Test Pensamiento Crítico Cornell
Test Pensamiento Crítico Cornell
Test Pensamiento Crítico Cornell
ED 003 818
24
65
.U. i. DEPARTMENT
OM* of Education
pylon
This document
or organ :Anionhas been reproduced exactly as received from the
Noted do not me pertly
PosWon or policy.
---afTRA/.-11DUCTIVE
REASONING IN ADOLESCENCE)
1965
0-1)3213
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
Frederick Stutz.
Project staff members, who gave far more than required of them,
of Education is great.
grants.
RHE and DP
ii
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Acknowledgements
1211t.
ii
List of Tables
vii
List of Graphs
Chapter No.
I
Introduction
I-1
II
II-1
III
-1
-1
-3
-3
-4
-4
-5
-5
-7
-7
IV
-2
-3
-8
-8
-8
-8
-9
iii
-1
-3
-4
-5
-6
-6
-7
-15
-16
-18
-26
-27
III-1
:1?
-19
-25
.25
iv
Chapter No.
2. Construct Validity
IV
13211.
-26
-26
-29
-33
-33
-36
V-1
-1
-2
-6
-6
-8
-10
-10
-10
-11
-11
-11
by age ]1 -12?
-12
48
G
g
The
......
Is there a development of logical
ability as children grow older?
2. Does the development come in stages?
3. Is conditional logic mastered by age
11-12?
4. Is class logic mastered by age 11-12?
5. Is the truth-valid:sty characteristic
achieved by age 11-12?
6. Within each type of logic, is there a
development of one sort of thing before
another? If so, what is the nature of
this differential development?
a. Differential Development of Knowledge
of Principles of logic.
1. The Fallacies
2., The Converse
3. The Contrapositive
4. Transitivity
5. The Comparability of the Two Types
of Logic.
-13
-14
-14
-17
-22
-25
-28
-29
-29
-29
-32
-33
-35
-36
Chapter No.
VI
Page,
-37
-41
-41
-42
-43
A. What Is Readiness?
VI-1
-1
1. Capacity and Willingness
-2
2. Dispositional Terms
-3
3. A Double Disposition
-3
4. Elusiveness of Readiness
5. A Substitute for the Identical Person
-4
-6
6. Suitable Conditions
-8
7. Summary
B. The Literature
-10
C. Procedures
1. Assignment of Grade Levels to Class
-10
and Conditional Logic; The Pre-Test.
-10
2. Total Teaching Effort
-11
3. The Actual Teaching
-14
4. The Post-Test
D. Results
-14
-15
1. General Qualifications
-18
2. Whet Did Our Subjects Learn?
a. Conditional Reasoning
-18
1. Total Scores
-18
-19
2. Component Scores
-21
3. Item Group Scores
-24
4. &mar/ and Possible Import for
Teaching
-25
5. Learning Words vs. Learning Logic.
-26
b. Class Reasoning
1. Total Scores
-27
2. Component Scores
-27
-28
3. Item Group Scores
-29
4. Summary
c. Possible Explanations of the Difference -29
Between Conditional and Class Reasoning.
-30
3. Can We State What Others Are Ready To
Master?
-31
a. An &le of the Use of a Multiple
Regression Equation for Making a
Prediction.
b. Making Use of the Generated Predictions -32
-37
c. Summary and Overview
E. FUrther Research
-37
F. Chapter Summary
-38
vi
VII
VIII
The Past
A. The
B. The
C. The
VII-1
-6
Summary
A. Introduction: The Statement of the Problems VIII-1
-2
B. The Nature of the Subject-Matter: Logic.
-5
-8
-9
-11
-11
-19
-21
-23
Roa
R-3
Appendix
A.
B.
C.
C-8
C-15
C-17
vii
LIST OF TABLES
II-1
II-10011.
11-2
II-12, 13.
III-1
111-2
111-3
III-80 9.
IV-1
IV-4, 5.
IV-2
IV-6, 7.
IV-3
IV-20
IV-4
IV-21
IV-5
IV-22
IV-6
IV-23
IV-7
IV -8
IV-31
V-1
V-16
V-18
viii
ELIE
V-3
V-19
Principle at
V-31
V-38
V-5
Three Components: Concrete Familiar,
Symbolic,
and Suggestive.
Rough it
Mitre Estimates of the Effort
VI-13
VI-1
Devoted to the Teaching of Each Principle
VI-20
VI-22
Taught
VI-4
Antecedent Principle:
VI-5
VII-1
A-1
Prediction Equations.
A-2
VII-7
ix
A-3
Page
Appendix
II
A-4
Indices by Grades on the Class Reasoning Test
for All Subjects on the Pre-Test.
Conditional Reasoning Adjusted-Mean Post-Test
It
A-5
Comparisons of Students to Whom Logic Was
Deliberately Taught and Students to Whom Logic
Was Not Deliberately Taught.
Class Reasoning Adjusted-Mean Post-Test Comparisons
"
A-6
of Students to Whom Logic Was Deliberately Taught
and Students to Whom Logic Was Not Deliberately
Taught.
A-7
A-8
II
II
A-10
A-12
A-14
II
A-13
II
It
It
V-1.
LIST OF GRAPHS
Conditional and Class Reasoning Mean Total Score
Page
V421
V-2.
V-23
VI-1
VI-35
Difficulty Indices and the Percentages
Meeting the Sufficient Condition and Failing
to Meet the Necessary Condition.
A-1 Plotted Points: Conditional Reasoning Mean Difficulty
Index vs. Percentage Meeting the Sufficient
Condition
Appendix
ti
Necessary Condition.
tt
tt
Chapter I - Introduction
are
ready
to
master
with
principles
of
of
1-2
eight chapters.
stcod in conjunction with the others. Probably the best order of reading
is to start with this, the introductory chapter; then to read the last, the
summary chapter; and then to read the other chapters in order (Chapters
II to VII).
headings:
Questions
IV.
Chapter Headings
INTRODUCTION
THE SUBJECT MATTER:
LOGIC
THE NATURAL-CUIMMAL
DEVELOPMENT OF
KNOWLEDGE OF LOGIC
I-3
Questions
VI.
Chapter Headings
THE DEVELOPMENT OF
READINESS TO
MASTER LOGIC
it would
appropriate,
a section clarifying the problem,
prior
empirical findings
contribution of
empirical work.
These
Chapter II.
In this chapter
of the
items) should be
LOgic
contemporary issues in
logical theory.
by B. Othanel Smith:
creative thinking.
(1953, p. 130).
been produced.
This distinction between critical
parts the problem of
in two
(critical thinking),
But
established criteria.
11.2
usage, but feel that so long as one is clear about Which notion he is using and
is workable.
thinker.
the selection, "A Definition of Critical Thinking" (Ehnis, 1964a), or in the more
Something is an assumption.
A theory is warranted.
in judging value statements, for the time being that proficiency is excluded from
our list because value statements constitute one area where fairly well estab-
critical thinking, as analyzed above. First of all, since it deals with the
question of whether a statement follows necessarily from another statement or
statements, it is at least central to the first of the nine aspects listed above.
II-3
However, though opinions may differ on this matter, deductive logic does
considerations.
seem as strict as that in the model provided by deductive logic. The correct-ness
of this claim about the relation between premises and conclusions and the
nature of the relationship that does exist are important topics for philosophi-
cal research.
granted that deductive logic plays at least a major role in tht first aspect
of critical thinking.
Secondly deductive logic plays
be investigated.
name de-
so grouped.
11.4
Sentence Logic.
Sentence logic is concerned with arguments in which the basic units are
sentences.
logical connectives as 'if', 'only if', 'then', 'and', 'or', 'not', and 'both',
appear essentially unchanged throughout the course of the argument.
Here is an
Ling
Tom may use paints.
Then would this be true?
Tom has cleaned up his clay work.
In that series the two sentencea, "Tom may use paints" and "Tom (or he) has
statements they are joined by the logical connective, "only if", but these two
basic sentences appear essentially unchanged throughout the course of the argu-
ment.
or
conditional arguments.
called
conditional reasoning.
nective, 'or'; 'disjunctive statements' those which use the connective 'not...both';
One
11-5
and 'conjunctive statements' those vthich contain the conjunction 'and' (Cohen
applies the
Al-
choice will have to be made in the continuation into these areas. The choice
phy of
in a 'not...both' statement
sepa-
rate name 'disjunction', and because the names of the former system seem more
natural.
Class Logic.
The familiar traditional syllogisms are arguments in class logic form, but
necessary.
are to be applied. It
is from
11.6
given statements present relationships between the first and second classes and
the third and second classes respectively. The statement about Which one must
decide suggests a relationship between the third and first classes. Thus the
subjects and predicates as represented by the classes are the basic units in
this kind of reasoning.
Admittedly the representation of subjects and predicates by classes is a
simplification which can result in philosophical problems. However, as long as
one is cautious enough to avoid thinking that the class relationships somehow
more suitably capture the meaning than the original statements, the transformations can be convenient in explanation and teaching.
CTdinalLogic.
A third type of logic deals with size relationships, such as, greater than,
equal to, leEs than, not greater than, etc. Here is an example taken from Bunt's
"Graded Reasoning Tests" (1919):
Tam runs faster than Jim; Jack runs slower than Jim. Who is the
slovest
Jim, Jack, or Tom?
even been prepared, so the best we can do here is to list some other types with
an explicit disavowal of comprehensiveness.
Mathematical reasoning is such that the conclusion is supposed to follow
necessarily from the premises and would therefore be classified as logic. Since
II-7
(1957, p. 58), alethic logic (traditionally called 'modal logic'), epistemic
logic, and deontic logic. Alethic logic is concerned with statements of possibility and necessity; epistemic logic with knowledge statements; and deontic
logic with statements of obligation. Each of these branches of logic is important in critical thinking, but no one of them has yet been sufficiently worked
out for us to do research on them of the sort which is being described in this
report.
terest in these fields will continue, so that some satisfactory criteria will
be available for use in research like ours.
Presumably other types of logic could yet be identified, because no one
has successfully presented a rationale for the exhaustiveness of some list,
and it has been our experience that numerous examples of inferences that seem
in a way necessary do not clearly and =controversially fit any of the types
mentioned.
statements containing such words as 'probably' and 'because' are the sorts of
thing we have in mind.
There is thus still much philosophical spadework to be done, both in
identifying types of logic and in determining vslid patterns of inference for
the relatively unexplored types. Until this philosophical spadework is done,
the investigation of patterns of development, learning, and learning capacity
in the types of logic must remain unfinished.
The criteria for judging arguments in these forms of logic are fairly
avoided it.
2.
These two types of logic, together with the other kinds of sentence logic,
are the things most commonly taught under the heading, "deductive logic", are thus
well associated with the term, 'deductive logic'. We felt that we were forced to select
from among the branches of sentence logic because of time
pressures, and picked conditional logic because the if-then relationship is
you read the next two reasons for our selection of certain types of logic, because
they argue for the inclusion of sentence logic instead of only conditional logic.
3.
occurred there.
of
obligation.
4.
We did include
it
to two.
11-9
is in order.
most
elegant form (for the more elegant they are, the less easy they are for most
people to understand),
With but one exception the principles are tested for in our tests, which will
be described later.
given in Chapter IV, which describes the
tests.
These combinations are not listed here.
as follows:
the
symbolic form. The argument on the right is an example taken from one of our
classroom presentation.
Principle
1. Given an
Symbolized Argument
if-then sentence,
then-part.
If p, thenq.
P.
Therefore q.
Valid.*
If p, thenq.
Concrete Argument
blue,
house,
Not p.
Invalid.
Therefore not q.
Logic
q.
Therefore p.
Invalid.
If p, then q.
Not q.
Therefore not p.
part.
Valid.
If p, then q.
is transitive.
If q, then r.
Therefore, if p,
then r.
Valid.
Smith's.
the bridge.
The
validity status of the arguments will only be specified for the symbolized ones.
It is the same in each
case for both the symbolized and concretearguments.
non-symmetric.
8.
part.
other part.
11.
part.
If p, thenq.
Therefore, if
not q, then
not p.
Valid.
If p, thenq.
Therefore, if
q, then p.
Invalid.
If the chair is
p only if q.
Therefore notp.
Not q.
Valid.
p only if q.
p.
Therefore q.
Valid.
the kitchen.
year.
Therefore notq.
p only if q.
Valid.
q.
Thereforep.
Invalid.
library is closed.
P only if q.
Not p.
Therefore notq.
Invalid.
year.
TABLE II-2.
Principles
Symbolized Arguments
Concrete Arguments
1. Whatever is a member of
2. Whatever is a member of
a class is also a member of
a class in which the first
is included. (Thisimplies
Therefore it is false
Valid.
3. Whatever is a member of a
transitive.)
4. Class exclusion is
symmetric.
Invalid.
Therefore no B's
are Jane's.
are A's.
Valid.
Therefore no A's
6.
Valid.
B's.
All the
None of John's
first.
Therefore at least
A's.
Valid.
On the other hand the principles of class logic are not strictly in a recommended teaching order, since our teaching method for class logic makes
use of
the circle system mentioned earlier. But we think that the first four of these
principles are grouped roughly in teaching order anyway.
A few words of summary of these principles are in order.
The conditional
principles cover affirming and denying the antecedent ("if-part" and "major part")
and consequent ("then-part" and "only-if-part") in both if-then form (1-4) and
the conditional logic principles. A person familiar with conditional logic will
recognize these as the basic elements of conditional logic, though he mightof
course feel some redundance if he seeks logical elegance.
spite of this sort of redundance, the principles must at least for teaching purposes be spelled out to the extent that we have done so. And then there is the
very difficult question of whether they really are redundant anyway, because the
different forms (as we have specified them) are used under different circumstances.
groups: those starting with the assumption that something is in* a class (or
part of a class), (2,3,8) and those starting with the assumption that something
is not in a class (or pert of a class), (5,6,7). Each group is then subdivided
into three parts according to whether that class (or part of a class) is
included in a
third (8,7).
third
(2,6),
.0
c) is excluded from a
1I-15
We regard class principles numbered 2 and 3 as the two mast important to
teach to someone if he does not know them. Number 2 catches the transitivity
of inclusion while number 3 catches its non-symmetry.
A good way to grasp the impact of the class principles, if the arguments
do not suffice as explanation, is to use circles inside one another or separate
or
from one another to represent the inclusion at exclusion relationships.* A
conclusion inescapably diagrammed by the diagramming of the premises follows necessarily.
ix-16
Piaget's logic have also been presented by Parsons (1960) and Revell (1963).
Points of Correspondence.
First of all Piaget did talk about logic. Secondly he does distinguish
between two types of logic, and thirdly this distinction basically seems to
correspond to the distinction between class logic and sentence logic that we
drew' earlier in the chapter.
Piaget seems to have adopted some of the basic moves and definitions in
He
makes use of the same letters as are traditionally used to represent propositions,
'p', 'q', and 'r'.
Along with us, Piaget resists the contemporary trend toward the merging
floating bodies are light', is transformed into the statement, 'For every x, if
x is a floating body, then x is light'.
Henceforth in this section on Piaget, all references made by the use of '1958'
shall be to Inhelder and Piaget's The Growth of ical Thinki From Childhood
to Adolescence. We believe that the parts to i
we re er were wr
en
Piaget and not Inhelder.
II-17
Sometimes the transformation goes further, putting the statement in terms
of existence, conjunction, and negation, making the above statement look like
this: 'It is not the case that there exists an x such that x is a floating body'
and x is not light.'
One of Piaget's reasons, with %thich we are in sympathy, is that to so
interpret class inclusion statements would be to use "a complex language for
describing phenomena which do not go beyond much simpler structures in the
subject's mind" (1958, p. 280).
3.
the distinction between propositional and class logic and our basis for the distinction between sentence and class logic. Piaget says that although class logic
does deal with propositions, "decomposing and recomposing the content of propositions" (1958, p. 292), it does not deal with the combination of these proposi-
seriations, etc."
(1950, p. 149).
Thus for Piaget, as for us, class logic is concerned with the internal
features of propositions which are not themselves composed of other propositions, whereas propositional (and sentence) logic is concerned with the relations between propositions (or sentences) which themselves remain essentially
His term,
'propositional' is in more common use among logicians; for that reason we would have
chosen it if we had not felt that communication with teachers and students
will be
II-l8
them.
in philosophy of logic, but the use of one term or the other does not necessarily
commit one to one of the positions, since the choice of one term or the other is
often simply a matter of convention or convenience. The positions that can be
marked by these terms are positions about the nature of the basic units that are
connected and modified by the logical connectives, 'or', 'if..., then', 'and',
'not', etc_
second.
person's reasoning is the extent to which he works within a system of all the
possible combinations of the variables and views what he
11-19
11-20
It is because of these statements and statements like them that we suspect
that Piaget holds that a definitionally necessary condition for the use of
propositional logic is that of working within a system which contains all the
possible combinations of the variables, and that a definitionally necessary
condition for the use of class logic is the lack of working within such a system.
What it is to work within such a system still remains to be clarified and un-
fortunately Piaget dces not make himself fully clear. Here is the best account
that we can work out:
According to Piaget, given two propositions (or classes), there are sixteen
possible ways in which they can be grouped. For propositions he calls these ways
the "sixteen binary operations" (1958, p. 293) and for classes he simply lists
them as "sixteen possible combinations" (1958, p. 277). The two lists correspond,
as he indicates in a series of footnotes in his discussion of the sixteen binary
operations (1958, pp. 293-303), so one will present only the list of the sixteen
binary operations.
In this list 'p' and 'q' stand for propositions. A denial of the proposition
is represented by the symbol with a line over it, e.g.,
A conjunction of two
propositions is shown by putting a dot between them e.g., 'p.q' which means
'Either p or q' is represented by 'p v q', and 'If p, then q' is
represented by
The sixteen binary operations:
v pq vv
6.
14.
pq
The negation of #3:
p v q
The negation of
p)q
The negation of
p.q
#5: 5.i
#7:
ci,P
The negation of #9: p.q
(p
q)(q,p)
p(q v q)
The negation of
q.(p v
of
#13:
v -q")
#15: "ci.(p v
11-21
A person acquainted with symbolic logic can see that (given the symbolic logic
interpretation of these symbols) this list contains the affirmation and denial
of each of the possible groupings of p and q and their denials. For him who is
not well acquainted with symbolic logic the exhaustiveness of the combinations
that Piaget sees perhaps can be shown thusly:
Let 'a' stand for 'p. q'
These are the four possible conjunctions of the assertion and denial of
'q'.
and
Then there are sixteen possible ways that 'a', 'b', 'c', and 'd' can be
grouped:
c
d
A.
B.
ab
ac
ad
1.
be
bd
ad
2.
abc
abd
acd
bcd
abed
0 (that is, none of them)*
If one accepts the assumptions, one can see the exhaustiveness of the gyitem of
possibilities.
temporary interpretation.
ficient if he does not operate within such a framework, but it would not deny the
II-22
application of the tem 'propositional logic', to the following argument,
if
advanced by a person who was not aware of nor working within a complete combinatorial framework:
If p, then q. But not q.
Therefore not p.
the greater simplicity of the system that he advocates. His system is more simple
in several different ways:
a.
given to the symbols shows that Piaget is accepting the reduction. of the various
logical operators to two: conjunction and negation.* FOr example, for him, 'If
T1, then q' means the same as 'It is not the case that both p and not q'. Symbolically,
:11 =
tpce
Common practice is to accept the above symbolic equivalence, but to deny that
'Ip:)q! captures the meaning of 'If p, then q'.
we mention the fact that prominent contenders are P. F. Strawson and P. H. Grice,
toward
supporting it.**
* Another way of looking at it is to say that the reduction is to 'v' and negation,
.
11-23
Our system differs from Piaget's in that we do not accept this reduction and
simplification
in our teaching of logic, but in the tests we built to determine a person's
not one that is accepted in the field of logic. First we must explain what a
propositional !Unction is and then we shall indicate the possible significance
of this merging.
Consider the statement, 'If a body floats, then it is light'. Although
body'
floats',
Since it does
not
meaning they have in that original statement, because they cannot stand alone
as a statement in propositional
II-24
Nov why
might
sitional logic? This is a difficult question and we can only hazard a guess, a
guess that does fit in with an earlier-suggested point of
noncorrespondence, his
casbinitorial criterion.
Note that the statement, 'If a body floats, then it is light' means roughly
the same as 'All floating bodies are light', the latter clearly being a statement
in class logic.
