What Is Philosophy - Dietrich Von Hildebrand PDF
What Is Philosophy - Dietrich Von Hildebrand PDF
What Is Philosophy - Dietrich Von Hildebrand PDF
BY
THE
SAME AUTHOR
Marriage
Liturgy and Personality
Fundamental Moral Attitudes
0
In Defense of Purity
Transformation in Christ
Not as the World Gives
Morality and Situation Ethics
The Art of Living
Man and Woman
Trojan Horse in the City of God
The Encyclical Humanae Vitae:
A Sign of Contradiction
Celibacy and the Crisis of Faith
Ethics
Devastated Vineyard
WHAT rs
Philosophy?
DIETRICH
von
HILDEB RAND
CHICAGO, 60609
NIHIL OBSTAT:
Censor librorum
IMPRIMATUR:
+ WILLIAM
E. CousiNs
Archbishop of Milwaukee
Ma rch 20, 1960
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
CONTENTS
Acknowledgments
Introduction .
1
11
Introductory Remarks
I.
13
Knowledge in General
II.
III.
26
38
prescientific knowledge.
IV.
63
V.
VI.
152
172
vii
viii
CONTENTS
VII.
185
VIII.
Index
and scientific
philosophy. 5.
227
239
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
INTRODUCTION
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
role. It was philosophy which gave the verdict about all kinds
of knowledge; their philosophy, negative though its content may
have been, claimed to be queen in the sphere of knowledge.
If we examine the relativistic or skeptical philosophies in
former times, we find that they did not refuse to grant phi
losophy an important role. They showed no tendency to favor
science at the expense of philosophy. Even Hume's skepticism
was directed just as much against science as it was against
philosophy.
Today, on the contrary, there is a boundless respect for,
and an unwavering faith in, science exhibited by the very
philosophers who deny objective truth and profess, as phi
losophers, complete relativism and subjectivism. Unlike the
skeptics of older times, they have an inferiority complex with
respect to the role and importance of philosophy. Yet strangely,
this does not hinder them from manifesting an arrogant, snob
bish attitude toward all the actual topics of philosophy, toward
all metaphysical realities, toward morality, and toward religion.
But at the same time they look upon science as something
incomparably superior, as something which is not at all affected
by the denial of objective truth which they profess. What are
the reasons for this surprising attitude?
First, we must realize that these men, although they call
themselves philosophers and are recognized as such by their
contemporaries, have abandoned the very method of philo
sophical research. As a matter of fact, positivism in its various
guises is not a wrong philosophy for the simple reason that it
is not a philosophy at all. Positivism borrows the methods of
certain sciences to deal with philosophical topics. Methods and
approaches which are legitimate, and even the only adequate
ones in certain sciences, are applied to the exploration of phil
osophical topics, for which they are absolutely inept.
There are many wrong philosophies, for example, subjective
idealism, or solipsistic psychologism, that can still claim the
INTRODUCTION
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
INTRODUCTION
pp.
6, 7 ff.
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
INTRODUCTION
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
INTRODUCTION
10
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
INTRODUCTORY REMARKS
12
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
CHAPTER
KNOWLEDGE IN GENERAL
14
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
KNOWLEDGE IN GENERAL
15
16
WHAT I S PHILOSOPHY?
the object discloses itself and unfolds before our spiritual eyes.
The idealistic interpretation of taking cognizance of some
thing as a spiritual building up out of an amorphous stuff and
as a creation of the object of knowing is, therefore, equivalent
to denying knowledge. Moreover, the misunderstanding of this
basic meaning of taking cognizance of something necessarily
travels in a vicious circle. Let us see why this is true. Transcen
dental idealism interprets taking cognizance of something as a
construction of the object and thereby denies that we are able
to grasp a real object such as it is. Yet it claims that philosophy
describes the real nature of knowledge. It is perfectly clear that
transcendental idealism does not consider its own interpretation
of knowledge as a mere construction and that it claims it to be
the disclosure of the authentic nature of knowledge. With this
claim it tacitly presupposes and silently reintroduces the real
nature and true notion of taking cognizance, namely, the grasp
ing of an object such as it is, and not the constructing of an
object. This intrinsic contradiction in transcendental idealism
is, however, inevitable. For the genuine datum of knowledge and
taking cognizance of something is so elementary that every
attempt to deny it or to interpret it as something else necessarily
leads to a vicious circle. Taking cognizance, as the genuine
receiving and grasping of a being as it is, is really so elementary
and inevitable a fact that it silently comes back into the picture
and regains its rightful place even when a person tries to explain
it away as something else.
Idealism declares that what presents itself to our naive under
standing as knowledge is in reality something completely differ
ent. The failure to distinguish between taking cognizance of
something and the other different theoretical acts, such as
judging and the like, has furthered this principal misunder
standing of the nature of knowledge. For such acts, in contrast
to taking cognizance of something, present us with an out
spokenly active character. By showing the different character of
KNOWLEDGE IN GENERAL
17
18
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
KNOWLEDGE IN GENERAL
19
Christian Ethics
a Ibid.
