both our personal and public lives. Rather
than the scholars study, the native home of philosophy lies in the
crafts we master: violin, pottery, and dance; scientific fieldwork,
salesmanship, and political deal making; and, yes, teaching, writing, and research. Mindful of the practice and care needed to develop such skills, craftspeople of different skills are able to
recognize one another. Great skill in any craft requires that we
subordinate our desires to the work before us. Dedicating oneself to
a craft is the sine qua non of freedom. Such craft work is implicit
philosophy. Through practicing and eventually mastering such
crafts, we create an experiential complement to philosophys linguistic aspect.
12
Geo-Logic
IV.
In addition to the projects of rethinking the nature and roles of
geology and philosophy in society, a third point needs emphasis here:
Geo-Logic is an essay in topical thinking.
Topical thinking begins from both natural and geographical locationsplaces in the literal sense of the wordand from personal and social circumstances, the metaphorical sense of place
implicit when we ask someone, Tell me where youre coming
from. Imagine you are on a trip to Morocco. Turning a corner in
Marrakech, you glimpse a picturesque gathering of Muslim
women. You lift the camera to capture the scene, and the group explodes: heads duck, backs turn, and hands raise before faces. Topical thinking begins from places like this, launched from a personal
anecdote or a telling example, and acknowledging the circumstances that motivate thinking. From such beginnings, topical
thinking follows a nomadic path that traces the implicit logic of a
problem wherever it leads: perhaps from politics to sociology, then
to economics, ethics, aesthetics, and theology, and finally back
again to politics. From the experience of picture taking in Morocco,
for instance, one might be led to ask how cameras enframe and objectify others, or to investigate the politics of gender, or to interrogate the role of tourism in intercultural communicationor from
one to another of these problems.
Topical thinking organizes knowledge differently from the approach that governs academia, where research is structured in
terms of the logical space of disciplines (chemistry, history, and the
like). Topical thinking does not, however, abandon the disciplinary
structure that defines knowledge today. A disciplinary approach to
knowledge is not unreasonable, but it is partial. It needs to be complemented by an approach that remembers that our problems are
always extra-disciplinary in nature. A medical patient, for instance,
consists of something more than a series of disciplines (or systems: cardiac, pulmonary, digestive, and so on) worked on by medical professionals. As necessary as an understanding of these
different systems is for treating a patient, medical practice suffers
when it loses sight of the fact that it is a transdisciplinary entity
(namely, a person) that is being treated. Likewise, our environmental problems resist simple division into the categories of environmental science, economics, and ethics. To confront these problems
effectively we must understand how these categories relate and
flow into one another at a particular location. Topical thinking is a
Introduction
13
14
Geo-Logic
existential and hermeneutic perspectives of Heidegger and MerleauPonty. Nonetheless, how I use these thinkers may be as foreign to
continental philosophers as to those with an analytic background in
philosophy.
Given this topical approach, it is reasonable to offer a short account of my own place that led to the present study. It was the
philosophic attractions of geology that led to my resigning a faculty
position in philosophy to return for a masters degree. The point
was not to approach the Earth sciences as a subspecies of the philosophy of science. Rather, I hoped to develop a scientifically informed phenomenology of the Earth that united geologic knowledge
with philosophic insight to help us understand how to live on Earth.
I had already spent some time in the field with geologists, and had
been struck by how their thinking was affected by walking the land
and interpreting its signs. Despite their invariably positivistic descriptions of the reasoning process within geologic fieldwork, I
found that geologists practiced a type of earthbound phenomenology rather than an activity best described by the covering laws of
the philosophy of science.
My intentions, then, were focused on developing a phenomenology of geology. But I soon discovered that geology as a discipline and
a social institution was in a state of flux. I also discovered that the
motivations of my fellow graduate students were markedly different
from what I had imagined. Few of them pursued their course work
for financial reasonsa point obvious to anyone familiar with the
job market in the Earth sciences. And while I found the geopoetic aspects of their science everywhere within their laborsimagining
worlds outside the compass of anyones experiencethis topic led a
decidedly subterranean existence. Not only were the perspectives of
philosophy and the humanities unfamiliar to them, they were also
highly suspect. For a field suffering its own identity crisiscuts in
funding and a fear that, in the words of the physicist Luis Alvarez,
fields such as paleontology may be nothing more than a type of
stamp collectingthe last thing geologists needed was someone to
draw out the connections between geology and the humanities.14
Better to emphasize the rigorous nature of the field, and geologys
ties to geochemistry and geophysics.
I found, however, that our interests intersected when they were
reframed in terms of epistemology and politics. Scientists are people
who go to great lengths to make sense of things. This drive takes a
distinctive form within the Earth sciences, where much of the evidence is lost, and what remains is bent, warped, baked, or dismem-
Introduction
15
bered. To be a field geologist, one must positively delight in conundrums, much as Sherlock Holmes enjoyed the complexities of his
profession. Whats more, Earth scientists commonly combine their
fascination with epistemological puzzles with serious ethical and political concerns. Typically individuals with a profound feeling for nature (although the forms of this feeling vary widely), they often
champion conservationist and/or preservationist stances toward the
natural world.
Under the influence of my new colleagues, I soon found myself
focusing upon the epistemological and institutional as well as the
phenomenological and philosophical aspects of the Earth sciences.
Indeed, a new thought came to the fore: we need to understand how
all the domains of the humanitiesepistemology and ethics, aesthetics and politics, metaphysics and theologymanifest themselves
in the study of the Earth. My goal at the outset was to develop a geologically informed environmental ethics and a phenomenology of
the Earth. But by the time I finished my degree, the goal had become to provide an ontology of the Earth sciences: to describe how
the various domains of knowledge (science, ethics, politics, aesthetics, metaphysics, and theology) are revealed within the discipline,
and how these domains relate to one another in various environmental controversies.
This ontological reevaluation of geology is being driven by the
most pragmatic of conditions. Both natural and cultural forces are
changing the role of the Earth/environmental sciences in society,
forcing the discipline to take on political responsibilities markedly
different from those of its own earlier history, as well as from most
other sciences. Whatever might be a scientists private motivations,
the overall role of science in culture has long been as an enabler
increasing the range of our power and control through the development of science-based technological development. This explains the
massive federal support of science (in 2000, around 40 billion dollars
for funding of non-defense-related science), and reflects our societys
desire for an ever expanding power over nature.
In its early years, geology fit within this frameworkif not entirely comfortably. As geology emerged as a separate discipline in the
early nineteenth-century, the field straddled two roles: its discovery
of the history of life profoundly affected how we understand our
place in the cosmos, while it also served as a handmaiden to industrial development, providing raw materials for the industrial machine.15 Certainly both of these roles continue todayalthough the
former, metaphysical issue is too often reduced to stale debates over
16
Geo-Logic
V.
To chart this ontological disruption, Geo-Logic begins from three
places or topoi: (1) the political controversies surrounding acid mine
drainage (chapters 2 and 3); (2) the nature of scientific research as it
is conducted in the field (chapters 4, 5, and 6); and (3) the challenges
facing public Earth scientists as they seek to serve the needs of communities (chapters 7 and 8). In each of these locations I explore how
reconfiguring the disciplines of the Earth sciences and philosophy
casts new light on our environmental challenges. My claim is
straightforward: we are not making good use of our intellectual resources, in large part because of the disciplinary presumptions that
dominate the production of knowledge today. Addressing societal
problems will require a type of transdisciplinarity that moves both
horizontally (across the disciplines) and vertically (between intellectual culture and society at large). To gain a purchase on our environmental problems requires that we break down the divide
separating the natural and cultural aspects of geology, and that we
make philosophy into a cultural practice as well as a linguistic
event. Rewriting the disciplines of the Earth/environmental sciences
Introduction
17
18
Geo-Logic
2
ACID MINE PHILOSOPHY
I.
The San Juans are possibly the most beautiful mountains in Colorado. To see for yourself, take the trail up to Ice Lakes Basin. Blue
spruce and quaking aspen cover the flanks of the mountains that rise
to snow-topped peaks. Naturally occurring mineral oxides paint the
rocky slopes above tree line yellow and red, while the trees themselves sprout from pale limestones, ruddy sandstones, ancient lava
flows, and beds of welded volcanic ash. Ridge lines stand jagged
against the sky: rather than eroding like granite, which peels like the
layers of an onion, the sedimentary rocks of the San Juans break
along or across bedding planes, all edges and sharp angles. Ancient
glaciers have also left their mark: eighteen thousand years ago, the
streams of ice reached deep down the valleys of the San Juans, carving grand, U-shaped troughs along the Animas, the San Juan, and
the San Miguel Rivers. Still relatively unvisited, these mountains
today contain three wilderness areas. If they were an hour from Denver the San Juans would be a national park.
Its all the more striking, then, when the trail turns and you find
an awful mess. Dilapidated mine works, rotten timbers askew, block
part of a gaping black portal. Jumbled masses of waste rock dumped
from the mine entrance have slid down the mountainside to Ice
Lakes Creek. Abandoned motors, twisted pipes, and corrugated sheet
metal rust in the sun. Thick rivulets of orange gunk leak from the
mine and run downhill to the creek, contaminating rainwater and
snowmelt with sulfuric acid and a variety of heavy metalszinc, copper, cadmium, lead, iron, aluminum. In many of the streams of the
San Juans, low pH and toxic metals have killed all the fish, both directly by their toxicity and indirectly by destroying the habitats of
insects that they feed upon (GL:CH2).
19
20
Geo-Logic
The problem is called acid mine drainageshorthand for concerns with abandoned mine lands and the streams that run across
them. Like many of our environmental problems, acid mine drainage
has sparked intense debate. In towns like Silverton, Colorado, the
controversy is over whether these areas should be restored. But to
what standard, and at whose cost? The debate rages in national and
global venues, but perhaps most fiercely in the American West,
where acid mine drainage is the single greatest water quality problem. It is a debate with a wide range of interested parties. Stakeholders in this dispute include landowners and local officials,
environmental organizations and mining companies, federal agencies
and lawyers, scientists, tourists, and local businessmen.
There is, of course, a standard way to settle such disputes
through the artful combination of science and public policy. Science
provides the facts needed for decision-making, and the law represents the will of the people: Lees compass and gyroscope. But to adequately address our environmental problems we need more than
good science and democratic policy. We also need philosophy.
For many, the word philosophy summons up an image of
Rodins Thinker: a naked man, fist to chin, turning in upon himself
in rapt reflection. Or perhaps of Socrates in a toga, distracting people from their daily tasks by asking a series of pointless questions.
But philosophy worthy of its name (philos-sophia, the love of wisdom) begins on the ground, scrambling over scree, poking around in
just such unsightly holes as the abandoned mines in the San Juans.
In its best dress, philosophy wears hiking boots and carries a walking stick. It wanders nature trails that lead into the heart of our
cultural wildernesses and the deeper, psychic sources of our environmental problems.
Philosophy can play two critical roles in environmental controversies like acid mine drainage. First, it can provide an account of
the specifically philosophic aspects of our environmental problems,
the ethical, aesthetic, epistemological, metaphysical, and theological
dimensions that we must acknowledge before we can solve. These dimensions are more central to our concerns with the environment
than we often acknowledge: in many cases, the law and scientific
data are stalking horses disguising the fundamentally philosophic
nature of our concerns.
Second, philosophy can offer a synopsis of how the various disciplines relate within a given problem. Questions such as acid mine
drainage refuse to follow strict disciplinary boundaries. They require
a logic that is willing to track an argument across all the domains of
21
22
Geo-Logic
can find massive, seemingly infinite amounts of knowledge on almost any subject, what we lackprecisely through of this glut of informationis a grasp of the whole. This sense of the whole was
what logic originally meant. For the Greeks, logos did not simply
mean the mechanical deduction of conclusions from premises, or the
linking of cause and effect. Rather, logos connoted the sense of orientation and placement that comes from knowing how things hang
together. Our society, then, while having made a monumental effort
in scientific and technical reasoning, has in this sense become
deeply illogical.
II.
The veins may have played out, and the mines lie quiet
at least until the next jump in the metals market. But the legacy of
mining remains. A casual car-tour of the San Juans is enough to
alert one to controversy. The San Juans contain more than fifteen
hundred abandoned mines. Depending on ones opinions about aesthetics, history, and nature, these old mines, buildings, mine dumps,
and tailing ponds are either picturesque, an eyesore, or a sacrilege.
What cannot be denied is that many of the streams of the upper Animas run orange, their water, rocks, and banks stained red and covered with a thick sludge. The lack of aquatic life in many stretches
has raised concerns about how healthy it is to drink the water or eat
the fish that remainconcerns for the people of Silverton, for those
downriver in Durango, Colorado, and Farmington, New Mexico, and
for the tourists who visit the area.
While not a household term, acid mine drainage is a problem of
wide effect. It is a serious issue in the eastern United States, where
the source is usually coal rather than gold mining. Acid mine
drainage has also caused substantial problems around the world, in
places such as Spain, Eastern Europe, Peru, and Indonesia.2 The
American West is home to several hundred thousand abandoned
mines that have contaminated thousands of miles of streams. Sites
and streams needing attention may number in the thousands. The
Mineral Policy Center estimates that the cleanup in the United
States will total between 32 and 72 billion dollars.3
In the San Juans, questions concerning acid mine drainage center upon the upper Animas drainage in the high mountains and valleys surrounding the town of Silverton. The confluence of three
streamsMineral Creek, Cement Creek, and the upper Animas
23
24
Geo-Logic
The miners came for the gold and silver, but the mountains
also contained large amounts of base metals (e.g., iron, lead) locked
up with sulfur as sulfide compounds. Exposing the metal-bearing
rock to air and water mobilizes these metals, releasing them as
well as sulfuric acid into the streams. The pH of the upper Animas
is in many cases low enough to cause aquatic life to be deformed or
die. A low pH also allows the heavy metals to stay in solution, causing the high concentrations of metals in the waterkilling more
aquatic life. The metals themselves have a wide variety of effects
upon the streams. Zinc, copper, and cadmium pass into the water
column and kill fish through their toxicity. Aluminum and iron settle on the stream bottom and disrupt the physical habitat of bottom-dwelling creatures (such as stone flies and caddis flies) that
the fish depend upon, by filling in the spaces in the streambed
where the creatures breed.
Despite (and in some cases, because of ) all this, the San Juans
are a magnet for hikers, backpackers, horseback-riders, four-wheel
enthusiasts, and history buffs. The areas historical attractions include a narrow-gauge railroad, ghost towns, and the old mines from
the gold strike days. The centrally located townvillage, reallyof
Silverton is ground zero for debates over the abandoned mine lands
of the San Juans. Silverton rests at 9,300 feet in a deep valley where
the sun sets early most of the year. In the winter, its population
numbers around three hundred. Most of the shops are boarded up,
with only the Avalanche Coffee Shop and the Miners Tavern regularly open. In the winter months avalanches sometimes close U.S.
550, the only paved road into town; in 1993, Silverton had no mail
service for a week. Many of the winter inhabitants are ex-miners
and people who still identify quite strongly with the mining ethos: a
popular bumper sticker in town reads: Earth First. Well mine the
other planets later. Silvertons population expands in the summer
with the arrival of absentee landowners and the owners of small
shops and galleries. For a few months the towns character lies
somewhere between mining town and tourist trap, living off of the
stream of tourists deposited daily by the Durango and Silverton
Narrow Gauge Railroad. Today the entire town is a National Historic Landmark, the local economy surviving on its history and the
areas natural beauty (GL:CH2).
Silvertons mining past remains a palpable presence. Beginning
in 1871, over 9 million ounces of gold have been taken from the
mountains surrounding Silverton, the second-largest amount of any
region in the state (the Cripple Creek district ranks first). Aban-
25
26
Geo-Logic
III.
We began with a hikers experience of abandoned mines and acid
drainage. But the areas mining history can inspire as well as repel:
But time has passed, the sounds have faded. The men are
gone. Empty buildings stand against the weather. An unsecured door bangs mindlessly against the wooden side of a
building once full of working machines run by men earnestly
pursuing their dreams. Now, the countryside is quiet. Arrastra Creek, its gentle flow broken by mining debris, no longer
tells its tales to passing miners. To be sure, an occasional
lessee may come into the gulch and for a while a mine will
run. But the boom is gonethe glory years are over.6
Seeing the conditions of the upper Animas as a problem, rather than
as picturesque, requires a certain perspective, one not shared by all
parties, and especially not by many of the locals. By what criterion
does acid mine drainage count as a problem? What should count as a
solution? Who decides who is responsible, and who should bear the
costs of correcting these problems?
In the thousands of pages of material on acid mine drainage, one
finds very little sustained reflection on these questions. Somehow we
have slipped from fundamental (if devilishly difficult) questions to issues that are more easily answered. Like the man looking for his
keys beneath the streetlamp because thats where he can see, our culture turns to science to deliver us from conflicting perspectives.
Make no mistake: a great deal of worthy scientific research on
acid mine drainage has been and is being done. Science has identified the sources of pH and heavy metal contamination, the toxicity of
pH and heavy metals in different species of fish and at different
stages in their life cycle, and the natural background conditions of
these streams before mining began. But few have considered the
question: to what degree is acid mine drainage a scientific issue
rather than an economic, ethical, aesthetic, or theological one? Certainly, part of the reason for this is that we know how to conduct scientific research and economic analysesnot to minimize the
difficulty of such workwhile our culture has largely given up on
thinking through the ethical, aesthetic, and theological aspects of societal controversies like acid mine drainage. It has been drummed
into our heads that these latter topics are not susceptible to rational
treatment.
27
28
Geo-Logic
29
30
Geo-Logic
31
shifted. Acid mine drainage became a problem through legal definition: the Clean Water Act drove the debate in the San Juans. But
the terms of Sunnysides mine closure now turned, not only on the
details and the interpretation of the Clean Water Act, but also
upon our understanding of the chemistry, hydrology, and geology of
the region. What would happen if the American Tunnel was
plugged? Why are there no effects from the cleanup of the A
sites? We find ourselves at a site of ontological disruption, as the
boundaries between our disciplinary categories begin to slip and
give way. The debate has moved from the interpretation of administrative law to the interpretation of geologic facts and hydrological
models. Let us, then, leave the Clean Water Act and focus our attention on the situation on the groundand beneath it.
IV.
