Sample 508538
Sample 508538
Sample 508538
Theories
Also available:
Theories of Art, 2: From Winckelmann to Baudelaire
Theories of Art, 3: From Impressionism to Kandinsky
THEORIES OF ART, 1
From Plato to Winckelmann
MOSHE BARASCH
Routledge
NEW YORK AND LONDON
p. em.
Rev. ed. of: Modern theories of art. 1990-c1 998.
Includes bibliographical references and indexes.
Contents: V.I. From Plato to Winckelmann ~ v. 2. From Winckelmann to
Baudelaire~v. 3. From Impressionism to Kandinsky.
ISBN 0-415-92625-4 (pbk. : v. I)~ISBN 0-415-92626-2 (pbk. : v. 2)~
ISBN 0-415-92627-0 (pbk. : v. 3)
I. Art~Philosophy. 2. Aesthetics~History. I. Barasch, Moshe. Modern
theories of art. II. Title.
N70 .B2 2000
701~dc21
0 0 -0 4 2 4 6 1
Publisher's Note
The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this reprint
but points out that some imperfections in the original may be apparent
For Berta
Contents
I.
xi
xxiii
Introduction
Antiquity
Introduction
I.
Plato
2.
Aristotle
IV.
V.
Xenophon
14
2.
Polyclitus
16
Xenocrates
18
22
I.
Social Conditions
23
2.
25
Plotinus
34
The Middle Ages
Iconoclasm
9
14
I.
Chapter Two:
I.
Scholasticism
4S
47
60
69
87
97
Chapter Three:
I.
108
114
120
127
Iv. Anatomy
V. Leonardo da Vinci
VI. Durer
130
14 2
148
Chapter Four:
i 3 2
I.
Paragone
174
I .
Social conditions
175
2.
180
186
III. Michelangelo
Chapter Five:
I.
16 3
16 4
186
20 3
20 3
20 9
I.
Vasari
20 9
2.
Vincenzio Danti
228
3 Armenini
III. Venice
23 6
24 1
I.
Prelude
243
2.
Hypnerotomachia Poliphili
247
viii
249
259
V.
262
I .
263
2.
2 70
3.
28^
291
2.
29J
Chapter Six:
1.
291
I.
Foundations
I.
3 10
3 10
New Institutions
3 10
33 0
I.
Le Brun
33 0
2.
"Les regles"
33 6
3 . "Grand gout"
344
349
349
35 2
355
359
3 65
Bibliographical Essay
379
Index
39 1
ix
Introduction to the
Routledge Edition (2000)
I
Few terms, or concepts, in the modern discourse on matters of art are
so vague, ambiguous, and surrounded by so many misunderstandings
and prejudices, as "theory of art." According to opinions and beliefs that
enjoy great popularity in the present-day world, art is the very opposite
of theory. To many readers the concept "theories of art" would seem a
contradiction in terms. How can art, so thoroughly based on intuition,
go together with theory, which is perceived as founded on detached reasoning? As such arguments are often heard in our time, it is appropriate
to preface a history of art theory with a brief reflection on, and justification of, the subject.
I am not going to offer a short definition of art theory. To do this, I
would have to be able to call on a simple and clear definition of art. It is
well known that, in spite of the endeavors of critics and philosophers,
such a handy definition is not available. Art is still something of a
riddle, not less now than centuries ago. Though in general we know
more or less clearly what we mean when we talk about art, we are not
able to cast our notions into a tight, formal pattern.
Instead of speculating about the essence of art, for the purpose of
the present study we can rely on the fact that a body of literature
xi
the issues that emerge from the process of creating a work of art are
laid out as they appear to the artist. Questions arising from the experience of making a picture or a statue are treated with great seriousness.
They are questions that have no proper place in the deliberations of
philosophers or even art critics.
A few examples of such questions will, I hope, immediately show
the particular character of the artists' contribution. One might be:
What is suitable to a specific type of painting-say, wall painting or
manuscript illumination-and what are the materials used and the
tools employed in this particular medium? If any answers to this question exist (and they do exist), they will be found to form part of what
the artists contributed to art theory. The presentation of pictorial
models, the training of the artist, and what he perceives as the necessary condition for his work (from the complex order in a medieval
workshop to the direct, immediate vision of an impressionistic
painter)-all these are themes of art theory.