20
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
KNOWLEDGE IN GENERAL
21
22
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
KNOWLEDGE IN GENERAL
23
can refer to as a spiritual "going with" the object and its nature.
I am thinking here not only of the preparatory acts, like atten
tiveness, that explicit turning of the mind toward the object
which displays itself in so many gradations. This is rather a
presupposition for taking cognizance of something, not an ele
ment of taking cognizance itself. It merely effects a contact
with the object on the part of the knower. If a person sees a
house, another person, or an event, without being attentive
to it, his mind is "absent," and consequently it does not linger
before the seen object. There is no real contact with the
knower's mind. But by the active, spiritual "going with" which
we have in mind here, we mean something which is an element
in the process of taking cognizance itself. It is, as it were, the
intentional echoing of the being of the object, the consumma
tion of the "understanding" of the actual momentary object, the
full, explicit, spiritual reception of the object.
This "going with" that belongs to taking cognizance of some
thing, this spiritual penetration, plays quite different roles in
the perception of the different kinds of objects. The higher and
more complicated the object and the more meaningful it is, the
more prominent becomes this "concerting" with the object
and the more essential is its part in the whole process of taking
cognizance. In the simple perception of a color it has not the
same meaning and depth as in the perception of another person
or even of an essence.
This active component in taking cognizance of something
in no way implies a contradiction to the basically receptive char
acter of knowing. The active component not only does not
cancel the receptive character, it does not even imply a limita
tion of it, for it may not in any sense be understood as any
kind of production of the object of knowledge. This "going
with" is only an active co-operation with the self-disclosure of
the object. It is not a production of the object. Neither is it a
"copy" of the object, not even in the broadest sense in which
24
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
KNOWLEDGE IN GENERAL
25
CHAPTER
II
27
28
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
29
30
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
31
32
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
33
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
35
36
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
37
CHAPTER
Ill
39
40
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
41
42
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
43
44
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
45
46
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
47
48
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
these moments are not given to every man in his lifetime. They
occur only in the life of a spiritually awake and deep person
ality. In addition, these moments in naive experience refer
exclusively to important objects, possessing a high content of
meaning and value. They may be found in the lives of great
artists and ethical personalities and likewise in the prephilo
sophical contact of genuine philosophers with being. This
superior form of nai've taking cognizance is by far the nearest
thing to philosophical taking cognizance. It is even more related
to it than all strictly scientific knowledge. These moments we
might call the philosophical moments in life. In the case of this
kind of taking cognizance there is a high thematicity of the ob
ject as well as of knowledge itself. The latter is here completely
unpragmatic. Indeed, it is even lifted above the actuality of fleet
ing, temporal existence. In it we momentarily gain, as it were,
the contemplative place of pure philosophical knowledge, a
place related to eternity. The insight given in this rare moment
might bear the character of an essential truth. In any case it
always takes a direction toward depth. Despite these similarities,
however, it still differs from philosophical knowledge because
it is uncritical and unsystematic.
We may summarize our results thus far. We have seen how
philosophical knowledge is distinguished from prescientific,
nai've knowledge in all its forms. The first type of nai've knowl
edge is completely casual and unthematic, whereas philosophi
cal cognition is always thematic. The second type of nai've
cognition, the ordinary acquaintance with an object, is only
implicitly thematic, whereas philosophical knowledge is always
explicitly so. In the third type of nai've taking cognizance of
something, the goal is always some pragmatic end, which com
pletely dominates and rules the situation, with the result that
the knowledge gained is always partial and one-sided, whereas
philosophical knowledge is completely unpragmatic and is con
cerned with the totality of the object. A fourth type of nai've
49
50
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
and toward the general and typical, not only possesses the per
fection of a standpoint related to eternity, and not only is more
distant from the existential situations of actual living, but it
is also always critical and always systematic.
2.
51
52
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
here the results are far more dubious, because they are more
distant from the thing in question, because the process of
knowledge is much more complicated, and because the language
of being undergoes greater refraction before it at length becomes
formulated.
Within the framework of this theoretical prescientific knowl
edge, however, we must distinguish between two essentially
different kinds: organic and inorganic knowledge. In proverbs
and sayings of wise men and poets we find the organic theoreti
cal prephilosophical knowledge. There is a relatively organic
path here which leads from naive taking cognizance of some
thing to a more general and theoretical awareness. Perhaps
these sayings and inductive conclusions stem from an incisive
and important experience of one's own life, or they may be
the results of what one often observes here and there. In any
event, they are always an organic outgrowth of a naive taking
cognizance of something. The reflections are consequent upon
it. They are, as it were, the theoretical awareness of impressions
condensed from a naive knowledge.