Approaching the San Juan Mountains from the south, driving
up the Animas River valley past the towns of Durango and Hermosa,
one passes massive cliffs of red and buff-colored sedimentary strata
that dip to the south. Coming to the San Juans from the north past
the towns of Ridgway and Ouray one faces a similar scene, but now
the layers dip to the north. It is as if a titanic force had pushed the
sedimentary beds from below, tilting the beds until it burst through
at what is now the center of the San Juans (GL:CH2).
This is roughly the account that geologists offer of the San Juan
Mountains. The sloping sedimentary strata all point upward toward
the center of the mountains, where one finds abundant evidence of
volcanic activity: lava beds, welded ash flows, mineralized rocks, and
deeply offset faults. In the mid-Tertiary, some 35 million years ago,
southwest Colorado became a volcanic landscape. The source of the
lava and ash was a huge mass of magma, which was also the source
of the minerals that someday would interest the miners. The volcanics continued for 10 million years; from the volume of the deposits it seems that many of the explosions dwarfed those of Mount
St. Helen and Mt. Pinatubo.
Silverton itself lies in the midst of the San Juan volcanic field,
at the edge of an area that geologists call the Silverton caldera. A
caldera is a volcano that has collapsed upon itself. After the explosive venting of its lava and ash the volcano gives way, leaving a concave depression. While the interpretation of the region is not childs
play, the signs suggest periodic volcanic eruptions, leaving multiple,
32
Geo-Logic
33
34
Geo-Logic
35
36
Geo-Logic
which promise reliable (that is, repeatable) results. What goes unappreciated is the fact that such lab results are themselves unreal.
The variability that a field scientist confronts is the variability of the
real world. Faced with such variability, field scientists have developed their skills at making sense out of the hints contained in the
rocks or the streams. In philosophy, hermeneutics, or interpretation
theory, describes those types of reasoning that rely as much upon experience and discernment as on the ability to calculate.
The question of the nature of field reasoning and its supposed
inferiority to the laboratory sciences is a topic of a later chapter. The
point here is this: science is typically brought into political controversies because it is seen as the means of resolving debates. The conflict between Sunnyside Gold and the State of Colorado was going to
be mediated on the basis of sound science. Instead, the science
itself has become a bone of considerable contention.
But is it possible that we have misled ourselves? Might the entire argument have gone off track? What difference does it make
whether the streams of the upper Animas are stressed as a result of
mining, or polluted by naturally occurring springs and seeps? A pH
of 3.2 is a pH of 3.2 in either case.18 This question is seldom faced
head-on, but it hovers about the topic like swamp gas. To address it
takes us beyond the discourses of politics and science to subjects
that are rarely taken seriously in our environmental debates.
3
CORROSIVE EFFECTS:
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
AND THE METAPHYSICS OF
ACID MINE DRAINAGE
I.
Drill, blast, crush, and scrape: extracting minerals from the
Earth is a brutal business. Even before the machine age, the effects
of mining were transparent: in the Metamorphoses (A.D. 7) Ovid
yearned for a lost golden age on Earth before men dug into her vitals, and Seneca described the results of mining as a sight to make
hair stand on end.1 Two thousand years later, Roman mines still poison Italian streams. These effects will not disappear with the development of a postindustrial economy. As long as mining continues,
cyanide spills, acid drainage, and heavy metals contamination will
persist worldwide. And, as the Roman example tells us, these are
problems that outlive the life span of civilizations.
In the summer of 1997, the U.S. Environmental Protection
Agency and the Colorado Division of Public Health and Environment sponsored a conference entitled Acid Mine Drainage: Problems and Solutions. As the director of the Southwest Earth Studies
Programa program funded for three years by the National Science
37
38
Geo-Logic
Corrosive Effects
39
40
Geo-Logic
to a two-hundred-year epistemological prejudice decreeing that certain topics are inadmissible in public debate. We are thus forced to
search, often in vain, for scientific, epidemiological, economic, or
legal arguments that match the intuitions that we dare not voice.
This chapter offers an account of the relation between these two
statementsthe dominance of science and the narrowing of environmental philosophy. It also reviews other recent attempts to expand
the conversation within environmental philosophythe environmental justice movement, and ecofeminism. In the end, it returns to
the topic of acid mine drainage to explore the metaphysical and theological dimensions of this controversy that have been marginalized.
II.
Science fails to resolve our policy debates, but not because it has
nothing to offer. On the contrary, science makes vital contributions
by drawing parameters around a problemeliminating some accounts and suggesting othersand by identifying possible scenarios
for the future. But scientific research rarely dictates our behavior,
and it cannot substitute for political debate. Science and politics operate within two different language games that rely upon different
tools and aim at different ends. The goal of science is a specifically
definedthe German philosopher Heidegger would say enframed
notion of truth pursued through controlled experimentation. The
goals of politics are, or should be, justice and the common good, pursued through the arts of conversation and compromise.
Daniel Sarewitz expands upon the disjunction between the aims
of science and those of politics by noting that, from the point of view
of politics, science provides us with an excess of objectivity.4 Sarewitz
doesnt question the objectivity of scientific data; in fact, he has little
patience for postmodern critics of science who see science as merely
a form of ideology. Rather, he highlights another problem: science
today is so rich and diverse that it is able to provide support for a
wide range of perspectives on a subject. On complex issues like
global climate change or the causes of the salmons decline in the
Northwest, science seldom speaks with one voice.
Consider the controversy over salmon. Different parties to the
controversy can each point to recent scientific studies that support
their own interpretations regarding which of the four Hs (hydropower
[dams], habitat degradation, hatchery misuse, and over-harvesting)
have caused the drastic decline in salmon populations. Invariably, the
Corrosive Effects
41
42
Geo-Logic
What, then, are our intuitions or first principles concerning environmental controversies such as acid mine drainage? Are we reasoning to a conclusion that we are unaware of, or from an insight
that already resonates deeply within us? It seems clear that in some
cases we are reasoning from an insight rather than to a conclusion.
In the 1960s, the proposed dams in the Grand Canyon struck many
as wrong, not chiefly because of scientific or economic arguments
concerning the poor returns on investment or the dangers of catastrophic failure, but because the dams would despoil a natural wonder. If this intuition lies at the heart of our concern with the Grand
Canyon (or with the salmon, or at the Longfellow-Koehler mine),
then why arent such metaphysical or theological intuitions appropriate within our environmental debates?
Serious consideration of either of these topics has been enjoined
for two hundred years. Across philosophy, and more generally
throughout intellectual culture, metaphysics and theology have been
dismissed as retrograde and irrational. Here I invoke the terms metaphysics and theology in a minimalist fashionarguing for the pertinence of that which is beyond the material or physical (meta-physics),
as well as for the widespread sense of reverence elicited by tremendous landscapes. This is in clear contrast to the stance of dogmatic
metaphysics and theology, which base themselves in unverifiable, unquestionable truth claims and remain closed to reform or evolution.
This essay takes a phenomenological approach: rather than admitting
only legalisms or testable realities to public debate, it also honors
claims based in the experience of the natural and the sacred. This approach places intuitions in dialectical relation with other views, and is
open to reformation by either scientific facts or other intuitions.
My claim, then, is that our relation with the natural world is as
much rooted in metaphysical and theological intuitions as it is in the
intricacies of scientific or ethical debate. In this sense, a metaphysically or theologically oriented environmentalism is also a deeply
practical environmentalism. But before exploring our intuitions concerning acid mine drainage, we need to account for the general
silence of environmental philosophy on these questions.7
III.
Environmental philosophy is a young discipline: its leading
journal, Environmental Ethics, was not founded until 1979. The
fields origins are straightforward, at least in outline: Rachel Car-
Corrosive Effects
43
44
Geo-Logic
Corrosive Effects
45
to music. His musical definition of justice emphasizes the importance of being properly attuned, both within the self (not too rash,
not too timid) and in ones relations to others. The melody or tone of
a conversation is as important as the lyrics (that is, the propositions)
uttered, and society is seen as a symphony within which everyone
plays the part proper to them. This is a strikingly different conception of ethics from todays rule-driven debates.
By the twentieth century, then, the modernist stance toward
nature had become the received wisdom within both the university
and the culture at large. The result was that environmental philosophy would be cast in terms of environmental ethicseven if
environmental debates regularly strained the bounds of this designation. The physical world was brute matter devoid of purpose, a
world that science could in principle fully describe. Metaphysics,
aesthetics, and theology were antiquated categories that had lost
their raison dtre, and were now seen as simple expressions of dogmatism and subjectivity. In the 1960s, when environmental issues
caught the attention of the public, these concerns were naturally
expressed in the two languages most likely to get a hearing: science,
which defined the real, and ethics, which addressed questions of
rights and obligations. By default, environmental philosophy became environmental ethics. Ethics may have been as subjective as
these other discredited fields, but it still retained a degree of importance, for people are always jealous to protect their rights. John
Passmore summarized the state of affairs within environmental
philosophy in the title of his book (one of the first book-length treatments of environmental philosophy), Mans Responsibility for
Nature (1974). Passmore argued that we could not have any responsibility to the brute, aimless material that is nature. Our only
responsibility was to guard against nature becoming the medium of
injustice to our fellow citizens, say through the improper use of natural resources.
We must not caricature environmental philosophys current situation. To take one example, within the journal Environmental
Ethics we find an impressively wide range of topics, including environmental policy, politics, aesthetics, metaphysics, and theology.
Furthermore, environmental philosophy hasnt entirely abandoned
metaphysical and theological perspectives. It is a commonplace
within the field to contrast the approaches to nature of Gifford Pinchot and John MuirPinchot is seen as representing the utilitarian
position, while Muir is seen as a religious mystic whose defense of
nature is grounded in pantheism.10 On this account, a metaphysical
46
Geo-Logic
or theological perspective lies at the roots of one of the two main currents of environmental philosophy. Similarly, the debate between
anthropocentrism and biocentrism, possibly the most rehearsed argument within environmental philosophy, is fundamentally an argument about natures metaphysical status. Biocentrism is often
described as a religious or metaphysical commitment, and the question of identifying natures value as having a nonhuman origin has
given birth to hundreds of essays and monographs.
Nevertheless, ethics still controls the discussion on philosophys
contribution to environmental debates. Environmental ethics dominates the titles of articles, books, journals, and conferences. Of
course, one may reply, these are only titles, but titles frame the logical space of the conversation. When such examples can be multiplied
(as they can within environmental philosophy), individual instances
begin to form a larger pattern: ethics rules our environmental conversations, muting other perspectives. While these other perspectives are present, they are sufficiently muffled so that, for most
outsiders, environmental philosophy and environmental ethics are
synonymous.
Environmental philosophers are responding to the presumption
of our culture at large, whose definition of the real is limited to the
results of the scientific method and the legalistic discourse of rights
and obligations. The intellectual classes, whether scientific or humanistic, have not taken metaphysics and theologymuch less aestheticsseriously since the Enlightenment. But if environmental
philosophy is going to make a greater contribution to culture than it
has to date, we must find a way to expand our cultures dialogue on
the environment to include these aspects of our response to the natural world.
IV.
In recent years it is possible to discern a shift in the center of
gravity within environmental philosophy. The environmental justice
movement and ecofeminism represent two innovations in environmental thinking.
The environmental justice movement aims to correct environmentalisms traditional disregard of our built environments. It criticizes the traditional focus of environmental ethics upon wilderness
preservation and endangered species, which it sees as evidence that
environmental ethics is out of touch with the lives and concerns of
Corrosive Effects
47
most people today. Instead, these authors and activists take up environmental issues that manifest themselves in our cities, suburbs,
and rural countryside. But despite this shift in focus, the environmental justice movement goes no farther than environmental ethics
in taking metaphysics and theology seriously.
Advocates of environmental justice analyze how environmental
risks are distributed through communities, and seek policies that
equalize who shoulders these burdens. In 1995, the U.S. General Accounting Office estimated that some 450,000 sites in the United
States qualify as brownfieldsabandoned industrial sites that
must be cleaned up before they are suitable for new uses. Not surprisingly, brownfields are disproportionately located in areas where
minorities and low-income groups live. Advocates of environmental
justice not only address questions of where dirty industries, incinerators, and waste dumps are sited, but also suburban sprawl and the
loss of open space, the role of citizens or stakeholders groups in the
framing of environmental policies, and the possible dangers of
genetically modified food (frankenfood).
Part of the reason environmental justice advocates put less emphasis upon the preservation of pristine nature is that they see it as
a dubious category. Our influence upon the land, the seas, and the
ice caps has been so pervasive that some authors speak of the end of
nature.11 Instead, environmental justice focuses on two issues: the
aforementioned concern with distributive justice, and the question
of how to restore lands that have been damaged through human activity or neglect. It is this second point, the philosophic questions
surrounding restoring lands damaged by human actions or neglect,
that is our concern here. Of course, not all of these compromised
sites are in developed areas. Some are in relatively wild places like
the San Juan Mountains. It is here that the clash of perspectives
among environmentalists becomes most clamorous.
The question of howor whetherto repair damaged landscapes prompts a wide spread of reactions. Some environmental
philosophers find the very idea of restoring nature offensive. Eric
Katz is concerned that the ability to restore damaged landscapes
undercuts the argument for preserving unspoiled places. Katz also
sees ecological restoration as a sign of our arrogance toward the natural world, expressing the ideology that as the masters and possessors of nature, we are free to manipulate the entire world to suit our
desires.12 In a similar vein, Bruce V. Foltz objects to transforming
the science of ecology from a descriptive science into a predictive and
manipulative one. He sees this shift as another step in the direction
48
Geo-Logic
Corrosive Effects
49
50
Geo-Logic
Corrosive Effects
51
52
Geo-Logic
mining is completed, to the point that no one can tell the difference
afterward?25 Elliott argues that such a re-created landscape is comparable to a forged painting. Even if the copy cant be distinguished
from the original, something essential has been lost.
That something is the lands origin and peculiar history. For not
only is the lands physical constitution important to us, but so too is
its ontological status. Elliott offers us the analogy of a beautiful,
handcrafted knife received as a gift. We cherish the knife and display it prominently in our home. We then discover that the gift was
fashioned from the bone of a person killed expressly for the purpose
of making the knife. This knowledge changes none of the knifes
chemical or physical characteristics. Nonetheless, its nature has
been irretrievably altered; the knife is now a source of horror rather
than delight. The knifes meaning has changed. Similarly, a reconstructed landscape or ecosystem might match the lands original
condition, down to the last detail. Nevertheless, the reconstruction
would lack the meaning inherent in the original landscape. The
unique origin and history of the land would have been destroyed,
and we would be left with a human artifact.
By focusing on the question of meaning, Elliott opens the door to
a phenomenological interpretation of our experience of nature. But
is the analogy of a restored landscape to a work of artfake or not
appropriate? The problem with this analogy is that it ignores the difference between nature and human creations. For the Greeks,
phusis identified the realm of self-organizing nature; techn, the artifactual world of human-created objects. Describing restored nature
by way of an analogy to a (faked) work of art thus misses precisely
what is distinctive about nature: its fundamental otherness, the fact
that it has an internal dynamic all its own, both before and after it
has been restored.26 While artifacts are passive, nature is recalcitrant. Even if we reconstruct the land in accordance with our wishes,
nature soon heads off in its own direction. (This is a constant problem in restoration projects, as the remediated site is likely to stop
functioning in way we intended, instead reaching a new state of its
own creating.) In this sense, we can speak of a restored landscape
regaining its naturalness, as it slowly reasserts its phusis. In contrast, the artifact has no internal principle of ordering that directs
its development. The only way it asserts its naturalness is by breaking down.
Nonetheless, Elliott has opened a trail that we can follow further. Let us turn, then, to a fuller account of the metaphysics and
theology of acid mine drainage.
Corrosive Effects
53
V.
. . . an act that evolves an evil, an impurity, a fluid, a
mysterious and harmful something that acts dynamicallythat is to say, magically.
Pettazzoni, La confession des pchs (1931)
The exotic carries its own peculiar certification, just as familiarity breeds, if not contempt, then nonchalance and a kind of
blindness. In an age governed by the notion of Homo economicus
the belief that our interests are fundamentally self-interested and
consumerist in orientationis it possible to treat the statement It
looks like sin seriously? Can a young mans comment be seen as
an expression of an experience of transcendence, similar to how
phenomenologist of religion Mircea Eliade interprets the myths of
the Kwakiutl, or the philosopher Paul Ricoeur the symbolism of poetry or dreams? Of course, this is to conflate the great with the
smallthe glittering traditions of world religions with a students
offhand remark. But how, then, are we to interpret the behavior of
the millions who each year make pilgrimages to natural shrines
such as the Grand Canyon and Yellowstone? Should the ongoing
work at Summitville, 150 million dollars of public monies spent to
remediate an obscure location high in the Rockies, be understood
as the logical result following the dictates of science, or as an act
of atonement?
Defilement is a category from a bygone era: we have lost the capacity to treat notions of stain and infection as objective reports of
our being. But might these intuitions live on as subterranean influences, reappearing in the passive voices of scientific papers? When
Ricoeur identifies the two elements of defilement as infection by an
obscure something, and dread of a looming retribution that bears
down upon us, it is not difficult to see how these points may be pertinent to contemporary environmental dramas like acid mine
drainage.27 Environmental concern may well become the organizing
principle of civilization, as Al Gore suggested in 1993, but this does
not preclude our interpreting the apocalyptic tones of much environmental rhetoricwhat Theodore Roszak has called guilt trips and
scare tacticsas expressions of the symbolism of evil.28
Invoking the sacred and its transgression in relation to environmental degradation does not imply an exclusively Christian perspective on environmental harm. Sin, transgression, and atonement
54
Geo-Logic
Corrosive Effects
55
others. More to the point here, the lived experience of the sacred is
distinct from questions about the place of organized, doctrinal religion in public life.
The sacred calls us to acknowledge and honor the otherness of
nature. It renounces the egotism demanding that the entire world
speak our name. The sacred implies the centrality of the notion of
carethe capacity to restrain oneself, to control ones desires in order
to make space for another. Only then can another being manifest its
own nature through the process of self-emergence that the Greeks
called phusis. Phusis and care provide us with another, nonhumancentered standard for measuring our environmental responsibilities.
Placing care at the center of an environmental metaphysics or theology offers us a criterion other than that of pH and conductivity for
approaching the problems of acid mine drainage.
