Assignment On Jurisprudence: Guided By: DR - Prof. Eqbal Husain
Assignment On Jurisprudence: Guided By: DR - Prof. Eqbal Husain
Assignment On Jurisprudence: Guided By: DR - Prof. Eqbal Husain
Assignment on
Jurisprudence
Jurisprud
ence
Acknowledgement
Writing the Acknowledgement for the project
in the subject of Constitution is a fairly
simple undertaking for anyone who has
attended even a single class of Dr. Prof.
Eqbal Husain. The clarity, the command and
the humour he brings into every class is
infectious, making any student believe that
there can be no easier subject that the
Jurisprudence and that anyone can master
it, provided he gives the subject the respect
and recognition that Sir himself gives the
subject.
Furthermore I would like to thank all those
people who gave the subject their time and
wrote books which I eventually referred and
also I thank the library staff who liaised with
us in searching material relating to the
project.
1 | Page
Jurisprudence
Definitions and
Explanations
Jurisprudence was the first of the social sciences to be born. Its province has
been determined and re-determined because the nature of the subject is that no
delineation of its scope cans be regarded as final. On torts or contracts,
for example, a student may be recommended to read any of the
standard textbooks with the assurance that, whichever book he does read, he
will derive much the same idea as to what the subject is about. With
2 | Page
"What is the relationship between law and morality?" and other such
questions that legal philosophers may engage.
Normative jurisprudence asks what law ought to be. It is close to
political philosophy, and includes questions of whether one ought to
obey the law, on what grounds law-breakers might properly be
punished, the proper uses and limits of regulation, and how judges
ought to decide cases.
Modern jurisprudence and philosophy of law is dominated today primarily by
Western academics. The ideas of the Western legal tradition have become so
pervasive throughout the world that it is tempting to see them as universal.
Historically, however, many philosophers from other traditions have discussed
the same questions, from Islamic scholars to the ancient Greeks.
Austin4 defines jurisprudence as Science of law which deals with analysis of
the concept or its underlying principles.
As per Salmond,5 jurisprudence can be defined in two senses
1. In the Generic sense jurisprudence can be defined as Science of Civil
Law
2. In the Specific sense jurisprudence can be defined as the science of the
first principle of civil law.
According to E.W. Patterson6, defines Jurisprudence it means a body of
ordered knowledge, which deals with a particular species of law.
According to Julius Stone7, jurisprudence means Lawyers extroversion. It is
the lawyers examination of the precepts, ideals and techniques of the law in the
light derived from present knowledge in disciplines other than the law.
It is the name given to a type of investigation into law, an investigation of an
abstract, general and theoretical nature, which seeks to lay the essential
principles of law and legal system. It, as philosophy of law attempts to correlate
4 The Province of Jurisprudence Determined
5 Salmond, Jurisprudence (10th Ed.) p. 1
6 E.W. Patterson, Jurisprudence (1st Ed.) p.1
7 Julius Stone, The province and Functions of Law p. 25
4 | Page
with Social values and provides practical solutions by way of fusion of facts,
justice and value. The people of this world have formed certain ideas and
conceptions about the nature if justice and law. It involves the study of general
theoretical questions about the nature of law and legal systems, about the
relationship of law to justice, morality and about the social nature of law. It, as a
science of law is primarily concerned with regulation of human conduct in
accordance with the set values, needs and goals of each society. As the values,
needs and goals are of a changing character, the nature of jurisprudence also
keeps on changing to cater to the need of a particular society.
According to Robert C. Clark, Jurisprudence is a science of law in general. It
does not confine itself to any particular system of law but applies to all the
systems of law or to most of them. It gives the general ideas, conception and
fundamental principles on which all or most of the systems of laws of the world
are based.
Jurisprudence is the most important and the most useful of legal studies as it
deals with the fundamental principles on which rests the superstructure of law. It
is very helpful as it provides an opportunity to bring the theory and life into
focus and how to think rather than just to know. It furnishes such materials
which ultimately help in cultivating ones own ideas in relation to a particular
theory.
Jurisprudence is a subject whose knowledge is the basis and the foundation of
the whole legal studies and that is why it has considerable importance for the
law students, law teachers, practicing lawyers and even the judges. It is not
mere knowledge of law; it is something more than that.
Introduction- Analytical
Jurisprudence
5 | Page
Central Idea
Law as it exists i.e. Law as it is, regardless of good or bad, past or future.
A law, which actually exists, is a law, though we happen to dislike it, or though
it varies from the text, by which we regulate our approbation and
disapprobation.8
Different Names:
Positive School, because it focused on, positum (Latin) which means,
as it is.
English School, because this school was dominant in England.
Austinian School, because it was founded by John Austin.
