Hernando de Soto The Mystery of Capital PDF
Hernando de Soto The Mystery of Capital PDF
Hernando de Soto The Mystery of Capital PDF
BOOK REVIEWS
Edited by N. Stephan Kinsella*
99
A similar analysis of the U.S., Hong Kong, and India can be found in John
Stossel, Is America Number One?, ABC News Home Video, 1999, videocassette. Stossel found that he could go into business in Hong Kong in one
day, and in New York City in a few weeks, but in India it would take several
months at least, and possibly several years.
100
Book Reviews
total direct foreign investment made during the 1990s into all Third
World and former communist countries.
But how could the simple formal recognition of property be the
solution for the development of Third World and former communist
nations? Continuing along the same line, de Soto argues that easy and
universal access to formal property would allow people to generate
productive capital. Formal property enables people to think about
assets not only as physical materials, but also as the description of
their latent economic and social qualities (p. 51). It integrates dispersed information into one standardized and integrated legal representational system, thereby making people accountable, since it shifts
the legitimacy of the rights of owners from the politicized context
of local communities to the impersonal context of law (p. 54).
The standardization that brings about formal property also serves
to make assets fungible, thereby reducing transaction costs involved
in mobilizing and utilizing assets. Moreover, these effects convert
people into a network of individually identifiable and accountable
business agents through which they can conjoin their assets into more
valuable combinations (p. 61). Finally, this network created by a formal property system constitutes a protection of property records (titles
and contracts) every time they are involved in transactions in time and
space.
Reduced to its bare essentials, de Sotos argument is that an easy,
universal, and integrated system of formal property enables people
to use their assets to produce and accumulate capital. Hence, the argument runs, formal property is the key to the division of labor and
increase of productivity; thus, it is the key to the success of capitalism in the Third World and former communist nations. Likewise, in
the international arena, it is the tool with which to take advantage of
the globalization process.
In order to illustrate his argument, de Soto turns to the American
experience. He shows that the problems now facing Third World and
former communist countries are not new. Not so long ago, the citizens of North America had to struggle against their governments and
their privileged elites in order to receive recognition of their property
over the resources they already controlled. Only then did the U.S. begin the process of capitalization that made this country what it is today: a rich, capitalized country.
There may be nothing logically wrong with this explanatory chain,
so far as it goes. Unfortunately, as soon as you go beyond the main
101
102
Book Reviews
opportunity. But for the moment, to achieve those goals,
capitalism is the only game in town. It is the only system
we know that provides us with the tools required to create massive surplus value. (p. 228)
Another interesting question is who should be in charge of recognizing ownership, since this is the way that de Soto plans to solve the
whole problem. For the author, the answer is clear: the State, through
its group of managers (the government), is the ideal agent to remedy
the chaos created through its previous policies. In fact, de Sotos vision of government is not one that passively allows people to arrange
their own lives; rather, he desires a government that actively moves
people in the right direction (possibly through the governments
contracting with a private company that will search for the needed
information). Thus, de Soto reasons that
[c]itizens inside and outside the bell jar need government
to make a strong case that a redesigned, integrated property system is less costly, more efficient, and better for the
nation than existing anarchical arrangements. (p. 159)
In view of all this, it should not amaze anybody that the author
dedicates six pages to the bright side of Marx (pp. 21218). While
do Soto is clearly not a Marxist, his facing up to Marxs ghost turns
out to be a cheerful reading of several Marxist concepts, especially
his class theory. For example, de Soto writes that when people are
extremely dissatisfied, the Marxist tool kit is better geared to explain
class conflict than capitalist thinking, which has no comparable analysis or even a serious strategy for reaching the poor in the extralegal
sector (p. 213). Marx divides social classes according to ownership
of the means of production, and de Soto adapts this theory to his main
claim, i.e., that classes exist because some people have access to formal property, while others do not; the latter, then, are condemned to
poverty (p. 213).
Although this view is popular and prevalent, it is incorrect. One
can hardly contend that Marxist class theory is richer in explanatory
103
See Franz Oppenheimer, The State: Its History and Development Viewed
Sociologically, trans. John M. Gitterman (New York: B.W. Huebsch, 1922).
104
Book Reviews
Finally, the book seems to follow from a good intuitionthat
you cannot have development without respect for property, and that
you cannot understand poverty or underdevelopment while disregarding the formal situation of property rights. But in the book itself, this
argument goes only so far. You cannot hold that, once you create a
framework where formal property is easily accessible for everyone,
development will be attained. It is true that, once you have a society
where legitimately acquired property is respected, development would
obtain or, at least, the best possible condition for development would
exist.
This environment can be reached by a voluntary restraint on aggression against other peoples property, or by using force to defend
legitimately acquired property. In the case where others do not engage
in voluntary restraint, we will need to defend property against aggressors. Such a defense can be undertaken directly by the property owner, or by contracting for it with a third party or agency. In this context,
formal property is just one factor that can be helpful in the defense
of property rights.
We still have to look at what kind of institution or agency would
certify this formal property, and, what is even more important, at the
very definition of property rights that the agency would use. During the
National Socialist period in Germany, formal property was respected
more fully than in many developed countries, but this did not prevent
property from being practically and legally managed from the Reichstag. Given enough time, the productivity and capital structure in Germany would have collapsed in a way similar to its subsequent collapse
in socialist countries.
Ultimately, and contrary to de Soto, while the formalization of
property rights might be of great importance for their respect and,
hence, for the development of a society, it is neither a sufficient nor
a necessary condition.
GABRIEL CALZADA LVAREZ
Universidad Complutense
de Madrid
105