What should we clean up, and to what degree? Those areas that
display a lack of care. A painstakingly woven wooden trellis-works
supporting an old mineworks; the remains of a mills carefully
worked stone foundation, left by an avalanche that hit in the winter
of 52; a miners bunkhouse hanging precariously at eleven thousand
feet, reachable only by an arduous hike: these places embody the
labors, the dangers, and the nobility of the miners life, and should
be preservedor perhaps allowed to weather, age, and eventually
decay of their own accord. In contrast, the heaps of rusting corrugated sheet metal and scattered pipes dumped along the side of a
jeep road, and the bright ooze leaking from an old mine shaftsuch
wanton carelessness we clean up, restoring the area to a semblance
of its former condition. The point of such restoration isnt to eliminate all signs of wear and tear, but rather to get nature started on its
way toward healing itself (GL:CH3).
As for the streams: clean up the mounds of mine tailings
dumped in the rivers, and correct the worst of our desecrations, such
as the violent mounds of gravel left along the Blue River in central
Colorado, the legacy of placer mining. Acknowledge the otherness of
nature by leaving the natural iron bog, while cleaning up our own
depredationseven at additional cost. If hydrologists are clear that
a stream was lifeless before miners arrived, let it be. On the other
hand, if it appears that a stream held fish before the miners arrived,
and that it can be coaxed back to life, let us do so. But if the task
would require a reconstruction so massive that it would leave us
with something more akin to Disneyland than nature, then let it
heal in its own time; over the millennia, natures own recuperative
powers will restore the land. If this seems too slow, let it serve as a
56
Geo-Logic
VI.
While cast in the languages of science, economics, and interest
group politics, our environmental debates are, in truth, caught up in
questions of metaphysics, theology, and aesthetics. Metaphysics and
theology express our concern with deep real and the sacred, while
beauty is the shining of the real, truth become sensuous. Unfortunately, these perspectives are able to gain little traction today, because of an epistemological presumption: reality is defined by those
facts discoverable through the processes of the scientific method.
Corrosive Effects
57
4
THE PLACES OF SCIENCE:
THE HEAVENS, THE LAB,
THE FIELD, AND THE SCREEN
59
60
Geo-Logic
Over the last twenty years, the field of science studies has challenged this assumption. Doing so has led to acrimonious debate. The
debate exerts a strong gravitational pull, drawing in anyone who
questions the standard epistemological account of the sciences.2 It is
a debate typically cast in terms of polaritiesscience as unimpeachable fact, or as ideological construction. In fact, a broad middle
ground exists that sees science as both a report on reality and as
deeply reflecting various types of values.3
The field of science studies has left its mark upon the philosophy of science; while some philosophers remain largely unaffected
(practicing what Giere calls analytical philosophy in historical
robes),4 the range of acceptable interests within the field has expanded. In The Dappled World, Nancy Cartwright distinguishes between two different types of philosophy of science. Citing Hackings
distinction between representing and intervening, Cartwright notes
that philosophers such as Bas van Fraassen are interested in questions such as How can the world be the way that science says it is or
represents it to be? Cartwright describes her own interest as How
can the world be changed by science to make it as it should be? For
Cartwright, the sciences consist of a series of regional accounts of reality with no clear hierarchy ranking them (i.e., physics does not
ground other sciences). She describes the relation between the various disciplines as here and there, once in a while, corners that line
up, but mostly ragged edges.5 But Cartwrights own question leaves
a great deal unanswered. It says nothing about the possibility that
science itself may be part of the problem, contributing to the problems we face, or that political, aesthetic, and metaphysical commitments may lie at the heart of science, or that what our society most
needs may lie in those areas of human endeavor associated with the
humanities. Absent these questions, we are left with a badly truncated philosophy of science.
There is also the question of audience. The groups interested in
science today may be roughly divided into four: practicing scientists,
professional students of science (philosophers of science, science policy analysts, historians, and sociologists), undergraduates (whose
knowledge of science largely comes from textbooks), and the general
public. Only the second group has the time to develop a nuanced understanding of how to marry traditional philosophy of science with
science studies. Undergraduate textbooks offer accounts of science
that still hearken to pre-Kuhnian positivism; and to a surprising degree, standard anthologies within the philosophy of science hardly
mention science studies. The publics understanding of science is
61
largely based on triumphal reports of the latest scientific innovations and discoveries.
Given sciences central position in societal debates, careful reflection on its use and misusethat is, a philosophy of science
should occupy a central place in public life. Regrettably, this has not
been the case. The philosophy of science has had little or no public
presence in interpreting sciences status and its relationship to society. The reasons for this are many and varied, but I want to explore
one important cause: the role that examples have played in defining
our cultures understanding of science. Societys understanding of
the power and limits of science has been inadequate in part because
of how science has been portrayed through the use of a few exemplary cases. Relying upon examples of science taken from the heavens and the laboratory, rather than the field, philosophers of science
have perpetuated a dangerously unrealistic image of science.
I will develop this point through a brief examination of four classic sites of science: the heavens, the lab, the field, and the computer
screen.
I.
In general, nature does not prepare situations to fit the
kinds of mathematical theories we hanker for.
Nancy Cartwright, How the Laws of Physics Lie
While philosophers commonly date its beginnings in the Vienna
Circles work of the 1920s, in important ways the field that came to
be known as the philosophy of science originated in the 1850s. This
was when the William Whewell coined the term scientist, and when
the older tradition of Naturphilosophie gave way to the positivist assumptions of Comte. At its birth, this new discipline might have defined its subject in a number of ways. It might have become a branch
of political philosophy, studying the effects of scientific discoveries on
society, and how science could best contribute to societal aims. Or it
could have become a subdivision of epistemology, focusing on the nature of the scientific method, and certifying the status of scientific
claims. Or it could have taken up both tasks, grounding the philosophy of science in both political philosophy and epistemology.6
The philosophy of science defined its task as being fundamentally epistemological in nature. For 150 years, the discipline has
62
Geo-Logic
63
64
Geo-Logic
an idealized space (i.e., one without friction) that Galileo can identify a law that describes how they always hit the ground at the
same moment. Similarly, Newtons laws of celestial mechanics offer
a powerful image of scientific reasoning, but they also provide a
convenient example of scientific certainty that is distanced from
everyday affairs. Science viewed from the perspective of Newtons
laws is disconnected from the traffic of everyday life, formulated in
a rigorously mathematical way, and summed up in a few equations.
Newtons research is an admirable example of the power of a certain
kind of science. But how appropriate a model is it, given the types of
challenges science must address today?
I am not suggesting that the only reason that Newton and
Galileo are used (literally) as textbook examples of scientific advance is that their work fosters a certain image of science. But we
must ask why these theories have the place they do in our accounts
of science. Why, for instance, does nearly every college course in
physics begin with Newtonian mechanics, rather than with an account of quantum mechanics, electricity, or optics? Newtons work is
our paradigm of scientific knowledge: powerful, mechanistic, and
certain (once we set aside the lifelike variables), and existing in an
ideal, mathematical space. Newtonian mechanics thus fulfills both
sciences and societys dream of a scientific truth that does not
entangle us in the complications of our social lives.
Of course, science did not stay in the heavens. But when the
work of science was brought down to earth, it was located in a
space that retained many of the characteristics of celestial space:
the laboratory.
The laboratory is, by definition, an unreal space. Within it, conditions are parameterized, objects are constrained, and materials
are purified. The space of the lab is utopian: in Greek, ou-topos
means literally a no place. The lab is a space abstracted from the
rest of the world; it makes no difference whether a lab experiment
is conducted in Dallas or Oslo.11 And not only is the space of the lab
idealized; in the laboratory, time is idealized as well. In the lab, history doesnt exist. Time exists, of course; it takes time to run an experiment. But the laboratory eliminates historythat is, the
nonrepeatable and contingent flow of events, both natural and cultural, within which we live our lives. The defining characteristic of
laboratory science is that the conditions and results can be repeated
on demand.
The situation within the lab may be summarized as follows:
what we gain in control, we lose in realism. The irony here is that
65
while the lab sciences are considered the gold standard for scientific
truth, the findings of the lab often dont apply realistically to the social controversies we face. The question that should lie at the center
of the philosophy of (lab) science, but is too often treated as incidental, is How do we relate the closed, ahistorical system of the lab to
the open and historical world that we live in?
This question has received scant attention from philosophers of
science. And no wonder. For this question would force the philosophy
of science to recognize how much the lab sciences depend upon analogical reasoning. Judging how the results from the labs closed and
controlled system relate to the open and historical world we inhabit
demands skill at drawing apt analogies. Now, a great deal of work
has been done on the role of analogy within scientific reasoning.12
This work, however, has been concerned with the cognitive or psychological role of analogy in the creation of conceptswith how
analogies help us imagine scientific problemsrather than with the
analogical relation between lab and reality. And while the exact relation between lab and field is a vexed question, this much is clear:
it will not be susceptible to mathematical formularization. Rather
than in mathematics, analogical reasoning finds its home in disciplines such as philosophy, history, and literary studies.
Our reluctance to think through the lab sciences fundamental
dependence upon analogy with the field has given birth to two kinds
of mischief. First, when society fails to apply laboratory results to
the world in which we live, it encourages disillusionment with science. And second, it has sponsored the devaluation of other types of
knowledgein particular, the historical sciences and the nonquantifiable humanitieswhen they, by their very nature, fail to live up
to the standards of the lab. The result of centering the philosophy of
science on the two spaces of the heavens and the lab has been the
creation of an enormously powerful intellectual apparatus with a
very tenuous relation to social concerns. In this way, the philosophy
of science has come to mirror the examples it has chosen.
II.
The fundamental problem with our discussions of science today
is that we have separated the two elements of the discipline that
must be held together. These two elements are the nature and status
of scientific knowledge, and the relation of science to the rest of our
lives. Separating these two questions has led to the development of
66
Geo-Logic
67
68
Geo-Logic
III.
Basing our image of science in the heavens and the lab has created a metaphorics of science as cerebral, ahistorical, and isolated
from the other aspects of our lives. In contrast, a field-based philosophy of science offers us a more socially engaged and epistemologically realistic image of science. To see why, consider the distinctive
nature of field science.
Science in the field proceeds at a different rhythm. Outside, in
the open air, the scientist is subject to the elements. Rather than the
controlled experience of the lab, the field scientist is immersed in a
constantly changing sensorium that expresses the wonder and
serendipity of experience. The conceptual and physical walls that
isolated the lab scientist are gone; the field scientist passes through
a shifting, frameless flow of events. In the lab, nature is constrained
so that it will show itself in a regular fashion; in the field, the scientist must adjust herself to natures patterns, cultivating a disposition of alert repose and anticipating the moment when the world
reveals itself. The biologist may wait all day for the chance appearance of a species, and the geologist devotes hours searching for the
telling fossil, splitting bedding planes in a shale unit.
While the lab narrows and controls the flow of information, the
fields perceptual and conceptual kaleidoscope exceeds our capaci-
69
ties to sort, test, and categorize it. Field scientists develop intuitive
skills for parsing knowledge in implicit, nonpropositional ways.
Walk an outcrop with a seasoned field geologist. Years in the field
have taught him how to sift through the superabundance of information and identify the significant anomalyan odd dip in the
strata, an unusual color along the bottom of a layer. Field scientists
do not operate in objective geographical space conceptualized by
Cartesian geometry. Rather, they move through a world of implied
meaning constituted by the acting and perceiving body as it interacts with its environment.
In geological fieldwork, the black and white stripes of paired
limestone and shale beds that are easily distinguishable at fifty meters grow indistinct at three meters, only to resolve themselves
again at fifteen centimeters. Similarly, the land unfolds for the geologist as he passes over it, revealing an infinite number of perspectives that are integrated and contrasted in his mind. Of course, out
of this, the geologist must abstract a testable hypothesis and numerical values. But these results are built upon the intuitive use of
judgment in which the geologist selectsand constructsa system
of signs and blends multiple perspectives from a nearly infinite
amount of potential data.
The field scientists interaction with the Earth depends upon
what Merleau-Ponty calls motor-intentionality.15 Motor-intentionality refers to the directed action-perception that operates before we
consciously posit an object for examination. In driving a car, we do
not consciously analyze traffic patterns and driving conditions. The
experienced driver does not stare at the road, but rather scans the
field of vision in search of clues: the faded yellow and white patches
of the street lines, the paired flashes of animal eyes, the flicker of
taillights, the telltale glimmer of bike metal. Like a surfer or a professional musician, the experienced driver is not so much following a
set of logical procedures as moving along in a flowing river of experience, on the lookout for clues that point toward alternative futures.
Indeed, while driving, it is dangerous to focus upon a single object,
thereby losing the ambient awareness of ones surroundings. Experienced drivers do not experience a distinct separation between
themselves and their automobiles. Such a separation only comes
into play on a conceptually and linguistically objectifying level of
consciousness. Similarly, fieldwork operates below the level of fully
conscious intentional activity, which involves concepts and introspective reasoning, and above such mere reflex movements as the
blinking of the eyes or the heartbeat.16
70
Geo-Logic
71
IV.
The days of being imprisoned within the messy, often
unpleasant realities of life on planet Earth are almost
at an end.
John Casti, Would-Be Worlds
When considered at all, field science has been seen as a poor
version of what properly occurs in the heavens or in the laboratory.
But in fact, an understanding of science based in the nature of fieldwork adds a realistic element to our understanding of science, reeducatingand in some measure, reducingsocietys excessive
expectations concerning scientific knowledge.
Some will be dismayed at the suggestion that science should be
allotted a more modest role in societal debates (say, in environmental questions, or in improving human health). Questioning sciences
status in society raises hacklesand not only in scientific circles.
Many still hold to the view that scientific and technological progress
are to be identified with progress tout court. Suggesting a more modest role for science in society is often seen as tantamount to repudiating the Enlightenment goal of progressively perfecting the human
estate. But this is unfair. Calling for more appropriate uses of science in society does not make someone antiscience any more than
promoting dieting constitutes an attack upon the food industry. Indeed, a more modest role for science even offers some benefits to the
scientific community itself. For one of the greatest dangers to science today is that it promises more than it can deliver in terms of
being able to resolve our political controversies.
But if fieldwork offers a powerful example of the sciences nature,
another image of science is coming to the fore, one that embraces and
extends the philosophic assumptions underlying laboratory science.
Today both the scientific community and society at large are turning
to a fourth image of science: the computer screen or cyberscience.
The term cyberscience refers to claims that computer modeling
presents us with a new paradigm for science in the twenty-first cen-
72
Geo-Logic
tury. Computer simulations and models are being aggressively pursued across the physical and social sciencesfrom planetary physics
to molecular genetics, from psychological metrics to economics and
political science. But their greatest attraction is that they allow scientists to address precisely those areas that, up to now, have not
been amenable to control in the laboratory. Computer models simulate phenomena that are too large, too complex, too expensive, or too
historical to be placed within the lab: in a word, the phenomena
studied by field science.
The rise of cyberscience has been supported by the steady expansion of computing power that allows us to manipulate amounts of data
that would have overwhelmed earlier investigatorsor crashed older
computers. But the cachet of cyberscience also reflects the continued
attraction of the Cartesian belief that reality is, at its core, something
clear and distinct and amenable to mathematical formulation, rather
than deeply sensual and interpretive in nature. Cyberscience speaks
to the desire to escape the uncertainties and ambiguities of our lives.
It establishes artificial worlds that we can control and manipulate
or for that matter, enter into via virtual reality. Cyberscience refurbishes the positivist dream of a type of knowledge that makes political
debate superfluous. However, the question remains: How do these
artificial worlds actually relate to the world that we live in?
The goal of a computer model is to fashion a set of equations
that perfectly mimic natural processes. Once the model approximates reality, it can be manipulated in order to test out different scenarios. For instance, a climate model can be run by factoring in
varying amounts of greenhouse gases in order to see how the results
differ over time. But there is a hidden ambiguity here. For some of
our most crucial questions, we either wont live long enough to verify
the prediction (will global mean temperatures be 5 higher by
2100?), or we will do our best to never run the experiment at all (e.g.,
actually seeing what would happen if the hole in the ozone expands).
As Naomi Oreskes notes, such computer predictions present us
with a conundrum. Claims concerning the distinctive character of
science turn on the testability of scientific claims. In these cases,
however, we are equivocating on the terms test or predict, when
there will be no way to confirm the model in the time needed to
make decisions.18 One way researchers try to circumvent this problem is to run a computer model backward in order to retrodict what
has already occurred: if the results match the historical data, the
model is considered verified. But this assumes that the system being
considered will function in the future as it has in the past.
73
74
Geo-Logic
75
5
EARTH STORIES
More than two millennia ago the Greeks began their quest for
logosa pattern or rational order to the world. With Plato, Greek
thinking came to focus upon a specific type of logos. Turning our attention away from our bodies, and from the body of the Earth, the
Greeks directed the rational gaze upward, toward the stars, and inward, toward a pure mental order. Thus the Greek search for logos
became a quest for a very particular type of orderone that was distant, regular, immutable, and certain.
The motivation behind this is clear. As Plato notes, our knowledge of things in the sensible world is always questionable. For how
can we claim to truly know anything that is constantly changing?
Time itself is the enemy of rationality, rendering every claim to
truth inconclusive and suspect. Knowledge must be grounded in
those realms beyond the corrosive effects of temporality. In fact, engraved in the portal to Platos Academy was the statement, Let no
one deficient in geometry enter. Only in the realm of thoughtand
in the celestial sphere, a region considered beyond material corruptioncould we find the conditions suitable for truth.
The creation of mathematics and geometry and the identification
of the celestial order were watershed events in the progress of human
rationality. With Plato defining reality as the rational, and rationality identified with the regular, immutable, and certain, the reality of
the sensuous world was denigrated or even denied. Through its long
history our culture has sided with this view. We have valorized the
enduring over the transientdown to the present-day priority given
to mathematics and the mathematically based sciences. Quantity
and objectivitythe former understood as the deep essence of things,
and the latter defining knowledge in terms of those things that we
can turn into objectsremain the tokens of the real.
77
78
Geo-Logic
Earth Stories
79
I.