Origin:
Imperative concept of law was first proposed by Bentham during his
life time (1742-1832) but his work remained unpublished till 1945.
Prof. Dias points that until recently John Austin used to be styled the
father of the English Jurisprudence, but it is now clear from a work of
Bentham first published in 1945 that it is he, if anyone, who deserved
such a title.
However, John Austin is considered the de facto originator of this school
of jurisprudence.
Analysis of the legal system and legal concepts such as Right, Duty
etc.
2.
3.
Analysis of the relation between civil law and other forms of law.
Analysis of the legal structure of a state and administration
of justice.
4.
5.
law.
6.
7.
cases.
8.
9.
of jurisprudence.
7 | Page
It enables lawyers and judges to interpret law with logic and efficacy for
smooth functioning of a legal system.
Analytical jurisprudence is using a neutral point of view and descriptive
language when referring to the aspects of legal systems. This was
a philosophical development that rejected natural law's fusing of what law is
and what it ought to be. David Hume famously argued in A Treatise of Human
Nature that people invariably slip between describing that the world is a certain
way to saying therefore we ought to conclude on a particular course of action.
But as a matter of pure logic, one cannot conclude that we ought to do
something merely because something is the case. So analyzing and clarifying
the way the world is must be treated as a strictly separate question to normative
and evaluative ought questions.
The most important questions of analytic jurisprudence are: "What are laws?";
"What is the law?"; "What is the relationship between law
and power/sociology? and, "What is the relationship between law
and morality?"
Legal positivism is the dominant theory, although there are a growing number
of critics, who offer their own interpretations.
Analytical jurisprudence is a legal theory that draws on the resources of modern
analytical philosophy to try to understand the nature of law. Since the
boundaries of analytical philosophy are somewhat vague, it is difficult to say
how far it extends. H. L. A. Hart was probably the most influential writer in the
modern school of analytical jurisprudence, though its history goes back at least
to Jeremy Bentham.
Analytical jurisprudence is not to be mistaken for legal formalism (the idea that
legal reasoning is or can be modeled as a mechanical, algorithmic process).
Indeed, it was the analytical jurists who first pointed out that legal formalism
are fundamentally mistaken as a theory of law.
Analytic or 'clarificatory' jurisprudence uses a neutral point of view and
descriptive language when referring to the aspects of legal systems. This was a
philosophical development that rejected natural law's fusing of what law is and
what it ought to be. David Hume famously argued in A Treatise of Human
Nature that people invariably slip between describing that the world is a certain
way to saying therefore we ought to conclude on a particular course of action.
8 | Page
Analytical Positivism
Positivism simply means that the law is something that is "posited": laws are
validly made in accordance with socially accepted rules. The positivist view on
law can be seen to cover two broad principles:
Firstly, that laws may seek to enforce justice, morality, or any
other normative end, but their success or failure in doing so does not
determine their validity. Provided a law is properly formed, in accordance
with the rules recognized in the society concerned, it is a valid law,
regardless of whether it is just by some other standard.
Secondly, that law is nothing more than a set of rules to provide order and
governance of society. No legal positivist, however, argues that it follows
that the law is therefore to be obeyed, no matter what. This is seen as a
separate question entirely:
What the law is- is determined by social facts (or "sources')
What obedience the law is owed - is determined by moral
considerations.
The analytical school is known by different names. It is called positive school
because the exponents of this school are concerned neither with the past nor
with the future of law but with law as it exists i.e., with law as it is. Its
founder was JOHN AUSTIN and hence it is also called AUSTINIAN SCHOOL.
This school takes for granted the developed legal system and proceeds logically
to analyse its basic concepts and to classify them in order to bring out there
relation to one another. This concentration of systematic analyses of legal
9 | Page
convinced that if the individuals comprising the society were happy and
contented, the whole body politics would enjoy happiness and prosper.
confused with what the American legal realists (an influential group of
theorists prominent in the early decades of the 20th century) called legal
formalism a narrow approach to how judges should decide cases. The American
legal realists saw Austin in particular and analytical jurisprudence in general,
as their opponents in their critical and reform-minded efforts. In this, the realists
were simply mistaken; unfortunately, it is a mistake that can still be found in
some contemporary legal commentators.
Second, Austin's work should be seen against a background where most English
judges and commentators saw common-law reasoning (the incremental creation
or modification of law through judicial resolution of particular disputes) as
supreme, as declaring existing law, as discovering the requirements of Reason,
as the immemorial wisdom of popular custom. Such (Anglo-American) theories
about common law reasoning fit with a larger tradition of theorizing about law
(which had strong roots in continental European thought e.g., the
historical jurisprudence of theorists like Karl Friedrich von Savigny (1975): the
idea that generally law did or should reflect community mores, spirit, or custom.