Given these
roughly
use either one he wishes as an interpretation of the thought that all floating
bodies are light.
or class reasoning, his criterion, is, say, the combinitorial criterion, then he
can adjust the form of the sentence selected to fit the decision called for by
the criterion.
To be more specific, suppose that on the basis of the subject's total behavior, we
within a framework
if-then form to
light,
sidering the
Suppose on the other hand that the subject is not operating within a framework that
considers
pick the class form of the thought that all floating bodies
We say that the subject is considering the view, 'All floating bodies
are light'.
Perhaps Piaget did not merge propositions and propositional fUnctions for
'propositional' and
'class'.
taught
11-25
logic that he investigated.
c. A lest simplification is Pieget's apparent
(see
mean
cover moves in alethic logic. Fbr example he wants to let
that each conjunction, 'p.q' and
represents a possible state of affairs.
The standard symbolic logic interpretation is that
v q':
is
E. is
endorses
is invalid.
Premise:
p.q. v
Conclusion:
p and not q, then p does not imply q, other things being equal. So Piaget has
particular
float and
1 Lril
"I
...
with 2.
* Assuming that
11-26
The statement being disproven in this selection is represented by tiv:)ce.
the rules of elethic logic (which are not yet well worked out, by the way).
In subsuming elethic logic under propositional logic, Piaget has done some
Thus there are points of similarity and points of difference between the
logic with which we worked and the logic reported on by Piaget.
Similarities
are that we both seem to be dealing with logic, that we both draw a distinction
between two types of logic, and that the distinction
to a concept or term)).
11-27
operators, in the merging of propositions and propositional fUnctions, and in
opinion
that our results can probably be compared with Piaget's, but want to retain
can be
CHAPTER SUMMARY
plays
types of deductive logic, have elaborated on two very basic types, and have
happens, and in order to work with types of logic that are both significant and
as the two on
Conditional logic is in
We have
CHAPTER III.
So that our readers will,
the subjects before we attempt to present, discuss, and interpret the results
in detail. In this chapter we shall indicate the institutional nature of the groups
with whom dealt, shall comment Where necessary on the instruments we used (except for
the logic tests, to which we devote the entire next chapter), and then shall
provide summary information about our subjects. In order that
The "LDT's".
work intensively.
worked for one period per day (around 40-50 minutes) for four weeks (20 instruc-
tional days).
teaching of logic.
alternate
school district' but also comprises suburban and rural communities which were
111-2
14,500, plus about 14,500 college students. The ixn industry in this community
is college education, but there are a number of medium- and small-sized factories
as well.
No census figures that indicate the nature of the school district population
are available, since in New York State, the boundaries of school districts do not
generally coincide with political boundaries. But we can give figures that indicate some things about the occupational nature of thepopulation of the city.
Fbr
comparison purposes we are also supplying similar figures for New York State and the
United States.
TABLE III-1. Percentage Occupational Make-Up of City, New York State and the United
States*
2.
3.
United
States
10.8
25.7
New York
State
12.5
18.9
18.1
14.4
16.8
9.3
8.4
Occupation
1.
Professional, Technical and Kindred Workers
City
4.
7.1
12.4
13.5
5.
6.8
18.1
18.4
5.9
9.0
8.4
Sales Workers
5.3
7.3
7.2
8.
Unemployed
3.5
5.2
4.9
9.
Miscellaneous
13.5
13.3
18.8
*U.S. Bureau of the Census. U. S. Census of Population: 1960. VOL I, Characteristics of the Population. Part 34, New York. U.S. Government Printing
Office, Part I, United States Summary, Washington, D. C., 1963.
In this city there is a higher percentage of professional, technical and kindred
workers than in the state and the nation.
We tried to secure classes that would typify this school systewand, to the
extent that this school system is typical of the United States, that valid be more
111-3
broadly typical.
worked were very helpful and did the best they could.
tion
The "LNDT-1's".
Hence the
designation,
'LNDT'.
Since there was another set of students to which logic was not directly
taught,
system.
was not secured, and the IQ scores were not from the same
III-4
test.
These subjects were used primarily for data on the natural-cultural develop-
Chronological age.
Sex.
I.Q. score.
techniques we used to gather these data. However, we shell not here be concerned
is devoted to them.
occurred in February
This
particular grade.
Where both verbal and non-verbal scores were available, we took the
arithmetic
III -5
tested
All I.Q. testing had been done within the previous two
grade respectively.
cure fairly comparable scores from the school's records for the LDT's
and
LNDT-1's.
The
Maturity, 57S,
Less
Socio-economic status.
to obtain it.
We
approach the subject's parents and ask them, feeling that this
able.
In exactly 11
iii-6
has been our experience that lack
is a good indicator of low
hold in every
not
scheme as presented
These changes
were
Although
We
number 1.
We changed that to 6.
We changed that to 4.
5,
own businesses.
After each rater had
reliability.
procedure of flipping
to plus99.
simple
wrongs plus 27
Each test had 72 items making the possible range run ftom minus 9
This scoring procedure and many other features of the test will be
in other chapters.
That completes the presentation
THE FIGURES.
of the groups and methods and/or instru-
mean
Chronological
IQ
Gradf
SES
SD Mean
SD
Age(mos.)
Group Male Female Total Mean
SD Mean
04 UT
05 LDT
LNDT-1
LNDT-2
LNDT-1
LNDT-2
11
19
11
28
14
26
12,
23
22
47
26
49
LNDT -2
07 LDT
LNDT-1
LNDT-2
23
18
14
11
23
11
26
34
44
14
27
25
50
10
24 152.0 4.5
11
LNDT-2
28
09 LDT
LNDT-1
LNDT-2
10 LDT
LNLT-1
LNDT-2
11
12
26
13
21
o6
11
14
24
49
4o
7.9 3.1
120.4
6.9
1.9
2.0
110.013.5
08
11 LDT
14
LNDT-1 11
L2J1T-2 19
lo
17
12
11
11
18
35
26
22
1.9
4.4 1.8
1.9
30
204.07.2
206.5 6.2
102.113.6
2.0
3.5 1.9
108.111.6 4.2
SD
199.84.3 116.011.9
SDI
Post-test
Mean
ConditionalReasoning
Poet-test Pre-test
Mean
SD Wan
17 183.49.o
23
122.2
Pre-test
S
rean I
4.6 2.1
114.013.4
4.0
11.655.0
13.1
63.710.5 80.716.4
IQ
SES
TotalLDT
Grand
Total
08
19
09
12
17
31
116.8
3.8
113.8
3.7
116.3
108.4
3.5
Conditional Reasoning
Class Reasoning
Pre-test
CHAPTER IV.
In order to measure our subject's knowledge of logic, we found it necessary to develop our own instruments, there being no instruments available that
acquired.
of mention here.
of
we shall give.
types of logic.
1919).
for
several reasons:
Possibly Burt's
instrument is adaptable (Fairgrieve, 1921), but we did not try because of other
It calls on the
(sometimes called
he was adding.
3.
is no score possible
on a type or sub-type.
IV-2
Granted that with individual testing, the
tions often get a fairly good idea of the nature of a person's difficulty with
an item, but there is danger that something else will without detection affect
the response.
sub
that
an argument is valid in which the conclusion actually contradicts the premises.
soreone might be inclined to call valid, but which really is not valid.
The
They
designed for use with any of the grades with which we were concerned (grades
4-12). Each item in virtue of its logical form was expected to play a role in
in virtue of its content it was expected to contribute to one of the three con-
tent components that we built into the test. First we shall discuss the logical
form of the items; then we shall discuss their content.
that
assigned to it exclusively,
assigned to it.
Principle Three.
class logic.
TABLE IV-1. Logical Form of and Answers to Items in "The Cornell Conditional Reasoning Test, Ppm X"
Item
Answer
for
Basic
to
If p, then q Yes
If p, then q No
: not q
: q
Form of CF4
form)
not p
If not p: then q
:
If p, then q
not p
3
-.1-
1-4
4
5
6
7
8
3
4
5
6
7
8
basic form
: not q
If p, then q
Maybe
Same as
Maybe p
If not p, then q
Maybe
basic form
If p, then q No
If p, then q Yee
: p
: not q
If not p, then q
not q
: p
not q
: not p
not p
not q
If not p, then q
7 40 27 14
19
If q, then r
: if p, then r
11
24 32
37 3u 41
8 35 29 16 22 39
: not p
basic form
If p, thenq
Maybe
: p
No
p only if q Yes
P
Same as
basic form
: if q, then p
p only if q
basic form
if not p, then r
p only if q
p
61
: if not q, then p
p only if q Yes
not q
: not p
73
If not p, thenq
31
9 13 26 18 34 23
not q
Maybe Same as
Item Numbers
If q, then notp
not q
not p
No not p
not p only ifq
44 57 77 70
50
59 64
12 21 42 25 15 36
10
17 20 33 38
28
: q
: not q
: q
Basic
Fbrm,
which
was
used
for the first two concrete
familiar items (CF1 and
Item Princi-(SY
and the
CF23,
suggestive
10
1&5 If p, thenq
or 1
Answer
for
Answer
Form of CF4
Basic
to
(Same answer as basic
Form Form of CF3 CF3
form)
No
If q, then r
: r
10 p, if and only if q No
ltell If p, then q
Same as
pot p
: q
12
If q, then r
applied If q, then r
twice : not r
11
If p, thenq
Maybe
r only if q
if q
not p
: not q
basic form
not p
: not r
47
: r
Item Numbers
CF1 CF2 CF3 CF4 SY SU
67 76
r only if q
not p
: r
* 'CF' stands for 'concrete familiar', 'SY' for 'symbolic', and 'SU' for
'suggestive'.
48
54 63 58
78 6o
53 71 68
65 75
TABLE IV-2. Logical Form of and Answers to Items in "The Cornell Class-Reasoning Test, Form X"
Basic
Form, which was used
for the first two concrete
not bs.
5
6
7
8 35 29 16 22 39
2 All As are Bs. Yes All As are Bs. At least some AS are Bs. 7 40 27 14 19
All Bs are Cs
: All As are Cs.
X is an A.
: X is a B.
As are Bs. Maybe All As are Bs. At least some As are Bs.
3 3 All
: All Bs are As.
X is a B.
: All Be are As.
4
Item Numbers
11
: X is an A.
24 32 37 30 41
All As are Bs. Maybe All As are Bs. At least some As are Bs. 9 13 26
3 All
Cs are Bs.
X is a B.
All Cs are Bs.
: At least some Cs are As.
: No Bs are As.
X is an A.
As are Bs. No
5 All
No Cs are Bs.
31
18 34 23
10
17 20 33 38 28
21 42 25 15 36
are Bs.
No Cs are As.
: No Cs are Bs.
6 All As are Bs. Maybe All As are Bs. All As are Bs.
not Bs.
44
57 77 7o 59 64
Item Princi-
Form
10
11
8
3.848
2
applied
twice
12
2 & 8
or 8
applied
twice
or
2,4&5
All As are B.
X is not a B
: X is an A.
Yes
basic form)
CFI* CF2 CF3 CF4 SY* SU*
At least some Asare 48 53 71 68 65 75
not Bs.
I.
X is a non-B.
are non-Bs.
: X is a non-A.
: At least some non-Bs
No
are non-As.
X is a B.
: X is not an A.
No
Yes
55 66 52 4* 73
43 51 62 72 67 76
: No As are Cs.
basic form)
47 54 63 58 78 60
46 69 74
56
61
50
IV-8
An additional logical principle
our assumption is false, the test is also a test for this prin-
ciple.
The Three Content Components.
In a frequently-mentioned study
a.
We have
are:
However, no
statements
of
objects.
subject is expected to
'A', and
be unfamiliar,
IV-9
d.
Suggestive, in which the content is familiar, but the truth status of this
In other words
the truth status of the conclusion was different from the validity status of the
argument.
make a difference.
generally
not know what to do with the conclusion anyway.
This is not to say that arguments with such content are useless in teaching,
for they can be very helpful in isolating questions of form, and they can be useful
in arousing interest, if handled properly.
are good indicators of grasp of form. But ultimately our interest is a practical
one, so we, given the testing time limits forced upon us by the situation, did not
include this type of content in our tests.
The six items in each item group were assigned to the three content components
symbolic content, and a sixth had suggestive content. There were some formal
and Table
IV-2.
It appears in
concrete familiar items, the symbolic item, and the suggestive item. The third
order to pro-vide
IV-10
Because class and conditional
variations differed.
In the conditional reasoning
the conclusion, unless
temptation to judge it
If the conclusion is
school", which is
Note that the denial of "If Sam misses the bus, then
which is awkward.
having premises in
Table
A class metbership
Item Format.
Be understandable to fourth
the supposition,
PUrthermore a brief
follows necessarily.
IV-12
instead of the two suggested by the distinction between validity and invalidity.
We vented three choices in order to lessen the attractiveness of wild guessing and to
response as
a correct answer by taking conclusions to valid arguments and then denying them.
Fbr the 'No' response, the proposed statement is then a denial of a conclusion that
follows necessarily from the supposed statement(s). A second reason for having
be invoked.
worth
the risk.
7.
A.
YES
B.
P3
C.
MAYBE
IV-13
In order to avoid possible confusion separate answer sheets were not used. Subjects
circled an answer on the right.
Although there are many strong arguments on both sides we directed students not
to guess wildly and used a scoring formula. We did this because, in addition to
the standard arguments, we feel that a critical thinking test should not encourage
wild guessing, end that part of being a critical thinker is knowing when
you do not
know.
Item Arrangement.
The first six items are sample items in each test. They are drawn from other
types of logic than class and conditional reasoning. Items 7 through 78 in each test
are divided in two parts, although the subject is not informed, of this fact. The
first part contains the item groups for the six easiest forms, as determined in our
tryouts.
The second part contains the item groups for the more difficult forms.
Thus it might be possible to cut the test in half for testing younger children or
for other purposes.
Since our item groups are generally numbered in recommended teaching order, and
not necessarily in order of increasing test difficulty,
six on the
to the subjects.
11c14
extent that our criteria are satisfactory and that the ques-
measure). Another
empirical
total
fiable observations
as follows
(abstracted from/Innis,
this specification
comes a statement of
empirical investigation.
2:principle'.
investigator;
tothe
pert judgments.
1964c):
judg-
the criterion-based
by an
Next
In
is such a chance in dealing with human beings, it is best to include such qualifiers in our operational definitions.
First we shall give an informal presentation of one of our operational defi-
nitions; then we shall give the same definition formally; finally we shall discuss some dangers in our approach.
Put informally the operational definitions of mastery of one of our principles go as follows: Given that we have administered. the "Cornell Conditional
Reasoning Test, Fbrm X" under standard conditions and have scored it according
to the key given in Table IV -l.
items 8, 16, 22, 29, 35, and 39, we can be fairly sure that he has mastered
Principle & (Given an if4hen sentence, the denial of the then-part implies the
denial of the if-Tart).
right, we can be fairly sure that he has not mastered Principle #4.
One might choose to regard the foregoing as two operational definitions or
as one.
definitions.
condition of mastery, given the operation; the second gives a necessary condition
If
Y is given
"The Cornell
Reasoning
standard
conditions;
then if Conditional
Y answers correctly
at Test,
least /bra
five of under
items
8, 16, 22, 29, 35, and 39, Y has probably mastered Principle IR.
IV-16
X" under
standard
8, 16, 22,
item group.
It is important to note that the above pair of operational
not specify a decision for a subject who correctly answers
definitions does
judged
to this fact.
Such people
group. We do not want to say that he has mastered the principle, and we do
to say that he has not mastered the principle.
that
not want
'mastery
"behaviors", as people
SD often say. A careful examination of the logical form of our definitions should
make it clear that we are not doing this.
committed to saying that no other test of mastery of these principles can attain
validity simply by virtue of the meaning of 'mastery of X principle'.
IV-17
Pressures that operated to keep down the number of items were the need to
avoid taking too much school time of our subjects, and the desirability of including
a variety of principles and combinations thereof. Given these pressures, together
with the fact that our items are so directly and clearly related to their principles,
a study of our tryout test reliabilities made us willing to utilize part scores based
This use of these part scores was fairly successful, from the point
of view of reliability.
con-
fusion with respect to those item groups which represent combinations of princ4''.es
and with respect to Item Groups #3 and
#4
not present complete interpretations of the meaning of terms, the double pair of
operational definitions of 'mastery of Principle #3' (class reasoning) supplement
each other.
Does this imply that we must have complete agreement between these two
item groups?
understandings are bound to slip in. One does not even expect (nor achieve) complete
I V 18
measures of the same thing, temperature, and are mentioned in operational definitions of 'temperature'.
A glance of the difficulty index development on class reasoning Item Groups
#3 and #4 (Table
p. 31) shows that these two item groups are not vastly
f4
rect
of principles.
dition instances,
Furthermore
mastered.
combinations thereof.
These operational interpretations
empirical dats and the
other
between
and tested in
IV-19
RELIABILITY
Because of the principle and content components of the tests) it did not
logic instruction, the LNDT-1's and the LNDT-2's. They are lumped together for
these purposes.
Accompanying these
estimates are the means and standard deviations on the pre-test for each score
on which a test-retest reliability estimate is presented.
tables.
However, a visual inspection of the reliability estimates suggests that
This
divided them into two groups and computed the mean standard error for each
group.
One group consisted of those for which the mean score on the item group
and 2.5.
were
We prefer to speak of
Type of Scoring
Score
Total
Formula
Content
CF
R
R
R
SY
su
Item
Group
Poss.
Score Mean
99
It
R
R
R
R
6
6
6
5
6
7
R
R
8
9
R
R
lo
11
12
6
6
6
6
6
Using Fisher'sZ.
SD
42.7 11.4
.76
Mean
SD
51.2 12.4
r Mean
.65
51.8
SD
Mean SD
Mean*
r
75
48 23.6 4.9 .6o 27.1 5.5 .63 27.5 5.1 .62 27.8 6.7 .74 .65
12
5.8 1.8 .48 6.6 1.9 .5o 6.6 2.0 .63 7.0 1.8 .48 53
12
4.7 2.2 .61 5.9 1.9 .4o 5.8 2.0 .62 6.o 1.9 .56 .55
1
3
Sax.
TABLE IV-4.
Total
Content
Formula
(R-W/2)+27
Score
12
12
4
5
7
8
10
11
12
R
R
R
R
6
6
6
6
6
6
R
F
6
6
6
6
.63
38.2
.80
25.5 7.6
SY
R
R
.66
.83
48
Group
1
17.9
r Mean SD r
71.4 12.0 .84 70.0 16.0 .86
43.7 15.6
R
R
SD
99
CF
su
Item
SD
Mean
Mean SD
53.3 14.9
Mean
.88 54.8
* Using Fisher'sZ.
.27
.53
Mean SD
5.1
0.8
1.2
1.7
1.3
1.2
1.0
1.7
.77
r*
.83
.79
.50
.63
.60
,55
.69
.52
.41 .38
.38 .52
.65
.76
.68
.46 .53
.45
.48
1.7 .5o
1.5 .51
1.4 .58
1.7
1.6
Mean
.52
.47
.36
.46
.41
IV-22
TABLE /V.5.
Item
Group
N = 76
Grade 05
1.1112
.92
N =75
Grade 07
Ak.
- Conditional Reasoning
64
Grade 09
51
Grade 11
i9
Jai
1.15
1.12
1.08
.84
1.14
.92
1.04
La
1.28
.98
1.16
1.01
1.04
1.00
.98
1.03
1.24
1.34
1.12
1.05
_1.12
,,
.88
1.34
1.06
.79
.86
.84
.99
.94
.74
.70
10
.98
1.15
.88
1.27
11
.99
1.25
.98
1.02
12
.85
.94
.93
.98
TABLE IV-6.
N = 71
Grade 04
1.25
N = 78
Grade 06
1.37
1.14
.64
1.o6
.72
4
5
1.19
1.08
N = 54
Grade 10
1.92
1.37
1.4o
.80
.52
.38
.95
.69
.71
.87
.98
.74
.98
.71
.92
.53
.79
Grade 12
1.09
.92
1.10
1.05
1.19
1.15
1.18
1.02
1.20
1.07
10
1.24
1.20
11
1.20
1.16
1.15
.97
1.00
1.081.25
1.111.26
1.26
12
N= 50
N = 76
Grade 08
.94
1.16
1.081.20
1.32
.76
1.05
1.15
.96
.91
Note: If the standard error is underlined, the mean score on this item group is
within 1.5 points; that is, between 2.5 and 5.5.
mean standard errors were 1.05 and 1.32 respectively, giving a difference in
item groups would be more sensitive around the mid-range than at the extremes.