Geology has received little attention from the humanities.2 Certainly, contemporary philosophy has not recognized the field as a
subject worthy of reflection. There is no philosophy of geology or of
the Earth sciences as there are philosophies of physics and of biology. The two main schools of contemporary philosophy, the analytic
and the continental, have ignored geology. It has been assumed (few
even thought to argue the point) that examining the Earth sciences
was unnecessary to understand the nature of science. Statements by
philosophers on the status of geology sound a common refrain: In
conclusion, then, the Principle of Uniformity dissolves into the principle of simplicity that is not peculiar to geology but pervades all science and even daily life, and Geology is a science just like other
sciences, for example physics or chemistry.3
We can find a few exceptions to this general neglect. Ronald
Giere ends Explaining Science by using the revolution in plate tectonics as a case study exemplifying his theory of science, and
Naomi Oreskes et al. address the limits of hydrological modeling in
a 1994 essay in Science.4 Kristen Shrader-Frechette offers a booklength analysis of the assumptions underlying the storage of nuclear waste in Burying Uncertainty.5 There are also two
monographs that offer a philosophical account of the Earth sciences: David Kittss from the perspective of analytic philosophy,
80
Geo-Logic
Earth Stories
81
with Descartes, that we understand objects and processes by breaking them down into their simplest parts.11 A synthetic science such
as geology could then be logically resolved into its constituents of
physics and chemistry.
The geologic community itself has given the most attention to
the philosophic aspects of geology. Gilberts and Chamberlins essays, dating from the classic era of nineteenth-century geology, embody the attitudes of natural history and natural philosophy.12 In the
twentieth century, various geologists have reflected upon the
methodology underlying particular subfields of geology, and have offered general accounts of geological research.13 Within the latter, the
work of Stephen Jay Gould is especially notable, but the writings of
Peter Ward, Niles Eldridge, and E. O. Wilson also show that the tradition of natural philosophy is not entirely extinct.14
While this work connecting geology with humanistic concerns
has made real contributions to our understanding of geology and science in general, it has also been characterized by two qualities.
First, it has accepted the description of geology as a derivative science. Earth scientists practice what Massey calls the reverential
referencetreating physics as the paradigm of reasoning, trolling
within physics or mathematics for an approach (relativity, quantum
mechanics, fractals, complexity theory) that gives a patina of legitimization to their softer discipline.15 (Whence the metaphorics of
the hard and the soft? One may wonder, when scientists are praised
for being hardheaded, whether another region of being is the
source of pride.) And second, for historical and cultural reasons that
I will discuss below, philosophically inclined geologists have usually
turned to only one of the two major traditions of contemporary philosophyAnglo-American or analytic philosophyfor help with
describing their science.
Are the Earth sciences best understood as merely applied and
imprecise physics, vainly attempting to achieve the high degrees of
resolution and predictability of physics? I offer a different view: geological reasoning consists of a combination of procedures that mirror
the reasoning we use in our public and private lives. This combination of techniques is not unique to geology, but rather is present to
one degree or another in most types of thinking, scientific or otherwise. But it is especially characteristic of the field-based Earth sciences. The sense of inferiority concerning geologys status as
compared with other, harder sciencesits physics envyis misplaced. A fully developed account of the Earth can provide the rational foundation for both our public and private lives.
82
Geo-Logic
II.
A prominent geologist describes the relationship between geology and philosophy thus: Earth scientists do not find philosophical
discussions of their field very interesting. In fact, many scientists
treat the philosophy of science with exasperated contempt. 16 It is
nonetheless true that the methodological self-understanding in the
sciences, as well as our cultures understanding of the scientific
method, is derived largely from the stories that philosophers have
told. This descriptionsciences self-understanding, and our cultures understanding of the nature of scienceis significantly different from the account of science that has recently developed within
contemporary philosophy and sociology of science. Busy with their
own matters, most scientists and citizens are only faintly aware of
this changed conception of scientific knowledgeor know of it only
through the dust-up surrounding Sokals hoax.17
To appreciate the nature of this new consensus, and what it
means for our understanding of the science of geology, we need to
first review the status quo. As mentioned, in the twentieth century,
Western philosophy has consisted of two main schools of thought,
analytic and Continental philosophy. The fundamental difference
between these two approaches has turned on their attitude toward
the nature and scope of scientific knowledge. At their most basic,
the original claims of analytic philosophy (circa 1940) can be reduced to two: (1) all knowledge available to humans is derived
through the method employed by science, and (2) the scientific
method itself consists of an identifiable set of procedures sharply
distinguished from other types of thought (other philosophic or literary approaches, such as traditional metaphysics, phenomenology,
or literary criticism).
Early analytic philosophers such as Russell, Carnap, and
Reichenbach developed a powerful characterization of the scientific
method. Their conclusions may be summarized by the following
three claims. First, the scientific method is objective. This means
that the discovery of scientific truth can and must be separated
from any personal, ethical/political, or metaphysical commitments.
This is the basis of the celebrated fact/value distinction, which
holds that the facts discovered by the scientist are quite distinct
from whatever values he or she might hold. Personal or cultural
values must not enter into the scientific reasoning process. Closely
related is the insistence that we must distinguish between the logic
of discovery and the logic of explanation. Identifying the particular
Earth Stories
83
84
Geo-Logic
Earth Stories
85
86
Geo-Logic
III.
Consider first the perspectives of hermeneutics, one of the
most characteristic tools of nineteenth- and twentieth-century
Continental philosophy. Hermeneutics is the art or science of interpreting texts. A text (by which is meant, typically, a literary
work) is a system of signs the meaning of which is not apparent,
but must be deciphered. This deciphering takes place when we assign differing types or degrees of significance to the various elements making up the text. The status of this deciphered meaning
has been the source of some dispute: in the nineteenth century
some claimed that, when properly applied to a text, hermeneutic
technique resulted in knowledge as objective as that of the natural
sciences. In the twentieth century, however, students of hermeneutic have claimed that the deciphering of meaning always involves
the subtle interplay of what is objectively there in the text with
what presuppositions and expectations the reader brings to the
text. In effect, hermeneutics rejects the claim that facts can ever be
completely independent of theory.23
Hermeneutics originated in the early nineteenth century as a
means of reconciling contradictory statements in the Bible through
a systematic interpretation of its various claims. In the early twentieth century, hermeneutics was applied to historical (including
legal) documents to help discover the original meaning of the author. Theologians used (and still use) hermeneutics to argue which
parts of the Bible to read literally and which metaphorically, and
what weight to give to each part. Similarly, the literary scholar
proceeds hermeneutically when she claims that a narrators comments are to be taken seriously rather than ironically, as does the
psychologist when he interprets a slip of the tongue to be significant or not.
In the twentieth century, however, hermeneutics has moved
from being a rather straight-forward methodology of the Geistwissenschaften (i.e., the humanities; literally, the spiritual sciences) to a more general account of knowing. Hermeneutic
philosophers such as Heidegger have argued that all human understanding (including the natural sciences, although this was not his
main concern) is fundamentally interpretive.24 Not only books, but
all of reality is a text to be read: rarely do we find completely objective data or information that is purely given. How we perceive a
thing is always shaped (though not completely determined; the
world asserts its own independence) by how we conceive and act
Earth Stories
87
88
Geo-Logic
Earth Stories
89
90
Geo-Logic
IV.
Another feature of geologic reasoning is worth noting: its nature
as a historical science. A historical science (a category which includes the disciplines of cosmology, geology, paleontology, anthropology, and human history) is defined by the role that historical
explanation plays in its work. Explanations within the historical sciences involve the tools common to all sciences (e.g., the deductivenomological model of explanation), but are also distinguished by
three additional elements: the limited relevance of laboratory experiments, the problem of natural kinds, and the role of narrative.
As noted above, to the degree that scientific research is based on
laboratory experimentation, it is essentially nonhistorical. In principle, the particularities of space and time play no role in the reasoning process. Not only is the space idealized, set up so that other
researchers can re-create the experiments conditions within their
own laboratory, but in a fundamental sense history does not exist.30
Of course, time and history are inescapable parts of every instance of
scientific research: a chemical reaction takes time to complete, and
every chemical reaction is historical in that it has some feature, no
Earth Stories
91
matter how insignificant, that distinguishes it from every other reaction. But our interest in chemical reactions lies not in chronicling
the specific historical conditions affecting a given reaction, but
rather in abstracting a general or ideal truth about a class of chemical reactions. A particular chemical reaction is approached as an instance of a general law or principle, rather than as a part of the
great irretrievable sweep of historical events.
In the historical sciences, the specific causal circumstances
surrounding the subject of investigationwhat led up to it, and
what issued from itare the researchers main concern. In geology,
for instance, the goal is not primarily to identify general laws, but
rather to chronicle the particular events that occurred at a given location (at an outcrop, for a region, or for that matter for the entire
planet). Hypotheses are not testable in the way they are in the experimental sciences. Although the geologist may be able to duplicate the laboratory conditions of anothers experiment (e.g.,
studying the nature of deformation through experiments with Playdoh), the relationship of these experiments to the realities of the
Earths history (e.g., the formation of the Rocky Mountains) will
always remain uncertain.
The crucial point here is that the historical sciences are distinguished by a different set of criteria for what counts as an explanation. To borrow and adapt an example from David Hull, when we ask
why someone has died, we are not satisfied with the appeal to the
law of nature that all organisms die, true as that is. We are asking
for an account of the particular circumstances surrounding that persons death. Similarly, in the Earth sciences we are largely interested in the specific histories of historical phenomena (a particular
stream, a region such as the Western Interior Seaway, a trilobite
species). We might identify general laws in geology that have
explanatory power; but the weight of our interest lies elsewhere.
A second aspect of the historical sciences merits our attention.
Historical entities present a unique challenge to the researcher; for
how do we define our object of study? In some sciences, the objects
appear as natural kinds: for instance, the nucleus of an atom consists of neutrons and protons, a distinction well grounded in the
atoms very structure. But historical entities do not spring into being
fully formed, nor do they remain unchanged until their destruction.
For instance, in investigating the history of the Colorado River
(which seems to have run in different directions at different times in
its history), we face the riddle of deciding when it first became the
Colorado River.31 How close to the current Colorado River must it be
92
Geo-Logic
Earth Stories
93
missal ignores the fact that narrative has its own distinctive logic. It
also begs the question of whether scientific explanation itself
depends upon the logic of the story.
Continental philosophers have been prominent in arguing that
scientific explanation and narrative understanding in fact complement one anotherscience providing facts that parameterize an
issue, narrative providing the overall goal and moral purpose of research. In Time and Narrative Paul Ricoeur claims that narrative
storytellingis our most basic way of making sense of experience. In
Ricoeurs view, scientific explanation itself depends on a framing
narrative: defining the scientific project and making sense of its results depend upon the place that this project occupies within one or
more story lines. These story lines (e.g., the pursuit of fame or
riches, the righting of a public or private wrong, the desire for truth,
or the wish for a better common future) provide the essential contexts for science. For instance, the development and testing of global
circulation models (GCMs) gain their rationale in terms of our concerns with the ethical, political, and natural effects of future climate
change. Earth-science information such as how much oil or copper
we have left, how likely a catastrophic flood or volcanic eruption
might be, and what the possible scenarios for our climates future
are makes sense only when it is placed within the structure of a
story. Such Earth stories operate at different levels of generality: at
their widest, these accounts frame not only our relationship to one
another within a given locality, but also to the natural world itself.
Finally, narrative logic is distinguished from scientific knowledge by the fact that the former has an inherent moral structure.
Narratives look to the future, not in the scientific sense of making
predictions, but in Aristotles sense of being concerned with final
causes. A story always expresses a moral vision of what the future
should look like (or in the case of dystopias, through warning us of
an undesirable future). Historians, philosophers, and littrateurs
excel at creating and interpreting the stories used to frame the
work of the sciences, bridging the chasm that separates science
and society.
V.
The Earth sciences only partially live up to the classic model of
scientific reasoning. But rather than viewing itself as a lesser or derivative science, geological reasoning provides an outstanding
94
Geo-Logic
model of another type of scientific reasoning based in the approaches of hermeneutics and the historical sciences. Geology is a
preeminent example of a synthetic science, combining a variety of
logical techniques to solve its problems. The geologist exemplifies
Levi-Strausss bricoleur, the thinker whose intellectual toolbox contains a variety of tools that he or she selects in accordance with the
job at hand.
There are at least two reasons we should care about these
claims. First, scientific reasoning in general and geological reasoning in particular are complex operations. It stands to reason that a
greater degree of self-consciousness about the nature of the reasoning process can help the scientist to better evaluate the epistemological status of his or her work. Second, this argument points the way
toward a more vibrant notion of reasoning within the sciences and
our culture in general. Scientific reasoning is too often caricatured
as a cookbook method that provides us with infallible answers.
When the inevitable disappointment sets in, this misrepresentation
damages both science and culture. The geologic reasoning process offers an account of reasoning more applicable to the uncertainties
and complexities of our lives. We seldom possess all the data we
would like for making a decision; and it is not always clear that the
data are unbiased or objective. Therefore, we are forced to fill the
gaps in our knowledge with interpretation and reasonable assumptions that we hope will be subsequently confirmed. The methods of a
hermeneutic and historical science better mirror the complexities we
face as historical beings.
We will soon turn to the social and political implications of these
points of epistemology. But before doing so, there remains one other
aspect to geologic reasoning we need to explorethe embodied and
kinesthetic aspects of geology exemplified in geologic fieldwork.
6
THE PHILOSOPHY OF
(FIELD) SCIENCE
95
96
Geo-Logic
97
and outcrops of the wafer-thin layered rock in the 50-million-yearold Green River Formation in Wyoming.5 From this, one can conclude that these outcrops represent an ancient environment similar
to what is found in todays freshwater lakes.
This is an eminently reasonable approach, and one that surely
advances our understanding of the story of the Earth. But the problem with this account is that it assumes that we will always be able
to find a contemporary matchin other words, that the full range of
past environments still exist today. But we are disabused of this assumption by a few elementary facts about the Earths history. For instance, it is estimated that less than 10 percent of the Earths past
consists of times like todays icehouse conditions with permanent
ice at the poles. Conversely, the greenhouse conditions typical of
the past (times with high levels of carbon dioxide and of volcanism,
and a much smaller difference in temperature from the equator to
the poles) lie outside our experience.6 Furthermore, some of the most
typical environments of the geologic past (for instance, saltwater
seas on continental landmasses such as the Western Interior Seaway, which covered a broad swath of land from Texas to the Arctic)
no longer exist. Finally, even in places where we do find comparable
modern environments, the scales of these environments are often
quite different from those in the past. There is no desert today that
matches, in age or extent, the tens of thousands of feet of sandstones
found on the Colorado Plateau.
As an argument from analogy, then, uniformitarianism presents
us with an enigma. The present is too smalland warpeda window into the past to provide the geologist with a full set of analogues. This is true in at least two senses. First, not only are we
faced with the problem described above, of trying to draw an analogy
from a nonexistent contemporary environment, but we also face a
second problem: there are inescapable disanalogies between our
human experience of time and the expanses of geologic time. The
principle of uniformity can never tell us how to adjust modern conditions to rocks that have been altered by the slow effects of millions
of years. Yes, we can travel to the Carolina Coast and excavate a
cross-section in a beach, thereby uncovering burrowing insects and
the trails they have left behind. But there is no process that we can
observe today that will tell us how the insect burrow will look in a
100 million years. We can, of course, attempt to model these changes
in the lab or on a computer, but this only recapitulates our problem,
for we cannot be sure of the parameters we set, nor can we run our
model for geologic magnitudes of space or lengths of time.
98
Geo-Logic
99
100
Geo-Logic
101
102
Geo-Logic
103
the midst of a cacophony of detail. The whole process is akin to working a jigsaw puzzle. When you first turn the pieces over, you are nonplussed by the task of distinguishing between such a monotonous
blur of colors. But as the work proceeds, differences begin to reveal
themselves: your eye catches the ever-so-slight shadings of red, suddenly recognizing them as the undulations of a velvet curtain. This
experience also called into question my initial distinction between
the visible and the invisible. I simply could not see what was clearly
visible to more experienced geologists.
But what about the dark shale beds? During my time at the outcrop, I had collected samples from each shale bed to look for microfossils known as foraminifera. Back in the lab, I processed the rock
from the bottom and top shale units by grinding the shale with a
mortar and pestle, and then washing and straining the forams
through a metal sieve. I then examined the resulting grit under a
light microscope. I had only a passing familiarity with micropaleontology, and my only help came from another graduate student, who
on a couple of occasions prompted me with questions as I looked
through the microscope. But by prompting me to find salient differences, his questions at once affected my ability to notice distinctions.
And so I embarked upon a journey into a world distant in both
space and time, scrutinizing the shells (tests) of creatures of infinitesimal size and nearly a hundred million years old. They were
strange geometric beasts: in the bottom shale bed they came coiled,
cone-shaped, and globular, sometimes symmetrically arranged
around a single axis, sometimes seeming randomly stuck together
spheres. In the upper bed, I also found the globular shapes (both
arranged around and without an axis) and those shaped like a cone,
but this bed also revealed two new types: a coiled, cocoon-shaped
creature and a columnar, ribbed, rectangular beast. Lacking any
larger interpretive framework in which to put these discoveries
and not wanting at this stage of my work to give myself over to the
paleontological literature, which would have rigorously defined all of
these specimensI put them aside, and they played no further role
in my description or interpretation of the outcrop (GL:CH6).
Finally, I looked for the influence of large-scaled features (e.g.,
faults, igneous intrusions, evidence of metamorphism) upon the
outcrop. The layers themselves were close to horizontal, with little
sign that the rocks had been deformed after deposition. It seemed
that the Arkansas River had simply cut down through a section of
Cretaceous-age strata. (It was later pointed out to me that this exposure of rocks was dependent upon a regional upliftthe Rock
104
Geo-Logic
105
106
Geo-Logic
107
108
Geo-Logic
amount of sediment input varies by factors such as changes in climate. I needed to look at the outcrop as a languagea system of interrelating and counterbalancing processes, tectonic and climatic
activity, Milankovitch cycles, changes of sediment production and
productivity.
109
110
Geo-Logic
Much of my education in field science has come through reflecting on my own failures in seeing what was obviously there. But my
chagrin at missing the obvious has been lessened by reports of geologists who have suffered the same failure. In his autobiography,
Charles Darwin recalls going into the field in Wales in 1831 with
Adam Segwick, nearly a decade before Louis Agassizs theory of continental glaciation:
Neither of us saw a trace of the wonderful glacial phenomena all around us; we did not notice the plainly scored rocks,
the perched boulders, the lateral and terminal moraines.
Yet, these phenomena are so conspicuous that . . . a house
burned down by fire did not tell its story more plainly than
did this valley.13
But while this experience is ubiquitous among geologists, the
process by which one moves from blindness to insight has been little
analyzed by either science or the philosophy of science. Nonetheless,
this experience is present throughout scienceas well as in reading
a poem and in judging the intonations and body language of a salesman. The act of semiosislearning to see something as a sign expressing meaningis arguably humanitys most basic rational
activity. It is this skill, rather than propositional and predicate calculus, that should be taught in logic classes; indeed, it should find a
home in every discipline across the curriculum. Skill in semiosis is
found in the scientists work in the lab or the field, the physicians
ability to recognize signs of incipient illness, and our ability to read
the motivations of the people we meet.