Another important contribution of the texts written by artists is what
they indicate, though usually in fragmentary form, about the creative
process itself, its division into distinctly separated stages, and the characterization of each stage. What artists have said about this crucial subject
does not form a systematic theory, but their observations reflect the
actual experience of painters and sculptors in the shaping of a work of
art. They allow us to witness what we now call "the creative process" as
closely as possible. This is not to say, of course, that artists pretended to
have solved the riddle of how a work of art is created, or in precisely
what material and technical properties its power consists. From their
reflections it clearly emerges that artists themselves marveled at the
puzzles of the creative process, and at what it is that (sometimes) endows
the works they produced with great power. Artists and critics alike
sometimes call that power to attract the spectator's attention je ne sais
quoi. Where does this mysterious power, or quality, come from, and how
does it get into a panel, a canvas, or a slab of marble? These questions
arise time and again, though in different forms and in different contexts.
While no definitive answer has ever been given, the renewed raising of
the questions shows that artists are aware of the problems and consider
them as crucial.
xiii
Plato decries perspective as a means of "lying," of creating false illusions, he is both close to the actual art of his world and focuses his
thought on a very specific issue. When Hegel created his system of the
individual arts (architecture, sculpture, painting, poetry) and presented a philosophical explanation of their character and the historical
sequence of their flourishing, he too was close to the arts, and concentrated his thought on specific issues. What Aristotle's Poetics did for
literary theory since the Renaissance, Plato, Hegel, and other philosophers did for the visual arts.
Art theory, then, is not composed by a single dominant type of
author, whether artist, critic, or philosopher. In view of this, it is
not surprising that art theory does not have one predominant style
of discourse. This is one of the difficulties in defining its scope and
literary character. The authors who have contributed to the theory
of art belong to heterogeneous groups, they come from different
social classes and cultural levels. No wonder then that the language
and literary character of their contributions is sometimes of a striking variety. The wide and nonuniform scope of art theory's subject
matter is made manifest by the disparateness of the styles in which
the different texts are composed. Some present-day scholars may,
therefore, call art theory a hybrid of many scientific traditions, different literatures, and the low-grade, simple talk of workshops and
artists' ateliers.
II
Art theory, we have said, is located between actual art, including the
making of the individual picture or statue, and the general culture,
including some aspects that, at least directly, have little to do with art.
Both worlds nourish the theory of art, and in all reflections on art we
easily detect their joint impact. But while the presence and interaction
of the two spheres is a permanent characteristic of the theory of art,
the proportion of what each contributes changes a great deal in the
course of history. When do the discourses of art theory let us perceive
more clearly the imprint of the artist's toil, and where do they more
clearly reflect the general trends of the surrounding culture?
xv
about composition, line, and color could, and in fact did, become elements in the shaping of works of art. However, the structure of
Kandinsky's thought does not lead to the shaping of a picture, nor is it
anchored in a specific category of painting. What Kandinsky said about
colors is one of the most important statements made about a subject that
is essential to any kind of painting. But it is abstract, more abstract in fact
than any former statement about the same subject. While his color theory applies to all kinds of painting, it does not take account of the color
difference between a fresco, with its monumental but detached tones,
and the translucent, changing colors of a stained glass window.
And what about the "outsiders"-the philosophers, theologians,
social critics, and other representatives of the audience? In traditional
societies, authors who do not originate from the workshop and have
no direct experience of its working have little to say about matters of
art proper. Let us take Thomas Aquinas as a representative "outsider" in
a traditional culture. Thomas had a surprisingly keen perception of the
suggestive power and specific limitations of the different artistic
media. His observation on the portrait of a black man done with white
chalk is surprising in its discernment of media character. Yet in his
enormous literary work he did not say anything about a specific work
of art or about the process of making it. It is characteristic of a traditional society that intellectual and artistic matters are tightly compartmentalized and the barriers separating the different domains are
rarely, if ever, broken down.
In a nontraditional culture this structure tends to be reversed. What
happens when the barriers between the domains are coming down is,
first, that the general character of art theory becomes less concrete as
the specifically pictorial issues play a less dominant part than before.
Second, the problems of producing a work of art are not in the forefront
of attention. Moreover, if these problems are treated at all, it is mainly
nonartists who are concerned with them. The philosopher and the general theoretician take over a subject matter that for a long time was
reserved for the practicing artist.