As is expected, the reliability estimates for the total scores are the
largest, running from a low of .65 on the conditional reasoning test for seventh
grade to a high of .88 on the class reasoning test for sixth graders. Correlations on the class reasoning test tend to run slightly higher than on the
conditional reasoning test, the mean total score correlation on the conditional
reasoning test being .75 and on the class reasoning test .83.
The component reliability estimates are not so high as those for the total
scores, presumably because of the fewer number of items. The concrete familiar
-- with a mean of
ranged from AO
on the conditional reasoning test for seventh graders to .73 on the class
reasoning
The item group test-retest correlations ranged from .26 for Item Group #10
of the class reasoning test at grade level six to .77 for Item 0roup #1 for grade
IV-25
reasoning test is .52 and .50 for the class reasoning test.
Since these item group reliability estimates are based upon only six items
apiece and are for snores to be used with groups rather than individuals, they
are encouraging even though they average around .5. The total score reliabilities
are of course more satisfactory, but have the disadvantage of representing a
composite score, rather than a fairly pure score.
VALIDITY
hcmrnudh sense one can make out of the investigations which depend upon the
nation of validity.
validity, and sometimes
In this
on all but the last of these approaches to the determiThe last approach, which sometimes appears as concurrent
Content
Part of our argument for content validity rest, upon the procedures which ve
and
our principles,
IV-26
pointed out in Chapter II, are basic and comprehensive.
Itirtheriore we engaged in continuous consultation with members of the
Cornell Philosophy Department who are interested in logic. Professor Keith
Donnellan, who has the major responsibility in the Philosophy Department for
knowledge of logic among graduate students, has examined and taken the tests,
and judged them to be valid.
Lastly the content of the items together with the instructions is evidence
of the test's content validity.
And the answers depend upon whether one has the right answer to that question in
each case.
principles.
Not only do to principles bray the right answers to the items, but generally
speaking, getting five or six of an item group right loosely implies a knowledge
of the principles.
provenOt
is one that we rest upon the intelligent judgment of informed interested people.
Construct Validity.
In looking at the construct validity of these tests, we are looking at
the degree to which they make sense in their internal and external relationships..
This makes our concern very broad, broad enough to include concern with content
validity as veil.
scores and
IV-27
increases with age (Burt, 1919; Piaget, 1950, 1958, 1959; Hill, 1961) - until
age for our subjects when the various grades are grouped together.
expect to find any sizeable relationship between me and le%ic knowledge when
sure.
Burt (1919), Miller (1955), and Hill (1961) found no relationship, but
Sweeney (1953) found that men did significantly better on logic tests, though
combined,
one can see, substantial correlations between IQ, grade held constant, and both
tests.
This is also the case for chronological age when grades are lumped
together.
generally negative, two of the nine being significant at the .05 level. This
is insufficient proof of a small negative relationship, but should there be one,
would
This
in turn suggests the explanation that inherent mental ability is a more signifi-cant
factor in logical ability than it is in grade placement. And this in turn fits in with
the substantial relationships that were obtained with IQ. These
There are generally small positive correlations between SES and logical
knowledge, six of the nine correlations being significant at the .05 level.
The correlations between the tests and sex are small and on either side a
zero.
IV-28
TABLE IV-7.
Grade
(Separate
Grades)
(Grades
Combined)
CA
CA
IQ
SES
SEX
.24
.00
.28
.17
.13
.17
.12
.09
.20
.10
z.g
.00
lat
!Ei
-.10
-.05
.26
-.09
Conditional Reasoning
..09
53
05
07
47
.61
..09
.64
..t
09
4o
48
-.24
-.05
188
-di
.70
122
11
5,7,9, & 11
...g
Class Reasoning
VT
=as
58
-.07
49
-.12
1E2
40
-.26
.26
41
.23
LE
.40
-.22
-.12
la
.26
-.00
o4
06
112.
./
.68
08
10
12
235
4,6,8,10, & 12
Notes:
These are based upon the pre-test scores of the LDT's and the UWI.l's.
IV-29
Item Analysis.
were computed.
It is
the
natural
knowledge will
cultural
are
development
of
logic
knowledge
and
the
capacity
V and VI
for
logic
30.2 -
These
IV-30
TABLE IV-8.
Grade
N =
Item
Group
71.4
74.7
77.3
78.8
1
2
22.7
27.4
24.8
35.3
17.7
26.8
31.5
35.7
55.7
68.7
59.6
65.o
56.7
67.9
66.3
76.1
56.5
66.2
57.7
65.3
14.1
24.1
28.6
43.2
68.6
80.6
77.9
85.7
70.8
78.3
78.6
87.6
10
54.7
71.2
68.8
77.6
11
54.6
66.o
64.2
66.2
12
26.3
17.8
19.4
21.6
CF
48.9
55.4
55.2
61.8
Sr
48.1
55.8
53.4
59.5
26.319.432.0
au
41.3
53.4
53.3
59.9
29.o
26.5
21.2
19.1
34.3
26.5
22.3
31.8
28.1
27.0
19.8
29.1
Mean over
all items
47.5
55.8
54.6
61.5
32.118.934.9
-17.9
16.7
5.3
27.8
-13.0
6.2
3.8
29.4
33.924.225.4
43.224.235.7
30.813.614.3
9.322.753.2
35.231.830.9
33.321.923.0
46.339.446.0
30.228.823.0
6.23.o5.6
IV-31
TABLE IV-9. Mean Difficulty and Discrimination Indices Fbr The Class Reasoning Test,
Based Upon Pre-Test of LtT's, LEM-1's, and LNDT -2's CaMbined.,
4
94
Grade
N =
12
72
12
72
Item.
Group
1
2
76.1
55.7
90.6
64.9
91.5
67.7
93.4
82.4
95.4
82.7
53.3
32.7
22.6
27.4
21.0
37.0
5.0
15.o
10.0
20.0
30.2
42.9
49.2
66.5
75.0
24.0
40.5
39.5
39.2
45.0
43.4
42.6
47.7
58.0
66.7
20.7
23.8
31.5
25.8
34.2
64.7
70.7
66.3
80.0
79.9
30.0
14.3
19.7
10.8
22.5
61.7
76.9
79.0
86.5
87.1
40.0
26.8
38.3
15.8
25.8
33.9
38.o
36.5
58.7
63.o
44.7
37.7
31.7
46.7
37.1
42.4
51.7
67.6
71.6
28.0
41.7
43.2
38.3
45.8
51.1
56.3
58.5
66.7
58.1
41.5
20.8
32.7
17.5
26.7
10
43.6
48.2
52.5
59.3
55.3
30.0
31.6
39.5
20.8
20.8
11
52.1
62.3
66.3
79.3
78.3
38.7
27.4
45.7
19.2
38.3
12
41.7
43.9
53.2
61.1
59.7
23.3
26.8
42.6
27.5
41.7
CF
54.5
64.8
67.2
78.5
77.3
32.3
28.9
32.5
19.2
29.o
SY
43.1
44.8
46.4
55.0
61.7
22.3
20.5
25.o
24.6
28.3
SU
40.1
47.2
56.2
67.3
67.0
33.1
40.0
48.2
28.3
44.6
56.6
60.0
71.6
72.7
30.7
29.o
35.7
22.2
31.5
6.7
Mean for
all
items
Mean
49.3
Total N = 444.
IV-32
ranges extend across grades, but one can see that certain item groups are more
difficult than others.
ciples of logic are more difficult than others and are learned later. It is in
conflict with the view that one kind of logic is learned at one stage in life and
another kind learned at a later stage.
learned before parts of the other and that parts of the other are learned before
parts of the one.
The level of the mean difficulty indices (ranges: 47.5
;9-7
reasoning and lef*N.404 for class reasoning) suggests that neither test,
When administered for purposes of securing a total score, is too difficult for
grades 4-12.
Our purpose in developing this test, however, was not primarily that of
securing a total score, but rather to enable us to determine Whether a certain
principle of logic has been mastered at a given level. Hence we do not approach
the test with a preconceived idea of what the mean difficulty levels of the
item, groups should be. Instead we in a way seek to find out What the mean dif-
ficulty levels are in order to find out What is mastered and What is not.
The discrimination index pattern, in conjunction with the difficulty index
pattern, is quite interesting from the point of view of development, but as we
saidl that is the topic of the next chapter. The following observations are
relevant here:
1.
levels of administration is conditional Item Group #12. This may be because of its great difficulty (mean always below 30%). With instruction in
logic incidentally, as will be seen in Chapter VI, the item group becomes
considerably easier in grade eleven with a mean difficulty of 62%.
the early grades or the advanced grades, the former apparently because the item
group is difficult at that level, and the latter because the item group is quite
easy at that level.
All low discrimination indices are thus accounted for except the fairly
low ones in grades nine (13.6) and eleven (14.3) for Item Group #6 in conditional
reasoning.
We do not have an explanation for these fairly low indices, nor for
the fact that they are so much lower than the index for this item group in grade
five (50.6).
However, they are not embarrassingly low; they are just fairly low.
With this one exception, then, all low discrimination indices are accounted
for by the purpose of the tests, Which was to ascertain whether members of a set
list of basic principles were mastered at various levels. Unsurprisingly there
are some which at a given level are either easy enough or difficult enough to
result in low discrimination indices.
Given the purpose of these tests, the discrimination and difficulty index
patterns are satisfactory.
construct validity tries to show that the results of the use of a particular
instrument make sense.
of the construct validity of the tests. Roughly speaking the more intelligible
the results, the more valid the teat is shown to be.
Several ideas for further development of the Cornell Deduction Test Series
(or of some other deduction test series) have occurred to us before and while
IV-34
Ordinal reasoning
Principles
of
types
of
logic
other
than
class,
sentence,
and
tests with lover elementary students (grades 1-3). One possible adjustment is
can be dropped off without destroying the item group structure. Instead six
procedures for administering early editions of deduction tests to lower elementary students.
For second and third graders items were simply read aloud while they
followed along and marked answers directly on the test booklets. Testing
time was broken up into separate periods of twenty or thirty minutes apiece.
Two people handled classes of twenty to twenty -five students in this manner.
minutes, the first of these periods being devoted simply to instructions and
practice problems.
very busy.
IV-35
On the basis of this experience we feel that group logic testing with
this sort of test is possible at the lower elementary level. Incidentally Hill
(1961) tested lower elementary students in logic, but did not face the problem,
which, as we indicated early in this capteryt should be faced, of getting subjects
to judge whether an argument is invalid or not, when the proposed conclusion does
not contradict the premises.
4.
these tests and an open-ended logic test in which subjects are asked to supply
the conclusion themselves, the intent being to see the extent to which a multiple
Choice test like these can be used as evidence of ability to deduce conclusions,
given only the premises.
group, thus achieving a more reliable measure of each principle, but of course
sacrificing either comprehensiveness or compactness. Such a sacrifice will be
necessary if one wants to use the test to measure and predict individuals'
scores, as can be seen from the item group reliability estimates.
6.
Hill
found that negation was an important source of difficulty in logic for lower
elementary students (1961, p. 66). In a way the conditional reasoning test
has a negation component built in by means of the C104 items.
difficulties Which were lover at each grade level than the totel mean difficulties and the mean difficulties for each of the components. CF4 mean difficulties at grades 5, 7, 9, and 11 are respectively 38.4, 45.8, 43.3, and 50.0
as compared with total mean difficulty indices of 47.5, 55.8, and 54.6, and 61.5.
Hence negation appears to be an important source of difficulty.
IV-36
is'relatively
developed.
test-retest correlations.
Reasoning Test".
two tests.
The mean correlations for the components and item groups are
Made.
tests
and format.
CHAPTER SUMMARY
Chapter V.
or
upper New York State students whose ages range from about 9 to 18, and Whose
not teach logic to these students prior to the test administration which
THE LITERATURE
Jean Piaget is the best known and most prolific contributor to the
literature on the development of knowledge of logic: First we shall examine his
characterization of the formal operational stage, which he holds runs
bearing
on these questions.
the
formal operational period, the apex in the development of thought (e.g.,
V-2
all others...,
to see whet
actually vritten
V-3
The formal
operatignal
thinker is able to
Or even if he
p. 148).
suppositions...tend to be foreign
(1963, p. 208).
p. 252).
'what if'
validity characteristic,
disbelieves.
The suggestive component
truth-validity characteristic.
status of the argument is
To
identify
and IV -2 in Chapter
.2)
A second feature
ability to operate in
given situation.
see Tables IV -1
not
t conclusion follows necessarily';
conclusion is true'.' The latter is suggested by his choice of
words, "belief in the conclusion".
by the combinatorial
system in distinguishing between concrete ... and
formal
... operations (1958, p. 280).
Chapter II attempts to
We do not think
we shall
this characteristic.
A third feature,
3)
the variations of
the Cornell Deduction
that this
associated factors.(1158',P4M)
alleged
cally
interdependent.
the formal
control variables.
4)
possible distinction
V-5
is problematic.
possible distinction is "the one from which Piaget derives all others",
so
well.
Omitted,
synonyms.
to conditionals:
Stages.
tional period running nun 7-8 to 11-12, and the formal operational period
because
the distinction between ILIA and IIIB is not a distinction between types of
logical knowledge.
Unfortunately the question of the existence of stages is basically an
unclear question because there is lacking a criterion of how much of a
leveling off is necessary for there to be a stage. The question is essentially a pragmatic question, since the
enough of a regular leveling off for a long enough time for the
v -8
at least partly indeterminate.
notion of purposiveness.
The age range covered by the present study (roughly 10 to 18) corresponds
approximately to that of Piaget's formal operational period (11-12 onward).
Because his work on this period is so extensive and well-known, we presented
for the natural-cultural part of our study. Of the four basic features of
the formal operational period (possession of the truth-validity characteris-
The
His
these questions still leave much that is indeterminate, they are more
V-9
definite then Piaget's claims and hence are an extension and refinement of
them.
in debt to Rapt. Mese questions were suggested by his work and strike
us as theoretically interesting and practically important, from the point
of view of someone making decisions about the development and placement of
materials in a curriculum.
older?
thing before another and are some things more difficult than others at a
given level? If so, What is the nature of this differential development? Of
the above questions, we feel that the last is the most interesting
and the one toward which this study makes an original contribution. The first
question which is about whether there is development, has an unsur-prisingly
affirmative answer from the present study. The second question,
once you are pest the problem of specifying the criteria for a stage, is
stage to be.
V-10
Other Studies.
hardly logic tests), Burt (1919), Winch (1921), Moore (1929) and Hill (1961).
Miner (1955), on the other hand, did not find development in ability to
recognize fallacies in grades 10, 11, and 12. However, many of Miller's
fallacies are not fallacies of deductive logic and he worked over a span of
only two years; 80 we are inclined to feel that the weight of evidence from
the literature is in support of the initially plausible view, that there is
development of logical ability as children grow older.
Burt (1919, p. 126) and Winch (1921, pp. 138, 209, 284) found
regular improvement with grade. Hill (1961, p. 51), working with students
of ages 6-8, found regular development in their knowledge of logic. Since
Miller (1955) fbund no development in ability to recognize fallacies in
grades 10-12, his results are not inconsistent with the stage hypothesis.
On the thole, we feel that the reports of research do not support any stage
hypothesis, particularly in view of the fact that we are unable to see
support for it even in the experimental findings of Piaget himself. But because of the context dependence of the question, one must not on this basis
make a definite Judgment about the existence of stages.
Considerable research has been done Which suggests (in conflict with
Piaget's claims) that children can do at least some conditional reasoning
before 11-12; Bonser (1910), Burt (1919), Winch (1921), Woodcock (1941, p.
p. 51).
it
has been mastered by age 11-12 has not been investigated. NowIlaget does
not state that it is fully mastered by the age 11-12, but he does not indicate the extent to which he thinks it is mastered after this age is attained.
The two earlier-mentioned characteristics of the distinction between stage
ILIA and IIIB do not help, because they are concerned with empirical rather
than logical matters.
The references cited under the previous question also support the contention that at least some class logic is mastered before 11-12. And Piaget
of the basic principles of class logic are mastered by the end. of the con-
teristic of this period, according to Piaget. However, all he says is that only
class logic is used in this period (1958, p. 1). Be never specifically
So far as we can determine, Piaget is the only person Who has made
claims about the attainment of the truth-validity characteristic before age
11-12.
on older people.
V-12
ally show that suggestive arguments with content are handled less ably than
arguments with concrete familiar content, the minimum answer suggested by
these studies to the question is that the truth-validity characteristic is
not fully achieved by age 11-12; So far as we can tell, Piaget does not
commit himself to a degree of attainment of the characteristic, just as he
does not commit himself to a degree of attainment of propositional and class
logic.
Within each
J- of 1
is
thing before another and are some things more difficult than others at a
given level?
There is not much evidence on this matter. Except for his attention to
the truth-validity characteristic, Piaget seems to have ignored it.
Hill
(p. 57).
However, her test, it should be remembered, did not test for any
fallacies.
his "Graded Reasoning Tests" held that the basic mechanisms of formal reasoning are all there by the mental age of 7, and that differences are results of complexity.
All the elementary mechanisms essential to. formal reasoning are
present before the child leaves the intents' department, i.e., by the
mental age of seven, if not soneWhat before. Development consists
primarily in en increase in the extent and variety of the subjectmatter to Which those mechanisms can be applied, and in an
increase in the precision and elaboration with Which those
mechanisms can operate. The difficulty of a test depends upon
V-13
of valid and invalid arguments, class and sentence reasoning, and various
rules of inference. It would be possible, but inconvenient, to think instead in
terms of Burt's four aspects of complexity, suitably reformulated. However,
before turning to Burt's categories we should try to work with the established
ones and see if differential development exists in terms of the established
categories.
categories of logic.
cate this study, but to compare the fruitfulness of the two conceptual
schemes.
Summary.
Plaget's discussion of four basic features of formal operational thought
(possession of the truth-validity characteristic,
current study is to a greater extent concerned with the extension and refinement of his views.
The evidence of others supports the contention that there it development of logical ability; does not support the view that this development comes
in stages; suggests that the basic principles of both conditional and class
logic are not mastered by age 11-12; supports the contention that the truth
validity characteristic is not fully developed by age 11-12; and has little
to say about the differential development of principles and components of
logic.
THE RESULTS
seen in a number of ways. In Chapter IV Tables IV-8 and IV-9, which give the
mean pre-test difficulty iLdices for item groups, components, and total test,
dhows development from the lowest grade to the highest on all item groups
except "12 conditional, on all components, and on both tests as a whole.
Apparently Item Group "2 conditional is just too difficult for any development to dhow within the range with which we worked.
Inspection of total scores on the tests for LDT's, LNDT-1's, and LNET-2's
V-15
test scores for each grade level, all subjects combined. Again development
with advancing age and grade can be seen. )br interpretation purposes this
table also presents the mean chronological age, IQ, and estimated mental age.
Even though the IQ scores are on different tests, resulting from the combination of the LNDT-2's with the others, these scores help to explain the
larger jumps found from the 5th to the 7th grade on the conditional reasoning
test and from the 8th to the 10th grade on the class reasoning test.
Table V-1 also presents the mean pre-test scores for all subjects com-bined
on the components and item groups. Again development is in evidence
in every case except for #12 conditional. If one looks more closely at these
figures than simply inspecting the figures for the youngest and oldest, the
significance of IQ as well as age and grade is again suggested.
There are altogether 112 different steps from one grade to the next tak.
ing into consideration total, component, and item group scores.Of these 112
Let us
examine
mean IQ from one grade to the next, and that is again for Item Group #12,
conditional.
tional; 4 occur in the shift iron grade 9 to grade 11, conditional; and the
other 5 occur in the shift from grade 10 to grade 12. In the first two of
these three shifts there is an actual decrease in the mean I.Q. In the
third shift the mean IQ (120) stays the
to 7, 4 to 6, 6 to 8, and 8 to 10)
However, there are still some steps that do not quite fit the explanation
question.
TABLE V-1. Mean Chronological Age; IQ; Estimated Mental Age; and Total,
Component, and Itim Group Conditional and Class Reasoning PreTest Scores; by Grade for All Subjects Grouped Together.
Grade
N =
Chronological
Age (nos.)