The skills exemplified in geologic fieldwork may be placed under
two headings: thinking in the interrogative mood, and the visible and
the invisible.14 To see the former, turn again to Platos Republic, a dialogue concerned with the question What is justice? One can read
the text many times before asking, Why does the story begin with
Socrates friends grabbing him by the sleeve and playfully forcing
him to stay for the afternoon?15 It is unlikely that most readers actually conclude that the incident is insignificant. It is more likely that
readers never raise the question at all, assuming that it is only a bit
of stage setting before the real dialogue begins. But once the question
is posed, this innocent beginning takes on a meaning that influences
ones interpretation of the entire work. For this small act of mock antagonism broaches the issue of the relation between violence and reason. Does the threat of violence itself motivate us to be reasonable? Is
111
112
Geo-Logic
But amidst this confusion, the athlete is still able to perfectly place
a pass.
Visual intelligence also involves more than the use of our eyes.
Spatial understanding is kinetic; to understand three-dimensional
space, one must move through it. Geology involves a tactile and
kinesthetic type of reasoning, demanding an active and mobile body
rather than the disembodied intelligence of mathematical knowledge. I needed to walkand climbthe cliffs in order to understand
them, to see them from a variety of angles and perspectives. The geologist stares at the outcrop, of course. But she also moves around in
order to see it at different angles. She strikes or digs the rock out,
feeling its density and resistance. She directs her body back and
forth, left and right, to take in the different geological features, intuitively seeking an optimum distance and observational angle for
the features being considered. When we view an object, we seek a
direction viewed from which it vouchsafes most of itself. MerleauPonty calls this the tendency toward gaining a maximum grip
upon the environment.17 In some cases, howeverfor instance, in
viewing the alternating layers of limestone and shale in the Bridge
Creek Formationthere is no single point of maximum grip. We
must try to hold onto a series of irreconcilable views of an object
geologic fieldwork as cubism.
To see the relation between the visible and the invisible, consider the work of the nineteenth-century French painter Paul
Czanne, especially his repeated rendering of Mont Sainte-Victoire
near Aix-en-Provence (GL:CH6). Czanne dismissed the title of impressionist. He described his goal as painting how we actually see
the world, the lived perception of an object rather than a geometric
or photographic one. He remarked to his friend Bernard, [W]e must
develop an optics, by which I mean a logical visionthat is, one with
no element of the absurd. Czannes wife described his manner of
working: He would start by discovering the geological foundations
of the landscape, convinced that these abstract relationships, expressed, however, in terms of the visible world, should affect the act
of painting.18 For Czanne, the surface of an object is not simply a
two-dimensional flat plane, but rather the surface obscuring a hidden depth, which reaches its expression at the surface.
Czannes goal was a rigorous fidelity to the object. But instead
of pursuing this by drawing the outlines of things and then coloring
them in, Czanne constructed objects not by lines but by color. The
contour of an object conceived as a line encircling the object belongs
not to the world but to geometry . . . the world is a mass without
113
114
Geo-Logic
How, then, does the geologist makes sense of the outcrop? One
aspect surely follows what is taught in introductory historical geology: through applying uniformitarian principles. Seeing the outcrop
is in part a logical process that depends upon syllogisms no different
from All men are mortal; Socrates is a man; therefore; Socrates is a
mortal. In stratigraphy, the syllogism might be: The coarseness of
sediment is a measure of the streams transporting power; sediment
becomes more fine-grained from east to west across the section;
therefore, the transporting power of the stream has lessened as we
move toward the west. But logic isnt simply, or even primarily, a
mechanical process grinding out such statements. Logic in the sense
of logos identifies that overall structure or context within which
things take on significance. The first sense of logic can be taught in
a rote way. But logic in the second, more fundamental sense relies
upon knowing your way around the outcrop, learning to pose appropriate questions, and envisioning the Earth, seeing the visible
through the template of the invisible. This second sense of logic requires the same rigorous clarity as the first, but also depends upon
the ability (and opportunity!) to muse, entertain doubts, and withhold judgment, opening up the mental space necessary for things to
reveal themselves as signs.
The importance of withholding judgment was apparent at
Starved Rock, where Chris and the stranger crouched down and
looked for fossils in the flagstone. Proof in such cases is improbable;
I could only provide Chris with the beginnings of a logos (Doesnt
this have the organized look of something organic? See how its patterned, with regularly repeated lines of structure? The elegant curve
from tip to tip?), and then invite him to enlarge his mind and create
a space of possibility where the marks in the rock could mean something. Rather than seeing is believing, here was a case where one
must at least believe in the possibility of something before one could
see it. As for the other man, who saw nothing, it is of course possible
that there was nothing to see. Certainly that is what he saw, nothing. But it may have been that the sources of authority in his life
made it difficult to see those marks as the signs of past life.
The scene at Starved Rock illustrates the interplay of authority
and reason in science. One element of Chriss conversion turned
upon the authority he granted me as someone more knowledgeable
in geology. Accounts of science commonly emphasize that authority
plays no role in its deliberations; science distinguishes itself from
other modes of life (e.g., religion) by relying exclusively upon evidential reasoning. But it turns out that authority plays a crucial role in
115
7
BEING AND GEOLOGIC TIME:
THE MEETING OF METAPHYSICS
AND POLITICS
What might geology look like in a postmodern era? In the modern era, geology was predominantly an economic discipline, supplying the raw materials needed for economic development. In the
future, the central role of the Earth sciences should be political, helping to define the limits that individuals and communities must live
within in order to flourish. These limitsmutable, and as motivated
by aesthetics and metaphysics as by science and economicswill be
best expressed as narratives that provide citizens with environmental contexts with which to script their lives. Embracing its nature as
an explicitly narrative science, geology would not only create scientific knowledge, but also (with the help of humanists) place it into
contexts that foster discussions about the common good.
I.
The most thought-provoking thing about this thoughtprovoking time is that were still not thinking.
Martin Heidegger
Heideggers comment is unfair, of course. There has never been
such an age of thinking. True, much of our thought now consists of
calculating and measuring, planning and orderingtypes of reasoning that for Heidegger do not rise to the level of Denken. But we also
employ significant numbers of people to study such topics as ancient
philosophy, medieval theology, and queer theory. What, then, is
117
118
Geo-Logic
119
120
Geo-Logic
Second, science and technology today live under the sign of infinity. Both have become infinite research projects, with no goal
short of total understanding and complete control. The questions
Do we know enough? and Is our power sufficient? have no meaning. Answering them would require an assumption other than the
formal one of increasing our comprehension and power. But this is
exactly what we lack. The technological imperative has become the
demand for ever greater augmentation of understanding and power.
In Forbidden Knowledge, Roger Shattuck notes how unusual this attitude is from a historical perspective: it has been a truism across
cultures that wisdom consists in recognizing limits, and that overreaching leads to disaster.2
It is thus doubly ironic that this ever greater understanding and
power is not our understanding and power: individuals today control
little and comprehend less of the technologies that influence their
lives. Technology confronts us as a world of anonymous and implacable systems that develop according to a logic of their own:
[D]igital technology is the solvent leaching the glue out of
old, much cherished social, political and business structures. . . . We are performing a great unwitting experiment
that is changing our social structures, our governmental
structures and our business structures. Everything, absolutely everything is up for grabs and nothings going to
make any sense at all for a couple of decades, so we may as
well sit back and enjoy the ride.3
Sit back and enjoy the ride? It is remarkable that we can be so sanguine about our great unwitting experiment. But few object to
incessant technological and cultural innovation. Evidently, the overwhelming majority of our fellow citizens view this experiment as an
inherently benign process.4
These two pointsour abandoning of the belief in inherent limits, and our tremendous and continually increasing technological
powerare essentially one and the same. Technology can become
autonomous only when we lose our sense of limits, our sense of the
natural. Our public conversations no longer focus on the question of
the nature of the good life. Seeing this question as essentially unanswerable, we have privatized the question of the good, leaving each
to define the good life in terms of his or her own chosen, idiosyncratic
pleasures. But while this postmodern condition strikes some as an
unalloyed good, it does raise a question: if we embrace logos without
121
telos, order without a pregiven end, then how do we choose the goals
that we as individuals and communities should pursue? By choosing to do whatever we want seems the obvious answer. But the
questions logic leads in another direction. While our desires are
granted a modicum of respect (Well, if thats what you want . . .),
they carry no real weight. They are simply a set of brute facts, explained by the idiosyncrasies of personalityor by what was once
called sociobiology, now known as evolutionary psychology. Or, on
another reading (which comes to the same thing), our desires are
seen as mere artifacts or cultural constructs. According to this view,
needs are simply expressions of the latest advertising slogans,
themselves understood as expressions of ideology and power. In either case, our desires have become fundamentally arbitraryas
Freud said, polymorphously perverse.
But can we function without a sense of the natural? Is it really
possible to live a life in which we understand our desires as merely a
set of evolutionary codes or consumer preferences? In his parable of
the Madman, Nietzsche is typically taken to be celebrating the
death of the proper. But as he foresaw, the death of Godi.e., the
death of the proper, of limit, and the naturalraises as many questions as opportunities:
The madman jumped into their midst and pierced them with
his eyes. Whither is God? he cried; I will tell you. We have
killed himyou and I. All of us are his murderers. But how
did we do this? How could we drink up the sea? Who gave us
the sponge to wipe away the entire horizon? . . . What festivals of atonement, what sacred games shall we have to
invent? Is not the greatness of this deed too great for us?5
Without a sense of the natural, the self is threatened with incoherence, as we lose the constancy of will to choose and stick to one thing
rather than another. People drift from one role to another, trying on
lifestyles like sets of clothes. People and projects are fascinating,
but are abandoned when they become difficult or inconvenient. After
a series of such star friendships (the phrase is Nietzsches) one
comes to anticipate how the next relationship will end. The lack of
any commitment beyond that of self-pleasure acts as an acid that
eats away at the relationship from the very moment that it forms.
Since even play requires tenacity, every relationship takes on an
amorphous and incomplete quality as all parties watch for the first
sign of vacillation.6
122
Geo-Logic
II.
Geology has an ambivalent cultural image. Equipped with a
rock hammer or manning a drilling rig, the geologist exemplifies
the view of the Earth as resource. Geology not only provides the materials to keep the machines running, but also supplies the materials with which we build the machines. The traditional character of
the geologist, however, also embodies a Rousseauistic ideal. For the
search for energy or the study of ecosystems implies a life spent outdoors, tramping the wilderness, beyond the bounds of civilization.
Indeed, this latter image is in ascendance today, precisely when the
field geologist is becoming an anachronism within his own discipline. Popular culture (e.g., the movie Jurassic Park) portrays the
geologist as a temporal Odysseus or Captain Cook, charting new
worlds and discovering mythic creatures across time rather than
space.
The Earth lies at the root of all economic activity. This is clear
enough when we are considering petroleum, copper, or coal; but its
less obvious that corn is geologic in origin. Soils are formed through
geologic processes over geologic periods of time: in the High Plains,
some of the best soils in the planet consist of loess deposits, the products of Pleistocene glaciers. Loess consists of silt layers, sometimes
tens of feet thick, in areas that once bordered continental glaciers. In
123
the Pleistocene, glaciers ground the rock underneath into tiny particles known as rock flour. The glaciers melting edge then released
large amounts of silt, which was carried by the wind in huge dust
storms that deposited the silt in downwind areas. Today 25 percent of
the topsoil of the High Plains is seriously degraded, with large
amounts having washed down to the Gulf of Mexico in the 125 years
since European settlementa permanent and irreplaceable loss,
from the perspective of human interests. Moreover, the groundwater
used to irrigate these crops is also Pleistocene in origin, fossil water
drawn from the Ogallala aquifer, the legacy of glaciers melting eighteen thousand years ago. It is estimated that at current rates of
drawdown the Ogallala aquifer will last another thirty to fifty years.8
But if geology is rooted in economics, it is also poetic and metaphysical in nature. As I tried to capture in earlier chapters, the historical geologists work is unusually dependent upon the capacity to
dream. Of course, every human endeavor, and certainly every science, requires imagination and creativity. But geology embodies this
point in a singular way. It is too often forgotten that, when we look
at re-creations of dinosaurs and the environments they inhabited,
these rich interpretations are based upon an extended series of inferences drawn from fragments of crushed bone pulled from twisted
and fractured strata.
This process of dreaming the outcrop itself depends upon a type
of ontological disruption, for the discipline of geology, in its development from the field of mineralogy, displaced our human-scaled sense
of time. James Huttons discovery of geologic time (1788)a length
of time so expansive that he could imagine no vestige of a beginning, no prospect of an endrepresents much more than an arithmetic fact. To open ourselves to the possibility of making sense of an
outcrop requires a transformation in ones lived sense of time, and
thus of reality. As John McPhee has shown in a series of books on geology and geologists, walking the Earth and thinking in terms of
deep time profoundly affects the way one experiences the world.
What was taken as real becomes ephemeral, while the inconsequential becomes freighted with significance. Viewed geologically, building condominiums on a beachfront is akin to setting up lodging on
an iceberg; the very term beachfront property becomes an oxymoron. And commonplace acts such as tossing away a Styrofoam
container that briefly held a burger become absurd and even obscene: we discard after a moments convenience a part of the worlds
shrinking petroleum inheritance that came down to us through a
150-million-year-process?9
124
Geo-Logic
125
126
Geo-Logic
III.
The suggestion that the twenty-first century will be the age of
geology rests on the claim that we are entering a period in which
natural limits will be the defining question of culture.
Ecogeologic abundance has been the sine qua non of the modern
era. It is impossible to separate the story of the rise of Homo technologicus from the effects of Columbuss discovery of the New World. At
that time, immigrants were presented with what was, by all practical
measures, an infinity of metals, timber, water, fish, farmland, and
space. The effects of such abundance were pervasive: ecogeologic
abundance encouraged a laissez-faire or libertarian attitude not only
127
128
Geo-Logic
129
130
Geo-Logic
who make the basic decisions that shape our futuresdo not
often pay much attention to such arguments. If one is to
argue constructively with the people who incarnate our cultural and political norms, one must argue the case in their
own terms. This requires that one adopt a fundamentally
empirical and scientific or agnostic approach, putting aside
the question of values, at least temporarily. . . .17
131
132
Geo-Logic
and meaning rather than fact. But while raising the indispensable
question of how sanely we have treated the Earth, Roszak overstates
the degree of uncertainty surrounding the scientific assessment of
environmental issues. There is today a fair degree of consensus concerning a number of environmental issues, from global climate
change to the future of recoverable oil reserves. Roszak seems to assume that science can only inform public policy decisions through its
predictive certainty. Missing from his account of science is Aristotles
sense of phronesis or practical wisdom. Phronesis is essentially a conservative approach to questions of public concern, a conservatism
rooted in recognizing the fragility of community and the irreversibility of the historical process. It identifies our capacity to reason about
social or political questions that are not susceptible to calculative reason. The ability to deliberateto weigh and consider, to ponder and
reflect and reach a consensus through the give-and-take of conversationwas once understood as the epistemology appropriate to political debate. In ancient Greece, the polis provided the social space for
deliberative dialogue among citizens.
The work of Ophuls contains one element of a larger environmental philosophy, and that of Roszak, another; what is missing is
the marriage between these two perspectives. By melding these two
perspectives, we may gain a realistic understanding of the type of
geologic scarcity that we will face. Both the Malthusians and Cornucopians have read scarcity along modernist lines, as indicating the
physical absence of a resource. Ecogeologic scarcity was a pure
given, beyond human interpretation, and thus beyond the boundaries of value. But as Roszak suggests, the scarcity we will face will
be as much a psychological and spiritual phenomenon as a physical
one. As we experience the stresses (psychological, aesthetic, theological) of too many people, too much congestion, and too many demands on our time, our experiential sense of scarcity will play as
large a part in our political debates as material scarcity.
Consider the case of Arches National Park in Utah. In 1989, the
National Park Service established the VERP (Visitor Experience and
Resource Protection) program at Arches. The goal of VERP was to
identify the point at which the visitors experience and the parks natural resources were unduly affected by the presence of too many people. As part of this program, the park asked visitors to look at a series
of computer-generated pictures of the trail running out to Delicate
Arch. The Park Service used this data for subsequent park management plans. For instance, it redesigned (and shrank) the Delicate
Arch trailhead parking lot to limit the number of hikers to the site. In
133
its account of this program, the Park Service emphasizes issues such
as the carrying capacity of the land and how trail overuse can damage the vegetation and the soil along the shoulders of park roads.24
Tellingly, while the importance of visitor experience is noted, the
Park Service does not analyze the term, and certainly doesnt discuss
the aesthetic and theological motivations that motivate many of the
Parks visitors. Once again, aesthetic or theological concerns have
been translated into the language of science or economics.
Geologic scarcity must be understood in a postmodern fashion.
Scarcity and limit are simultaneously natural and cultural concepts,
marking the interplay of physical limitsalways uncertain, and
subject to change through new discoveries and technological advanceand a complex range of cultural limits involving economics,
ethics (questions of justice), aesthetics (quality-of-life issues), and
theology (a sense of the sacred). As I have noted earlier, the interdisciplinary nature of environmental issues has already affected the
discipline of geology. It has become a commonplace within the geoscience community to replace the term geology with Earth science or Earth systems science. These new terms were coined to
express the recognition that nature is an integrated whole that we
must approach through a combined examination of the atmosphere,
hydrosphere, lithosphere, and biosphere. Understanding issues such
as global warming or the loss of biodiversity requires the combined
efforts of atmospheric physicists, oceanographers, paleoclimatologists, and biologists.
But the redefinition of geology has paused before the next and,
in my opinion, inevitable step. In holding to the older term geology,
I have tried to emphasize that we must see limit as simultaneously
scientific, economic, political, aesthetic, and theological in nature.
The original sense of geology emphasizes this point. A truly integrated Geo-logos would recognize that we must treat these various
perspectives on the Earth as complementary rather than opposed. In
brief, the Earth sciences must begin to integrate the humanistic and
political as well as the scientific aspects of their discipline. But how,
practically, are we going to accomplish this?
IV.