As long as a person, during times of misfortunes, merely en
dures many disappointments at the hands of his fellow men,
he simply perceives the fact that one is left alone in mis
fortune. He may even infer, on a nontheoretical level, that
this fact is true in general, but still his knowledge remains
on the plane of a naive living contact. As soon, however, as
he wishes to emphasize the general truth, as soon as this fact
takes on the character of a proverb, with its outspoken thema
ticity of knowledge, he quits the level of naive knowledge. A
completely new consciousness begins, which goes far beyond
a naive knowledge-contact with an object. Nevertheless, this
prominent conscious awareness of the general fact is linked in
an organic way to the naive cognizance of it.
If a man "reasons" about life, moral values, art, and so forth,
without relating his mind to the language of the objects he has
53
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
55
56
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
57
58
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
59
60
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
61
62
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
CHAPTER
IV
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
64
Strict Necessity
65
66
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
67
68
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
69
Incomparable Intelligibility
70
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
71
72
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
73
74
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
75
to here must be free from all the imperfections which are proper
to the observation of merely contingent facts. Only a "given
ness" completely different from that of observation and induc
tion can support and truly give absolute certainty.
If there is an insight into an essentially necessary and abso
lutely certain state of facts, there is no question of observa
tion of actual being. Whether or not I am the victim of fantasy
or hallucination or whether I am dreaming or truly perceiving,
is strictly irrelevant to the reality of a necessary state of facts.
Let us assume, for example, that I perceive the color orange
on the fruit of the same name. In this perception I realize
that this color lies, according to the order of similarity, be
tween red and yellow. The reality of this fact is in no way
jeopardized by the realization that I may later on discover
that my "perception" was not a genuine perception of an actual
object, but rather an hallucination. For the question, whether
or not the orange color is here and now present in real
ity, is irrelevant to the reality of the state of facts that
"Orange lies between red and yellow." To grasp the truth of
the state of facts, the "such-being," the essence of the color
orange must be given to me. The real, actual existence of the
color orange, however, need not be given to me. The fact in
question is grounded exclusively in the such-being of red,
orange, and yellow. Its reality, therefore, is independent of
the validity of my grasping real beings endowed with these
three colors. This does away with the possibility of dis
appointment, to which all mere observations are open. It
also erases any question as to the incapacity of beings to grant
us absolute certainty. Here the perception has only the func
tion of affording me the opportunity, by the unfolding of a
certain such-being before my spiritual eye, to gain an insight
into the truth of the state of facts. But the perception, insofar
as it is an observation of an actually existing being, does not
act as a proof for the knowledge of the existence of this essential
76
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
state of facts. In the case of the necess ity of natural laws, that
is, of the merely though highly probable propositions of chemis
try and physics, perception actually does take on this role of
proving the truth and reality of states of facts.
If the observation that "Hydrogen and oxygen in a specific
compound yield water" should be an hallucination, then the
general state of facts concerning the chemical make-up of
water would hang in the air. Again, if a physicist should find
that the observations reporting that a body expanded when
heated were all made in a dream, then the inductive conclusion
affirming a causal relation between heat and the expansion
of a body would not be verified. He could not then lay it down
as a law of nature that "Heat expands a body."
On the other hand, the truth of an essentially necessary state
of facts in no way depends on mere observations. For ex
ample, take the proposition, "An object cannot be willed unless
I am conscious of it." The truth of this proposition does not
depend on whether my grasp and clarification of willing con
cerned a real willing or simply an imagined one. It does not
matter whether I realized this truth in a dream or while I
was awake. If in a dream I clearly and distinctly grasp will
ing in its such-being, so that I grasp as evident this state of
facts to be essentially rooted in the such-being, then my knowl
edge is as valid and as certain as it would have been if I
had been awake all the time. For, whether awake or sleep
ing, I have grasped a necessary fact which I understand to be
rooted in the essence of willing and not in the actual, here
and-now existence of this or that act of willing.
States of facts which are essentially necessary and immedi
ately understood are in reality completely independent of actual
existence here and now. An essence is given to me. In it are
grounded necessary states of facts, and in it, in the "givenness"
of the essence, I understand these necessary facts. In other
words, facts of this kind require only the "givenness" of a
77
78
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
79
80
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
81
82
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
83
84
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
85
86
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
87
definite type of reality, but above all it here signifies the com
plete lack of knowledge of the such-being in question. We may
call this experience the "experience of such-being," in opposi
tion to blunt, empirical observation.