A single example will again have to suffice as illustration. In the very
years in which Kandinsky wrote The Spiritual in Art, the German
philosopher Wilhelm Dilthey composed the studies published as Das
xvii
III
Following the development of modern historical studies, one repeatedly comes across scholars who have asked "What for?" What is the
purpose of studying history? In the final years of the eighteenth century the great poet (and professor of history) Friedrich Schiller
opened his course at the university of a small town in Germany with a
lecture he called "What is and to what end does one study world history?" A century and a half later, in the 1940s, the important medieval
historian Marc Bloch began his Apolo8ie pour l'histoire by having his
little son ask him: "Tell me, daddy, why does one study history?"
Bloch's short book was written while the author, dismissed from his
university chair, was in hiding from Nazi persecution (eventually he
was executed), and in these conditions the question is particularly
poignant. Prefacing the reissue of a history of art theory, I am tempted
to apply that old and venerable question to my field of interest. Why
should one study art theory in general and its history in particular?
Though art theory, or any other discipline of study, is in no need of a
particular apology, it may be useful to outline, even if only in the
broadest of contours, where such study is able to shed most light.
The discourse of art theory is of obvious significance for our cognition and understanding of art itself. The value of the texts assembled in
art theory is especially manifest when we attempt to unriddle the
xviii
A final example showing the value of art theory for the study and
understanding of art is the rise of the Primitive in late-nineteenthcentury art and thought. We are familiar with the catchwords (in
themselves part of art theory) that were current among artists and
critics of the generations that experienced the sometimes dramatic
rise of the Primitive. But what were the actual models, and particularly what were the spiritual trends that prepared artists and audiences
to derive a new ideal and a concept of art from the few African masks
and other objects known in Paris in the first years of the twentieth century? In the third volume of the present work I have tried to outline
the wide range of sources that nourished the new vogue of the
Primitive. The texts that reflect these sources were sometimes written
for purposes other than a discussion of art-they include anthropological studies and criticism of modern painting, the history of Egypt and
the ancient Near East, and interpretations of the recently discovered
prehistoric cave paintings. Yet, though arising in different contexts, the
texts, I believe, are part and parcel of twentieth-century theory of art.
So far I have briefly suggested what art theory can contribute to the
experience and study of works of art. But students of other disciplines,
such as historians, and philosophers, psychologists, students of religion, and many others, also have reason to be interested in the theory
of art. Art is one of the essential components of culture. This is also
true for the culture of iconoclastic periods, when people tried to ban
images. When we speak of "art and culture," this should not be understood as a juxtaposition in the sense that art is a sphere separate from,
and outside of, culture. Our juxtaposition is rather that of the specific
with the general. Art has always enjoyed some degree of autonomy, as
it offers something that no other activity or medium can provide. It is a
truism, however, that it is interwoven and integrated in the whole fabric of culture. Not only the study of art but quite specifically the study
of art theory may shed light on some aspects of general culture that
would otherwise remain obscure.
One group of materials that goes under the label of "art theory,"
such as iconologies and emblem books, offer us the possibility to make
contact with the imagination of historical periods. In modern research
the need to study the imagination of past periods or cultures has often
xx
*
For all these reasons artists and students of art in different periods
have appealed, time and again, to the venerable tradition in which
attempts to understand art and to shape its directions are collected.
We now turn to the ideas and history of these attempts.
M.B.
1999
xxii
Introduction
Introduction
color). Not only did it not deal with the specific problems of the other
arts, such as sculpture, but it omitted many general aspects of image
making and image reading that now seem part and parcel of art theory.
Even in the minds of twentieth-century scholars the outlines and
character of art theory are not always perfectly clear. One of the earliest discussions of the subject, Achille Pellizzari's I Trattati attorno Ie arti
figurativi (Naples, 1915), employs trattatistica as equivalent to "art theory," thus referring to the external literary form rather than to the
central problems of art theory. Schlosser's classic Die Kunstliteratur
(Vienna, 1924, and updated Italian translations) includes art theory
among other types of texts dealing with the visual arts (guidebooks,
local histories, biographies, etc.) and calls the whole phenomenon "art
literature." Schlosser made important contributions to the study of art
theory, yet he saw the whole field largely as an area of "sources."
Interest in the development of art criticism has led to the study of
art theories from a particular point of view. Thus, in Albert Dresdner's
Die Entstehung der Kunstkritik (Munich, 1915), some art theories are
discussed as sources of art criticism. This is also the case in the interesting work by Lionello Venturi, The History if Art Criticism (New York,
1936). Venturi is thoroughly familiar with the texts of art theory, but
the questions that guide him refer to the contribution of these texts
to the formation of canons of judgment, and whether one cannot see
them as art criticism avant la lettre.