The political expression of limit is authority. Authoritydefined
as the legitimate exercise of power over othersis nearly an
anachronism in our culture, a victim of the democratic and scientis-
134
Geo-Logic
tic spirit of the age. Nothing characterizes modernity better than scientism, the belief that the scientific method defines the realm of
truth, and that traditional ways of knowing (e.g., philosophy, religion, art) are chimerical. Our cultures acceptance of scientism has
made suspect anything other than scientific authority, and libertarianism the default position on matters beyond the bounds of science.
Since it is impossible to reason about claims made in ethics, politics,
aesthetics, or theology, authority in these fields is inherently illegitimate. The only reasonable political attitude is that everyone should
be as free from control as is humanly possible.
For all their differences, the political left and right today share
a root libertarian impulse. The difference is that each applies libertarianism to a different arena of contemporary life. A mark of the libertarian positions success is that each side wins when it argues from
libertarian grounds: the right in terms of economics, the left in cultural matters. The demand for less control has been successful in
both economics and personal morality. Questions concerning the nature of the good life have become privatizeda result rooted in
Descartess rejection of the Aristotelian model of knowing, in which
the intellectual virtues include phronesis and nous (intuitive reason)
as well as epistem (scientific knowledge).25
The question facing us is whether libertarianism remains tenable
in an age of geologic scarcity. I believe that it does not. We must relegitimize moral limits and political authority in order to contend with
the challenges we face. One step toward invigorating limit and authority within our culture lies in moderately reconfiguring the role of
the public scientist. A restructured (or postmodernist, in Borgmanns
sense of the term) discipline of the Earth sciences offers the means to
revitalize moral limit and political authority. It may help to bring the
reign of Homo technologicus to a close. To explain this claim, I offer an
account of the U.S. Geological Survey, the nations oldest Earth science agency. In terms of the federal government, the USGS is a relatively small organization, with ten thousand employees and a 850
million dollar annual budget (by comparison, NASAs 2002 research
and development budget was almost ten billion). Nonetheless, as I
will show in the next chapter, the agencys history highlights the political and philosophic dimensions of Earth science information and
perspectives, and stands as a token of the possibilities inherent within
public or political science.
8
SCIENCE AND THE PUBLIC SELF
135
136
Geo-Logic
necessarily relevant to anyone. These agencies are coming to acknowledge two distinct responsibilities: to produce impartial, highquality scientific information, and to place that information within
the variety of societal contexts helpful to policy makers, private
industry, and citizens groups.
Recognizing this dual charge, however, has given birth to a
whole series of questions. The changing demands made upon the
GSC and the USGS offer yet another example of the ontological disruption affecting both intellectual culture and society at large. Is it
proper for scientists to engage in political activities? Wont such efforts undermine the uniquely objective status of scientific information? What is the role of public science agencies in negotiating the
boundaries between science and society? And, what do we make of
attempts such as the virtual display at Science World? Do they bring
us closer to the natural world, or are they a distraction, replacing
the environment with a virtual world so seductive that it relieves us
of the need to go outside at all?
This mix of scientific, political, and metaphysical concerns have
become deeply intertwined in public debates over public science. The
questions raised above are the subject of sustainedand sometimes
rancorousdebates within the GSC and the USGS, as these agencies struggle to define the proper range of public science. But before
turning to these issues, let us review the background of this disruption in categories.
I.
In 1995, the 104th Congress abolished the Bureau of Mines, a
$140 million federal science agency concerned with environmental
geology and mine safety. In the same session, Congress came within
a few votes of eliminating the U.S. Geological Survey. The USGS
conducts research on a wide range of topics. It analyzes earthquakes, provides mineral and energy assessment, water monitoring, and biological surveys, and identifies natural hazards. While
the Survey survived the vote in Congress, it was not without cost.
In the reorganization that followed, the Geologic Division of the
USGS lost 525 jobs.2
On several grounds, congressional critics questioned the need
for these agencies. First, they were concerned with the relevance of
the scientific research. How did studies in paleontology, hydrology,
or deep mantle processes serve the needs of the nation? Second was
137
138
Geo-Logic
to funding fundamental scientific research.4 In all of these discussions, critics questioned the legitimacy of the governments being
involved in the production of knowledge. The 1995 congressional debates surrounding the BLM and the USGS resurrected these
ghosts. The question now was whether such research should be privatized, either by turning the research over to academics and private industry, or by funding universities to conduct the research
through such agencies as the National Science Foundation and the
National Institutes of Health.
The question of the relation between knowledge, government,
and democracy has been a perennial one within American culture.
In a political culture born of the Enlightenments rejection of traditional claims to authority based in heredity, military power, or religion, the federal government was bound to be drawn into the
production of knowledge. In Enlightenment cultures, knowledge has
been the fundamental way to legitimate decision-making. Of course,
populist proponents of pure democratic self-expression challenged
the claim that political legitimacy should be based in knowledge or
expertise. But others argued that the democratic expression of opinion is meaningless and even dangerous without the constraints of
education. Indeed, this latter point provided the initial justification
for compulsory education (rather than the economic benefits of
schooling). An educated electorate was understood to be crucial to a
properly functioning democracy.
In a curious case of unintended consequences, the antiauthoritarian attitude typical of American democracy served to strengthen
the authority of (especially scientific) knowledge. The Founding Fathers sought much more than a simple substitution of a president
for a king; American government was founded upon a conservative
political philosophy that distrusted authority. American institutions
were designed to impede politicians ability to make decisions.5 This
philosophy underlies the distribution of power across three branches
of government and between local, state, and federal powers, and the
existence of devices like short terms of office for members of the U.S.
House of Representatives. Even the design of the nations capital expressed a political point: in order to de-emphasize the presidencys
power, the National Mall culminates in the Capitol rather than in
the presidents home. The net result has been that an inexperienced
political class has often found itself depending on the more permanent class of intellectuals (e.g., university presidents, scientific committees such as the National Academy of Science, and think tanks)
for the ideas underlying governmental policies.
139
140
Geo-Logic
II.
The tension noted earlier between two visions of geologyas exclusively economic in nature, or as including political as well as aesthetic and theological dimensionsruns through the history of the
U.S. Geological Survey. Founded in 1879, the USGS grew out of the
141
military and civilian land surveys that mapped the vast lands of the
West. The original charter of the USGS called for the classification
of the public lands, and examination of the geological structure, mineral resources, and products of the national domain.6 Clarence
King, the USGSs first director, personified the economic interpretation of this mission. Early Survey work centered on studying the origin of ore deposits and mapping the mineral districts in Colorado
(Leadville) and Nevada (the Comstock). King, however, left office
after only eighteen months, presenting the second director, John
Wesley Powell, with the opportunity to redirect the USGS toward a
more politically and even philosophically oriented role in society.
The range of Powells interests is reflected by the fact that, during
and after his thirteen-year tenure at the USGS, he also directed the
U.S. Bureau of Ethnology. As its director, Powell guided the creation
of the bureaus two-volume Handbook of American Indians, the
groundbreaking summary of Amerindian cultures published shortly
after his death.7
In contrast to King, Powell saw geology lying at the intersection
of nature and culture, at a site he called the geosocial. In his view,
geological and hydrological questions naturally flowed into issues of
land use policy, anthropology, and philosophy. The natural and cultural worlds were discrete, but continually intersected with one another. Moreover, Powell believed that civil servants can inform public
decision-making and provide guidance to democratic decision-making. He espoused a strong model of governance: politicians and civil
servants should not merely reflect community values, but should
rather take a leadership role in the forming of public policy. Michael
Sandel has called this the republican model of governance; the voters
role is to select the candidate whose outlook is most consistent with
their own, and then allow him or her to govern. Voters retain ultimate control, for at terms end they may choose to remove the officeholder. Sandel contrasts this with the representative model of rule, in
which the elected official mirrors the voters views, no matter how inconstant, and the civil servant functions simply as a servant, following the views of the body politic rather than being in dynamic
interaction with them.8 It is, of course, the representative model that
is exemplified by the poll-driven politics of current political life.
Powells notion of the geosocial is clearly present in his 1878 Report of the Lands of the Arid Region. Wateror the lack of itis the
central fact of Western life, destined to affect the regions style of
human settlement. The new culture of the West begins at the onehundredth meridian, the line of longitude running through western
142
Geo-Logic
North Dakota and South Dakota and down through Kansas, Oklahoma, and Texas that marks the isohyetal line of twenty inches of
annual rainfall, the minimum amount needed for unirrigated crops.9
West of this line, farming and settlement depend upon streams,
groundwater, and technology.
Powell saw the USGS as helping to create a drylands democracy that configured itself to the conditions on Americas arid lands.
In this spirit, he was the inspiration behind the 1888 federal statute
that mandated the completion of an irrigation survey of all public
lands in the arid regions before they were opened to public settlement. Powells irrigation survey would identify the water resources
throughout the West. Local, state, and federal governments would
then use this information for the rational design of communities.
While Powell had a strong utilitarian streak, believing that natural
resources should serve the peoples needs, gathering and using this
information was more than simply a point of Taylorist efficiency.
Scarce resources invariably invited monopolies to corner markets. If
there was not enough rain for crops to grow, then whoever controlled
the water sources controlled the entire region. Powells goal was to
place the results of the irrigation survey in the public domain, available to all, thereby encouraging political discussion and rational
planning. His point of view is encapsulated by his insistence that
state boundaries should follow the natural boundaries of watersheds, rather than the abstract lines of a Cartesian grid laid out on
a map in Washington, D.C.
Enacted by Congress in 1888, Powells irrigation survey soon
ran into stiff political opposition. In 1890, the law was repealed by a
combination of Western money interests, advocates of small government, and the eras general land-rush mentality. In 1891, and again
in 1892, the Surveys funding was slashed as a sign of congressional
displeasure. Powells own salary was cut as well. Powell resigned,
and the Survey retreated, reaffirming its role as public servant, and
returning to a fundamentally economic understanding of its mission.
Within the Survey, Powell was seen as having nearly destroyed the
organization by willfully disobeying the peoples representatives
rather than seen as having been engaged in a legitimate and noble
(if ill-fated) political exercise.10
The upshot of this controversy was to short-circuit public debate about the unique societal position of agencies such as the
USGS. In addition to his willfulnessfor Powell was not as politic
with senators as he might have beenPowells failure was ascribed
to his attempt to direct the Survey toward investigations that were
143
too theoretical in nature and better suited to universities. The Surveys third director, Charles Walcott, is seen as having properly reoriented the Surveys work toward the nations practical needs. But
this miscasts the debate. Powell was not primarily interested in
pursuing theoretical science. Rather, he wanted to create a federal
Earth science agency that functioned as something more than a
public lackey. Powells USGS sought to be the sensing organ of the
body politic, but it would not stop there. The USGS was to be an
advocate for the public good.
Is such a vision relevant today? In an era characterized by the
belief in rampant subjectivism on questions of value, and dazzled by
claims of difference (political, cultural, and sexual), an appeal to
the notion of a common good can seem anachronistic and naveor
authoritarian. The USGSs role is further circumscribed by longstanding philosophical commitments that see science alone as providing objective knowledge. But these objections miss the point. The
idea of a public life without the idea of a common good itself depends
on the effective infinity of natural resourcesa situation now coming to an end. Under conditions of natural limitthe parameters of
which the discipline of geology will describe, in rough outlinewe
need a rough consensus on a wide range of societal issues. Given
these conditions, few people will embrace the utter relativity of ethical judgments. Indeed, it is often those within the social constructivist camp who clamor most insistently for environmental justice.
The USGS experienced steady growth throughout the early and
mid twentieth century, greatly benefiting from expanded public
funding for science after World War II. But the increase in funding
did not lead to a more nuanced sense of the complex relationship between science and politics. Moreover, talk of natural limits was at
low ebb. The environmental movement lay in the future. Survey
work came to be characterized by a Lone Ranger mentality, in which
a Survey scientist chose a topic of scientific research according to his
or her own interests. Isolation from the political realm and its controversies was seen as a sign of the integrity of Survey science, a
token of its lack of an agenda and thus a marker of its objectivity.
By the mid-1980s, however, the Survey budgets had flattened,
and the USGS found itself squeezed by a shift in social tectonics.
Two features had changed. First was the fact that the Surveys original missionmapping and identifying the nations natural endowmentwas largely complete. New discoveries would be made, and
maps would need revising, but the great era of geologic discovery (at
least in the United States) was over.11 Second, geology had become
144
Geo-Logic
III.
More than any other figure in contemporary culture, the scientist functions as the arbiter of truth. The debate over global climate
change is shaped by the conclusions reached by the U.S. Global
Change Research Program, just as the data informing the acid mine
drainage controversy in the San Juans has been generated by the
U.S. Geological Survey. There are, of course, experts in many other
professions, such as law and the military, but even these fields are
becoming ever more dependent upon science. The explosive growth
of scientific knowledge constantly spawns new experts and domains
of knowledge. At the same time, this flood of facts makes it progressively more difficult to gain a synoptic understanding of a problem.
The growth of knowledge thus stymies democratic decision-making
as much as it promotes it.
In 2002, the U.S. federal government spent more than 40 billion
dollars on non-defense-related scientific research30 percent of all
145
146
Geo-Logic
147
148
Geo-Logic
debates, in which a variety of other values will come into play. For
instance, the community might decide to preserve historic buildings
that sit in the path of the lahar, in full knowledge of the likely consequences. But the sense of selfhood described here does allow us to
understand advocacy as something other than simply the expression
of a personal opinion. It also suggests that such advocacy is, at least
at times, intrinsic to the public scientists work.
In such cases, the public scientists responsibilities come to resemble those outlined in the codes of ethics of professionals such as
engineers. Engineering codes of ethics emphasize that the engineer
has a fundamental ethical responsibility to the public that at times
supercedes their obligations to their client. It is telling that scientists have been slow to be included within the ranks of professionals
such as engineering, the clergy, the military, lawyers, academics,
and physicians. We do not need to search far to find the reason for
this. The scientific community has sought to avoid the political or
ethical commitments that are implied by the notion of the professional. The concepts of professional responsibilities and professional
ethics are based upon the distinction of a public from a private self
a distinction whose time has come for the scientific community.
But to accomplish this will require that we revive a more developed notion of the public or political realm and limit the language of
economics that has dominated our understanding of the relations
between science and society. In recent years, public science agencies
have come to recognize the need to address the question of societal
relevance. But again, in too many cases this point has been expressed in the language of economics. By speaking of politicians and
the public as customers, public scientists have tried to preserve a
type of objectivityor more precisely, subjectivity, in that the public
scientist is understood as simply serving the needs of his or her
clients. Thus one finds that the USGS Refocused Strategic Plan for
19972005 emphasizes the USGSs responsibility to serve its customers.15 But the relationship between public science and society is
political, not economic. In fact, only the political nature of this relationshipthe search for a common goodcan save agencies such as
the USGS from being eliminated, and their work being farmed out to
private concerns.
The public realm is more than a site of electioneering and special interests; it is also the place where we can express ourselves in
ways that are impossible through the private pleasures of sentiment
or consumerism. But realizing ourselves in this way entails that we
reclaim the special dimension of the self exemplified by government
149
IV.
Following the political and financial shocks of the 1990s, it has
become clear that the very existence of public science agencies depends in part upon their skills at being boundary organizations.
Boundary organizations serve as buffers and mediators between
contrasting interests, translating and interpreting information, values, and perspectives between groups that are often at odds with one
another.16 In the case of the U.S. Geological Survey and the Geological Survey of Canda, these agencies occupy the boundary between
society and the environmentPowells realm of the geosocial. Indeed, it has even been possible that today these organizations should
give as much attention to their responsibilities as boundary organizations as they do to the production of scientific knowledge. Placing
Earth science information within meaningful contexts to help us live
in a more environmentally benign manner, and learning to treat
conversations with the public as dialogues rather than monologues,
are two means through which public science can be translated into
forms people can use.
Such claims still lie at the margins of policy debates within public science agencies. But even if they were generally accepted, we
would be left with the question of skillful meanshow to effectively navigate the boundary between science and society. Recently
within the USGS, efforts at linking science to society have focused
on the concept of decision support.17 The term is a slippery one, and
appears in a variety of contexts. Broadly speaking, decision support
consists of attempts at managing and disseminating information.
Within the field of knowledge management, decision support involves everything from policy to personnel skills to analyzing interactions with the public. Within the artificial intelligence community,
decision support focuses on creating expert systems, identifying
ways to capture and represent knowledge within a particular domain in order to simulate expertise. Finally, from a software perspective, decision support creates tools that help experts (or in some
cases, replace them), through geographical information systems
(GIS) and various types of statistical tools.18
150
Geo-Logic
In its attempts to better serve the public, the USGS is increasingly relying on decision support systems, information tools that use
algorithms to produce well-defined answers to complex problems.
For instance, the USGS Moist Soil Management Advisor is a software program that helps wildlife refuge managers manage wetlands
by calculating what manipulations will control vegetation or salinity
problems, and how to properly time floods. Decision support relates
science to society primarily by bringing computer technology to bear
upon a problem. In the words of one U.S. government publication,
As the decision making process becomes more complex, there will
be increasing demands for technology to help decision makers explore and evaluate these issues.19 In another, the author asks us to
imagine county officials, landowners, and citizen groups coming
together to discuss a proposed land use development project:
Using the Internet, the group is able to access much of the
needed data to combine with information it has acquired itself . . . they are also able to access the numerical simulation
models needed to conduct their analysis, and the visualization software required to display the results.20
The author goes on to imagine a resource map projected on the
screen at the front of the assembly or as a holographic image in the
center of the room. . . . Next, computer model simulations are run
depicting potential flood scenarios. . . . A consensus begins to emerge
on a land use plan. In short, the community has built and used a
decision support system (DSS) on the fly.21
The ruling assumption of such efforts is that decision making
is primarily a technical process rather than a political and dialogical one. The bias here is not so much intellectual as informational:
it overestimates the usefulness of information in the decision-making process. But rather than more information, or ever more elaborate displays, what people often need most is a chance to speak and
the time to mull things over. Coming to understand anothers perspective on an issue is often a matter of sympathy rather than
technology. In fairness, the decision support literature sometimes
recognizes the fact that, in addition to technology, the public also
needs a better understanding of science. But there is little appreciation of the fact that decision support is at its heart a political
process rather than a technical one; or, for that matter, that the
process of education needs to involve the scientist as much as
the public.