Perception is the starting point for each of these two kinds
of experience. Still this should not make us unaware of the
essential difference between them. It is true that, when an
object is given to us, when it stands in its self-presence
before our minds, it gives us an original knowledge of its such
being and also a knowledge of its real existence. Both go hand
in hand in perception. Nevertheless, these two kinds of taking
cognizance of something are different one from the other. We
have already seen the proof of this, for we have seen that even
when an observation is invalidated because the "perception"
later on turns out to be an hallucination, still taking cognizance
of the such-being remains untouched. Thus if someone be
comes acquainted with the color red through an hallucination,
the result is that he had no experience of an actually existing
red thing, but he most certainly had a genuine experience of
its such-being.
At this point it is legitimate to ask: Are there contents
which need never be given to us in their such-being at least
once? Are there contents which we know independently of
every concrete perception of such-being? A blind person does
not know what colors look like. Not only can he not grasp
the real existence of a color, he also does not know the such
being of the colors red, yellow, blue, and so forth. These
singular qualities have not disclosed themselves to his mind
in their essence. Evidently, in the case of colors we are deal
ing with contents which, before they can be known, must
have been presented to the human mind in their such-being
at least once in a concrete instance. But is this true of con
tents like "unity," or of the basic ethical values, "good" and
"bad"? Is it necessary that unity, which plays such a funda-
88
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
89
90
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
91
92
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
93
94
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
95
96
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
97
98
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
99
1 00
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
101
102
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
103
of them as real types. Their unity forms the basis for a true
universality. Here there is not a generic character which im
plies exclusively an opposition to the single existing individual.
Rather a certain stage of generality is to be found here which
allows many possible future differentiations (from species to
sub-species) .
Moreover, the stage of generality is not an arbitrary one,
but is grounded in the meaningful unity of the such-being.
The "suchness" of a scribbled geometric figure or of a heap of
junk is completely arbitrary in its generality. We cannot, fur
thermore, form a concept of this unity but we must content
ourselves with a description of the such-being as a whole.
The such-being present in a genuine type evidently has
an inner consistency that is quite different. It is something
objectively meaningful, standing in sharp contrast to what is
purely accidental and factual. It is not simply held together
from "without," but rather possesses a unity from the "center,"
and its elements are combined, not accidentally, but intrinsically
and meaningfully.
Compared with beings possessing an impoverished, radically
contingent unity, genuine types have a further dignity. They
are, in a completely new sense, serious "somethings." What
ever has only a meaningless, impoverished such-being is not a
species nor can it ever be a serious object for science. In addi
tion, whatever is held together exclusively by de facto accidental
existence has, from the point of view of existence, a nonserious
character.
We must, however, distinguish two strata in those beings
whose such-being has the character of a true type. In the
one stratum we find the such-being of appearances, e.g., the
appearance of gold, of metal, of water. This "type," which the
appearance offers to us, and which is the starting point for
naive concepts, we may call its "face," its outer or "appearance"
unity. We must distinguish it from the second stratum, which
1 04
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
105
106
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 07
108
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 09
IIO
WHAT I S PHILOSOPHY?
Ill
1 12
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
113
1 14
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
115
116
WHAT I S PHILOSOPHY?
117
118
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 19
120
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
121
In our next chapter, we shall deal in detail with the reality of this aspect.
122
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
123
124
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
125
126
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
127
1 28
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 29
1 30
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
131
1 32
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
133
1 34
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
135
for all further insights into the essential facts related to the
essence, the essence is revealed in a way which differs com
pletely from the "transparency" of an essence that makes it
possible for us to define the object. We should fall into a
vicious circle, and, indeed, put the cart before the horse, if
we first demanded the kind of knowledge of an essence which
can be projected into a definition in order to acquire insights
into the state of facts in question. This, of course, is what
actually happens in the case of tautological propositions. Here
an essence is circumscribed in the sense of breaking it down
by a definition. Then the predicate simply repeats the state
of facts which was the ground of the definition in the first
place. Second, if we should know every state of fact pertinent
to an essence, the disclosure of the essence itself would be
completely different from the transparency which provided
the basis for definition. To appreciate this fact we must under
stand that most essences are basic and primal data. This means
that we must perceive each essence if we are to know it. We
cannot deduce it from other data. All essences which are indeed
primal in this sense are, therefore, something more than a "sum
of properties." For this reason they can never be dissolved
into a mere sum of characteristics, into a unity made up of
transparent and definable parts. Out of the knowledge of a!!
necessary states of facts grounded in an essence, a light flows
and illumines the essence itself and reveals it to our minds. But
this light does not dissolve the necessary and essential unity
into components in such a way that a definition cast from
these components could replace the intuitive grasp of the
essence.