Histories of aesthetics have also taken notice of the special domain
of art theory. To mention just one recent example: Wladislaw
Tatarkiewicz, whose valuable History if Aesthetics has recently been
translated into English (The Hague and Warsaw, 1970-1974), adduces
quite a few passages from texts that belong to the core of art theory.
From his comprehensive point of view Tatarkiewicz can afford to disregard the differences between these texts and those of philosophical
aesthetics and the aesthetics of poetry or of music.
The difficulties of definition I have mentioned should not detain us
too long. As we follow the course of reflection about the visual arts,
particularly the notions originating in close contact with the work of
art itself, we become aware of a domain that, though bordering on
and partly overlapping other areas, never fully coincides with any of
xxiv
Introduction
them. In this book, while following the path of art theory in history, I
shall only incidentally touch on questions of value or canons of criticism, and considerations of a broad aesthetic nature will also remain
marginal. On the other hand, I shall frequently have to show that
meditations on art range into matters pertaining to the sciences, technology, perception, and practice. From our history, art theory will
emerge, I hope, as a field of study of unique-though not unifiedcharacter; at its center are problems that cannot be dealt with adequately by any other discipline. The production of paintings or statues
and their appearance and function, it will appear, have rarely been
taken for granted. In most periods they have caused wonder, have
called for explanation, and have often led to the articulation of rules
to direct the artist in his creative work. The comments containing
such questions, explanations, and rules, usually emerging from a close
contact with the emerging or completed work of art, make up the
core of art theory.
It hardly needs stressing that the term "theory" should be used only
with many qualifications. A student embarking on the investigation of
art theory should not expect the systematic, comprehensive, and wellordered presentation that is the usual connotation of any theory in the
usual sense. The materials I shall present do not form a consistent doctrine. Yet what they lack in overall consistency they often compensate
for by their vividness of testimony. Most of the texts on which this
book is based are lively reflections of the attempts that artists made to
understand their own work and to come to terms with what was
required of them; they also show the efforts made by the public, those
who look at works of art and use them to grasp, interpret, and direct
the art of their own time (as well as the art of the past).
I now owe the reader some indication of the frontiers of the map I
shall draw. I have imposed two major restrictions on my presentation
of the history of art theory.
The first concerns the scope of the subject matter. This book deals
with the theories of the image-producing arts, that is, primarily painting and sculpture; it does not include theories of architecture. It is a
matter of historical knowledge-and will be amply borne out by the
testimonies here adduced-that the artist who carved his work in stone
xxv
Introduction
Introduction
Introduction
xxviii
1
Antiquity
I. INTRODUCTION
Theories
if Art: From
Plato to Winckelmann
ness. Does this vagueness result simply from the loss of texts, or does
it perhaps reflect some profound ambiguity of the concepts themselves?
Classical literature, as everybody knows, has come down to us in a
fragmentary state, and the literary historian sometimes resembles the
archaeologist attempting to reconstruct a whole work from a few sentences that have happened to survive, frequently as a quotation in
another work of literature. Art theory is no exception to this rule. The
De architectura by the Roman architect Vitruvius (late first century B.C.)
is the single completely preserved ancient treatise that deals directly
and exclusively with art, but its subject matter is architecture; it refers
to the representational arts only in passing, and it does not provide a
theory of painting and sculpture. Yet can we really assign the absence
of treatises on the representational arts only to the randomness of
survival? As Jakob Burckhardt has noticed, among the numerous titles
of lost books transmitted to us by Diogenes Laertius not a single one
indicates a treatise on painting or sculpture. And the Sophists, who
paid such careful attention to technique in all fields of human endeavor, seem to have disregarded the representational arts altogether
(with the exception of Hippias of Elis, who is said to have "talked
about painting and sculpture"; d. Philostratus, Vitae sophistarum I. 11).1
Compare this state of affairs with the many treatises (extant or known
to have existed) on music, poetry, and rhetoric, and the absence of
discussions of the representational arts becomes clearly not merely a
matter of texts that happen not to have survived.
Is it not possible, one is tempted to ask, that the paradox of familiarity with the works themselves and the absence of a coherent theory
reflect an ambiguity inherent in the Greek and Roman view of the
representational arts?
