Interactive Time Travel
Interactive Time Travel
Interactive Time Travel
CITATIONS READS
6 28
1 author:
Ezequiel Di Paolo
Ikerbasque - Basque Foundation for Science
173 PUBLICATIONS 3,970 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related
projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Ezequiel Di Paolo on 02 October 2015.
Interactive Time-Travel
On the Intersubjective
Retro-modulation of Intentions
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
Correspondence:
Ezequiel Di Paolo, Ikerbasque, Basque Foundation for Science, Spain; Univer-
sity of the Basque Country, Spain; Centre for Computational Neuroscience and
Robotics, University of Sussex, UK. Email: ezequiel.dipaolo@ehu.es
important in what follows our bodies are often moved by the world
even when we do not intend to move.
That this self-understanding can often be radically enhanced while
engaging with others is not news. As participatory sense-making
works by modulating interpretive attitudes towards both the other and
myself, the meaning of events, moves, and utterances remains open as
their place in the interactive organization is negotiated. There is,
through this open temporality, an element of retroactivity at play,
which is applicable, because of my self-opaqueness, not only to the
intentions of others but also to my own. Making sense in participation
has a wide temporal focus, and therefore meaning does not emerge in
discrete packages but is always unfinished as other participants and
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
[1] One could speculate that the experiential roots that motivate the causal story have been
influenced by taking these crystallized forms of reflective self-knowledge as given: not as
the achievement of a full body activity but instead as so-called inner mental states, moti-
vations, desires, and goals. As self-explicitation gives the appearance of a separation
between such mental states from other facets of the act to which they still bear an inner
relation, it is not a big leap to posit that this relation is one of causality (an answer to a
why-question) between an intention reflectively disengaged from other parts of the act,
i.e. the acts effective or expressive world coupling.
INTERACTIVE TIME-TRAVEL 53
intended but not always the most reliable one (Pippin, 2010). The
interpretation of this disclosure is a temporally extended process
always open to some degree of negotiation, as we shall see, particu-
larly in live interactive situations.
Asking how best to interpret the intersubjective retrospective deter-
mination of intentions in Hegel, Laitinen (2004) describes as
epistemic the possibility of a retrospective awareness, justification,
and appropriation of our intentions-in-action. He finds this epistemic
sense unproblematic as it simply involves an achieved reflection on
our past actions and motivations and so any notion of retrospection
is limited to the (not necessarily trivial) explicitation of motives. For
the enactive, non-causal notion of intentions-in-action this reflexivity
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
would in itself constitute a change to our acts and our intentions. The
passage from corporeal to reflective intentionality, as I discuss below,
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
2. Enacting Intentions
As a first step, we should examine whether an intention-in-action is
best conceived as a simple actual event. In the causal view this must be
the case because it is after all its efficacy in determining the conditions
and motivations for action that compels it not to post-date the act
itself. Here the enactive notions of autonomy, adaptivity, and sense-
making can help delineate a different conception of intentions. I turn
now to a brief explanation of these terms.
For the enactive approach, an autonomous system is an operation-
ally closed organization, whereby precarious processes form a net-
work via two conditions: 1) each process in the network is enabled by
at least another process in the network, and 2) each process in the net-
work is an enabling condition for at least another process in the net-
work2 (Di Paolo, 2005; 2009; Di Paolo and Thompson, 2014;
Thompson, 2007). The outcome of the operation of all these processes
is the sustaining of the closed organization in time, its systemic iden-
tity. This closure is organizational, not interactional, which means of
course that there are dependencies and influences on processes
affect, and related (but not identical) usages of the term virtual by
Bergson and Deleuze. For our purposes, we additionally use the rich
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
and-now. By this I mean that, given the current situation, not only the
actualized states matter to the sense-maker but also the virtual traces
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
and tendencies that surround these states, whether they become actu-
alized or simply modified but not necessarily actualized in the course
of events.
From a dynamical systems vantage point, this is no surprise. Let us
consider three widespread characteristics that become obvious when
agents are considered in dynamical terms. 1) The current state of a
system reflects a history of changes that the system has undergone
over time. In this way, past events are brought to bear on the current
situation and so the accumulation of experience allows the agent to
discriminate between different contexts when exposed to identical
sensory perturbations. 2) The behaviour of the agent as a dynamical
system depends on its limit sets, i.e. the macro-configuration of states
that need not be actually ever visited by the system. Since through
continued coupling with the environment the agent is able to reach
different areas of state space, from different initial conditions the
agent may then follow different tendencies as determined by the
attracting and repelling sets. Experience can therefore tune those limit
sets globally such that the agents movement through state space cor-
responds to the desired response that a given situation solicits. 3)
Future tendencies depend on how the agents dynamics moves
towards the limit set in whose basin it finds itself; asymptotic states
need not ever be reached (actualized) or even known, but they never-
theless exert an influence in these tendencies.