IQ
Conditional Reasoning
11
05
07
09
78
102
99
8o
04
94
129
108
203
109
117
109
127
153
117
184
110
Class Reasoning
08
10
06
103
loo
75
166
113
190
120
214
120
187
44.3
159
53.4
57.8
228
71.2
256
73.4
142
112
Estimated Mental
Age (mos.) (CA x
IQ/100 before
rounding)
139
Total Score*
42.4
179
51.7
201
55.3
220
56.6
Component**
CF
SY
23.3
5.8
27.1
6.7
29.0
6.5
29.5
7.2
25.6
5.1
30.2
5.3
32.1
5.9
38.2
6.9
39.0
7.5
su
4.6
6.o
6.4
6.4
4.7
5.6
6.7
8.3
8.2
4.3
4.5
4.9
4.7
4.3
5.4
5.5
5.7
5.8
1.4
1.7
2.1
2.2
3.7
4.3
4.5
5.2
5.2
1.2
1.6
2.1
2.0
1.8
2.5
2.9
4.o
4.6
3.3
4.1
3.8
3.9
2.6
2.6
2.9
3.5
4.1
3.4
4.0
4.2
4.5
3.6
4.2
4.2
4.7
4.8
3.3
4.o
3.9
3.6
3.5
4.5
4.7
5.3
5.2
0.9
1.5
2.0
2.6
2.0
2.2
2.3
3.7
3.9
4.1
4.9
4.6
5.2
2.3
2.5
3.o
4.2
4.5
4.3
4.7
4.6
5.2
2.9
3.3
3.5
3.9
4.1
3.3
4.3
4.2
4.5
2.5
2.7
3.1
3.5
3.3
11
3.2
4.o
4.1
3.9
2.8
3.4
3.9
4.9
4.7
12
1.6
1.0
1.8
1.3
3.5
3.6
4.2
4.8
4.6
9
lo
V-17
seen
condi-
of
tion for
meet the necessary condition are those who marked correctly three or fever
of the items in an item group. Hence those subjects vho marked correctly
exactly four of an item group neither met the sufficient condition, nor
failed
add
up to 100%, the difference between 100% and the sum of the percentages given
for a given grade being the percentage who marked correctly exactly four
items in an item group.
An inspection of these two tables again shows development in logical
ability.
culty index tables (IV-8 and IV-9) and in the absolute score table (Via)
are again apparent in these necessary and sufficient condition tables.
These will be discussed under the topic of differential development.
In sumary there is quite clearly development of logical ability in
subjects like those we tested. Even though this was not a longitudinal
study, it wild be very difficult to deny the development hypothesis and
still offer a satisfactory explanation of the data.
2. ...21gAt:...eZEEELTELIELOAPAY
As indicated earlier, the answer to this question depends upon *et degree and length of leveling off shall count as a stage -- and this depends
in part upon the general context in which the question arises. Hence for
this question there are not only problems of errors and gaps in measurement
there are also problems of interpretation of the question. We are thus in
Table V-2.
Percent Meeting the Sufficient Condition and the Percent Failing to Meet the Necessary
Condition Pbr Mastery of Each Principle at Each Grade Level on the Conditional
Reasoning Test.
Grades
N =
Item
05
102
53.
Group
1
co
5
6
I7
30
25
34
10
53
46
11
26
12
23
07
99
09
8o
11
78
56 66 62
6
41
45
40
5
63
63
52
40
4
.4
35
4o
35
11
70
69
53
46
1
12
3
35
58
33
19
79
ft
58
4o
0
05
102
07
99
09
80
11
30 26 21 22
92
94
54
48
51
94
31
26
54
51
86
80
92
36
38
36
84
20
17
30
37
91
90
89
41
35
45
80
13
23
34
33
93
73
85
4o
22
47
68
9
5
23
36
95
Table 37-3.
Mastery of Each Principle at Each Grade Levelon the Class Reasoning Test.
Grades
N =
Item
Group
1
2
3
103
loo
75
72
56 79
91 92
97
34
55
80
21
44
75
44
04
94
Condition
06
103
33 10
10
12
loo
75
72
08
5 1 3
6
7
8
lo
11
12
15
10
lo
68
41
83
28
66
25
63
t5
6
22
15
24
43
71
72
68
148
32
31
37
46
63
67
4o
24
24
17
3o
56
63
83
85
15
13
35
46
83
22
79
19
17
24
37
11
47
73
4o
42 r4
1
22
lo
15
30
V-20
Graph V-1 depicts the total score vs. chronological age coordinates
for each test, making use of the means that are presented in Table V-1.
The lower line connects the points for the conditional reasoning test, and
the upper line those for the class reasoning test. Since the points are
approximately two years apart in each case, and since there are only four and
five sets of coordinates respectively, the graphs are difficult to interpret.
1k
to the question.
However, there is some indirect evidence against the existence of stages
straight line than do the points in the chronological age graph. In other
lords the degree of abruptness that is found in the chronological age graph can be
at least partially explained by variations in IQ from one grade level
to another.
Naturally this method using estimated mental age is not a precise one,
since it is based upon different tests,
so we used it.
assumptions.
Even with the mental age adjustment, there is still not exactly a
reasoning.
If so,
do not feel
90 ...Total
Score
80
70
60
50
4o
30
12
10
Class Reasoning
El
Conditional Reasoning
11
A set of coordinates
point is
is plotted for eachgrade. Each
labeled by the number
of its grade level. Source
is Table V-1.
straight lineof
200
Chronological
Age (mos.)
V-22
by examining Table V-3, which give the percentages at each grade level vho
met the sufficient condition and who failed to meet the necessary condition
at the various grade levels, as presented in Table V-10 and judge Whether any
or all of such mean scores indicate mastery. A third way is to look at
the mean difficulty indices given in Chapter IV in Table IV-8. Each of these
ways supports a negative answer to this question, whether interpreted in
terms of chronological age or mental age.
Age 11-12 years is equivalent to 132-144 months. In chronological age
this corresponds to our 5th and 6th graders, in mental age to our 4th
and 5th graders.
conditional reasoning.
is the difference among the item groups. But let us leave that fact aside
and 12.
9C--Total
GRAMMV-2. Conditional and Class Reasoning Mean Total Score vs. Mean MentalAge
Score
Class
Reasoning
70
60
Conditional Reasoning
11
50
the
reasoning test.
A set of coordinates
level.
A straight line of
I
120
140
160
180
200
220
240
260
280
V-24
roughly half of the subjects and probably not mastered by about a third
(with about a sixth falling in the borderline area). The situation in grade
5 dhows a lesser degree of mastery but on the same order as in grade T.
Hence the answer to the question that is here suggested is that there is mastery
of some of the principles by some of the people of age 11-12, but rarely (if
ever) mastery of all of the basic principles and frequent non-
for all of our subjects in grades 5 and 7 are 42 and 52 respectively out of
a possible 99.
ciples embodied in the conditional reasoning test are not mastered at this
level.
score of 80.7 reported in Table 111-3 in Chapter III for llth grade students
who have been taught conditional logic by one of our staff members.
The mean difficulty indices given in
gest that conditional reasoning is not mastered by age 11-12, the mean total
around 50%.
It should be
remembered
Such an
ithether a
V-25
In summary, it seems clear frmn any and all of the three ways of presenting the data that the basic principles of conditional reasoning are not
mastered by age 11-12, given the contemporary cultural background of these
subjects.
these students.
score on the total tent was only 57 out of the possible 99.
This is not to say that the 11th graders are incapable of mastering the basic
principles of conditional logic. It is simply that under contemporary
shown
by the performance of the 11th gradera to were taught logic by a member of
our staff.
the
next chapter.
V-26
fail to satisfy the necessary condition for the principles and combinations
corresponding to item groups 3, 4, 7, 8, 9, and 10. Only for two principles
is the sufficient condition satisfied for more than 50% of the grade 6 sub
jects.
Thus the necessary and sufficient condition tables indicate that the
basic principles of class reasoning are not yet mastered at age 11-12,
whether put in terms of mental age or chronological age.
A similar conclusion can be drawn from the mean total score, which is
given in Table V-1 as 53 out of a possible 99 for the 6th graders. And the
mean difficulty index (58%) at the 6th grade level, which is given in Table
IV-9 in Chapter IV, supports the view that the basic principles of class
reasoning are not mastered by age 11-12, though of course there are some
students who have mastered some of them.
Even the oldest subjects, those In grade 12 (mean chronological age of
slightly under 18 years and mean estimated mental age of 256 mos., or
slightly over 21 years*) have not fully mastered the basics* of class reason-
ing, although they seem to come fairly close. For only two principles have
over 80% of them attained the sufficient condition, and for five principles
(or combinations)
tion.
Their mean score on the test is 73 out of the 99 possible, and their
V-27
explicitly requests.
Probably some of them have mastered all of the basic principles, some have
mastered most and some have mastered only a few.
qualified with the word 'probably' because our analysis is of groups, not
of individuals.
Thus we do not find full mastery of class reasoning even at age 17-18.
Hence Piaget's characterization of the concrete operations *period as one in
which class logic can be done deserves qualification, if our data are taken
at face value.
jects, fully mastered during the concrete operations period. Not until
some years later is mastery of the basic principles of class logic approached.
logic scores are generally higher than conditional logic scores (this assumes
that conditional logic scores are representative of scores that would. be
Obtained on a complete sentence logic test). But it is not a matter of one
being mastered at one stage, and then the other being mastered at another
stage.
sons could be made at some other time on subjects who take both tests. But
Graphs V-1 and V-2 do suggest differences in overall performance on class
reasoning and conditional reasoning. It is the sort of difference suggested
by these graphs that supports Piaget's implicit contention that class logic
v-28
is easier than sentence logic. Naturally the support must be qualified by
the lack of tests of statistical significance, which we feel should wait
until more directly comparable scores are available.
items, of Which there were twelve in each test. These suggestive items, it
au.
will be remembered, usitsuch that the truth status of the conclusion is different from the validity status of the argument, so a person who cannot
judge the validity without being swayed by his beliefs will do poorly on
these items.
The mean difficulty indices for the conditional reasoning test suggestive items are 41.3 and 53.4 respectively for grades 5 and 7; hence the
average suggestive item was marked correctly about 41% of the time by 5th
graders and 53% by 7th graders.
ing figures are 40% and 47% for 4th and 6th graders. These percentages
indicate that there is a degree of achievement of this characteristic, but
that the achievement is not complete.
The percentages for the 11th and 12th graders on the conditional and
class tests respectively are 60% and 67%. These show greater achievement of
the truth-validity characteristic, but still indicate that the achievement
is yet incomplete.
findings
question.
V-29
6.
before another.
1)
The Fallacies.
principles (except for conditional 12) are embodied in Conditional Item Groups
2, 3, 7, and 12 and Class Item Groups 3, 4: 7, and 8. Their symbolic manifestation is also presented in the tables in Chapter IV. For quick identification in Tables IV-1 and IV-2 one can use the answer 'Maybe' as a sign of
a fallacy item group.
follows necessarily.
item groups are keyed 'Yes' and 'No' respectively. Hence items embodying
bet6er able to tell that something which follows, does follow; than that
something which does not follow, does not follow.
FUrthermol, there is generally considerable improvement among the
'Maybe' items.
for fallacy groups (8 and 7), and the fourth fallacy group (4) is among the
FUrthermore it is
not a pure fallacy group; it is the only one Which embodies a combination
of principles.
It appears then that although the fallacy principles are the most difficult at ages 10-12, there is great improvement in knowledge of these princi-
*In the sufficient condition table for class reasoning, Item Group 10 intrudes by
two percentage points.
V-31
TABLE V-4.
Item
Group
1
Difference Between Lowest Grade and Highest Grade Mean Item Group
Difficulty Indices; Item Group Answers
Conditional
Class
Difference
7.4
Answer
Yes
Difference
17.3
Answer
No
12.6
Maybe
26.7
Yes
18.0
Maybe
44.2
Maybe
9.3
No
23.3
Maybe
19.4
Yes
15.3
Yes
8.8
Yes
24.8
No
29.1
Maybe
29.1
Maybe
17.1
No
34.5
Maybe
16.8
Yes
15.6
Yes
10
22.9
No
15.7
No
11
12.6
No
26.2
No
12
-5.3
Maybe
4.9
Yes
Note: Item group answers are given because they indicate the type of item
group: 'Maybe' for fallacy item groups; 'Yes' for item groups in which
the conclusion to a valid argument is offered; and 'No' for item groups
in Which the denial of a conclusion to a valid argument is offered.
The question inevitably arises as to whether, using these imp.ovement
figures, the actual improvement in amount of knowledge is necessarily being
compared.
V-32
in the comparisons that are being made. Nbre specifically, given our assumptions, there is on the whole more improvement in the fallacy principles than
in the other principles for which we tested. This does not preclude there
having been an even greater improvement in some of the principles, skills,
and/or combinations thereof for which we did not test.
This defense of principle improvement comparisons does not extend to
component and total score comparisons, for those are not master: scores.
In those comparisons differences in improvement scores might not reflect
differences in amount of improvement in the thing being measured. Artificial
test ceilings might be operative.
2)
The converse.
statement with the parts reversed. One basic fallacy rule is that a statement does not imply its converse.
In other words:
That all A's are B's does not imply that all B's are A's.
'If p, then q' does not imply 'If q, then p'.
These two rules are among the most basic in the practical application of
logic.
appear in the raw score table, Table V-1. The two elementary converse item
groups start with the lowest raw scores and register the greatest absolute
gain over the range that we tested.
V-33
The results are not quite so striking (though almost so) then the necessary and sufficient condition tables, Tables V-2 and V-3, are examined. In
each case the converse principles tie for the position of greatest difficulty.
Furthermore the simple class reasoning converse item group (p3) does register
the greatest gain in percentage meeting the sufficient condition and the
greatest reduction in percentage failing to meet the necessary condition. And
the conditional reasoning converse item group registers the greatest reduction
in percentage failing to meet the necessary condition. But it does not register the greatest increase in percentage satisfying the sufficient condition,
presumably because not enough subjects even at grade 11 have mastered the
converse principle.
Another interesting fact about the converse principles is that at the
top grade levels in our range they had (as shown in Tables IV-8 and IV-9)
high mean discrimination indices, the highest for conditional reasoning
(53.2%) and among the highest for class reasoning (45.0%0 which is 1.7 percentage points from the highest).
conversion is, of the subtest factors with which we worked, among the most
closely related to total performance on the logic tests.
In sum the greatest improvement within the range of levels measured in
this study occurred for the converse principles of both conditional and
class reasoning.
difficult and for those around 17-18 were among the most discriminating. This
is in some contrast to the contraposition principles, which we consider next.
The Contrapositive.
V-34
That all A's are B's does imply that all non -B's are non -A's.
'If p, then q' does imply 'If not q, then not p'.
These two rules are put more elegantly as Conditional Principle 6 and Class
Principle 8 in Tables II-1 and 11-2 in Chapter II. They are directly tested
for by Conditional Item Group 6 and Class Item Group 9, as shown in Tables
IV-1 and IV-2 in Chapter IV.
These item groups are of medium mean difficulty at the outset (56.5% and
15.6) compared to the other item groups in a given type of reasoning test.
Each of these improvement figures is the third smallest for its type of
reasoning.
discrimination index (50.6% and 41.5%), which drops considerably by the end of
the period with which we worked (14.3% and 26.7%). This is just the re-
contraposition principles.
sort of thing that people can learn than the contraposition principles,
the
groups, on the assumption that learning plays a larger role in test perfor-
V-35
understood by all students, but that the contraposition principle vas either
understood right away or not at all. Contraposition did not seem as teachable
as conversion.
in the early grades answered the conversion and contraposition items on the
basis of whether the conclusion feels or sounds like the premise. Given that
nobody at these early ages is any good at logic, the ones who worked this war
could get the high total scores and would get the conversion items wrong and
the contraposition items right. In the early grades that would make the
former items more difficult and the latter more discriminating. Later on
students begin to reason logically and the high scorers are those who do so.
They get the conversion items right because they know better, but they miss
the contraposition items because a little knowledge is a dangerous thing.
Hence the conversion items become easier and more discriminating) while the
contraposition items become little easier and less discriminating.*
Research is needed on the reasons for this difference between the conver-
Transitivity.
14,-36
improvement registered for each in the range covered: 19.4, 26.7, and 26.2
power as
given in the discrimination indices is somewhat better than that of most of
the item groups.
Thus the transitivity principles, although they start out fairly easy,
are ones in which there is considerable improvement given the range within
One rather striking feature of the above discussions of fallacies, conversion, contraposition, and
definite similarities between the two types of logic being studied. The
thesis
each type.
this study.
V-37
b.
suggestive component, next the concrete familiar component, then the systolic
component.
Table V-5 also shows a very striking difference between conditional and
class reasoning in the comparison of components at each grade level. In the
conditional reasoning test the differences among the components are small,
varied, and not statistically significant.
In contrast there are regular differences among the same components on
the class reasoning test, the concrete familiar being easier. At three
(6, 8, and 10) of the five grade levels, the differences between the concrete familiar and the symbolic components are statistically significant
(5% level) and in the other two are nearly so.
concrete familiar and suggestive components are less marked but an inspection
of the chart shows that they are regular. At grade 6 the difference is
statistically significant; at grade 4 it comes within two tenths of a percentage point of being so; and at the other three grades the differences
are about two-thirds of what is needed for statistical significance.
These tests of significance are the relatively conservative Tukey test.*
When the less conservative t-test was performed on the above differences at
each grade level, all except those at grade 4 turned out to be statistically
significant.
we report the Tukey test results in Table V-5, but do find the t-test results
rather striking, so we mention them too.
TABLE Y-5. Comparisons of Mean Difficulty Indices of Three Components: Concrete Familiar, Symbolic,
and Suggestive.
Dirt.**
Needed
26.6 26.1
Needed
2 means
24.6 24.1
Dirt.***
21.2
25.4
19.2 19.2
17.1
15.8
14.6 18.5
V-39
Except at the lowest level (grade 4) the suggestive component is not
so difficult as the symbolic component. The differences are not statistically
significant using the Tukey test, as can be seen from an inspection of
Table V-5.
One wonders why there are these regular superiorities in the Blass
reasoning test of the concrete familiar component over the symbolic and
suggestive components, but not in the conditional reasoning test. Two ideas
have occurred to us, one for the CF-SU comparison and the other for the
CF-SY comparison.
nature.
is the case,
CF-SU comparison.
are also SU items and thUs have the SU difficulty built into them. Thus we
would expect no difference between the CF and SU components on the conditional
test.
The class reasoning CF items on the other hand do not have this
v-ito
is
On the
If p, then q.
Not q.
Therefore not p.
Perhaps it is the use of symbols as variables, rather tlisn simply the use of
symbols that makes for difficulty. If so, then the difference between the
class and conditional reasoning tests on the ccmparison between the concrete
familiar and symbolic components is understandable.
v-'11
It appears then that the order of difficulty of these three components,
if one accepts the auxilliary hypotheses mentioned above, is as
our subjects:
follows for
(listed in order
CHAPTER SUMMARY
This chapter presents a review of the literature and the results of our
study of the development of knowledge of conditional and class logic of
students roughly in the chronological age range 10-18 under the environmental
conditions of a contemporary upstate New York area. These students had not
to our knowledge been deliberately exposed to instruction in deductive logic.
The Literature.
The review of the literature focused on the work of Jean Piaget. Fou
basic features of his formal operational period of thought, which he holds
runs from age 11-12 onward, were described. They are 1) possession of the
truth-validity characteristic; 2) ability to operate within a combinatorial
framework; 3) ability to control variables; and 4) ability to do propositional
(sentence) logic.
The testing of Piaget's views, because of their vagueness, was not the
primary emphasis of this chapter. Instead it was concerned with questions
which are interesting, practically important, and were generated from a
consideration of Piaget's interests and concepts. Hence this part of the
study is to be considered an attempt at extension and refinement of Piaget's
work, rather than primarily a testing of his views.
The review of the literature (including Piaget's work) suggested the
following:
v.lte
That one might infer that Piaget thinks that class logic is
mastered by age 11-12.
extent
of
mastery
of
Findings.
age 17.
much
easier
this range
at for older
students.
11.43
Needed Research.
The following types of further research are called for:
2.
3.
1.
CHAPTER VI.
is a
key concept in this chapter, we shall present an examination of the concepts
readiness and readiness to master a principle. Then, after noting the dearth of
literature about readiness to master logic, we shall describe the experimental
procedures, including the teaching that we did, and present the results of this
inevitably limited study of the readiness question. These
WHAT IS READIRESS?
logic.
of
in
concept readiness would be in order. This is not to deny that much of what
problem.
This is not
intended
arAt21122111-1-AMTEI
When one inquires whether
not asking whether he has done the something, and one is not simply asking
he is ready to do it.