151
152
Geo-Logic
and institutional changes. One part of the public scientists job will
continue its traditional roleto research areas that are either outside the nexus of economics, or are too charged with social significance to be privatized. But a sizable partin principle, halfof the
public scientists responsibilities should be devoted to public communication and dialogue. One corollary of this is that science education must move in two directionsscientists learning about
public values as much as informing society about the results of science. This will require that public Earth science agencies integrate
their research with skills that are native to the humanities. To fulfill their public charge, public agencies will need to meld environmental justice, epistemology, metaphysics and theology, the
perspective of history, and the narrativizing of knowledge with their
scientific products.
We inhabit a moral universe; we make sense of experience in
terms of intentions, conflicts, and goals. Individuals and cultures
cast the events of their lives into a narrative structure in order to
understand who they are, to uncover how they came to be the way
they are, and to anticipate where they might be going. In everyday
life, people depend upon a narrative logic rather than scientific rationality to make sense of their lives. The vast majority of cultural
communicationhow to fulfill ones role as friend, parent, or sibling,
and what counts as laudable behavior or a worthwhile lifehas always been expressed through myths and stories. These narratives of
personal or societal goals give meaning to the struggle for personal
excellence or social justice. These stories also allow us to evaluate
the actions of ourselves and others.
We make sense of experience through the logical structure of a
narrative. We understand our current situation in terms of our past
and possible futures. Narrative logic provides the context of understanding that people need to make sense of facts. When summarizing
the findings on global climate change, rather than simply providing a
set of contextless numbers (e.g., the prediction of a 1.55 increase in
mean global temperature by the year 2100), the scientist can describe
a series of possible scenarios or plotlines: more severe storms in the
Atlantic, droughts in Colorado, increased crop yields in Siberia, or
saltwater intrusion along the coast of Louisiana. By describing these
as possible scenarios, the scientist acknowledges his or her lack of
certainty. But by placing the results of scientific work within a narrative framework, the scientist helps the community grasp the possible implications of its decisions. A narrative can help people make the
connection between (for instance) the use of private rather than pub-
153
9
CONCLUSION
155
156
Geo-Logic
as a cobble of stone laid on steep slick rock to make a trail for horses
in the mountains. For Snyder, it also describes the way thoughts
and things fit together: thinking as a process of placing well-dressed
stone, and the universe a mosaic too neat to be accidental and too
odd to ever be completely comprehended.
Geo-Logic has sought to mark out a common space for the Earth
sciences and philosophy. It has framed a mosaic of science, poetry,
epistemology, personal experience, metaphysical reflection, and political engagement. Geology has been read as simultaneously scientific and humanistic in naturethe fitted stones of geoscience,
geopoetry, geopolitics, and geometaphysics. Fieldwork has been described as a meditative sciencea conceptual and toolish riprap
constructed from humanistic arts and scientific procedures. Public
science agencies have been placed within a border region between
science and society, properly responsive to and guiding a patchwork
of intersecting groups, perspectives, and interests. Addressing these
varied publics requires rhetorical nuance and narrative skill as well
as logical acumen. Altogether, the sciences and the humanities have
been portrayed as the joint links between society and nature, connecting much more than two things, since neither society nor nature
is a single entity.
Scott McLean, Eldridge Moores, and David Robertson argue
that scientific advances do not truly become the possession of a culture until these discoveries are expressed through that cultures art
and poetry.1 They interpret Snyder as serving a role for 20th century
geology similar to John Donnes for 17th century astronomy. Just as
Donne expressed the existential consequences of the Copernican
revolution, Snyder helps us understand the implications of recent
revolutions in our understanding of the Earth.2 Snyders poems render deep time into our own time, finding the pulse of shifting plates
within rigid strata warped by overwhelming pressures. Snyder gives
words to the meanings implicit within limestone and gneiss, where
space is shown to be the inscription of time upon reality:
ten million years ago an ocean floor
glides like a snake beneath the continent crunching up
old seabed till its high as alps.3
But there are also other ways to explore the new space that geology inhabits. One example is Real World Experiments, a program launched in the spring of 2002 at the University of Bielefeld in
Germany. Directed by Matthias Gros and Holger Hoffmann-Riem at
Conclusion
157
Bielefelds Institute for Science and Technology Studies (IWT), realworld experiments are attempts to solve environmental problems
under uncontrolled or field conditions. Experiment is understood
here as a process of iterative self-experimentation involving both nature and societyan approach that is in stark contrast to the isolated terms of the laboratory experiment. Real World Experiments
is focusing on a set of case studies of human intervention in ecological systems, including dune restoration, landscape design, lake
restoration, and waste management. The overall aim of the program
is to develop intellectual tools for the planning and implementation
of scientifically reliable and socially robust approaches of environmental design4 (GL:CH9).
A second, similar effort underway is New Directions in the
Earth Sciences and the Humanities. New Directions was launched
in the spring of 2001 with an initial grant from the Colorado School
of Mines. It has subsequently received support from the NSF, NASA,
the USGS, the EPA, the National Endowment for the Humanities,
the National Center for Atmospheric Research, and the Geological
Survey of Canada, as well as a consortium of universities (numbering eleven to date). The work of New Directions turns on three questions: What can the humanities contribute to environmental
solutions? How can we make scientific information more pertinent to
society? And, what is the future of knowledge? (GL:CH9).
In addition to a number of workshops and conferences, New Directions has provided initial funding for seven interdisciplinary case
studies. These case studies are run by teams consisting of at least one
scientist and one humanist. For instance, in the project Humanizing
Environmental Research on the South Carolina Coast, a marine biologist and a philosopher work with students to link scientific data to
the needs of local communities. In Ecology and Cultural History of
the Neva River, St. Petersburg, Russia, experts in Russian literature, landscape architecture, and geology examine the relation between the Neva Rivers ecological problems and its iconic status in
Russian history and literature. The upshot of these efforts will include improving the usefulness of public science, creating new venues
for citizen and stakeholder participation in environmental decision
making, gaining greater understanding in how to conduct interdisciplinary research and dialogue, and how to more richly express the
human dimensions of our relationship with the environment.5
Another attempt at integrating the sciences and the humanitiesalso concerned with the problem of acid mine drainageis
AMD&ART. Drainage from abandoned coal mines is a widespread
158
Geo-Logic
environmental problem in Pennsylvania and Appalachia, with significant regional economic and social impacts. AMD&ART is working to amend the negative attitudes toward and within this region
through the creation of large-scale public places that address the
problems of acid drainage from scientific and artistic points of view.
In existence since 1994, AMD&ART combines these different perspectives with the engagement of local communities for the design of
interpretive trails will draw together historical information, the science behind passive AMD treatment, and the newly healed ecosystem that will thrive in the wake of remediation. Working with a
number of partners at three sites in Southwestern Pennsylvania,
AMD&ART is attempting to prove that such as approach can succeed on both the watershed and regional scale6 (GL:CH9).
A final example is worth noting, one that is operating on the
K-12 level. The Flatirons Outdoor Classroom is a project within the
Boulder Valley School District in Boulder, Colorado, that consists of
an interdisciplinary outdoor learning environment combining elements of science, art, social studies, and the humanities. The project
has two parts. Phase 1 (now largely completed) focused on the creation of an integrated outdoor classroom space. Phase 2 proposes the
development of curriculum projects to make full use of this unique
space.
The classroom itself consists of four elements. A riverbed runs
the length of the school building (135 feet), offering a depiction of
the Boulder Creek watershed. At the top, students are able to fill a
600 gallon reservoir with water, and then send a flood down the
channel. Streamflows are used for experiments in hydrology and
sedimentology, as well as for thought experiments in water politics
(e.g., learning about senior/junior water rights and the possible effects of 100 year floods along Boulder Creek). The water is captured
in a large underground cistern, and pumped back up to the reservoir for repeated experiments. Second, a geology exhibit uses samples of local strata to represent the Flatirons and other regional
features of the Rocky Mountains and High Plains. Adjacent to the
rocks, on the side of the building, a large mural is being created
that depicts Colorado across geologic history. Utilizing reproductions of paintings commissioned by the Denver Museum of Nature
and Sciencea partner on the projectteachers will be able to
move back and forth between the representations of ancient Denver
and the rock outcrops, instructing students in the nature of scientific research by juxtaposing the geologic strata to pictures of the
geologic past.
Conclusion
159
NOTES
Preface
1. Information on Global Climate Change and Society can be found at http://
sciencepolicy.colorado.edu/gccs.
2. Earth Matters: The Earth Sciences, Philosophy, and the Claims of Community,
ed. Robert Frodeman, (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall), 2000.
Chapter 1. Introduction
1. Cf. Jrgen Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere,
trans. Thomas Burger. (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1989).
2. Readers will find ambiguities in my use of geologyreferring at times to
lithology, the integrated study of the Earth, and finally to a full-bodied logos of Gaia that
integrates the humanities. I trust that context will be sufficient to distinguish which
meaning is primary. It is also worth noting that my use of Gaia implies no attachment
to Lovelocks Gaia Hypothesis. For Lovelocks views, The Ages of Gaia: A Biography
of our Living Earth (New York: Norton, 1988).
3. On the former point, see Paul Shepard, Nature and Madness (San Francisco:
Sierra Club Books, 1982), and David Abram, The Spell of the Sensuous (New York: Pantheon, 1996).
4.Kai N. Lee, Compass and Gyroscope: Integrating Science and Politics for the
Environment (Washington, D.C.: Island Press, 1993).
5. There is no accepted definition of which disciplines constitute the humanities.
I will use the term to include philosophy, literature, foreign languages, history, theology
or religious studies, art history, and the nonquantitatively oriented parts of the social sciences. Cf. Robert E. Proctor, Defining the Humanities (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1998).
161
162
Notes
6. This assertion will draw fire. And certainly values are debatable: that is the
function of democratic debate. But, to take two simple examples: few would argue with
the claim that open-mindedness is better than dogmatism, or that pluralism is preferable
to bigotry.
7. Stephen J. Pyne, How the Canyon Became Grand (New York: Penguin Books,
1998).
8. Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. James W.
Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1981), p. 2.
9. It is worth noting that our standard for what counts as a competent degree of
expertise is as much a social, political, economic, and technological question as it is an
epistemological one: standards of sufficient expertise change as societys interests
change, more money is invested, and technology advances.
10. Ralph Waldo Emerson, The American Scholar, in Selections from Ralph
Waldo Emerson, ed. Stephen E. Whicher (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1960), p. 70.
11. Zen and the Ways, trans. and ed. Trevor Leggett (Boston: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1978), p. 221.
12. Not a nuclear explosion, but rather a hydrothermal explosion when water
comes in contact with hot nuclear waste, potentially spreading radionuclides throughout
the water table.
13. E.g., Alphonso Lingis, Excesses: Eros and Culture (Albany: SUNY Press,
1984); Abuses (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994), and The Community of
Those Who Have Nothing in Common (Bloomington: University of Indiana Press, 1994).
14. Recent years have seen another dustup around the question of evolution involving mathematicians and physicists versus biologists and paleontologists. Is biology
too difficult for biologists? begins a 1998 book review in Nature written by Per Bok, a
physicist who claims that the mathematics of complexity theory can account for the
mass extinctions found in the fossil record. See Richard Monastersky, Fossils vs. the
Formula, Chronicle of Higher Education, 47, no. 35 (11 May 2001): A16A18.
15. On the emergence of geology out of mineralogy, see Rachel Laudan, From
Mineralogy to Geology: The Foundations of a Science, 16501830 (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1987).
16. One sign of this transitional status is the recent National Academy of Science
report: Committee on Future Roles, Challenges, and Opportunities for the U.S. Geological Survey, Future Roles and Opportunities for the U.S. Geological Survey (Washington, D.C.: National Research Council, 2001).
Notes
163
2. For instance, in Spain in April 1998 a mine tailings pond failed, releasing zinc,
lead, and cadmium along a twenty-mile section of the Guadiamar River. The accident
contaminated the aquifer connected to the Donana wildlife reserve, and destroyed six
thousand hectares of farmland.
3. Cf. Carlos D. Da Rosa and James S., Lyon. Golden Dreams, Poisoned Streams
(Washington, D.C.: Mineral Policy Center, 1997), p. 13. In 1996, the U.S. General Accounting Office assessed the impacts of mining to include five thousand miles of impacted streams, 50 billion tons of mine waste, and fourteen thousand sites in need of
serious remediation.
4. Navigable is here meant in the common, rather than the technical, sense of
the Clean Water Act (see below).
5. For an account of the Summitville site, see Geoffrey S. Plumlee, The Summitville
Mine and its Downstream Effects: An on-line update of Open File Report 95-23. Available
at http://greenwood.cr.usgs.gov/pub/open-file-reports/ofr-95-0023/summit.htm.
6. John Marshall and Zeke Zanoni, Mining the Hard Rock in the San Juans (Silverton, Colo.: Simpler Way Press, 1996), p. 24.
7. See Olga L. Moya and Andrew L. Fono, Federal Environmental Law: The
Users Guide (St. Paul, Minn.: West Publishing, 1997), p. 288.
8. Under the Clean Water Act, navigable is defined as including almost any body
of water (with the exception of groundwater), including potholes, intermittent streams,
dry washes, canals, and wetlands.
9. Moya and Fono. Federal Environmental Law, p. 289; Clean Water Act Section
101, 33 U.S.C. 1251 (1972).
10. In at least some areas (e.g., EPA Region VIII, covering the Rocky Mountains) the
EPA has exercised its authority more subtly over time. Region VIII strives to work with
states on the front-end of rule-makings, rather than just rejecting them months or years later.
11. Animas Status Report, Colorado Center for Environmental Management,
May 1996.
12. Interviews with Chris Hayes, attorney for Sunnyside Gold Corporation, 11
February 1999, and Carol Russell, EPA official, Region VIII, 16 February 1999.
13. Interview with Chris Hayes.
14. These included the possibility that efflorescent salts that formed during mining could lead to the continued production of acidic waters even after flooding, and the
difficulty of completely flooding the mine due to myriad fractures and seasonal variations. Kirk Nordstrom, U.S. Geological Survey, personal communication, 15 April 1999.
15. Interview with Larry Perino, Sunnyside Gold Corporation, 12 April 1999.
16. W. G. Wright, Natural and Mining-Related Sources of Dissolved Minerals
during Low Flow in the Upper Animas River Basin, Southwestern Colorado, USGS
Fact Sheet FS 148-97, October 1997.
164
Notes
Notes
165
166
Notes
24. Robert Elliott, Faking Nature, Inquiry 25, no. 1 (March 1982): 8193. Expanded into Faking Nature: The Ethics of Environmental Restoration (Lanham, Md.:
Rowman and Littlefield, 1997).
25. Many will doubt that it is possible to fully restore an ecosystem or the natural
features of the land. But to argue on these grounds is to make the preservation of nature
dependent upon technological insufficiency. Ifor better said, given the speed of technological advance, whenwe are able to reconstruct ecosystems, this objection becomes irrelevant.
26. Andrew Light observes that a restored landscape might better be compared
to a restored work of art, rather than a faked one. Andrew Light, Ecological Restoration and the Culture of Nature: A Pragmatic Perspective, in Gobster and Hull, Restoring Nature.
27. Paul Ricoeur, The Symbolism of Evil (New York: Harper and Row, 1967), 33.
28. For the former claim, see Al Gore, Earth in the Balance: Ecology and the
Human Spirit (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1993); Theodore Roszak, The Voice of the
Earth (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1992).
29. Mircea Eliade, The Sacred and the Profane, trans. Willard Trask (New York:
Harcourt Brace, 1968), p. 10. Italics in the original.
30. The sacred tree, the sacred stone are not adored as stone or tree; they are worshipped precisely because they are hierophanies, because they show something that is
no longer stone or tree but the sacred, the ganz andere [wholly other]. Ibid., 12. Italics
in the original.
31. Man first reads the sacred on the world, on some elements or aspects of the
world, on the heavens, on the sun and moon, on the waters and vegetation. Ricoeur,
Symbolism of Evil, p. 10.
32. A wilderness, in contrast with those areas where man and his own works
dominate the landscape, is hereby recognized as an area where the earth and its community of life are untrammeled by man, where man himself is a visitor who does not
remain. An area of wilderness is further defined to mean in this Act an area of undeveloped Federal land retaining its primeval character and influence, without permanent improvements or human habitation, which is protected and managed so as to preserve its
natural conditions and which (1) generally appears to have been affected primarily by
the forces of nature, with the imprint of mans work substantially unnoticeable. . . . Public Law 88-577, 88th Congress, S. 4, 3 September 1964.
33. Two recent examples are the 2001 annual meeting of the International Association for Environmental Philosophy, which sponsored a day-long meeting with the title
Nature and the Sacred, and the Lilly Fellows National Research Conference entitled
Ecology, Theology, and Judeo-Christian Environmental Ethics, held at Notre Dame
University on 2124 February 2002.
Notes
167
168
Notes
Structures II: Research Programs. 10. Feyerabends Anarchistic Theory of Science. 11.
Methodical Changes in Method. 12. The Bayesian Approach. 13. The New Experimentalism. 14. Why Should the World Obey Laws? 15. Realism and Antirealism. (Such examples can be multiplied).
14. Steve Fuller has argued along similar lines: see Social Epistemology (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002).
15. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Phenomenology of Perception (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962).
16. These points are further developed in Thomas Raab and Robert Frodeman,
What Is It Like to Be a Geologist? The Phenomenology of Geology and Its Implications, Philosophy and Geography, July 2002.
17. Hubert L. Dreyfus and Stuart E. Dreyfus. Mind over Machine: The Power of
Human Intuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer (New York: Free Press,
1986).
18. Naomi Oreskes. Why Believe a Computer? Models, Measures, and Meaning
in the Natural World, in The Earth Around Us: Maintaining a Livable Planet, ed. Jill
S. Schneiderman (New York: W. H. Freeman, 2000).
19. John Harte, Consider a Spherical Cow: A Course in Environmental Problem
Solving (Los Altos, Calif.: W. Kaufmann, 1985).
20. Cf. Victor R. Baker, Conversing with the Earth: The Geological Approach to
Understanding, in Earth Matters: The Earth Sciences and Contemporary Culture, ed.
Robert Frodeman (Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 2000).
21. Starlink, the creation of AgrEvo, Inc., is a type of corn genetically modified
with a gene from a bacterium that kills worms that eat corn. The EPA, concerned that
Starlink could cause allergic reactions, approved corn for animal feed, but not for human
consumption. AgrEvo signed an agreement that it would oversee the distribution of the
seed so that it would not get mixed with corn for humans. The company claimed it had
a set of procedures to ensure the two would be kept separatee.g., a 660-foot buffer
around fields of Starlink. But Starlink was discovered in taco shells in October 2001
leading to a nationwide recall of this and other products containing the corn. This affected farmers nationwide).