There is yet another possible misunderstanding which we
must eliminate. In our elaboration of the specific character of
apriori insights, we have always chosen as examples self-evident
and readily acknowledged facts, such as, "Something cannot
be and not be simultaneously"; "Moral values presuppose a
1 36
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 37
1 38
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 39
140
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
141
142
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
143
144
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
145
146
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
147
148
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
149
1 50
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
151
CHAPTER
1 53
1 54
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 55
1 56
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 57
1 58
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
in the same sense, whether or not the human mind exists. For
idealism, the proposition refers to objects which would be differ
ent as soon as we prescind from man's mind; moreover, in its very
validity the proposition is relative to a human mind - to the
way men are constructed as opposed to other beings who might
be knowers. From this it follows that all metaphysical facts are
inaccessible to our mind. Man cannot attain eternal verities in
the Augustinian sense. Idealism of this kind has, therefore, by
reason of its doctrine of "subjective" validity, a restrictive and
negative character. Even so, its meaning for "subjective" is not
at all the same as the fourth meaning - that of a mere
semblance.
The sixth and final meaning of "subjective" refers to what is
the topic of this chapter, the fact, namely, that the co-operation
of a human mind is presupposed for certain data, such as the
notions of "above" and "below." This co-operation refers only
to an aspect or appearance of certain objects in the exterior,
extended world. These aspects constitute themselves only for a
human mind and are, therefore, in some sense subjective; for
they cannot be regarded as properties of beings independent of
the human mind. Because this meaning of the term "subjective"
involves the question of how the aspects "actually are," it rightly
includes an epistemological feature.8
In this chapter we simply want to ask: Is this type of depend
ence upon man's mind incompatible with objective validity?
s We prescind here from the extremely important meaning of "subjective" as
referring to all the realities which are constituted for an individual person. The
value which an object has for us because we received it from a beloved one is,
on the one hand, completely valid, but, on the other hand, this value exists only
for me, and not as such, independently of the fact that it was a manifestation
of love of a certain person, whom we love. This meaning of "subjective" is, as
we can easily see, in no way opposed to validity, and has no pejorative connota
tion whatever. Our appreciation of this gift is most objective, i.e., it is the
objectively right attitude toward it. Being a manifestation of the love of a
beloved person, the object really assumes a great preciousness. It is true that this
preciousness exists only for me, but this does not efface its full validity because
objectively it should be precious to me. This meaning of subjective and subjec
tivity. is extremely important and plays a great role in Kierkegaard and existen
tial philosophy.
1 59
Must we say that colors, that notions like above and below, are
"subjective" in the sense of "nonobjective" semblances, or in
the sense of "relative to man's mind"? Shall we say that the
blue color of the sky is only a mere semblance, a kind of optical
deception? Shall we thereby deny it any objectivity and validity?
Human experience offers us as aspects of the exterior world a
universe of colorful, sounding, odorous things. Is this world less
objective than the one offered by physics and chemistry? In
the words of Gustav Fechner: "Is the Naclltansicllt ( night
view) more objective and more real than the Tagansicht (day
view)?"
The question of objective validity of aspects depends, of
course, upon the aspects themselves and varies with their specific
nature. For the moment, however, we limit ourselves to this
general question : Is it true that the objective validity and reality
of an :;spect is the same as its independence from man's mind?
It will become clear that this is not true if we start with some
thing that is indeed merely a subjective semblance ana contrast
it with the aspects that are our topic here.
The most radical case of a merely subjective semblance is an
object of a dream. True, if in a dream we grasp the fact, both
necessary and highly intelligible, that "Moral values presuppose
a person as bearer," the truth and validity of this fact are in no
way prejudiced by our having grasped it in a dream instead of
in the waking state. When, however, not a necessary and essen
tial fact, but rather an event, a deed, or a person is given in a
dream, then these things are stripped and deprived of all ob
jective validity and are rightly regarded as mere semblances.
If a person we know suddenly looks different in a dream, has
blond hair instead of black, is tall instead of small, this aspect
is definitely a pure semblance.4 The same applies analogously
to an hallucination.
4
1 60
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
161
nature color refers to the way a thing looks, and the fact that
one and the same thing appears differently colored does not
imply a contradiction like that between a broken and an un
broken oar. But there is a still more important difference.
The semblance of the broken oar includes no contribution to
reality. It does not enrich the world, nor does it form a member
in the chain of elements which build up a meaningful aspect
of the exterior world and are bearers of its beauty. But this all
applies to the blue color of the mountains.
The blue color of mountains seen from afar is a great en
richment of the world. It definitely has an important function
in the beauty of nature; it contains a "word" full of significance,
a message frequently the theme of poets. It fits meaningfully
and organically into the general aspect of nature and especially
of the landscape. It includes a specific meaningful message,
whereas the appearance of the broken oar is a mere deception.
The blue color of mountains seen from afar definitely can
not be placed on the level with the appearance of the broken
oar. It would be impossible to consider the former a mere
deception.
The question now arises : What place has this blue color in
reality? It certainly presupposes a human spectator, and does
this fact deprive it of all objectivity and validity, and exile it
from reality?
Are we not here confronted with a case in which the de
pendence of something upon man's mind does not deprive it
of its objective validity and its place in reality?