VI-2
Dispositional Terms.
sugar is soluble is not to say that is has dissolved, nor that it will ever
dissolve, but simply that under suitable conditions it will dissolve.
is noncontroversial.
That is, it is not controversial that a person who has mastered the prin- ciple in
question should be able to do something of the sort, under suitable
conditions.
VI-3
seems arguable.
3.
......1"InaafL11111E11112E-
More manageable,
has mastered.
in the
is
Elusiveness of Readiness.
disposition to dissolve.
is soluble)
principle unfortunately is
knowing whether it exists
before it is exercised.
Once exercised, it is
This
Readiness to master a
every
A rough compromise
VI-5
is the study of a range of people. Such study will call for the measurement
of one or more variables which are correlated with the extent, after the
suitable conditions have been provided, of mastery of the principle.
Thc_e correlations could be used in the development of multiple regression
equations, which would serve the function of predictor equations since the
values of the variables, as determined be_ fore the introduction of the
vague-
VI-6
there will be two lines, which will be called the "necessary condition
line" and the "sufficient condition line". If the prediction falls below
the necessary condition line, then we judge that the person is probably
not ready to master the principle.
principle.
On the simpler approach Which does not make use of an area of uncertainty,
the judgment would simply depend on whether or not the prediction falls
above or below the line.
Judgments about groups would not be as subject to error as judgments
about individuals. A procedure for making judgments about groups will be
described later.
Suitable Conditions.
la
VI-7
But the difficulty of performing this task, the production of predictability for
varying degrees of effort, is great.
teaching that we did, but the previous statement suggests some of the
dimensions of effort and to most people will suggest some that we had to
ignore.
find that people of that sort do master the thing in question, when provided with a given sort of instruction, then we can say that a person of
VI-8
confidence that we say that such a person is not ready, because there
might be another feasible and successful way of conducting the instruction.
This is one of those rare cases when a positive answer is easier to give
than a negative one.
Summary.
subject's
Readiness is a practical notion in that the means needed to produce the mastery for which the subject is ready must be feasible.
Cisatleasttp...2ziehasthedissirincile)tioikiiven suitable
conditions to devel
VI-9
the sort of behavior that a person Who has mastered principle X would shor.
and the results announced, there is still much cautious judging to be done.
The inference leap to another person is one that must be undertaken with
care when the relevant factors have been examined. The judgments about
the feasibility of the means selected must be made. If the subjects used
did not succeed, then one must consider the question of whether better
methods might yet be developed.'
Hence the results of a readiness study are likely to be rather modest.
THE LITERATURE
There is practically no literature on the question under consideration in this chapter. Piaget's bountiful contributions concern themselves
only with what children know, not what children can learn. The only thing
that we have been able to find that is relevant is the effort of Hills
restricted way of teaching: telling children, when giving them a logic test,
But
of course Hills' main purpose was other than seeing the effects of teaching
logic.
The current study is the first study of readiness to learn logic with
which we are acquainted.
VI-10
PROCEDURES
was
Test,
Form X ", at grades 5, 7, 9, and 11, "The Cornell Conditional
Reasoning
at each of grade
logic test, and conditional logic to those who took the conditional logic
test.
This pre-test was given primarily in order that the scores might be
one period per day for 15 instructional days for the purpose of
instruction in logic.
VI-11
member taught more than two classes per day, and when there were two classes
per day they were in the same type of logic. Thus staff teachers were provided
with time to plan and to develop written exercises. Each member of
the course of instruction, though it might have been near the beginning,
middle, or end of the instruction aimed at that particular principle.
The language in which the principle was stated, and the person
(teacher or student) by whom it was stated varied frameless to class
and principle to principle.
were used.
and examples, though they used each other's ideas. Examples of the
teaching materials will be found in the Appendix.
class reasoning.
tion Tests, nor was practice given in the specific mode of response
used in the tests.
VI-l2
achievement in logic
receive. They
were also
Hawthorne effect.
reasons for this:
First ve were
trying to find out what was possible and took advantage of whatever
motivation was available.
ciple. That is, the techniques of the use of circles in doing class logic
apply to all the principles; hence much of the instruction applies to all
of the principles, making class reasoning time allotment somewhat meaningless,
VI-13
TABLE VI-1 Rough psi
Conditional Reasoning
Principle
Item Group
lo
11
ec.-apination
Grade
80
9
80
11
70
150
60
60
65
125
75
75
65
70
80
100*
125
To
25
40
40
To
50
7o
710
65
5o
4o
4o
7o
40
45
45
3o
35
15
15
30
5o
loo
loo
6o
30
30
6o
10 & 12
85
2
3 & 4
75
65
70
75
4o
75
6o
70
To
40
50
60
50
55
20
25
65
45
40
120
120
120
10,11U2
120
120
120
Colibination
200
li
225
150
70
160
75
165
15
165
*Mote:
that the reader will take this estimated time allotment for that it is:
had it to do over,
which we used.
amount
of effort at the lower grades
The Post-Test.
taught by members of
conclusion of instruction,
a post-
presumed not to be taught (the LVDT-1's). The post-test vas the same test
that was administered as a pre-test, the class reasoning test to grades 4,
A check vas made to see if logic had been taught between test
RESULTS
The results of this readiness study are divided into two parts, one dealing
wIth the nature and extent of learning of logic that vent on in the
VI-15
groups to which we deliberately taught logic, and the other dealing with
attempts to predict What other students could learn, given comparable
instruction.
The first part asks What the students in this study were ready to learn
before we taught them logielthe second asks what some other students are
ready to learn.
General Qualifications.
Four important qualifications should be kept in mind as one reads
this section.
subjects (about 20-30 at each of nine grade levels). The reason for this
was that it was important to worm intensively, rather than extensively in
this study.
was taught rather than something else. And it vas desirable to give the
staff teachers adequate time to plan, prepare written exercises, and read
students' papers; they were pioneering the teaching of this subject matter
at grade levels lower than those at which it is ordinarily taught.
As a result of this small number of subjects results are more erratic
than they presumably otherwise would be. And also in our comparisons
between the LDT's and the LED-1's some actual differences have inevitably
failed to reach statistical significance.
In order to state the other three qualification we must first distinguish
Hence we
school authorities and some are more or less beyond their control. Factors
1 and 2 can be introduced by the school authorities. Factors 3, 4, and 5
are increasingly out of their control.
As a practical matter, when we ask whether a student is ready to learn
something, we are concerned with the probable results of the deliberate
introduction of factors under our control. Hence we are in this study
primarily concerned with the effects of factors 1 and 2.
Since the test-wiseness part of the second factor will give spurious
results, we would like to discount these. When we simply ask what our students
learned as a result of teaching and look only at the before and after test
results, the results of this test-wiseness factor creep in. When we ask,
however, whether they have learned more than they otherwise would have,
and use a comparison with a control group to help answer the question, the effect
of this factor is presumably controlled for to some extent at least.
With the other part of the second factor, the learning of logic as a
result of taking the
We
velcame the operation of this factor when we ask what the students have
VI-17
this factor is controlled for, even though we
happen. After all, our interest is in the learning that occurs as a result
of what we do. So the results of the comparisons with the control groups
mask the results of actually taking the tests,
of instructional procedures.
Another source of error is the operation of factors
4 and 5 on entire
noise while the test was being taken, the presence of a smart
-aleck or two
occurred and that we had no check on them other than alertness and care
in avoiding them is a weakness of the study. As we will explain later)
we suspect that some factor of this sort operated to the detriment of the
LET's in the 9th grade.
Tb have provided a statistical check on this sort of thing it would
have been desirable to use a number of groups with random assignment as
LET's and LNDT-l's.
b.)
c.)
VI-18
d.) Factors affecting total class groups can without detection
(except for internal consistency evidence) give spuriously
high or low scores.
rem
to learn.
period learn much conditional reasoning until the upper secondary level, at
which time they made a vast improvement, primarily in avoiding the fallacies.
On the other hand in class reasoning moderate improvement was registered at
all'levels with which we worked, except the lowest. These general statements
need amplification and qualification.
Conditional Reasoning.
Total Scores.
and post -test total scores on the conditional reasoning test as given in
Table III -3 in Chapter III.
in Table A.5 in the Appendix. These comparisons show that in grades 5 and
there is no statistically significant superiority one way or the other. In
grade 9 there is a statistically significant superiority favoring the students
who were not taught logic, and in grade 11 there was a greater superiority
favoring the students who were taught logic. The superiority of the taught
11th graders is quite striking, with a difference of
means on the post-test.
15.2
points in adjusted
VI-19
Adjusted.)
The situation in grade 9 is puzzling.
have a significantly higher adjusted mean, but the mean score (unadjusted)
of the taught 9th graders was actually lower
than
That is, it
that at this level the teaching that has occurred has been effective enough
to interfere with the "feel" method of judging arguments, but not effective
enough
lies with the students themselves. It might be that there was an important
difference between the two groups which did not show up on any of the measures
that we used.
It might
We tend
to favor this the third explanation, which, if the proper one, makes suspect
the findings about conditional reasoning at the 9th grade level. It was
only at this level that such motivational problems were reported by members
of our staff.
Component Scores.
As can be seen in Table VI-2 the situation is roughly the same as viewed
through the component scores.
VI-20
TABLE
VI-2.
Conditional Reasoning
5
11
9
7
27
24
17
26
Grade
Niatlit2
26
25
Total Score
23
Class Reasoning
10
4
6
8
25
25
27
22
22
22
34
R
24
-
18
12
23
17
R
Component
CP
SY
..
MD
MD
..
41M
MD
...
..
..
...
..
MD
MD
GM
4m
..
'.
MD
ND
..
GB
MD
al
IID
Mb
GP
..'
UV
MO
ca b
s:..cycs
SU
Item Group
9
10
MI
MI
11
12
lo
s use
..gcateas t a
R
.C1
ference favoring the group that vas taught logic. The syMbol
is used to indicate a statistically significant difference favoring
the group that was not taught logic. A dash is used to indicate lack
of statistical significance. The 5% level was used throughout.
A yard of caution:
VI-21
built into the test.
and at the 9th grade level on the concrete familiar component there is another
reversal.
The great superiority of the 11th graders who were taught over those
who were not taught seems to lie mainly in the fallacies, but also in
contraposition, basic and practical, and perhaps with affirming-theantecedent items.
By 'practical contraposition'
we mean the valid move from 'If p, then q' and the denial of 'q' to the
denial of 'p'.
latter, which we have also called 'denying the consequent' (Chapter II),
appears as Principle 4 and Item Group 4. The two forms are logically similar,
as can be seen by saying them over to oneself.
The four fallacy item groups (2,3,7, and 12) and the two contraposition item groups (4 and 6) stand out uniquely on the covariance
comparison.
On all of these item groups, but only these item groups, are
the 11th graders that we taught significantly better than the ones we did
not teach.
It also comes through in Tables L-7 and A-8 in the Appendix, which
give item group pre- and post-test measures on the groups to which we taught
logic.
the difference between pre- and post-test measures for each item group in
the 11th grade.
VI c2
TABLE VI-3.
N=26
Improvement in
Improvement in
Percentage Meeting
the Sufficient
Condition
15
Item
Mean Difficulty
Indices
9
Group
1
Increase in
Percentage Failing
to Meet the Necesnary Condition*
- 8
2**
50
3**
53
73
-69
4***
11
27
-8
6***
19
39
-19
7**
27
42
-35
65
-61
-11
15
-13
-15
lo
11
- 1
44
50
-65
12**
'which
This table is taken from Tables A-7 and A-8 in the Appendix,
all grade
present the
pre- and post-test scores and differences for
levels to vhich
VI-23
Perhaps the
word 'only' was previously quite clear, but that what they were taught about
the word 'if' by itself confused their understanding of 'only if'.
reference
to Table VI-1 shows that about an hour was spent teaching the
'only-if' principles.
to this concept.
was confused.
There is slight improvement on the transitivity item groups, numbered
5 and 10, but one does not know whether this represents a real improvement
or not. There is a greater improvement on the most basic move of all, the
affirmation of the antecedent (represented by Item Group 1), but not enough to
reach statistical significance in the compariscn with the students not
taught logic.
reasoning principle.
TABLE VI-4.
Principle
Improvement in
Grade
Improvement in
Percentage Meeting
the Sufficient
Condition
Increase in
Percentage Failing
to Meet the Necessary Condition*
18
27
Mean Difficulty
Indices
9
7
9
24
17
11
- 3.2
11
26
15
- 8
VI -24
sentences.
statistically significant.
At this
antecedent is in a
way
a transitivity principle (the affirmation carries through from the antecedent
as contrasted
be investigated.
The sufficient condition
the
things that can be taught
teaching.
* Incidentally this sentence
graders
grade LDZ's.
VI-25
on
which we worked is
percentages
meeting the sufficient
levels
, together with the percentages that have mastered them in the 11th
in the Appendix.*
An intriguing questionais
registered in the four
of logic, or whether
as it is properly used.
is commonly taken
sufficient condition.
knowledge of logic;
* A possible objection
at the lover grade levels is that the
combinations of principles.
combinations, how
teachable at the can we suggest that this particular combination is not
lower grade levels, one might ask.
In reply we would
of the
say that an effort was made to teach the affirmation
antecedent
principle and the transitivity principle, but it had no
noticeable effect. Hence we conclude
or with
that the combination of one with another
itself would not
have been effectively taught at the lover grade levels.
VI-26
This is an extremely puzzling issue. As Benjamin Lee Whorf has
pointed out, our language, our conceptual structure, and our power to
think are intimately related. But it does make sense to suggest that the
distinction that we represent by the words 'if' and 'if and only if' was already
known to our subjects (even though they do not use these words to represent it)
and that they used 'if' to mean what we mean by 'if and only
if'.
meaningful question.
If this verbal interpretation of the learning that went on is accepted,
then the learning has less significance than otherwise supposed. Under
this interpretation we were not teaching the students to think; we were
it is
words allows that there would not be much learning of transitivity. But
the learning of contraposition and what there was of affirming the antecedent
is contrary to the verbal hypothesis, because these things seem to be clearly
evidence
might be explained away be the suggestion that for these things they learned
Class Reasoning.
The situation in class reasoning is rather different from that in
conditional reasoning.
upper elementary levels, somewhere around age 12; but that there is a line
is not clear.
the 4th graders, but generally had a positive effect on those from 6th grade
up to 12th grode. This effect is not nearly as striking as the effect
of teaching conditional reasoning to the 11th graders.
Total Scores.
The change in mean total scores for the LDT's over the interval between
pre-test and post-test is positive in grades 6, 8, 10, and 12, but not in
grade 4.
The improvements
registered are 9.5, 3.8, 8.3, and 6.8 respectively. These are considerably
smaller than the improvement of 17.0 points registered by the 11th graders
on conditional reasoning.
In a post-test comparison with the
Component Scores.
The situation is generally the same when scores are broken down into
their components. As indicated on Table VI-2, there is some statistically
significAnt superiority of the LET's at grades 6 and 12, and also at grade
Since in the
teaching frequent use vas made of such phraseology as 'All A's are B'e',*
this difference in the symbolic component is understandable. It is perhaps
noteworthy that only in the 6th grade were the LET's statistically significantly superior on two of the components. In no grade was this the case for
three components.
symbolic component.
* The letters at the end of the alphabet (e.g., 'X' and 'Y') were used in
the test, not the ones at the beginning, which were used in teaching.
111 -28
In the class reasoning item groups there is nothing that compares with
the remarkable improvement made by the 11th graders on the conditional
reasoning fallacy item groups.
Group 2 and basic contraposition is tested for an Item Group 9. There was
some improvement in each of these, and according to hypothesis abovefthere
VI-29
something of a puzzle.
are not large enough to make the problem serious. When the study is
which
single
But
again
puzzle.
Summary.
age 12 onward.
symbolic component.
A possible explanation of
since class
VI-30
siderable
reasoning.
Appendix.
mean difficulty indices on the pre-test were 340 45, 51, and 71 in grades 4,
and 10
6, 8,
verbal
It might be urged
to do it.
explanation
The attempt to
VI-31
score.
equations
were prepared: one made use only of information which is generally available
total
An I;
,
scion
=tion for
on.
11
63.7
(.314) (4.26) -
+ 1.34
1.26
1.26 =
cross validation.
These figures,
together
But predictions
for
to generate a predicted
go further.
the principle.
VI-33
TABLE VI-5.
Conditional
94
Without
using
Pre-Test
Pre-Test
Rm Rxv
SE
Rm Rxv
SE
N=
Total
Score
and
Class
123
Using
Pre-Test
Rm Rxv
SE
Without
Pre-Test
Rm Rxv
SE
.81
.77 12.07
.73
.69
13.85
.87
.86
.81
.78
CF
.82
.78
5.17
.71
.66
6.31
.84
.82
.77
.74
5.51
SY
.72
.65
1,74
.67
.62
1.83
.78
.75
.76
.73
1.77
SU
.72
.67
1.69
.69
.64
1.74
.84
.82
.77
.74
1.91
.59
.47
1.05
.52
.41
1.10
.75
.71
.93
.59
.53
1.12
.77
.71
1.45
.65
.58
1.69
.71
.66
.84
.67
.62
.88
.59
.48
1.60
.59
.50
1.59
.76
.72
.66
.62
1.38
.63
.53
1.42
.51
.40
1.54
.6o
.53
.54
.47
1.69
.61
.50
1.28
.46
.32
1.42
.63
.56
.89
.60
.54
.91
.56
.42
1.55
.40
.22
1.69
.73
.68
.94
.64
.59
1.05
.66
.58
1.81
.6o
.53
1.91
.65
.59
.46
.26
1.48
.40
.21
1.51
.76
.73
.54
.46
1.77
.36
1.55
.00
.31
1.56
.65
.60
.0o
.56
.47
1.49
.53
.46
.53
.45
1.45
.68
.64
1.21
1.04
.56
.49
1.11
11.71
Component
Item
Group
lo
.67
.59
1.44
.60
.53
1.53
.58
.5o
.65
.56
1.46
.49
.37
1.66
.74
.70
.56
.43
1.76
.52
.42
1.79
.64
.57
Note:
SE is the
standard error.
1.39
VI-34
So we plotted each mean difficulty index against each percentage
meeting the sufficient condition on the pre- and post-tests for each of the
two types of reasoning studied. These plotted points are reproduced in the
Appendix as Graphs A-1
and A-3.
graphs and appears in Graph VI-1 in this chapter. A similar process was
carried out for the percentages failing to meet the necessary conditions.
See Graphs A-2 and A-4 in the Appendix. The line of best fit thus derived
also appears on Graph VI-1.
for
the 11th grade LDT's were 15% and 77% on the post-test.
Making use of the previous analysis of readiness for mastery and
accepting the limitation imposed by our being able to provide only a given
amount of a given cost of instruction, we can now exemplify the type of
of the members of
VI -35
GRAPH V1-1.
100
90
NM.
w
it
80
0
0
ti
0
P4
70
aro
60
MM.
0
v4
4---SUFFICIENT
NECESSARY
0
C.)
4,
50
40
CO
30
112
20
10
10
20
50
60
70
80
90
100
VI-36
who are ready to master
not ready.
Referring to Table A-8 in the
at least 50% of the
that
At least 22.%
At least 13%
We do not want to be
committed about the readiness of
other 15%.
(100 -50 -22 -13 = 15)
the
Several qualifications
Obviously
with
should be introduced.
to master
a confidence interval.
that this procedure
we have.
only say
a confidence interval is
VI -.37
accrues therefrom.
When
pre-test scores are not available, the sufficient condition statements must
be about percentages who either have mastered the principle or are ready to
do so.
of these scores.
One would still talk of the percentage who are not ready.
These equations can also be used to predict group mean total component
The trouble
is
FURTHER RESEARCH
of class-wide factors.
The
intensive
logic in order to
the meaning or
Another set of
variables.
study.
if possible.
require sophisticated
CHAPTER SUMMARY.
concept, readiness to
dispositionality of the
dispositionality.
suitable conditions,
To say that Y
VI-39
would show.
'mastery'
capacity
readiness statements.
instruction.
ast7
There
was
those
reasoning on
possibly sooner.
of
previous
analysis of 'readiness
percentages who
are ready to master the principle and who are not ready to
type of reasoning).
This smallness
be intensive:
was pelished in 1962 and has been under constant revision since then.
set of short reviews of works related to critical thinking was prepared
and made available in 1962.
suppetted
involve some of the basic work necessary before applied curriculum and
method studies could be performed.
all aspects of critical thinking, was the one most fully developed, and
VII-2
As soon as we
principles of deduction,
We had to select
types.
ordinal reasoning.
present natural-cultural
basic principles of
one of working on
system.