The elusiveness of ancient thought on the visual arts is compounded
by the strange fact that classical culture did not have a specific term
for what we now call art. Probably closest to our modem concept is
the Greek term techne (TEXV1]) and its Latin equivalent, ars. When
examining these terms, one is struck by their exceedingly wide scope,
which almost makes them unusable in our discussion. Techne (or ars) is
not limited to fine arts but rather denotes all kinds of human skills,
crafts, or even knowledge. Thus, one can speak of the art of agricul2
Antiquity
Theories
Plato to Winckelmann
opinions were held regarding the artist? Two great cultural traditions
form our principal sources: the doctrines of the philosophers and the
teachings of the workshop. Let us now tum to these sources.
II. THE PHILOSOPHERS
The philosophers of Greece and Rome did not contribute directly to
the theory of the visual arts. They were usually quite removed from
the workshop experience, and whatever they may have had to say
about painting and sculpture is fragmentary and marginal to their thought,
although sometimes indeed they offer surprising insights into the artist's work, and, above all, they formulate the conceptual framework
for the discussion of art in most later ages. But they reflect and helped
to establish the broad cultural context in which the visual arts were
viewed in Antiquity.
I.
PLATO
Antiquity
ical reality is but an approximation of "absolute existence" (Le., of the
Ideas) but falls short of them (Phaedon 74b ff.) and is therefore only
their "image" (Phaedros 250b). Plato's use of the term "image" shows
that his theory of imitation is closely related to his hierarchical conception of reality. The pictorial image is never more than an approximation of the material object that it imitates; it is never a true copy
of it. "I should say rather that the image, if expressing in every point
the entire reality, would no longer be an image. . . . Do you perceive
that images are very far from having qualities which are the exact
counterpart of the realities they represent?
"Yes, I see." (eratyius 432b, d).
Imitation is, then, never more than a suggestion or evocation.
The classical formulation of this view is an often quoted passage in
Book X of the Republic, where Plato introduces the famous example of
the couch. 5 There is only one form or idea of the couch. The carpenter
imitates this idea by making a certain couch of a specific material and
in a concrete form. The painter who represents the couch does not
actually reproduce the craftsman's product; he portrays only its optical
appearance, the couch as he sees it from a certain angle, in a certain
light, and the like. The painter is thus twice removed from lasting
reality, that is, from the idea.
Plato's rejection of pictorial imitation is based on the illusionistic
character of painting. Sense perception is confused, and the realm of
optical experience, on which painting is based, is devoid of truth. "And
the same objects appear straight when looked out of water, and crooked
when in water; and the concave becomes convex, owing to the illusion
about colors to which the sight is liable. Thus every sort of confusion
is revealed within us; and this is that weakness of the human mind on
which the art of painting in light and shadow, the art of conjuring,
and many other ingenious devices impose, having an effect upon us
like magic" (Republic X. 602c-d). Skillful uses of perspective and
polychromy are therefore denounced as imposture and jugglery. The
painter is also compared to a revolving mirror: "you would soon enough
make the sun and the heavens, and the earth and yourself, and other
animals and plants, and furniture and all the other things of which we
were just speaking, in the mirror."
Antiquity
Behind Plato's condemnation of visual imitation one sometimes senses a different attitude, an awareness of the symbolic significance of
the act of artistic creation. This attitude is only vaguely intimated-it
can never be firmly established-but, given Plato's overwhelming impact on European thought, even this shade of meaning was influential.
It can perhaps best be grasped in Plato's view of the universe as a
work of art created by the divine artist. By imitating the world of
Ideas the divine artist fashions the real world. The word used for the
divine artist, "Demiurge," is a word the Greeks, and Plato specifically,
also applied to an artisan engaged in useful activity, as a rule of a
manual type. The physical world created by the Demiurge is of course
not able to match the world of unchangeable ideal patterns at which
the Demiurge looked when he was shaping the cosmos, but within its
own limitations it is "likely and analogous" to the world of Ideas
(Timaeus 29c). It is somehow implied, though never expressly stated,
that the artist may sometimes be granted the ability to envision ideas
or eternal patterns.