It seems that we must distinguish between two radically
different types of dependence upon man's mind or two different
types of subjectivity: the first is due to a limitation of man's
mind and consists in a deformation of reality or in semblances
which are completely cut off from reality.
The second is an appearance of reality which implies a
meaningful message directed to man. We could say of the
1 62
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 63
164
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 65
1 66
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 67
1 68
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 69
Idealism claims that all objects depend on, and are relative to,
our mind; whereas we concede this dependence and relativity
only for the aspects of the corporeal world. Idealism impairs
the validity of all objects because of their dependence on our
mind; we extend validity even to the aspect which in a certain
way depends on man's mind. Our position is just the opposite
of idealism: in idealism every content of our knowledge is
reduced to a subjectivity which is in marked contrast to ob
jectivity. In our scheme, even certain contents which depend
upon our mind, and are in this sense subjective, share in the
objective validity.
It is clearly impossible, therefore, to gain support for sub
jective idealism by applying our arguments for the objective
validity of the human aspects of the exterior world.6
Let us consider a further argument. When we grant objective
validity to certain aspects of the exterior world, we see that
the very possibility of this validity depends upon the aspect's
being framed against the background of an objective reality
which is in its existence completely independent of our mind
and which can be known by us. Our view does not point to
any grand discrepancy between "things-as-they-really-are" and
"things-as-they-appear-ta-man" in any and all possible experi
ences. This is the axis of Kant's idealism, but it has nothing
to do with our view on the validity of certain subjective aspects.
The discrepancy we notice is a limited and local one: between
the aspect which corporeal beings afford us in a naive experi
ence and the one afforded in a scientific experience. Naive
a The contrast of our position with the idealistic one discloses itself drastically
when once we realize how impossible it would be on idealistic principles to
interpret the aspects of corporeal phenomena as valid messages from God. I f
idealism were true, the merely subjective categories and the entire aspect o f
experience which they afford u s could never b e considered as valid messages from
God. Even more, subjectivistic idealism bars the possibility of our knowing God's
existence since it denies the possibility of our knowing something transcendent.
In such a scheme, therefore, there is no possible ground to state that certain
things dependent upon man's mind are nonetheless valid because they are mes
sages of God.
1 70
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
171
CHAPTER
VI
171
1 74
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
175
176
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
This does not mean, of course, that the very first perception of an object
suffices to inform m e about its entire such-being. In many cases, as we saw before,
a complicated research alone can inform me about a certain such-being. Yet in
this process of research, in experiments, for instance, perception will always have
a privileged position.
a We shall see later on that with respect to certain objects, intellectual intui
tion is the most privileged form of taking cognizance of their such-being.
177
178
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
1 79
180
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
181
1 82
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
183
1 84
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
CHAPTER
VII
DISTINGUISHING MARK OF
PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE AND
INQ UIRY
186
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
that of the object. This is the case in the basic attitude charac
teristic of the sciences.
Someone might object that the pragmatic character of certain
sciences, of a great part of physics for example, contradicts our
statement that in science the object-thematicity is less than
the knowledge-thematicity, for to be pragmatic means to be
concerned with the object much more than with knowledge.
This objection, however, is based on a misunderstanding of
the nature of pragmatic interest. Suppose I am interested in
elevating an enormous weight of several hundred tons and I
desire to exert only a small force to accomplish this. I immerse
myself in the study of hydraulics and I devise a lift that oper
ates on the familiar principle of hydraulics known to every
automobile mechanic who has ever used a hydraulic jack. Is
my interest in the laws of hydraulics pragmatic? Indeed it is.
Is it therefore highly concerned with the object? Am I really
interested in the mysterious fact that liquids may be only
slightly compressed, that pressures on a small area can affect
the entire volume of liquids, and so forth? Does the object
itself draw me to itself and invite me to delve into its depth?
No. Although a pragmatic approach in science means that the
theme of knowledge is not very prominent, this does not there
fore guarantee a full object-thematicity. The truth is that in
such a case of pragmatic interest, the object is looked up
on simply as a means to something else. Hence we are not
preoccupied with it as such : its nature, meaning, and value.
Rather, our interest is fixed on something else, the end for
which the object in question is a means. Thus, the entire
question of hydraulic systems does not interest me in its own
right. I study hydraulics simply to accomplish something else
which does interest me, namely, the elevating of the enormous
weight.
It is true that the pragmatic approach, by putting little value
on knowledge as such stands in sharp contrast to a real knowl-
187
188
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
189
190
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
ject belongs to its most basic and ultimate attitude. This long
ing penetrates its entire knowledge process, and it is this which
gives to philosophy its characteristic solemnity.