VII -3
After
extensive
item and test tryouts, one test for each
three typical
This
(two weeks).
lessons:
in
general
learning logic.
student's time
That in future readiness studies, much more of a
must be
Because ve were both
devoted to the study of logic.
operating on a small
what
scale and insistent upon control over
was being taught, we had to
staff members into
introduce our own
resulted
the schools. This inevitablytime
by
we
in strong limitations
the schools on the amount of a student's
A
could have.
possible way around this problem, a way not open to us this
last
and
pilot
deduction,
with
VII-4
5.
6.
Since something
had to go, we dropped the years in which the most central parts of logic,
given our limited amount of teaching, were not getting across to the students.
The second year's study is that described in the body of this report.
The Tests.
The original plan called for one deductive logic test, consisting of
six items per grade level of about 50% difficulty for the given grade level
VII -5
in Chapter IV, yield a score which hopefully has meaning which is not as
this study.
items apiece).
An
were conducted.
in the preparation of the tests, and about 500 students were used in various
stages of tryouts.
VII -6
The Future
This report covers only the first of a number of phases in the study
1-12.
In the tentative
designations
of phases to follow, we have broken the process of doing a readiness study
each aspect of critical thinking. Starting one aspect per year would
result in an overall time commitment of about 10 more years.
VII -7
Table VII-1.
Academic
Year
1967-68
1968-69
1969-70
Test
Development
Ordinal Reasoning
Generalizing
(revision)
Class and Conditional
Reasoning
(Grades 1-3, adaptation)
Alternation and Dis-
Alternation and
Reliability of
junction Reasoning
Assumption-Finding
Generalizing
Disjunction Reasoning:
Grades 1-12
Assumption-Finding:
Observation Statements
1970..T1
1971-72
1972-73
1973-74
Reliability of
Authorities
Hypothesis Warrant
Detecting Ambiguity
Overvagueness and
Theory Warrant
Grades 1-6
Class and Conditional
Reasoning:
Grades 1-3
Grades 1-12
of
Observation Statements
Generalizing:
Grades 1-12
Reliability of
Reliability of Obser-
Authorities
Hypothesis Warrant
vation Statements:
Grades 1-12
Reliability of Autho-
Detecting Ambiguity
rities:Grades 1-12
Hypothesis Warrant:
Overvagueness and
Grades 1-12
Detecting Ambiguity:
Overspecificity
1974-75
Teaching,and
Readiness
Equations
Ordinal Reasoning:
Overspecificity
Grades 1-12
1975-76
1976-77
Instead of aspect
analysis and new test
development, this portion
)will be devoted to
repeating some
investigations, and
writing a total
report.
Overvagueness and
Overspecificity:
Grades 1-12
Theory
Warran
t:
Perhaps
Grades
1316
that we set for ourselves, the interpretation of our key concepts, the
our results.
Many
qualifications
sub- headings.
Introduction:
for the clarity and understanding they provide in dealing with the
empirical questions.
of logic.
The
in logic.
VIII -2
at a given moment.
research,
report.
In order to discuss these questions some conceptual problems had to be
definitions of 'mastery of
num.erical limitations of
But the
conceptual
The subject matter, the mastery of rich is the subject of this study,
VIII -3
thinking.
It is that part of
of it.
of critical thinking
Ti o Types of Logic.
relationship of necessary
class logic.
Conditional logic deals with
The part
of
"antecedent".
The
the
presenting a conditional
conclusion follow
VIII-1t
Here is an example of
Premises:
In conditional logic,
independently of each
or groups.
or the other.
W. Smith's cars",
is a class logic
"the
are
groups.
Here, for example,
Premises:
All the
All W. Smith's
Conclusion:
VIII-5
Principles of Logic.
selected mhat seemed to be
exemplified
in Chapter II:
Conditional Logic:
Given an if-then
not
sentence, the affirmation of the then-part does
by itself (as
a result of its being a then-part) imply the affirmation
of the if-part.
Given an if-then
of the if -part.
1
2
2.
An if-then
Given an only-if
one
part of
an if-and-only-if
statement
Given an only-if
not
sentence, the affirmation of the only-if part does
by itself (as
a result of its being an only-if part) imply the
affirmation of the major part.
Given an only-if
itself
sentence, the denial of the major part does not by
(as a result
of its being the major part) imply the denial of the only-if
part.
Class Logic:
Whatever is a member
vice versa.
vni-6
Whatever is a member of
a class is also a member of a class in *WI
the first is included.
(This implies that class inclusion is
transitive.)
Whatever is a member of
necessarily
*
*
relationship)
Whatever is not
a member of a class is not (as a result of that
relationship) necessarily
a member of (nor a non-member of) another class
which is excluded from the first.
Whatever is not
conversion, negation of
'only-if' principles.
3. We call them
Negation of Antecedent:
invalidlmove.
"fallacy principles",
reasons as well.
of
This is also an
It consists of
Conditional
VIII-7
second part of a statement and on that baAis concluding that the first
If X has a given
'Only-if' principles:
but not necessarily sufficient condition for the truth of the rest of the
sentence.
arguments.
We group all
viii-8
An intensive study of Pieget's logic was conducted for the purpose of
comparison with the types of logic presented above. Basically we found the
logics similar although we had reservations. We concluded that Piaget's
conclusions and cur conclusions are therefore relevant to each other.
Because of the large amount to be learned in each of the two types
of logic we studied, we assigned these two types of logic to alternate grade
levels within the range studied. Conditional logic was tested for and
taught at grade levels 5, 7, 9, and 11, while class logic was tested
were 217 of these subjects, called the "LDT's" (for 'Logic Deliberately
upper New York State school system from which they were drawn.
From the same school system comparable classes were selected, again
'Logic
From another upper New York State school system another 375 students,
called the "LNDT-2's", were selected for use, together with the LDT's and
1 is
VIII -9
LDT's
LNDT-1's
217
211
Mean IQ
116.8
116.3
LIET-2's
375
108.4
None Calculated
112.7
Total
803
SES
3.8
3.5
Fbrm X" and "The Cornell Class-Reasoning Test, Form X". These tests were
constructed with the purpose of determining whether all but one of the
principles of logic listed earlier are mastered or alternatively, the
test.
group
were scattered.
groups.
VIII -10
lack of mastery.)
Fbrmally put,
Principle 14
Principle 4.
(1928) ve includ
in the tests:
the concrete
item.
Concrete familiar items
to objects in the
items are such that
They
The
furthermore, there is
VIII -11
as such.
answer of "Yes."
The directions do not vaguely ask
Reliability.
The
Mean concrete
neutral
test-retest correlations
class reasoning.
again lower.
Validity.
Means were .52 for conditional and .50 for class reasoning.
Basically
the
editorials,
VIII -12
was conducted.
concentrated effort
item format,
directions,
be clear applications
reasoning test.
All significance
These particular
played
conditional reasoning N
"III-13
correlations between subject matter tests and IQ.
Correlations with the
occupationally- based index
statistically significant.
There appears to be
If a relationship
one.
That
there
be either no relationship
If bright
young
ledge of logic is
related to brightness,
between chronological
would be defeated.
If knowledge of logic
should be a positive
And if logic is an
should be related
assumption that
VIII-14
in logic.
The results on these tests conformed to expectations and are under-
support the argument for construct validity. Naturally this is only support,
not confirmation, since other interpretations could be given to
the data.
Item analysis information, which
We have no
61.5
- 72.7 for class) show that the tests are not too
difficult for the grades at which
satisfied in order
that the
That it is
for
was evident,
VIII-15
which calls for the combined
hL
those groups.
is thus
assumption
that greater understanding
this
Is there actually
older?
Is the truth-validity
VIII -16
in the literature/and
study,
follows:
Yes.
Partly.
Partly.
Partly.
It is the
empirical findings.
the size of the
We found considerable
two types of logic studied,
VIII -17
improvement in the
transitivity principles.
Although we found
of reasoning (concrete
both tests.
parallel
feature that
fairly
On the conditional
significant.
differences between tL
familiar components and the suggestive
And the
concrete
component also exceeded ten percentage
significant.
Previous studies that have shown the
to be more difficult
reasoning.
vin-18
conditional reasoning.
suggestive and symbolic
component in class
sentences.
The Development of
.o master Principle X
given suitable
Y is ready
have in
disposition to show,
is in part provided
analysis is complicated
The
disposition to develop
analysis twice makes
And the
'suitable conditions'.
But
The
Y
is ready to master Principle X implies
VIII-19
mastery exist and are feasible, but the means are not necessarily
readiness.
is vague.
for mastery:
second a question
of prediction.
per day, and approximately six weeks later, were given the post-test,
which was the same test
natural-cultural development of
teachability of principles
period.
virtually no improvement,
by
and were
scores.
was done
VIII -20
onwards.
Students younger than that did not benefit from the 15 days of
conditions
From
great strides.
principles.
VIII -21
were not.
variables, we constructed
of predicting what other
Using
and sex.
prediction of individuals
scores.
There
VIII-22
of central tendencies of
interest in working out
operational definitions
that are predicted to
on p VIII-10.)
is to be found in
above-described
percentage that
(See
ix is
group mean
Principle
predicted
empirically derived
through of the
purposes of illustration.
IQ
Socio-economic Status
Sex (male, 1
female, 2)
Total Score on Pre-Test
Pre-test Score
Mastery of Conditional
effort:
Measured
Value (rounded)
11
199.8 mos.
116.0
3.5
1.5
63.7
4.26
Weight
-.001
.0074
.0064
-.127
.423
.0384
.314
Constant:
-1.26
VIII -23
Predicted score = (-.001) (11) + (.0074) (199.8) + (.0064)
1.26
is
are desirable:
VIII-24
again
logic among the LDT upper secondary students, with this specific question
in mind:
Such investigation
should attempt to indicate the extent to which such procedures are likely to
be in error.
10. The investigation of the readiness development
and natural-cultural
of the aspect. It
VIII -25
Overview.
CITED REFERENCES
Brogden, Hilbert E.
Tr, 121427.
Fairgrieve, M. MacCallum.
pp. 27-33.
Unpublished
Inhelder, Barbel and Piaget, Jean. The Growth of Logical Thinking from
Childhood to Adolescence: An Essay on the Construction of Formal
Operational Structures. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958.
Miller, Elmer H. "A Study of Difficulty Levels of Selected Types of
Fallacies in Reasoning and Their Relationships to the Factors
of Sex, Grade Level, Mental Age and Scholastic Standing," Journal
of Educational Research, Vol. 49, No. 2 (1955) pp. 123.429.
R-1
R-2
Moore, Dom Thomas Verner.
First
"The Reasoning Ability of Children in the
Years of School Life,"
Studies in Ps chol and Ps chiat
Parsons, Charles.
"Inhelder
and Piagett
II.
Piaget, Jean.
Kegan Paul,
Intelligence.
Routledge
and
1950.
London:
New Jersey:
Ryan, Thomas A.
Research,"
Smith, B. Othanel.
1953.
1949.
Wilkins, Misuse. Cheves.
on Ability to
Winch, W. H.
"Children's Reasonings:
In School Children,"
Vol.
(1921),
The Journal of
Experimental Pedagogy,
Woodcock, Louise P.
Logical Studies.
London:
GENERAL REFERENCES
Note:
Seymour B.
Arleta, S.
Baldwin, G. Bernard.
Black, Max.
Bonser, Frederick G.
Brogden, Hubert E.
and Design,"
"Statistical Theory
Annual Review
of Psychology
Bruner, Jerome S., Goodnow, Jacqueline J., and Austin, George A. A Study
of Thinking.
New York:
R-3
American
R-4
Dewey, John.
How We Think.
Paul
L.,
Evaluation.
and
Mayhew,
Lewis
General
Education
Ekplorations
in
B,
Ithaca, New
Form 74."
Form Z."
1964b.
.
Mimeographed.
"Operational Definitions,"
Fairgrieve, M. MacCallum.
"A Mass Test with Mr. Cyril Burt's
Intelligence Questions,"
Journal of Experimental Pedagogy,
Vol. 6 (1921.), pp. 27-33.
Flavell, John H.
Glaser, Edward M.
1941.
Gordon, Raymond L.
"The Effect of Attitude Toward Russia on Logical
Reasoning,"
Journal of Social Psychology, Vol. 37 (1953), pp. 103111.
Gottschalk, Louis.
Understanding History.
New
1951.
Guillet, Cephas.
Hazlitt, V.
"Children's Thinking,"
Vol. 20 (1930), pp. 354-361. British Journal of Psychology,
Hempel, Carl G.
Science. Chicago:
Hdrix, G. "Developing
Henle, M.
R-6
Henle, M., and Michael, M.
Unpublished
London:
Pp. 94-119.
Operational Structures.
Kane, R. B.
Leeper, Robert.
Lefford, A.
R-7
Macmillan, C. J. B. and Ennis, Robert H.
to Critical Thinking,"
Junior Hi
mimeographed
Maier, Norman R, F.
of
McCarthy, Philip J.
York
State School of Industrial and Labor Relations, Ithaca, New York:
1951.
East Lansing:
129.
pp. 123-
Mohandessi, K.
Relational
Concepts In a
Younj Child.
New York: Bureau of Publications, Teachers College,
Columbia University, 1955.
Oakes, Mervin E.
of Publications, Teachers
Bureau
R-8
Oliver, Donald W., and Shaver, James P. "The Analysis of Public
Controversy: A Study in Citizenship Education," Vol. 1 and 2.
A Report from the Laboratory for Research in Instruction, Graduate
School of Education, Harvard University, 1962.
Parsons, Charles.
"Inhelder and Piaget's
Thinking," II A Logician's
The
Viewpoint.
Growth of Logical
British Journal of
1957.
Richter, Maurice N. Jr. "The
Syllogistic Reasoning,"
pp. 341-344.
Robinson, Richard.
Definition.
Oxford:
Oxford
University Press,
1954.
Russell, David H.
Children's Thinking.
Boston:
Ryan, Thomas A.
Scheffler, Israel.
Sell, DeWitt E.
Sells, S. B.
No. 200.
R. E.
Problem-Solving," Psychology
"Relationship of Attitude
to Logical
R-9
"Critical Thinking,"
An Hypothesis," Psychology
Straw3on, P. F.
Sweeney, E. J.
Tabal Hilda.
Thistlewaite, D. L.
Thompson, Jane-
Thorndike, E. L.
R-10
Valentine, Charles W.
Von Domarus, E.
In J. S.'Kdsmin,
Warner, W. Lloyd.
Wason, P. C.
Pp. 30-34.
Welch, Livingstone.
Eduard Eftynard.
Watson-Glaser Critical
(1928).
Williams, E. B.
Woodcock, Louise P.
R -11
The tables and graphs presented in this part of the appendix are
"1
!
TABLE
Sub-
jects LDT
LDT
Pre
Post
Pre
Grades
N=
102
05
Item
Number
p then q. p.
14
68
78
63
74
63
19
86
85
96
07
27
Mean
74
48
75
71
jects
Pre
63
59
67
68
78
70
78
78
77
61
76
95
75
72
71
75
34
13
24
23
26
05
18
34
Mean
32
27
41
37
37
00
44
19
37
44
04
33
Post
07
24
24
Pre
80
96
78
79
62
63
90
69
75
78
76
83
77
33 33
43
58
67
loo
88
71
96
83
92
Not q.
Item
09
Pre
Sub.
jects LDT
41
34
23
13
42
15
22
11
lo
23
30
25
28
29
21
04
25
13
21
5o
25
13
33
13
28
75
34
23
09
33
09
25
Pre
LDT
Pbst
09
17
17
SUbgloats
Pre
78
LDT
Pre
11
UR
Post
26
26
81
96
q.
Number
LDT LDT
99
27
27
eub-
53
71
94
59
88
82
74
e;
54
49
24
49
39
88
47
81
92
78
00
100
100
83.
83
82
65
18
92
100
12
4o
24
35
31
19
39
19
34
96
992
97
85
85
73
85
85
89
84
FAN3
I.T.T
gistimEotiA
4,11
c%a4,ag:
ogMtc;
Hi
M
Po
ZI
r4 UN el ri
Ps
LIA
ai
r9
s:411
3N
:111 al
cTo
;11
ar
0'
4)4
43
c;.
Cp
a
1
NCO
03
gAR.;*4
["8 fr'tN
81.1Li
t44
Po
f- P`RPMP
`401t117
A.tigiti&A
I cAaptatzfil
4 VI I'
"nP2R)S
xri
I
OD
I-1
ha P. 1-1
M"
41 .9 N
FA I-a 1-1
tna
t40 r%j%
tel
vi Jut-4 4" Al 4r 4
ro
pa
1.8
W
-43 Q
co
ODtaOD Y1
tal
V-St'V
ZA
1.%)28M
ON 0%%,0 f9 ON-4 0%
1 4 ataNcriA%/i
03 'dal 03w
03SMNn
ta3 -mos
,W VeiTra'
118401481
w qr.
M.
Qat
01V1
ChVI
1 1. VI ri ta VI
tr.1
%,ft
41.11)
1-
Na vi
4r
N
1.1
if
n-ic+
:1 18? iMV--11 1
4m
VI
el i4'3.M23&
-t":3
ri
%/I
V:n NN
gv
AN
8\ 2 g v
1C)
-4 v1-4 co.a 71
WviOvIvir-4 r9 cn oN.o 74
O wr, -4 -4 r0 i-, 0
10 Q
P'1
0
19t
WI
g .1 if) g tie)
63
e+
11
-4
10
0%n F MovCSi 0
steal:piss
e ,T,DA-wagg
Z vt .P-01-4 cr.
n; t. A ) .1vi p CNV1
A i ..n o3 co co co
MH-4v11-1
v nes e.,3m0::$v.
83 V.eggi'l IU:411
MO AS
`43 1St ii s a
A
IR 0
Et C113131)
0
1-#
b)
CO t.4 CA 46' 0 14 c)
1:3 ctWat:
:esj
23 tS 23
113 1-+
IV
CO
i 4- CO us
!AV
I%)
P'w
VLa
TABU:A.-lb Individual Item and Item Group Mean .Difficulty Indicesby Grades on the Class Reasoning Test for All
Subjects on the Pre-test and Also for LDT Pre- and Post-tests.
All*
LDT
Subjects LDT
Pre Pre Post
Grades
o4
94
N =
25
25
All*
Subjects LDT
Pre Pre
103
06
LDT
Post
25
Subjects LDT
Pre
Pre
08
All*
LDT
Post
27 27
At least some As are not Bs.
25
:
All*
100
All*
Sub-
Pre
Pre Post
10
Sub-
jects LDT WI
Pre Pre Post
22
72
96 100 100
93
75
22
12
24 24
Item
Number
08
16
22
91
94
85
29
35
100
84
88
96
68
19
27
49
Mean
*
LDT's
***
loo
97
95 100
94
88
96
96
95
85
loo
92
92
93
89
95
93
96
85
100
93
89
93
91
92
91
95
loo
95
93
96
91
96
96
96 loo
93 96 96
92
35
28
84
96
64
8o
loo
88
35
6o
72
65
74
86
82 86
80 86
55 86
loo
694
86
5
75
30
68
89
96
94
95
96
99
93
89
78
72 90
71
83
55
82
LNDT- 2's
.** The basic
&L21DT1's &
symbolic form for each itemgroup is presented.
are
given
in
Chapter
IV
.
Variations
96
86
loo
92
97
100
loo
loo
96 96
100 loo
94
loo
95
99
96
100
92
loo
loo
96
96
100
98
96
62
25
56
4o
91
93 loo
92
31
92
85
8o
26
96
92
loo
91
Item
Number
07
76
96
92
99
91
39
Mean
96 100
96
88
100
96
100
76 loo
83
92
89 98
i guy 11,
RA
%%0'
ca
Vi
fV, R Cr:
tr
fil
pl
p.
g
o'S\
:a 8203%8
sa
6"
S Pa 803
..* in ...7 mp, CV MIA
Crl
'4'
UN CIO _Q CrICO
t'n
ATA431A
uN
uN
so
CO
t...-
Cu
UN
t....o.u.c...cncv
so vs 0 g....
V.
ON
co col u1
?4
(%8_,r41g.
a. 1"St8win
13
7 r-I
cr)
W%
UN
Al3
g. IVP8oVfl`..
8 PErtatts2
g
Mt
mnrTABLE-A-2
cont. 04
94 25 25
103
25
16
25
100
84
78
27 27 75 22
24
Item Group 06. All As are Bs. No Cs are Bs. : At least some As are Cs.