Within the specific medium of painting Plato distinguishes between
artists who are altogether dependent on sensory impressions and poietic
painters who are not wholly engulfed by the world of physical objects
and optical appearances, but retain a certain independence. The poietic
painters, deliberately directing their glance to one side or the other of
what they represent, and thoughtfully and attentively blending their
colors, "produce . . . that human image in the conception of which
they let themselves be guided by what Homer described as divine and
godlike when met with among mankind" (Republic VI. 501). The poietic
painter is perhaps endowed with the ability to create images of examplary figures, in a sense "likely and analogous" to the unreachable
ideal. Here Plato does not speak of individual, historical artists. But in
another context he refers with admiration to Phidias as an "outstandingly fine craftsman" (Meno 91 d). In his admiration for Egyptian art
Plato attributes to it some of the qualities--especially rationality and
permanence--that are characteristic of the real or the eternal patterns.
"Ten thousand years ago . . . paintings and reliefs were produced that
are no better and no worse than those of today, because the same
artistic rules were applied in making them" (Laws II. 656e ff.).
7
Theories
I?f Art:
Antiquity
example, in Republic VI. SOla-c): the first consists in preparing a clean,
probably white surface; the second is the outlining, the drawing of a
contour. (Plato does not actually say much about this step, but his
remarks seem to have some relation to "measuring"-perhaps the establishing of correct proportions-and from the context it follows that
he endowed this stage with particular significance.) The third step is
"shading and coloring." A picture, finished as regards its outlines, reaches
completion only by the addition of the appropriate and correct colors
(Statesman 277b). Of shading and coloring, though they are only "completion," Plato speaks more often than of the other stages, and he
shows greater familiarity with the details. Thus, he is aware that this
particular step is open-ended. In the Laws (769b) the Athenian says in
the tone of somebody presenting common knowledge: "You know how
painting a picture of anything seems to be a never-ending business. It
always seems as if the process of touching up by adding color or relief
(or whatever it's called in the trade) will never finally get to the point
where the clarity and beauty of the picture are beyond improvement."
In summarizing our brief observations we can say that the conflict
indicated at the beginning of this chapter is clearly manifested in Plato.
Both his attitudes to the visual arts-the outright condemnation, and
the half-mystical fascination-became authoritative sources of inspiration in the history of ideas and, at different periods, were factors of
great weight in determining the appreciation of the arts and of artists.
2.
ARISTOTLE
Aristotle paid only slight attention to the visual arts, and the few remarks that are pertinent to our subject cannot be construed as an
articulate theory of art; unlike Plato, he does not seem to have been
fascinated by the visual arts. 7 But some of his general concepts became
crucial in the art theory of later periods, and they should be briefly
discussed.
Aristotle's general philosophy is a fertile soil for the growth of art
theory. Broadly speaking, in his thought on nature and the human arts,
he replaced Plato's dualism of Idea and Appearance with the notion of
a relationship between Matter and Form. The concepts of Becoming
and Producing therefore play an important part in his doctrine. Unlike
9
Antiquio/
Aristotle's answer is ambiguous. His formulation-"it is his knowledge of his art, and his soul, in which is the form, that move his
hands"-reflects a problem rather than gives an answer: Is it the individual artist's personality, or is it art as an objective, superindividual
tradition that is considered the creator of the work of art? In other
treatises he seems to suggest the individual artist, or craftsman, as the
source of the work. In Book VI of Metaphysics Aristotle, speaking of the
causes of different things, says, "but from art proceed the things of
which the form is in the soul of the artist" (1032a 32). In De anima he
calls the soul "the place of forms" (429a 27 ff.), and earlier in the same
work he defines more precisely the place within the soul in which the
form dwells: it is "the thinking part of the soul" (429a 15 ff.). Bernard
Schweitzer, in his study, "The Artist and the Artistic in Antiquity,"S
stresses the significance of this last sentence: Aristotle, he says, sees in
a specifically intellectual element the origin of the creative process; the
"form" that dwells in the soul is not just a group of impressions
gathered from the external world and stored in one's memory; it is an
"idea," something one knows. But, whatever the precise meaning of
"form" and "soul" in this particular context, it is clear that Aristotle
here seems to consider the individual artist or craftsman, rather than
an impersonal techne, as the moving force of the process.
Elsewhere, however, Aristotle seems to suggest tradition itself as the
creator, some kind of collective, impersonal artist. His examples refer
to architecture (De neneratione anima/ium 734b 17), but they can also
include sculpture. Thus, he says once that what happens in nature
spontaneously-for example, the restoration of health-must be premeditated in art, and the premeditation should be of the same kind as
the work produced. "The products of art, however, require the preexistence of an efficient cause homogeneous with themselves, such as
the statuary's art, which must necessarily precede the statue; for this
cannot possibly be produced spontaneously" (De partibus anima/ium 640a
30 ff.). The cause of the statue, then, is not the spontaneous artist,
motivated by emotions or even by forms dwelling in his soul, but the
statuary's techne itself.