The contact with truth which philosophy desires is, therefore,
of a nature different from that of the other sciences. The
philosophical seeker intends ultimately to rest in a contempla
tive vision of truth. Philosophical knowledge is, therefore, the
most extreme antithesis to every kind of knowledge which, as
it were, "abandons" the object after having reached a knowledge
of it. It distinguishes itself from the kind of knowledge-attitude
for which knowledge is a sort of conquest of being with the
result that one gains a superior position to the object by having
known it or "seen through it." Of course, every other serious
science likewise disowns this disrespectful knowledge-attitude,
which from the start prohibits any real penetration into the
essence of the object and which advertises its boast of "seeing
through" the object only because it suffers from an illusion.
But the philosophical attitude is the most extreme antithesis to
it. Philosophy does not pretend to assume a position superior
to the being it intends to know. Rather, it considers this being
as a "partner" in which it wants to participate. It seeks to know
the object, not in order to abandon it triumphantly when
conquered, but to be able to be devoted to it more deeply and
authentically. For this reason, a truth that is already known
never becomes old or outdated for philosophy - not even in the
sense in which something true becomes obsolete for the other
genuine sciences. Philosophy is not content with the contact
with the object that is given in the mere knowing of it, but
it seeks also a wedding with the object that is given in the
contemplative having of it. Hence, in the most ideal knowledge
penetration of an object, the object never ceases to possess a
real interest to the knower.
Thus philosophical knowledge is marked by a threefold the
maticity in its ordination to the world of centrally important
191
192
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
193
194
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
195
their lives, works, deeds, and the like. Neither does it ask about
the natural laws which lie at the root of the burial of Hercu
laneum and Pompeii. It asks only about the facts themselves and
their historical importance. Characteristic of the philosophical
attitude is that its point of view not only has a fundamentum
in re, as is true of all other genuine intellectual disciplines, but
also is oriented around the main theme of the object or object
territory. The factual themes around which our knowledge
can be oriented do not simply stand with equal rights, one
beside the other. On the contrary, they have an order of rank,
a hierarchy, according to their relation to the real meaning-axis
of the object. I can look, for example, upon a landscape from
the aesthetic point of view, the economic, the geological, the
zoological, the botanical, the historical, the strategical, and many
others, but always from a special point of view. None of these
points of view is arbitrary, to be sure. It is also true that there
is a difference in the content of the object revealed under
these viewpoints, a content which rests on the fact that some of
these points of view are of purely knowledge-interest, whereas
others have pragmatic interest. Prescinding from this difference,
we still notice that the various themes of pure knowledge-interest
do not stand on the same level. For the question which seeks
the main and the subordinate points of view is given objectively,
independent of our knowledge interests. Thus the strategical
and economic viewpoints, inasmuch as they are pragmatic, are
already much further removed from the fullness of the main
theme. Of the two, the economic is indeed incomparably less
impoverished, arbitrary, and external. For the need it serves is
by far the more classical and it touches a point lying much
closer to the meaning of the object than does the strategical.
Thus, the botanical point of view is more pertinent than the
historical to the full main theme of a landscape. Again, if we
think of a literary work of art, we can consider it aesthetically,
196
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
197
198
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
199
200
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
201
202
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
203
204
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
205
206
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
fulness with the inner essence of the object. The mind moves
out from the core and penetrates into the single elements and
necessary components of the essence. From this enviable stand
point, the mind perceives the state of facts grounded therein,
and, with each enlightened insight, it penetrates more deeply
into the essence of the object so that this essence glows with
more and more light.
We speak, for example, about "love" as something entirely
familiar. We casually regard it as a self-evident, familiar thing.
As soon, however, as we delve deeply into the essence of love,
in a philosophical direction, a completely new and enlightened
contact begins. We place ourselves in a close contact with
the object and we are touched by its breath; simultaneously,
we stand on a level remote from all contingencies - the de
actualized philosophical stand mentioned above. It is just in
this manner that we glance into the interior of this essence
instead of glancing, as before, alongside or around it. In looking
at this essence we grasp certain constitutive elements of it, as
well as states of facts necessarily grounded in it. We grasp,
for example, the ordination of love to a being possessing a
value, and also the essence of love as a value response. We
understand that its two basic components, namely, the intentio
unionis and the intentio benevolentiae, are constitutively
grounded in its essence. All this takes place neither in going
around the object and observing it from without, nor by reach
ing through induction facts or features hidden to our immedi
ate approach, but in an intuitive penetration of the object "from
within," from the very core of its essence.
Obviously this type of knowledge possesses another level of
rational light and intelligibility than observation and induction.
This "insight" has a character of understanding which the mere
stating of something "from without" lacks completely. Here
our mind is supported and embraced by the very meaning of
207
208
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
209
210
WHAT I S PHILOSOPHY?
211
212
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
facts which are the silent bases for the respective single sciences.
They deal, for example, with the essence of history, of language,
of law, and so forth.