24
Item
Number
12
15
21
25
36
42
Mean
51
36
56
80
48
72
79
60
48
64
60
56
32
36
28
34
36
08
61
56
To
53
6o
92
100
80
52
56
86
91
82
85
91
91
93
97
96
7o
86
93
loo
loo
85
59
86
100
100
91
83
84
67
82
88
76
83
52
39
67
63 77 77
22
32
37
31
30
57
67
80
37
81
59
59 56
96
89
84
54 61
79 92 88
Item Group 07. All As are Ba. No Cs are As. : No Cs are Bs.
62
60
91
89
92
92
92
100
85
87
93
Item
Number
44
57
59
611.
70
77
33
22
48
34
32
20
52
40
Mean
34 36
Item Group 08.
48
53
65
68
71
75
Mean
12
48
56
34
45
35
20
50
53
20
24
56
52
48
32
32
60
56
38 41 47
39
52
48
52
36
48
27
79
73
68
88
36
75
79
83
73
63
82
6o
41
68
82
77
77
75
63
67
72
88
77
63
Item
Number
52
25
38
4o
38
46
31
29
37
lio
24
36
4o
36
28
34
3o
52
49
44
41
4o
42
36
64
64
52
56
28
50
42 36 52
57
59
66
44
42
68
54
68
46
50
56 55 73
88
63
TT
67
52
73
59
89
52 54 67
64
76
68
86
77
79
loo
92
86
79
92
96
55
91
73
50
82
68
65 75 88
96
64 84
78
74
54
71
92
67
92
83
88
72 83 90
04
Grades
08
o6
100 27
94 25 25
103 25 25
Item Group 09. All As are Be. : All Non -Bs are also Non-As.
N =
27
75
52
61
7o
59
81
76
60
10
22
22
12
72 24
24
Item
Number
45
33
4252
54
52
24
52
49
44
63
49
72
52
36
64
48
56
52
64
52
56
56
83
48
40
52
52
84
40
43
28
20
48
51
37
69
34
45
49
56
56
44
44
44
32
34
32
55
66
73
47
56
48
61
68
64
71
loo
54
67
24
39 46
44
56
79
32
41
65
54
63
58
81
47
59
57
93
52
59 77
64
82
68
73
96
55
91
50
64
64
Mean
51 49 53
56 54
68 68 73
59 To 65
Item Group 10. All As are Be. All Non-Cs are Non-Bs. : At least some As are not Ca.
68
67 88
76
86
79
83
96
96
65
83
50
83
67
71
58 78
88
83
86
Item
Number
62
67
72
76
Mean
44
4o
64
47
20
44
39
Number
47
61
52
44
54
59
60
3o
60
68
16
44
68
52
24
4o
28
58
63
78
Mean
56
75
33
52
36
46
43
41
87
35
47
46
48
68
76
48
56
56
56
6o
92
28
60
53
59
53
61
78
43
54
86
61
63
74
37
48
63
55
45 50 55
76
87
36
43
69
77
73
18
55
82
64
73
41
50
55
59 59 56
51 50 63
72
96
79
28
42
50
54
63
67
75
64
50
79
88
75
55 63 73
All Cs are Ds. All Bs are Cs. : At least some As are not Ds.
63 76 68
7o 78 85
74
62
75
68
48
56
4o
36
59
79
36
62
80
84
8o
64
68
24
65
75
75
66
82
80
45
66
VA5
86
79
81
85
85
74
85
81
83
81 77 64
93
96
loo
8o
82
68
71
93
57
73
77
41
64
SI.
77
79 74 78
72 67 83
92
loo
88
79
88
88
79
89
58
88
96
92
75
92
83
78 88 85
TABLE
A4
cont.
04
06
Grades
25 25
100 27
103 25 25
Item Group 12. No Bs are Cs. No Ds are Cs. All As are Bs.
N =
94
Item
Number
93
63
37
56
32
61.
47
52
46
56*
1 Z
54
49
48
44
68
48
60
56
56
Mean 50 46 58
63
34
64
36
12
56
67
63
32
52
84
48
64
72
80
53 43 70
10
08
71
55
89
68
56
78
73
Tz
TT
64
T8
27 75 22 22 72 24 24
: No Ds are As.
91
85 T9 100
To 57 59 77
69 71 100
85 85
82
78
57
55
78
85
TT
TT
79
84
86
T7
TT
91
72 72 83
59
71 92
68
88 92
96 88
78
72 81 94
Ay
on the Pre-Test.
Grades
2116
05
07
09
11
102
99
80
78
26
59
19
30
15
22
56
41
52
56
37
32
3.3.
30
27
31
40
Mean
23
14
27
27
43
43
10
29
52
23
33
19
35
11
43
26
29
-26
23
-15
0
15
-22
22
a5
18
26
34
Mean
-18
9
33
48
10
28
38
- 30
-22
- 30
5
- 9
29
38
43
-30
-18
17
-1
23
22
4
16t
0
5
26
15
- 7
-7
4
6
-13
18
4
414
43
29
Mean
27
24
14
67
36
-14
37
22
33
34
24
25
15
56
19
37
41
41
38
05
102
07
99
22
33
37
37
30
63
37
30
59
37
30
41
63
43
73
Mean
32
18
23
32
32
24
50
56
61
69
74
Mean
48
1
9
48
43
36
57
41
41
37
41
30
67
70
48
22
37
26
30
51
33.
lbp
14
32
o
9
14
14
it
0
-199
29
14
77
Mean
-4
0
-19
-22
-7
22
11
12
4
7
9
41
59
33
41
63
48
48
33
33
41
33
33
37
35
-22
9
9
43
27a
62
43
52
71
41
32
23
27
23
23
36
27
55
32
118
53
33
14
5
76
29
29
31
05
102
07
09
99
80
30
52
27
Mean
37
48
26
33
74
11
52
26
33
52
40
14
3.9
19
36
32
10
10
67
23
22
14
23
56
51
48
48
6
33
33
26
56
3o
41
62
67
72
76
Mean
22
41
36
55
57
55
48
50
36
43
43
27
48
14
38
39
46
Mean
48
52
22
26
10
63
41
41
36
36
32
27
36
52
30
29
23
-u
19
56
44
rlt
76
29
14
5
-15
48
53
65
68
71
75
11
. 7
Mean
15
. 7
18
18
4
0
0
5
3.5
-22
-5
19
-14
-33
- 5
0
The top and bottom groups fah each were compared were made up off'
27% of this N.
Table A.J.
Grades
Ob
Pm
Item Group 01.
94
Item Number
08
16
22
29
35
39
Mean
44
40
52
36
68
8o
53
06
103
08
100
21
18
32
15
75
0
14
19
50
30
10
5
5
5
5
23
21
33
30
59
10
5
30
30
26
10
0
15
5
15
15
10
07
14
19
27
4o
Mean
1$0
28
32
20
68
8
33
19
52
0
15
30
37
30
15*
25
45
0
30
15
20
36
28
52
24
4
24
32
43
25
43
61
39
48
37
-4
60
4o
52
52
52
43.
4o
36
21
29
15
37
56
25
45
55
45
Item lusher
09
13
18
23
26
Mean
441
57
33
24
32
5
40
50
30
10
20
26
30
?g
60
20
25
34
Table AA cont.
Grades
I Is
Item Grow 05.
04
94
06
08
10
l03
100
75
Item Amber
10
17
20
28
33
38
Mean
36
52
16
32
-4
18
14
7
30
4
4
50
3.1.
48
30
44
40
4
80
4o
36
ho
40
-1
16
25
43
14
20
5
25
15
10
10
33
33
15
20
-10
3.3.
23
52
33
30
5
55
25
ho
35
35
10
To
5
Item Amber
12
15
23,
25
36
42
Mean
43
14
71
56
52
38
7
27
15
-5
15
1.0
16
35
15
26
Item Amber
44
57
59
64
70
77
-12
-16
32
20
7
52
37
-7
71
29
61
43.
44
59
38
39
45
16
65
432
71
4
36
16
28
53
68
75
26
24
k ,
59
U
52
42
44
43
40
60
-15
35
30
ho
32
55
55
-5
70
bo
65
47
ap
V-SPA19
ra
II
Aes`kmv._Ir
g
P1-1
1 0o
jat
TABLE A.5.
Grade
LDT
17
9
ENDT-1
23
LET
26
ERDT-1
22
47.3
54.3*
77.6*
62.4
11
LND-1
LDT
24
L1111T-1
11-
LET
27
Total
Score
46.4
45.6
55.4
56.2
CF
24.2
21.5
29.025.7
SY
6.2
5.9
7.4
7.5
6.3
7.0
10.0*
7.8
su
5.6
5.5
6.5
6.2
5.2
6.0
9.2*
6.5
4.6
4.4
5.2
5.1
4.7
5.2
5.7
5.2
1.4
1.8
1.8
1.3
1.4
1.2
5.1
2.0
2.1*
1.0
3.13.4
2.1
1.2
1.7
1.5
4.8
1.7
4.6
3.9
3.9
4.8
3.9
4.8
3.8
4.6
5.2
5.1
4.0
4.1
2.3
3.8
5.1
3.4
1.2
1.8
1.8
2.4
4.7
2.6
5.2
4.6
5.1
4.4
4.6
5.3
5.1
.5.0
5.0
4.7
5.7
4.4
4.7
3.9
5.1
5.5
3.7
4.6
3.1
4.2
4.2
4.4
1.0
1.1
0.6
1.1
3.8
1.2
Group
26
25
Component
28.1*38.0*
31.8
Item
Group
4.03.9
4.o3.9
1.21.3
3.94.0
4.04.5
3.03.7
4.4
4.7
5.5
4.7
2.93.2
1.81.2
TABLE A-6.
Grade
Group
4
LDT
MDT -1
6
LND-1 WI'
LDT
NM
Total
44.8 47.3
63.8*
Score
10
15
LNLT-1 Wr
LNDT-1
Llif
68.1 65.4
81.4 77.3
36.7 35.1
40.7
7.5* 6.1
12
LIDT-1
87.8 82.6*
55.3
Compo-
nent
CF
26.2 26.8
34.8* 31.2
Sit
5.1
4.9
6.74
su
4.7
5.3
7.0
5.3
.6.2
7.8
41.0
43.7 42.1
9.1
7.9
10.3* 8.8
9.6
9.1
10.5
10.0
5.7
6.p
5.9
5.9
4.8
5.4
5.5
5.8
5.8
3.8
5.2
4.6
5.5
5.3
5.3
4.8
5.7
5.2
5.4
7.3
Item
Group
1
3.9
4.3
4.1
4.0
4.9
2.2
2.4
3.4
2.7
4.2
2.1
2.7
3.5
2.5
3.1 2.8
4.8
3.9
4.1
4.8
4.4
5.2 4.6
5.1
3.8
3.2
4.7
4.4
5.2 4.5
5.2
5.5
5.6
2.0
2.3
2.9
2.3
3.5 2.9
4.4
4.1
44 ce
2.1
2.2
3.1
2.8
4.1
2.8
5.2
4.4
5.5
4.9
3.2
2.9
4.0
3.4
3.7
4.0
4.5
4.o
5.2
4.8
10
2.3
2.2
3.6
2.7
3.2 3.4
3.5
4.5
4.2
4.3
11
2.6
2.6
3.8
3.4
4.7
4.6
4.9
5.4
5.1
5.2
12
4.0
3.8
4.6
3.7
4.9
4.1
5.2
5.5
5.7
5.4
An
asterisk
adjuiteed
is
moo:.
placed
0:1 et '4-'714
5.7
by
each
5.3
5.6
4.6
5.3
*5.7
statistically
3.9
5.2
significantly superior
TABLE A-7.
r
Item
Group
1
tirade
Test
Pre
Post
1h
27
66
Change
7
24
77
9
76
83
7
30
23.
Pre
Post
Change
Pre
Post
Change
Post
Change
24
35
35
11
11
49
- 2
56
Pre
Post
Change
Pre
Post
Change
Pre Post
Change
Pre
28
7
24
51
Pre
25
74
6
73
67
80
44
71
65
21
15
- 67
21
20
15
5
Post
71
83
Change
63
- 77
- 8
Pre
Post
Change
70
6
83
72
91
Pre
Post
Change
Post
Change
Pre Post
Change
50
76
48
78
-2
Pre
47
72
48
1
65
31.
30
-1
26
74
78
4
ea
97
9
15
34
24
9
84
29
41
31
68
11
11
17
50
94
53
59
63
71
82
11
68
65
87
58
37
67
86
19
28
53
80
-3
-21
33
5
91
27
71
79
88
80
-8
80
93
80
84
-13
68
62
-6
88
91
3
62
72
49
71
-7
-13
-1
16
13
28
10
18
62
44
-3
-18
TABLE A-8. Pre- and Post-Tests Percentages of LDT's Who Met the Sufficient
Condition for Mastery, and Percentages Who Failed to Meet the
Necessary Condition for Mastery of Principles of Conditional
Reasoning, By Item Group and Grade.
e
e
ng
Necessary Condition
5
11
9
27
26
24
17
04
17
24
08
aye
Sufficient Condition
Item
Group
1
grade
11
26
81
Test
Pre
27
48
24
17
54
53
63
15
59
5
53
Post
Change
Pre
04
Post
Change
Pre
22
18
85
00
00
00
59
77
04
00
0
06
65
08
-26
63
04
17
00
81
96
74
17
59
6
23
73
5o
33
74
-22
21
50
- 9
24
63
-11
41
25
4
21
47
- 6
Post
4
00
0
00
96
15
12
Change
Pre
19
13
-
91
12
-12
100
00
- 8
73
94
6
88
12
-61
81
82
12
-69
23
83
-
8
96
6
53
Pre
19
61
41
77
27
81
44
25
30
70
9
57
47
6
18
83
2
42
33
- 8
21
41
67
Post
Change
Pre
25
41
31
Post
Change
35
-22
00
06
81
39
35
38
13
92
76
-12
06
33
-34
96
94
12
-19
58
77
42
88
93
- 3
41
79
-13
21
82
-12
24
23
-35
00
18
6
12
15
15
00
12
0
08
8
41
08
12
4
23
Post
Change
26
Pre
o4
o
37
09
9
65
12
6
Post
Change
Pre
37
0
48
-17
65
12
Pest
Change
Pre
52
75
71
56
88
13
63
76
81
22
-15
10
Post
Change
Pre
47
81
52
59
4
50
41
- 6
29
89
8
52
0
56
17
0
47
6
11
Post
Change
Pre
29
41
50
19
07
46
4
04
18
-11
12
Post
Change
Pre
0
00
56
0
78
37
8
92
59
18
88
post
04
50
85
96
no
22
19
-
07
26.
-
00
4
06
17
37
-11
96
50
4
22
08
04
4
1.7
4
8
27
4
100
35
-65
4
In the neemarY conditon calms a minus sign In troutt of a change
Change
Note:
77
35
8
12
35
41
11
04
53
15
-
12
Item
Group
25
91
10
22
96
64
-12
68
97
6
74
93
- 2
72
96
98
- 1
84
89
70
2
34
86
12
45
90
18
90
98
9
85
38
56
84.
4
49
11
41
72
21
49
13
61
92
7
77
55
51
Post
Change
37
-12
65
14
69
78
80
19
80
78
1
88
Post
Change
69
4
54
80
11
82
87
9
92
84
4
81
95
7
91
84
88
4
40
85
Post
Change
61
7
36
56
93
2
70
Post
Change
34
- 2
39
47
6
42
59
19
54
75
19
64
77
7
83
34
- 5
49
50
8
54
67
13
70
84
20
68
90
7
'78
53
69
15
65
- 5
61
73
86
8
63
55
56
- 3
Pre
Post
Change
Pre Post
Change
Pre
Post
Change
Pre
Post
Change
Pre
Pre
Pre
Pre
Pre
Post
Change
Pre,
Post
Change
Pre
Post
Change
Pre
Post
4
25
76
24
8
27
95
Test
Grade
N=
4
47
56
52
41
5
59
99
74
73
10
88
83
78
85
43
77
72
-3
70
27
79
83
11
39
- 8
46
53
- 3
59
43
65
6
46
58
12
-3
Change
6
81
81
TABLE A-10. Pre- and Post-Test Percentages of Students Who Were Deliberately
Taught Class Reasoning Who Met the-Sufficient Condition Fbr
Mastery and Percentages Who Failed to Meet the Necessary Con-
Item
Gro
1
Test
Pre
Post
Change
Meeting The
Sufficient Condition
12
6
8
10
4
25
22
24
2
27
Grade
N=
50
-12
100
16
39
16
00
84
100
16
-4
00
O
00
31
20
04
05
35
04
-16
04
O
09
4
68
59
40
22
-37
To
82
Post
Change
58
76
32
89
19
86
4
Pre
04
16
30
Post
Change
04
0
12
44
28
56
26
77
36
84
89
-28
16
15
32
59
62
8o
63
46
08
4
46
28
12
26
11
59
84
25
65
63
88
31
44
-36
20
56
36
27
73
_7
04
18
-28
09
42
64
28
76
81
18
93
82
9
77
96
8
88
19
12
07
09
- 12
0
09
72
93
0
86
9
88
0
16
22
23
37
15
Pre
Post
Change
Pre
4
27
Post
Change
39
12
Pre
00
Post
Change
08
8
04
32
00
4
27
Post
Change
27
10
Pre
11
-4
79
46
8
08
08
04
5o
80
63
46
23
63
13
64
-16
52
26
36
71
20
12
16
44
18
41
68
32
41
79
8
5o
3o
-26
19
48
32
30
- 11
14
79
29
30
12
24
37
32
33
Post
Change
Pre
12
20
19
36
19
-18
67
36
4
46
Post
Change
15
- 4
36
0
74
7
64
18
Pre
Pbst
Change
Pre
16
08
Pre
35
20
67
Post
Change
42
7
64
44
78
u.
55
59
73
14
-u
32
14
-18
24
00
0
04
00
_4
08
04
_4
21
08
- 13
011
00
05
_4
0
36
55
27
-28
12
-25
16
56
- 13
23
13
- 8
46
11
37
-9
59
26
79
55
15
56
19
55
52
15
0
18
75
- 4
67
12
36
15
14
67
52
26
48
64
28
-36
15
4
04
-27
32
59
88
21
12-
44
Pre
Note:
96
42
12
96
0
Pre
Post
Change
89
-11
55
21
25
-21
08
17
9
08
00
-A
00
8
TABLE A.U.
Grade
CA
7.826
-.4261
IQ
SES
Total
Score
Compo-
:7480
18.62
.1179
-1.531
.0385
-.460
-.652
-;o584
.970
6.86
.0189
-.174
.419
.0803
-.127
2.37
o084
-.294
.503
.0614
-.120
2.77
.173
.0290
.011
1.94
-.018 -.0113
.614
1.68
-.472
.133
5.15
.495
nent
CF
2.760
SY
.845
su
.899
-.0372
.254
-.0166
.0155
-.056
1.307
-..0647
.0035
-.0914
1.379
-.0809
- .001
.0014
.0064
-.127
.423
.008
-.0039
.0190
-.082
-.275
.0367
.324
.39
.123
-.0193
0163
-.215
.747
.0761
.005
3.81
.648
-.0215
-.0142
.28o
.0137
.406
.51
.088
.0093
.0202
.082
.0282
.129
-.1424
-.olta
Item
Group
0062
.018
-.097
.0003
.0384
.314
1.26
rvy
clin
..
.271
.0173
.0224
-.097
-.453
.0192
.016
10
.177
-.0018
.0384
-.001
-.249
.0239
.305
11
- .322
.0176
.0123
.006
.638
.0757
alio
- 3.61
12
1.489
-.0954
-.0245
-.254
-.090
.0037
.029
.82
3.49
9.05
TABLE A-12.
Grade
Total
Score
CA
.116
-.5330
.4074
-1.332
.592
10.33
CF
5.327
-.2557
.1770
.457
-.495
11.21
sr
1.216
-.0531
.0443
- .169
.462
1.55
SU
1.211
-.0501
.0280
.280
.483
2.58
.402
-.0192
.0305
-.046
.211
1.38
1.640
-.0905
.0016
-.080
-.489
5.20
1.432
-.0841
.0060
-.059
-.558
5.66
.152
.0100
.0362
-.108
.464
-3.30
.263
-.0074
.0147
-.055
-.083
- .76
.512
-.0302
.0134
-.196
.757
2.96
Lilo
-.0430
-.0132
.069
.126
1.70
.113
.0033
.0360
-.085
.085
-.113
.0123
.0347
-.092
-.465
.75
10
.361
.0020
.0601
.010
-.279
-4.88
11
.056
.0098
.0469
.028
.728
-5.07
12
1.536
-.1003
-.261
-.017
10.72
Component
Item
Group
-.0308
.96
TABLE A-13.