In general, one might look at many of the theorists prior to Austin as
exemplifying an approach that was more community-oriented law as arising
from societal values or needs, or expressive of societal customs or morality. By
contrast, Austins is one of the first, and one of the most distinctive, theories that
views law as being imperium oriented viewing law as mostly the rules imposed
from above from certain authorized (pedigreed) sources.
More top-down theories of law, like that of Austin, better fit the more
centralized governments (and the modern political theories about government)
of modern times.
Third, within analytical jurisprudence, Austin was the first systematic exponent
of a view of law known as legal positivism. Most of the important theoretical
work on law prior to Austin had treated jurisprudence as though it were merely
a branch of moral theory or political theory: asking how should the state
govern? (And when were governments legitimate?), and under what
circumstances did citizens have an obligation to obey the law? Austin
specifically, and legal positivism generally, offered a quite different approach to
law: as an object of scientific study, dominated neither by prescription nor by
moral evaluation. Subtle jurisprudential questions aside, Austin's efforts to treat
law systematically gained popularity in the late 19th century among English
lawyers who wanted to approach their profession, and their professional
14 | P a g e
training, in a more serious and rigorous manner. Legal positivism asserts (or
assumes) that it is both possible and valuable to have a morally neutral
descriptive (or conceptual though this is not a term Austin used) theory of law.
(The main competitor to legal positivism, in Austin's day as in our own,
has been natural law theory.) Legal positivism does not deny that moral and
political criticism of legal systems is important, but insists that a descriptive or
conceptual approach to law is valuable, both on its own terms and as a
necessary prelude to criticism.
There were theorists prior to Austin who arguably offered views similar to legal
positivism or who at least foreshadowed legal positivism in some way. Among
these would be Thomas Hobbes, with his amoral view of laws as the product of
Leviathan (Hobbes 1996); David Hume, with his argument for separating is and
ought (which worked as a sharp criticism for some forms of natural law
theory, which purported to derive moral truths from statements about human
nature) (Hume 1739/2000); and Jeremy Bentham, with his attacks on judicial
lawmaking and on those, like Sir William Blackstone, who justified such
lawmaking with natural-law-like justifications (Bentham 1970, 1996). Austin's
famous formulation of what could be called the dogma of legal positivism is as
follows:
The existence of law is one thing; its merit or demerit is another. Whether it be
or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an
assumed standard, is a different enquiry.
A law, which actually exists, is a law, though we happen to dislike it, or
though it varies from the text, by which we regulate our approbation
and disapprobation.
Fourth, Austin's version of legal positivism, a command theory of law,
was also, for a time, quite influential. Austin's theory had similarities with views
developed by Jeremy Bentham, whose theory could also be characterized as
a command theory. Bentham, in a posthumously published work, would
define law as:
as assemblage of signs declarative of a volition conceived or adopted by the
sovereign in a state, concerning the conduct to be observed in a certain case by
a certain person or class of persons, who in the case in question are or
are supposed to be subject to his power: such volition trusting for its
accomplishment to the expectation of certain events which it is intended such
15 | P a g e
Command
Commands are expression of desire given by superior to inferior. This
relationship between superiors and inferiors consist for Austin his ability to
punish him for disobedience. Austin distinguishes law from other commands by
them generally i.e. law being general command; and indeed laws seems much
less like the transitory commands barked out on the parade grounds and obeyed
there and then by the troops, and much more like such things as the standing
orders of a military station which remain in force generally and continuously for
all persons on the stations.
Political Superior
Some criticize the positive theory as gunman law on the ground that it make
no real distinction between law and the command of a bank robber who points
his gun at the bank clerk and orders him to hand over content of the but such
criticism overlook the Austins second requirement for to qualify as law a
command must have been given by a political superior or sovereign. To Austin a
sovereign is any person or body of person whom the bulk of a political society
16 | P a g e
habitually obeys and who does not himself habitually obey same other person or
persons.
Sanctions
Law stands in need of sanctions. Not for the positivity in this a mere practical
need, law to him is something for the citizens to obey not as he pleases but
whether he likes it or not and this cannot be without some of the methods of
coercion. Therefore, sanctions are a logical part of the concept of law; they
consist of the penalties inflicted on the order of the sovereignty for the violation
of law in the words institutionalised punishment.
Criticism
1.
of rule of law.
2.
3.
4.
5.