Notes
169
3. See Nelson Goodman, Uniformity and Simplicity, in Uniformity and Simplicity: A Symposium on the Principle of the Uniformity of Nature, ed. C. C. Albritton Jr.
et al., Special Paper (New York: Geological Society of America, 1967), 99; and Richard
Watson, Explanation and Prediction in Geology, Journal of Geology 77 (1969): 488.
Although not concerned with the question of the status of geology as a science, John
Salliss Stone (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994), is a recent exception to
the general neglect of geology by philosophers.
4. R. N. Giere. Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1988); N. Oreskes, K. S. Shrader-Frechette, and K. Belitz, Verification, Validation, and Confirmation of Numerical Models in the Earth Sciences, Science
263 (1994): 64146.
5. Kristen Shrader-Frechette, Burying Uncertainty: Risk and the Case against
Geological Disposal of Nuclear Waste (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993).
6. David B. Kitts, The Structure of Geology (Dallas, Tex.: SMU Press, 1977); W.
V. Engelhardt and J. Zimmermann, Theory of Earth Science (1982; reprint, New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1988).
7. For accounts on the latter, see Alexander Koyre, From the Closed World to the
Infinite Universe (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1957); and Thomas
Kuhn, The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western
Thought (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1957). Deep time was coined by John
McPhee: cf. Basin and Range.
8. Since Hegel, time has been a central issue within Continental philosophy.
One measure of this is Heideggers Being and Time, the twentieth centurys most influential work in Continental philosophy. But despite the prominence of historicist
approaches within contemporary Continental philosophy, geologic time has gotten
no attention. The cultural implications of geologic time are more typical of the history of ideas than of philosophy: see Charles Gillispie, Genesis and Geology (New
York: Harper, 1959); Stephen Toulmin and June Goodfield, The Discovery of Time
(New York: Harper & Row, 1965); and Stephen Goldman, Modern Science and
Western Culture: The Issue of Time, History of European Ideas 3, no. 4 (1982):
371401.
9. I met a traveller from an antique land
Who said: Two vast and trunkless legs of stone
Stand in the desert. Near them, on the sand,
Half sunk, a shattered visage lies, whose frown,
And wrinkled lip, and sneer of cold command,
Tell that its sculptor well those passions read
Which yet survive, stamped on these lifeless things,
The hand that mocked them, and the heart that fed;
And on the pedestal these words appear:
My name is Ozymandias, king of kings:
Look on my works, ye Mighty, and despair!
Nothing beside remains. Round the decay
170
Notes
Of that colossal wreck, boundless and bare
The lone and level sands stretch far away.
Percy Bysshe Shelley (1818)
10. My account here is a gloss upon a story that is quite complex. One might well
reply that today, when the philosophy of science considers physics the paradigmatic science, it has in mind physics qua relativity theory and quantum mechanics rather than
classical mechanics. My point turns upon distinguishing between the state of knowledge
within a given field and the representation of that field outside the realm of specialists.
Possibly the most remarkable thing about the new physics is how little impact it has had
upon our cultures general epistemological views, whether within the intellectual community or the public at large. Physics qua classical mechanics still provides us with our
basic model for understanding the nature of knowledge. Consider, for instance, how introductory physics is taught in American collegestypically beginning with several
weeks on classical mechanics. Quantum mechanics is not taught until the third semester
of physics, well after the vast majority of students have stopped taking physics. While
physicists struggle to integrate quantum physics into an overall picture of reality, classical mechanics still provides the pedagogical model for understanding the nature of science, and indeed of knowledge in general.
11. For the classic statement of this claim, cf. Descartess Rules for the Direction
of the Mind, trans. with an introduction by Laurence J. Lafleur (Indianapolis: Liberal
Arts Press; written in 1627 and first published in 1701).
12. See G. K. Gilbert, The Inculcation of Scientific Method by Example, American Journal of Science, 3d ser., 31 (1886): 28499; and T. C. Chamberlin, The Method
of Multiple Working Hypotheses, Science 15 (1890): 9296.
13. See, for instance, Claude Albritton, The Fabric of Geology (Reading, Mass:
Addison-Wesley, 1963); Stanley A. Schumm, To Interpret the Earth (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991); and Derek V. Ager, The Nature of the Stratigraphical
Record (Chichester, NY: J. Wiley 1993).
14. Stephen Jay Gould, Times Arrow, Times Cycle (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987), and Wonderful Life (New York: W. W. Norton, 1989); Peter D. Ward,
Time Machines: Scientific Explorations in Deep Time (New York: Copernicus, 1998);
Niles Eldredge, Dominion (New York: H. Holt, 1995); and Edward O. Wilson, Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge (New York: Knopf, 1998). Goulds Wonderful Life, pp.
27791, is especially relevant to the points I will be making.
15. Doreen Massey, Space-Time, Science, and the Relationship between Physical
Geography and Human Geography, Institute of British Geography 24 (1999): 264.
16. Schumm, To Intrepret the Earth, p. 5.
17. See Alan Sokal, Transgressing the Boundaries: Toward a Transformative
Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity, Social Text, nos. 46/47 (spring/summer 1996):
21752, also available at http://www.physics.nyu.edu/faculty/sokal/.
What follows summarizes a complex and controversial history. Its complexity derives partly from the fact that we are simultaneously considering discussions by philoso-
Notes
171
phers of science, along with the impact of these discussions upon those within the scientific community. For other accounts see Ian Hacking, Representing and Intervening
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983); John Rajchman and Cornel West, PostAnalytic Philosophy (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985); Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979); Ronald
Giere, Explaining Science (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988); Joseph Rouse,
Knowledge and Power (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1987); and Philip Kitcher, The
Advancement of Science (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993). It should be emphasized that the new view of science that I argue for in terms of Continental philosophy, could also, with some modifications, be made in terms of recent analytic
philosophy of science.
18. Feyerabend was an important early exception to the belief in the scientific
methods unity. Paul Feyerabend, Problems of Empiricism, in Beyond the Edge of Certainty, ed. R. Colodny (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1965).
19. This positivist orientation remains important within analytic philosophy of science. Recent work in the fields of cognitive science, artificial intelligence, and evolutionary epistemology still shares these general assumptions. See H. Kornblith, ed.,
Naturalizing Epistemology (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985); Paul M. Churchland, Matter
and Consciousness (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1988); and Paul Thagard, Conceptual Revolutions (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992).
20. While Kuhns work was the single most important impetus for the changes that
I will discuss, he is a symbolic figure representing a larger movement within the philosophy of science. Other important authors include Toulmin and Goodfield, Hanson,
and Feyerabend.
21. This is a strong interpretation of Kuhns work. Kuhn himself vacillated on
the degree to which the results of science are shaped by social values. In his later essays
(e.g., The Essential Tension [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977]), he retreated
from some of the claims made in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. This has not
stopped others from following the earlier, more radical Kuhn. Joseph Rouse speaks of
there being two Kuhns, one more radical, the other more conventional in his attitudes.
22. Exceptions to the general neglect of the philosophy of science by Continental
philosophy include Patrick A. Heelan, Space-Perception and the Philosophy of Science
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983); Joseph J. Kockelmans and Theodore J.
Kisiel, eds., Phenomenology and the Natural Sciences: Essays and Translations
(Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1970); Joseph Rouse, Engaging Science:
How to Understand its Practices Philosophically (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
1996); Babette E. Babich et al., eds., Continental and Postmodern Perspectives in the
Philosophy of Science (Brookfield, Vt.: Avebury Press, 1995); and Glazebrook, Heideggers Philosophy of Science.
23. For an introductory text in hermeneutics, see Josef Bleicher, Contemporary
Hermeneutics (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980). Hans-Georg Gadamers Truth
and Method (New York: Seabury Press, 1975) offers a more sophisticated historical account.
172
Notes
24. For a recent account of Heideggers views on natural science, see Glazebrook,
Heideggers Philosophy of Science.
25. On the visual nature of the science of geology, see Martin J. S. Rudwick, The
Emergence of a Visual Language for Geological Science, 17601840, History of Science (1976): 14995.
26. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Eye and Mind, in The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics
Reader, ed. Galen A. Johnson, trans. Michael B. Smith (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern
University Press, 1993).
27. Sokal comments, in the essay where he revealed his hoax, that anyone who believes the laws of physics to be mere conventions is invited to try transgressing those
conventions from the windows of my apartment. (I live on the twenty-first floor.) His
example, however, is telling. Socially relevant science, like questions of acid mine
drainage and global climate change, defy simplistic accounts of scientific objectivity.
See Alan Sokal, A Physicist Experiments with Cultural Studies, Lingua Franca,
May/June 1996, pp. 6264.
28. The following argument, dependent upon an entire tradition of hermeneutic
philosophy, relies upon Heideggers Being and Time, trans. John MacQuarrie and Edward Robinson (London: SCM Press, 1962), originally published in German in 1927.
29. Work on the social and political influences upon scientific research include
Bruno Latour and Steven Woolgar, Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Fact (Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage Publications, 1979); Andrew Pickering, ed., Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992); Sharon
Traweek, Beamtimes and Lifetimes (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1988); and
Karin Knorr-Cetina, Epistemic Cultures: How the Sciences Make Knowledge (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999).
30. Harry M. Collins and Trevor Pinch have described the extraordinary difficulties scientists sometimes face in duplicating experiments. See The Golem: What Everyone Should Know about Science (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993).
31. For an account of the history of the Colorado, see Ivo Lucchitta, The History
of the Colorado River and the Grand Canyon, in Grand Canyon Geology, ed. Stanley S.
Beus and Michael Morales (Flagstaff, Ariz.: Museum of Northern Arizona Press, 1990).
32. See Hayden White, The Logic of Historical Narration, Philosophy and History 3 (1963): 414; D. L. Hull, Central Subjects and Historical Narratives, History
and Theory 14 (1976): 25374.
33. On the role of prediction in the Earth sciences, see Naomi Oreskes, Why Predict? Historical Perspectives on Prediction in Earth Science, in Prediction: Science,
Decision Making, and the Future of Nature, ed. Daniel Sarewitz, Roger A. Pielke Jr.,
and Radford Byerly Jr. (Washington, D.C.: Island Press, 2000), pp. 2340.
34. On the question of narrative and the historical sciences. See David Carr, Time,
Narrative, and History (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1986), for an excellent
summary and a set of references.
Notes
173
174
Notes
15. Polemarchus said, Socrates, you appear to have turned your face townward and to be going to leave us.
Not a bad guess, said I.
But you see how many we are? he said.
Surely.
You must either then prove yourselves the better men or stay here.
Why, is there not left, said I, the alternative of our persuading you that you
ought to let us go? But could you persuade us, said he, if we refused to listen? (Republic 327c. trans with notes and an interpretive essay by Allen Bloom [New York: Basic
Books, 1968], 34).
16. Don L. Eicher, Richard Dinar, Origin of the Cretaceous Bridge Creek cycles in
the Western Interior, United States. In Paleogeography, paleoclimatology, paleoecology,
74, 12, pp. 127146, 1989.
17. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963), pp. 300ff.
18. Johnson, Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader, p. 67.
19. Ibid., p. 65.
20. Martin Rudwick, The Great Devonian Controversy: The Shaping of Scientific
Knowledge among Gentlemanly Specialists (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1985); Stuart McCook, It May Be Truth, But It Is Not Evidence: Paul du Chaillu and
the Legitimization of Evidence in the Field Sciences, Osiris 11 (1996): 17797.
Notes
175
176
Notes
Notes
177
11. This belief has prompted sharp rebuttals from some geologists. Granted, maps
are the answers to a set of questions put to a landscape; when the questions change, so
will the answers (and maps). Nonetheless, from the perspective of the originating legislation of the Survey, the task of mapping has largely been completed.
12. Cf. the American Academy for the Advancement of Science web page for current figures at: http://www.aaas.org/spp/dspp/rd/caprev00.htm#hi.
13. There is a large literature on this point: see, for instance, Shrader-Frechette and
McCoy, Method in Ecology.
14. Monroe H. Freedman, Professional Responsibility of the Criminal Defense
Lawyer: The Three Hardest Questions, in Ethics in Professional Life, ed. Joan C. Callahan (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 5158.
15. http://www.usgs.gov/budget/stratplan.PDF.
16. For a brief discussion of scientific institutions as boundary organizations, see
Guston, Between Politics and Science.
17. There is a remarkable variety of terms and disciplines that wrestle with the
question of knowledge management. Policy science is a general term that includes
such diverse areas as policy analysis, science policy, policy studies, information management, and decision support systems. Lasswell, the father of the policy sciences, has
defined the policy sciences as fields that study the process of deciding or choosing and
evaluate the relevance of available knowledge for the solution of particular problems.
Harold D. Lasswell, Policy Sciences, in International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (New York: Macmillan, 1968), pp. 181189.
18. I am indebted to Robert Harrap for this typology.
19. Case, in Gene Lessard, ed., Decision Support Capabilities for Future Technology
Requirements: Interagency Group on Decision Support (IGDS), Washington, DC., 2001.
20. John Kelmelis, The Changing Decision Environment, in Report on the Decision Support Systems Workshop, ed. Gene Lessard and Thomas Gunther (USGS Open
file report 99-351), 1999, p. 5.
21. Ibid.
22. Information about these USGS programs can be found through searching the
Surveys webpage at www.usgs.gov.
Chapter 9. Conclusion
1. W. Scott McLean, Eldridge M. Moores, and David M. Robertson, Nature and
Culture, in Earth Matters: The Earth Sciences, Philosophy, and the Claims of Community, ed Robert Frodeman (Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 2000), pp. 141150.
2. John Donne, The Anniversaries, ed Frank Manley (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
Press, 1963), p. 7374.
178
Notes
The Sunne is lost, and thearth, and non mans wit
Can well direct him, where to looke for it).
And freely men confesse, that this worlds spent,
When in the Planets, and the Firmament
They seeks so many new; they see that this
Is crumbled out againe to his Atomis).
Tis all in pieces, all cohaerence gone;
All just supply, and all Relation:
Prince, Subject, Father, Sonne, are things forgot,
For euery man alone thinkes he hath got
To be a Phoenix, and that there can be
None of that kinde, of which he is, but hee.
3. Gary Snyder, Mountains and Rivers without End, (Washington, D.C.: Counterpoint, 1996), p. 145. Quoted in Nature and Culture, op. cit., p. 148.
4. See http://www.uni-bielefeld.de/iwt/realworld/.
5. See http://www.mines.edu/newdirections.
6. See http://www.amdandart.org/.
INDEX
179
180
Index
cosmology, 43
Cover, Jan A., 667
Cuomo, Chris, 49
Curd, Martin, 667
cyanide heal leach mining, 25
cyberscience, 715
limits of, 734
Dalai Lama, 118
Darwin, Charles, 44, 110
dEaubonne, Franoise, 49
democracy, 56, 131, 1378
Denver Museum of Nature and
Science, 158
Derrida, Jacques, 62
Descartes, Ren, 9, 44, 81, 134
Donne, John, 156
Durango, CO, 22, 31, 39
Dutton, Clarence, 6
Earth Day, 43
Earth Science Engineering and
Management, 48
Earth sciences, 3, 12 146
and the humanities, 7980
philosophy of, 15, 79, 93
transdisciplinarity of, 156
vs. geology, 3
see also field science; geology;
philosophy of science
Eastern Europe, acid mine
drainage in, 22
Echo Bay Mines, Inc., 29
ecofeminism, 40, 46, 4951
ecogeologic abundance, 1267, 129
see also environmental
philosophy
ecologic constraints, 16, 12930, 132
see also geologic scarcity
ecologic restoration, 479
see also acid mine drainage;
environmental debate
Eicher, Don, 111
Einstein, Albert, 63, 67
Eldridge, Niles, 81
Eliade, Mircea, 534
Index
Gaia, 3
Galileo, 44, 63, 67
General Accounting Office, 47
geographical information systems,
149
geologic fieldwork, 10, 69
methods, 968, 1027, 109,
1112, 1145
see also field sciences
geologic reasoning, 81, 90, 93
see also philosophy of science
geologic scarcity, 1334
see also ecological constraints
geologic time, 80, 902, 97, 117,
1246
Geological Survey of Canada (GSC),
178, 1356, 149, 151
geology
age of, 1268
cultural image of, 80, 122
definition, 133
economic roots of, 1223, 126, 133
need of integrated study of, 34
philosophy of, ix, 6
see also philosophy of fieldwork;
philosophy of science
relation to humanities, 34, 14,
79, 81
geometaphysics, 123, 126, 156
geopoetry, 24, 14, 115, 123, 128,
156
geopolitics, 24, 126, 128, 156
Georef, 96
Georgia Basin, 135
geoscience, 128, 156
geosocial, 141, 149
geotheology, 24, 128
Giere, Ronald, 79
global circulation models, 93
Global Climate Change and Society
Program, ix
Goodman, Nelson, 83
Gore, Al, 53
Gould, Stephen Jay, 81
Grand Canyon, 1, 6, 42, 53, 111, 129
Green River Formation, WY, 97
181
182
Index
Index
philosophy of science, 14, 43, 57,
5963, 824, 96, 110
analytic, 79, 825
continental, 79, 845, 93, 128
epistemology of, 5963, 678, 84
history of, 612
neglect of field science, 70, 801
physics model, 801, 83
place in public life, 61
political aspects, 613, 65
purview of, 5, 63, 668
role in environmental debates,
202
scientists role, 14553
see also Earth sciences;
environmental philosophy;
environmental debates; field
science; philosophy of
geological reasoning; natural
science
Pierce, Charles Sanders, 1067
Pinchot, Gifford, 45
Plato, 434, 77, 99, 110, 137
Polanyi, Michael, 35
Popper, Karl, 83
postmodernism, 1289
Powell, John Wesley, 6, 1413
public science, 17, 13653
economic issues, 13940, 142
funding, 15, 62, 1435
history of, 1379
philosophy of, 17
range of, 136, 140
role of, 14453, 156
vs. private, 13740
see also philosophy of science;
science
Pueblo State Recreation Area, 98
Pyne, Stephen, 6
Quine, Willard, 83
rationality, Platonic, 778
effect on geology, 789, 82
Real World Experiment program,
1567
183
184
Index