IQ
Sex
Pre-Test
Score
.767
-1.250
.6209
.1555
.353
- .221
.0885
.415
-10.06
.0931
.0230
-.079
.237
.0289
.154
7.09
.0003
.0501
.197
.154
.0860
.104
6.06
.040 -.0009
.0212
.121
- .007
.0114
.668
- 2.21
.337 -.0257
.0254
.035
.025
.0242
.089
1.54
- .220
.0173
.407
.57
.036 -.0000
.396
3.58
1.08
Grade
CA
-.778
.2014
.3467
CF
-.049
.0450
SY
-.678
SES
Pre-Test
Score
tent
Total
Score
-39.46
Compo-
nent
SU
.160
Item
Group
1
2
3
-.112
.0229
-.0011
-.052
-.394
.0540
.0053
-.078
-.086
.0124
.0248
.002
.270
.0095
.170
-.246
.0251
.0286
.086
.275
.0144
.350
- 3.53
-.045
.0077
.0236
-.006
.181
.0304
.373
- 3.01
.057
.0135
.0104
.016
.084 -.0241
.430
.47
-.055
.0089
.0321
.092
.098
.0286
-.007
- 2.73
10
-.277
.0329
.0353
.107
.226
.0019
.297
- 5.31
11
-.092
.0124
.0302
.079
- .123
.0359
.149
- 3.71
.098 -.0051
.0128
- .175
.0294
.144
.77
12
.095
TABLE A-14.
Grade
CA
IQ
SES
Sex
Constant
Total
Score
.741
.2405
.6369
.593
-2.221
-50.54
Compo-
nent
CF
.636
.6191
.2835
.310
-.841
-12.43
SY
-.527
.0914
.0423
-.094
-.274
- 7.57
SU
.363
.0095
.0970
.172
-.299
8.17
-.003
5.78
Item
Group
.246
.384
-.057
-.215
-.057
-.0107
.0450
.103
-.0224
.0396
.037
.0335
.0202
.0448
.0074
-.072
.0145
.0316
.169
.0162
.0483
.228
.0049
.0441
.015
.0147
.200
.0181
-.0041
-.134
-.191
- 1.97
.000
.236
.83
.023
- 3.53
2.60
1.04
-.016
-.221
3.56
.011
-.278
- 1.47
.084
-.143
3.24
.125
-.341
6.06
.074
-.134
- 5.21
.082
-.253
.15
.0453
-.013
.0427
-.062
.0127
-.355
.0106
.95
-.006
-.312
.0436
.0547
.0321
100 II
a
90
8o
IP
0
41
10
20
60
30
9.4
I ..,
40
ammr=LLormarawriagamma
50
6o
To
80
90
100
Grath A-2,
Plotted Points:
4111
or
30
1111101011.
20
10
10
201H67-4-14-44--14
Difficult( Index
616.--IVIE100
100
ell
90 1--
6
80
111
I
10
20
30
40
60
Difficulty Indices
50
90
100
Plotted Points:
Graph A-4.
100
4011111.
Wil
tt.
20
10
10
IIIIII I.
eo
3o
4o
93
6o
To
11440'
80
90
100
APPENDIX B.
The following two tests, which are delicribed in Chapter IV, are
the ones that were used in this study. The copies appearing here are
exactly the same as those that were used.
Each consists of 22 pages with 78 numbered items, the first six
of which are sample items. Answers are given in Chapter IV, Tables IV-1
and IV-2.
The trial answer sheet, which was mentioned in Chapter IV, is
reproduced here in order to show the direction of our thinking in
extending these tests to the lower elementary levels.
TEST, FORM X
by
Robert H. Ennis
William L. Gardiner
John Guzzetta
Richard Morrow
Dieter Paulus
Lucille Ringel
MM.
Do not
write in
this space:
years
month
day
day
year
year
Your grade
Your school
Your regular teacher at this time
Today's date:
month
General directions:
This is a test to
We
call it
"conditional reasoning".
You will see that you already do some of this kind of
thinking.
The sample questions make clear what is expected.
There is a
If you
you
0 1964 by R. H. Ennis
Publidhed. by Cornell
Page 2
You will be given one or more sentences with which to think. You will then be given
another sentence, about which you must decide, using only what you were told.
There are three possible answers.
Sample questions:
Read the first question and see how it is marked.
1.
1.
B.
NO
C. MBE
The correct answer is A, "YES". If Bill is next to Samothen Sam must be next to
Bill. It must be true, so a circle is drawn around "rEsn.
Here is another sample.
2.
le".
A. YES
B. NO
C. MAYBE
then the
hawk
Page 3
3.
A. US
B. NO
C. MAYBE
be
The correct answer is C, "MAYBE ".
Even if Jane is standing near Betsy, Betsy might
sitting. Betsy might be standing
or
near Jane, but she might be sitting near Jane,
something else.
You were not told enough to be certain about it, so "MAYBE" is
the answer.
h.
YES
A.
B. N)
C. MAYBE
neer to California.
Page 4
So far in the sample questions you were told only one thing.
told two things. Circle your answer.
/ES
NO
The pit is inside the cherry.
MAYBE
The correct answer is C, "MaBE". All
are both in the mouth of the fox.
the cherry or not=
This time the letters "X" and "Y" are used. They can stand
for anything you like. Circle your answer:
6.
X is next to Y.
Then vould this be true?
B.
la
C. MAYBE
I is next to X.
The correct answer is Al "YES",
A. YES
If Xis next
Page 5
7.
7. A.
B.
YRS
ND
C. MUM
8.
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
9. A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
10. A.
YES
B.
ND
C.
mArm
Cornell Conditional
Page 6
A.
YES
93
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
N)
MAYBE
to W. Brown.
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
MD
C.
MAIBB
Cornell Conditional-Reasoning
Test,
Fbrm X
Page 7
enough to be
15.
that
is a Y.
There is not a Y.
Then would this be true?
15.
C. MAYBE
There is an X.
16.
A. YES
B. ND
yesterday
16. A.
B.
C.
yesterday
YES
NO
MAYBE
afternoon.
17. Suppose you know that
clay work.
Tom may use paints.
17. A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
Tom has
cleaned up
18.
A. YES
B. ND
C. MAYBE
Page 8
19.
19.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
A.
YES
Z
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
Test, Form X
Page 9
must be true.
It can't be true.
MAYBE It may be
enough
23.
can
fly.
23. A.
B.
C.
YES
BO
MAYBE
that
a pet dog.
Then would this be true?
24. A.
Bill has
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
Jerry is not
asked to
play ball.
home only if
true?
25. A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
green house,
is Jones.
green
house.
26. A. YES
B. ND
C. MAYBE
YES
It must be true.
IX1
It can't be true.
MAYBE It mey be true
Sue.
A.
YES
?X)
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
NO
If there is an X,
YES
MAYBE
then there is a Y.
There is a Y.
A.
YES
B.
N)
C.
MAYBE.
Page 11
31.
B.
YES
D3
C.
MAYBE
31. A.
Suppose you
horse.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
32. A.
know that
B.
YES
ND
C.
MAYBE
33. A.
34. A.
YES
B. ND
C. MAYBE
Page 12
35.
B.
YES
MO
C.
MAYBE
A.
..nommiorr
A.
BO
37
YES
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
Page 13
C.
39
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
41.
42.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
42;
Sally.
Page 14
43.
44.
C.
YES
IL)
MAYBE
43. A.
B.
44. A.
YES
B.
ND
C.
MAYBE
46.
45. A.
B.
YES
N3
C.
MAYBE
46. A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
Page 15
47.
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
48.
A.
YES
B.
C.
NO
MAYBE
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
49.
50.
Page 16
51.
51.
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
53.
52.
54.
53. A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
54. A.
YES
B.
N)
C.
MAYBE
Page 17
55.
56.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
55. A.
57.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
56. A.
58.
57. A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
B.
YES
N)
C.
MAYBE
58. A.
Page 18
59.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
60. A.
YES
B.
11)
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
Page 19
63.
true?
B.
YES
BO
C.
MAYBE
63. A.
65.
Suppose you
B.
YES
BO
C.
MAYBE
64. A.
know that
A.
YES
BO
There is a Z.
MAYBE
A.
YlS
B.
C.
jumping rope.
NO
MAYBE
Page 20
67.
68.
B.
YES
13
C.
MAYBE
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
67. A.
68.
69.
70.
70.
Page 21
71.
72.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
71. A.
72. A.
73.
YES
B.
1134
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
box.
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
Page 22
It can't be true.
MAYBE It may be true or it may not be true. You weren't told
enough to be certain whether it is "YES" or "NV.
75.
75.
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
76. A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
4111.1111111110fillMIIDI
YES
MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
END OF TEST.
by
Robert H. Ennis
William L. Gardiner
Richard Morrow
Dieter Paulus
Lucille Ringel
DO not
write in
this space:
years
.1111111111.
month
day
day
year
year
Your grade
Your school
Your regular teacher at this time
month
Today's date:
General directions:
call
it "class reasoning".
thinking.
answer, but are not sure, mark that answer. But if you have
no idea, then skip the question.
1964 by R. H. Ennis
We
Ithaca, N.Y.
Page 2
In answering each question, use only what you are told in that question. In
order to do this, you should imagine that your mind is blank, because some of the
things you are told are obviously false. Even so, you should suppose that they are
true--for that question only.
You will be given one or more sentences with which to think. You will then be
given another sentence, about which you must decide, using only what you were
told.
The meaning of the possible answers is given at the top of each page to
you remember.
Each question has only one correct answer.
help
Mark your answers on this booklet by drawing a circle around the right answer.
Remember: If you have no idea what the
to
answer is, skip the question and go on
the next.
Do not guess wildly, but if you think you know, then answer the
question.
Sample questions:
A.
NO
MAYBE
'01
2.
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
Page
3.
A. YES
B. NO
C. MAYBE
Circle the answer to this next sample question. Remember that your mind is
supposed to be blank at the beginning of each question.
4.
4.
A. YES
B. NO
C. MAYBE
Remember:
You should suppose that that you are told is true -- for the
question you are answering.
Page 4
answers:
So far in the sample questions you were only told one thing.
A.
YES
B.
C.
BO
MAYBE
All you are told is that the pit and the cherry are
both in the mouth of the fox. There is no way to be certain tether the pit is in the
cherry or not.
X is next to Y.
Then would this be true?
Y is next to X.
A. YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
If X is
IDIDTODO SO.
Page 5
T.
C.
MAYBE
YES
8. A.
B.
YES
NO
T. A.
B.
760
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
BO
C. MADE
10.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
1.111111111111111
Page 6
41111111111101111111111111111011110111.1.1111011111.16,
11.
12.
11. A.
B.
C.
YES
NO
MAYBE
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
12. A.
13. A.
B.
C.
YES
NO
MAYBE
Jean's.
C.
/ES
NO
MAYBE
Page
C., MAYBE It may be true or it may not be true. You weren't told
enough to be certain whether it is "YES" or "NO".
15.
Then would
this be
true?
MAYBE
16. A.
YES
B.
BO
C.
MAYBE
that
C.
17.
B.
YES
NO
15. A.
I17. A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
18. A.
Page
0101.101111
=11111111111111110111110M111111111,
A.
YES
BO
MAYBE
YES
BO
MAYBE
Suppose you know that
A.
At least
NO
2?.
YES
MAYBE
At least
A.
YES
ND
MADE
Page
23.
23.
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
24.
25.
25.
26. A.
B.
C.
YES
BO
MAYBE
Page 10
answers.
27.
27. A.
NO
C.
MAYBE
28. A.
YIPZ
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
30
B.
29.
YES
29.
A.
YES
B.
AO
C.
MAYBE
30. A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
Page 11
Test, Ibrm X
31.
"YES" or "non.
31.
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
Yaw
YES
32. A.
B.
NO
MAYBE
A.
YES
B. NO C..
MAYBE
11111!,
Suppose you know that
All X's are Y's.
All Z's are Y's.
Then would this be true?
At least some Z's are X's.
34.
YES
A.
B. NO
C. MAYBE
Page 12
The Cornell Class-Reasoning
Test, Form X
answers.
can't be true.
yellow.
35.
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
36.
C.
made of wood.
MAYBE
37.
A. YES
B. NO
C.
A. YES
B. NO
MAYBE
38.
A. YES
B. NO
C. MAYBE
Page 13
39.
4o.
39. A.
B.
C.
YES
NO
MAYBE
All the cookies Jane made for the fair had nuts
in them.
All the cookies with nuts in them were sold.
Then would this be true.
41.
YES
NO
C. HAM
sold.
Suppose you know that
40. A.
B.
41. A.
B.
YES
NO
C. MAYBE
42. A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
Page lei
43.
43.
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
44.
45.
46.
46. A.
B.
YES
1)
C.
MAYBE
Page 15
YES
It must be true.
NO
It can't be true.
MAYBE It maybe true
A.
YES
NO
pencils in the box are
MAYBE
not sharp.
None of n
are wool.
A.
NO
At least
49.
YES
up
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
NO
MAYBE
All fast
No horses
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
Page 16
41111
Here is a reminder of the meaning of the possible answers.
51.
51. A.
B.
52.
C.
YES
N3
MAYBE
53.
52. A.
B.
YES
N3
C.
MAYBE
53. A.
54.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
B.
YES
ND
C.
MAYBE
driving test.
All people who are allowed to drive have a
license.
Then would this be true?
At least one of Bill's uncles has not passed a
driving test.
54.
Page 17
55.
55.
A. YES
B. NO
C. MAYBE
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
57 A.
NO
58.
YES
MAYBE
on Route 55.
Then would this be true?
58.
A.
B. NO
C. MOM
Page 18
YES
N3
No Z's are X's.
MAYBE
Suppose you know that
All teachers
A.
YES
NO
MAYBE
YES
C.
NO
MAYBE
not swimmers.
Frances is a swimmer.
Then would this be true?
A.
YES
NO
BUBB
Page 19
MAYBE
It may
64.
A. /ES
B. ND
C. Man
A. US
BD
MAYBE
Jo Vs are I's.
No I's are Ils.
Then would this be true?
At least some Z's are X's.
65.
A.
!NB
JO
)SAM
moil's pencil
is not red.
A. =3
NO
MADE
Test, Form X
Page 20
Then
68.
C. MAYBE
that
this
be true?
At
A. YES
B. M)
67.
flowers
68. A.
B.
C.
EIS
NO
MAYBE
69.
that
are
Dick's.
69. A.
us
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
All the people who live near the lake can swim.
None of the students in Mr. Smith's class live
near the lake.
Then would this be true?
At least
KM
70. A.
B.
YES
NO
C. MADE
Page 21
71.
71. A.
B.
C.
YES
NO
MAYBE
72. A.
B.
C.
YES
NO
man
1
73.
A.
YES
B.
NO
C.
MAYBE
A.
YES
B.
NO
C. NUN
Page 22
75.
75.
A.
B.
YES
N)
C.
MAYBE
A.
B.
YES
NO
C.
MAYBE
76.
TT.
Tr.
A. =3
B.
Ito
C.
MAYBE
END OF TEST.
78.
A. YES
B. 113
C. MADE
Students
Name:
ril
P5-]
45 N.
YES
NO
MAYBE
MAYBE
SKIP
SKIP
15
MAYBE
SKIP
YES
NO
MAYBE
NO
MAYBE
MAYBE
SKIP
SKIP
map
NUE
I
a=
SKIP
34
Class Reasoning Exercises Used in 10th and 12th Grades, Consisting of Three
Used Early in the Instructional Period and One Used at the Ehd.
Name
Exercise 1.
Define "set"
e.
b.
c.
d.
a.
Redefine "set"
Define "element"
books -
b.
dogs
C-2
Ekercise 1, continued
nations A
subjects taken in school days of the week List five objects in this room which are elements of sets:
a.
b.
c.
d.
e.
C.3
Miran 2
Name
Each of the following pairs of words includes one set and one element
of that set.
subjects in school
subjects in school
American History
American History
teachers
Mr. Morrow
Monday
days of the week
newscasters
Chet Huntley
this
trout
fish
logicians Leonhard
Euler
you
students of logic
birds
Wes- blooded animals
Name
Exercise 3.
universities state
universities
American nations
North American nations
summer months
months
suits
clothing
things
*Leh
entertain
movies
presidential candidates
Republican presidential candidates
Redefine the relationship of total inclusion, using your own words and
without
looking back
C-5
Quiz
Name
If the conclusion
either can't follow or may or may not follow, circle the word "INVALID".
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
ValidInvalid
At least some Republicans do not support Rockefeller. All
the Cayuga County supervisors are Repbulicans.
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
ValidInvalid
c-6
At least some Finns oppose Communism. No
Marxists oppose Communism. Therefore,
no Finns are Marxists.
ValidInvalid
At least some doctors are not surgeons. All
brain specialists are surgeons.
Valid
Invalid
ValidInvalid
At least some cameras are expensive.
At least some Japanese products are not expensive.
Therefore, at least some cameras are not Japanese products.
Valid
Invalid
Invalid
Invalid
ValidInvalid
C-7
ValidInvalid
At least acme cancers can be cured.
Nothing that can be cured is a terminal case.
Therefore, at least acme cancers are not terminal cases.
ValidInvalid
chief.
T.
conned.
c-8
fail the
Ithaca team.
scrabble.
York.
C-9
'ftercise 2'
2.
3.
Premise
Premise
Conclusion
Therefore, (
Premise
Premise
Conclusion
Therefore, (
Premise #1
Premise #2
Conclusion
Therefore, (
If (Joe makes that free throw), (we will win the game).
)
(there is a square)
)
)
4.
5.
Premise
-
Premise
Conclusion
Therefore, (
Premise
Premise
Conclusion
Therefore, (
Premise-
7.
8.
of legs)
If (John is a junior),
eggs)
Premise
Conclusion
Premise
Premise
Conclusion
Therefore, (
Premise
Conclusion
Therefore, (
Premise
1
(
)
)
Therefore, (
antecedent)
9.
Premise
Premise
Conclusion
Therefore, (
C-11
'ftercise 3'
Study each of these arguments,
If
you
pass
all
your
tests,
you
Will
Valid
pass
Invalid
the
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
Lemonade is bitter if
Valid
Invalid
If
ve
win
the
slalom,
then
we'll
Valid
have
Invalid
gold
Valid
Invalid
If p, q.
P.
Therefore, q.
Valid
Invalid
C-12
q if p
Therefore, p.
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
C-13
'Ekercise 14,
Name
if this questionnaire asks whether the person thinks slave labor wrong,
if there is at least 90% response, and if everyone tells the truth - then,
the community really thinks slave labor is wrong, if at least 80% say they
members of Smithtown, and it asked whether they thought slave labor was
wrong.
Therefore,
it is false that at least 80% of the adults of Smithtown said that they
think slave labor is wrong.
Steps
1.
2.
3.
4.
5
6.
7.
8.
9.
Reasons:
c-3.4
Reasons:
12.
etc.
Grade
Name
Date
Directions: Read the arguments carefully. Then using the Euler circle,
diagram them.
each question.
Parisians
Frenchmen
are
Frenchmen.
are
Europeans.
All
All
Good 'Blinking!
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
All Europeans are people.
All Parisians are people.
4.
a) Valid
All rainbows are trout.
b) Invalid
a) Valid
b) Invalid
C15
C-16
No A's are B's. No
B's are C's. No
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
Valid
Invalid
correct.
conclusion.
If
this
is
Buick,
then
it
is
an
If you like ice cream, then you will eat it often. You do eat
ice cream often.
Therefore, you like ice cream.
If
this
is
book,
then
it
has
is
C-18
If zebras have stripes, then so do tigers.
Zebras do not have stripes.
C-19
If
vheee
0000m,
then
g000sh
braaack.
Wheee
0000m.
Either you like sunny days or you like rainy days. You like
sunny days.
Therefore, you like rainy
days.
I f %, then S.
Not $.
Therefore, not %.
If you are old enough, you may stay up until 9:00 P.X.
C-20
This is a simple machine, if it is a pulley.
This is not a simple machine.
Therefore, nothing follows necessarily.
Therefore, hee.
25.
C.21
This is a wedge only if it is not a pulley.
It is a wedge.
ERRORS
H. P. Grice
'deliberately'.
g should read:
Cronbach's
inconsistent
content..."
N=82.