But even where philosophy deals with objects which are
basic, in one sense or another, for the other single sciences, its
function and importance are never a mere preliminary service
for science. It would be completely false to assume that the
meaning and importance of philosophy lie in its being a formal
methodology of sciences, or even a merely formal basis of them.
This assumption overlooks the most important parts of phi
losophy, whose objects lie beyond science.
What the philosophy of right or of language or of history
offers are genuine philosophical insights, which have in no way
the character of methodological preludes for the respective
sciences.
On the other hand, it must also be said that neither do these
sciences depend in their own research upon the related philo
sophical disciplines. The historian need not know the true re
sults of the philosophy of history in order to be a great his
torian. If it is true that philosophy is not the handmaid of
the sciences, it is also true that philosophy is not the master
of sciences. They are in general independent of each other
even when they deal with the same topic, in a larger sense
of the term "topic."
Historically speaking, philosophical views have had a tre
mendous influence on the development of science, and scientific
discoveries have had a great influence on the views of many
philosophers. We are not here concerned, however, with the
mutual influences of philosophy and science which de facto
took place, but rather with whether objectively they depend
upon each other. In this respect different sciences vary to a
great extent.
There is a scale with respect to the mutual influence between
philosophy and science. The scale varies with the specific
213
214
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
4.
215
216
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
217
218
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
219
220
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
221
222
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
Phenomenology
The term phenomenology has already assumed an ambiguous
character today. One meaning of phenomenology is that which
Husser! gave to this term after 191 3, in his Ideen, and all sub-
223
224
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
225
226
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
CHAPTER
VIII
228
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
229
230
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
231
232
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
233
234
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
235
cal
Of course, we do not mean to contradict the fact that the inner philosophi
tradition actually belongs to the students and disciples of the philosophers.
236
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
237
238
WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
INDEX
63 ff
Apriori knowledge, absolute certainty
of, 70 ff; characteristics of, 63 ff;
criterion of, 1 30 ff; incomparable in
telligibility of, 69 ff; possibility of,
summary, 99 f; range of, 129; re
futes all skepticism, 140; strict
necessity, 64 ff
Aristotle, discoveries in logic, 1 37; dis
tinction between final and efficient
causes, 208 f
Augustine, St., on knowledge and con
templation, 182; "Si falJor, sum,"
74, 124, 146 f, 208
160
Beatific Vision, 182
Being, architectonic structure of, 92
Bergson, Henri, 8; distinction between
technical and intellectual memory,
32 n; on memory, 1 50, 214
Blind familiarity, 200
Blonde!, Maurice, 8
Body-soul relation, 1 5 1
Bracketing, o f existence, 97, 9 9 n, 128
"By definition," 80
Cartesian doubt, 73
Certainty, of apriori knowledge, 70
Certitude, about recollection,
3 5;
proper to knowing states of facts,
35
Chaotic unity, 100 ff
"Cogito, ergo sum,"
1 36
as
239
Distortion 1 1 6
Doxa, and inorganic theoretical knowl-
240
INDEX
235
78
Existential
closeness,
of philosophy,
199
Experience, and the
meanings of, 86 ff
apriori,
96 ff;
181
116
Immediacy, of perception, 174
Induction, fate of, 72
Innate ideas, in Descartes, 88
Inorganic theoretical knowledge, 53 f
Insanity, as related to grasp of necessary essences, 1 1 5
Insight, 69
InteiJigere, meaning of, 69 f, 134
In telligibility, of apriori knowledge,
69 ff; of apriori states of facts, 69 f;
frontiers of, 144
Intuition, of genuine essences, 97 ff;
intellectual, 1 1 3, 183, 215; in phi
losophy, 214 f
Intuitive "having," of necessary es
sences, 139
Inventions, 1 1 0
Judging, not the same a s taking cogni
zance of something, 16
Judgment, marks by which it is dis
tinguished from taking cognizance,
1 8 ff
Kant, Immanuel, on discrepancy be
tween appearance and reality, 1 69;
distinction between analytic and
synthetic propositions, 208; extent
of his subjectivity, 166 f; on knowl
edge of things-in-themselves, 147;
meaning of subjective, 1 57 f; on the
noumenon as inaccessible to man,
157; on phenomena, 1 52 f; on the
possibility of experience, 93; on pre
suppositions, 92; on the role of in
tuition, 84; on tautology, 77
Kantian categories and forms of intui
tion, 88
Kennen, having knowledge of' 33; as
opposed to wissen, 3 3
Kierkegaard, S., on subjectivity, 158 n
INDEX
241
120;
as
object
152
f,
1 57
242
INDEX
sum,
"
analyzed, 14 7
Skepticism, contemporary, 1; of Greek
Sophists, 1; of Hume, Z
Soul-body relation, 1 5 1
States of facts, definition of, 3 3; as
object of an assertion or judgment,
17
Status viae, man's earthly situation,
11
197