In Hart's view, the rule of recognition arises out of a convention among officials
whereby they accept the rule's criteria as standards that empower and govern
their actions as officials. The rule is cognizable from the social practices of
officials acknowledging the rule as a legitimate standard of behaviour, exerting
social pressure on one another to conform to it, and generally satisfying the
rule's requirements. To this end, as explained by Hart, the rule has three
functions:
1. To establish a test for valid law in the applicable legal system,
2. To confer validity to everything else in the applicable legal system, and
3. To unify the laws in the applicable legal system.
According to Hart, any rule that complies with the rule of recognition is a valid
legal rule. For example, if the rule of recognition were "what Professor Savellos
says is law", then any rule that Professor Savellos spoke would be a valid legal
rule.
moral, religious, social, and other accretions that are not strictly law had to be
eliminated. This type of positive law approach is therefore in the tradition of
Austin. He rejected Austins definition of law as command as it introduces
subjective consideration whereas he wanted legal theory to be objective. He
defines science as a system of knowledge or a totality of cognitions
systematically arranged according to logical principles.
impose, accept or evade such a penalty. In reading Kelsen, however, one has to
bear in mind that, when he refers to a 'norm', he is usually speaking elliptically:
he is uttering a legal proposition which stands for a legal norm, in much the
same way that a picture of a dog shows the dog but does not bark.
This kind of 'purity' already excludes ideas of natural law, in which description
and evaluation are intimately connected. That leaves as the subject matter of
legal science only positive law. Kelsen is a 'legal positivist' both in that he
excludes evaluation from legal science, through a strict separation of 'is' and
'ought', and in that he considers only positive law to be law. Although he never
made much sense of the idea of 'custom', he included all public international
law as 'law'.
At the same time, although it is not easy to reconcile with his rejection of
practical reason, Kelsen was emphatic that politicians should support and make
use of legal science. And legal scientists should assist them, for instance in law
reform. Although if, when doing so, they go beyond the role of mere technician
and recommend policy-based choices between possible norms, they will no
longer be acting as legal scientists. For Kelsen, 'is' and 'ought' occupy separate
worlds as a matter of logic, but not in practice. Their logical separation should
be incorporated into practice.
23 | P a g e
law. The third function is to explain the systematic nature of legal norms. These
three issues are not un-related.
Kelsen rightly noticed that legal norms necessarily come in systems. There are
no free floating legal norms. If, for example, somebody suggests that the law
requires a will to be attested by two witnesses, one should always wonder
which legal system is talked about; is it US law, Canadian law, German law, or
the law in some other legal system? Furthermore, legal systems are themselves
organized in a hierarchical structure, manifesting a great deal of complexity but
also a certain systematic unity. We talk about Canadian law, or German law,
etc., not only because these are separate countries in which there is law. They
are also separate legal systems, manifesting a certain cohesion and unity. This
systematic unity Kelsen meant to capture by the following two postulates:
Every two norms that ultimately derive their validity from one
basic norm belong to the same legal system.
All legal norms of a given legal system ultimately derive their
validity from one basic norm.
Criticism
The concept of a basic norm involves an infinite regress. If the basic norm of a
particular positive-legal order is an authorising norm, one can ask what is the
source of the authority of the basic norm itself. If 'is' and 'ought' are to remain
entirely separated, that can only be a still more 'basic' norm; and then the same
question could be asked again, and so on infinitely. The concept of a basic
norm is doubly contradictory: it is self-contradictory in that it involves an
infinite regress; in addition, since no such norm actually exists, to presuppose
the existence of such a norm contradicts reality. The concept is a full 'fiction' in
the sense to be found in Hans Vaihinger's 'philosophy of "as if"'.
My Point of View
Jurisprudence, as a discipline of research, has a vast scope and it shall not be
limited by any attempt at fixing its external boundaries. Any theory which
confines the jurisdiction of jurisprudence reflects narrow vision and
conservative approach. Thus, a synthesis of more than one school of thoughts in
jurisprudence is necessitated which shall embrace all emerging trends and tackle
the existing challenges resolutely.
Conclusion
Jurisprudence, in its existence as a discrete discipline of social science owes its
birth largely to the analytical school. It has succeeded in resolving much of
the complexities faced by the jurists, lawyers and judges in the early stages
of its development. However, its strict adherence to the limited domain of law,
as it is restricts it from evolving into an all- inclusive school of thought. The age
of information technology and globalization where cyberspace laws and
international laws are growing prominent every day, requires analytical school
to review its doctrine and extend its spectrum in order to accommodate the
missing factors which presently earn itself strongest criticism from the jurists of
the other schools of thought.
Legal philosophy is often divided into questions of analytical jurisprudence,
concerned with the nature of law, and questions of normative jurisprudence,
concerned with questions about what the law ought to be. This familiar
distinction can be drawn in a number of different ways. These differ less in their
25 | P a g e
attitudes towards the significance of morality for law everyone agrees that law
morally ought to conform to moral demands but rather than their attitude
towards the significance of law for morality, whether basic legal concepts are
morally fundamental.
26 | P a g e