Aristotle's appreciation of sculpture (which can sometimes be sensed)
is probably related to his conceiving this art as governed by rules.
I I
Theories
if Art:
Antiquity
Poetics, is the action of men. He is thinking mainly of the arts using
"rhythm, language, and harmony," that is, of the theater, but he finds
the same definition also valid for the arts employing "color and form"
(Poetics 1447a 18 ff.). Such imitation can have different levels. The objects the imitator represents are actions of men: "it follows that we
must show men either as better than in real life, or as worse, or as
they are. It is the same in painting. Polygnotus depicted men as nobler
than they are, Pauson was less noble, Dyonisus drew them true to life"
(Poetics 1448a 3 ff.). Whomever the artists referred to may have beena matter of dispute among classical scholars-Aristotle clearly has a
hierarchy in mind. But a hierarchy of what? Did the painters mentioned differ from each other by portraying different people and/or
actions, or did they represent the same people and actions but in
different manners? Is the difference between them one of ideas and
subject matter or one of form and style?
Partisans of the first interpretation may perhaps find some support
in Aristotle's view (not directly related to painting) that Homer's personages "are better than we are," whereas those appearing in parodies
are worse (PoetiCS 1448a 12 ff.). In a remarkable passage of the Politics
(1340a 32 ff.) we read that "young men should be taught to look, not
at the works of Pauson, but at those of Polygnotus, or any other
painter or sculptor who expresses moral ideas." Those who favor a
more formal interpretation may invoke a tradition (formulated in writing later than Aristotle but persistent throughout Antiquity) that ascribed measurability and precision to Polygnotus. Quintilian (/nstitutio
oratoria XII. 10. 3) attributed to him simplex color (which can only mean
that he used few and pure colors, and this in turn suggests a linear
style); and Aelian (Variae historiae IV. 3) ascribes to him "precision,"
which also suggests a linear style. And the predominance of line, as we
have seen, was considered superior, and may well also have carried
some moral connotations. The meaning of these passages has not been
sufficiently elucidated in the many discussions from Seneca to Boileau,
nor has modern philological research achieved any definitive clarification.
As we have seen, the visual arts had only marginal significance for
Aristotle, and his acquaintance with them was rather limited. His maIJ
Theories
if Art: From
Plato to Winckelmann
XENOPHON
Antiquity
facets. The painter represents bodies "that are high and low, in light
and in shadow, hard and soft, rough and smooth, young and old."
These qualities are not only structural but are also textural, and since
Xenophon never implies the sense of touch, the textural qualities ("hard
and soft, rough and smooth") should also be understood as visual qualities.
However, the main question that Socrates raises transcends the realm
of the visible or, perhaps, shows its profundity. Is the visible diaphanous so that what is hidden behind it can shine through? Turning to
the painter, Socrates asks: Do you also represent the "disposition of
the soul," or is this impossible? Now it is the painter's tum to insist
on sheer visibility. "How could such a thing as a state of mind be
represented," since it "has neither proportion nor color . . . and which
it is not even possible to see at all?" But Socrates considers the expression of emotions (and of character, we should add) an essential quality
of the work of art. "And the representation of the passions of men
engaged in any act, does it not excite a certain pleasure in the spectators?" he asks in Cleito's workshop. Of course it does. But how can
this be achieved? How can the invisible be made to appear on the level
of visual experience?
Socrates'--or Xenophon's-answer is a formulation of both the
problem of expression, as discussed in aesthetic thought ever since,
and of a fundamental principle of classical art, and of the art that
follows the classical tradition. Let us speak in modem terms: Socrates
does not assume any direct contact between a mood and an artistic
form. To use a formulation favored by some contemporary philosophers: sadness itself is not black; nor is joy itself bright. What Socrates
suggests is that the artist portray real human beings, as they really look
and as they change under the impact of emotions. Everybody daily
reads people's moods from their faces and gestures. "Is it not often
observable in a man that he regards others with a friendly or unfriendly look?" Socrates asks. Everyone knows that it is. This look can
be represented in shapes and colors because it appears in our visual
experience. Aristotle, as we know, also considered the expression of
emotions a principal task of "imitation," but for him the medium of
imitation was action, and he therefore saw the actor's art-an art that