One by one, these properties bear a correspondence with three key
aspects of Merleau-Pontys notion of motor intentionality (Burhmann,
Di Paolo and Barandiaran, 2013; Burhmann and Di Paolo, 2014). 1)
The accumulation of experience serves to discriminate, with increas-
ing specificity, situations that solicit a particular response (separation
58 E. DI PAOLO
level or stepping along the border of the terrace of a tall building, even
if the sensorimotor trajectories that should be actualized are nearly
identical. For the average pigeon the two situations are similar. This is
because both are differently sensitive to risks and have different
capacities to respond to them.
Act and intention are not separable but they correspond to different
aspects of sense-making. The latter is an operation on virtual fields
whose consequences are both actual and virtual, which involves a pro-
cess of actualization with overt and introvert phases. Therefore, I pro-
pose to use the term intention to describe the virtual configuration
surrounding the current situation including the agents tendencies and
capacities and how this configuration relates to the agents self-sus-
tained identity. I propose to use the term action to describe any actual-
ization process that ensues in the context of an intention and which
tends to modify the virtual configuration in ways that avert risks and
exploit opportunities for the agents viability. This of course includes
overt behaviour but it also includes actualized bodily self-affection,
feelings, and any form of introvert explicitation of intentions. To per-
sonally experience ones own intention and to get to know it, in this
sense, is already part of an act. We can call this part of the act its mani-
fested intentionality.
This is quite different from the causal model of intentions. Never-
theless, the temporal thickness of sense-making and its relation to vir-
tuality can be described concretely both dynamically and phenomeno-
logically and studied empirically and through models. There is no
magic involved.
In summary, to intend and to act in enactive terms are respectively
the virtual and the actualized aspects of an agents active engagement
INTERACTIVE TIME-TRAVEL 59
with the virtual field that surrounds a current situation, with the aim of
making sense of this virtual field and changing it by modulating actual
states. This virtual field is never fully exhausted as we have said, nor,
crucially for our discussion, forever fixed.
3. In the Thick of It
According to our proposal, it is misleading then to conceive of an
intention as an event on a par with a movement, or a physiological
change those are already processes of actualization and therefore
parts of an act. This conception, needed for the causal view, often goes
together with another habitual assumption that we should also ques-
tion. This is the assumption that the undetermined intentional situa-
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
tion is poorer than the determined one, as if the state prior to a formed
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
ing term; and yet the founding term is not primary in the empirical sense
and the founded is not merely derived from it, since it is only through
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
dations (not merely reveal them), and it is only when those alterations
predispose the body to repetitions that a habit establishes itself in this
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
particular mode of relation to the world. The related terms are there-
fore continuously modulated by the relation they sustain as the act
of walking and the laying down of the proverbial enactive path.
What this tells us is that even if we dont conceive of intentions and
acts as discrete, casually linked events there is an inner logic that
relates both terms as aspects of corporeal intentionality. The inner
relation flows both ways, so that the intentional aspect the rich
intentional reservoir is permeable to modification by actualized
action.
We reach then a more sophisticated perspective on the problem. 1)
The efficacy of intentions involves elements of the virtual as well as
actualized manifestations. 2) The original state prior to a determined
intention (the core intentionality of precarious, concernful life) is
already intentional in a rich sense, and so the body is capable of
engaging in action before specific intentions reach their full determi-
nation. 3) The relation between bodily intentionality and its explicita-
tion/determination, be it in the form of explicit acts or reflective
consciousness, is mutual (leaving intentional aspects open to ongoing
alteration by the very acts they found).
One can argue that even within this perspective a strong ontological
retroactivity of intentions is still inconceivable since the act, however
undetermined, must have certain conditions for it to count as such, and
these must cohere with its intention, however undetermined. This may
but need not happen strictly prior to the overt act but apparently it
could never happen after the act, because the act itself is an actualiza-
tion of the intention. This argument, which makes sense from a meth-
odological individualistic standpoint, loses its strength as we regard
the process of social interaction.
INTERACTIVE TIME-TRAVEL 63
[3] See also the relevant discussion on the passage between the Fundierung and reversibility
models in the case of Merleau-Pontys thinking about language in Dillon (1988).
66 E. DI PAOLO
a couple of days ago I was having dinner with my partner and a friend.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
At some point, I was cutting some cheese for myself. I noticed my part-
ner looking at the cheese and thought I would offer him some, because it
looked like he might want some. When I did so, he accepted it. I asked
him whether he had wanted it while looking at the cheese before (i.e.
while I had noticed him looking at it and he had noticed me looking at
him and it), and he said that he had not really. The desire for cheese in
this case only crystallised at the point of accepting the slice from me.
This indicates that fresh intentions can sprout from interactions and that
what may often happen is that we back-track, newly emerged meaning
in hand, and stick this meaning onto our previous actions. It may have
looked like he wanted the cheese, since I noticed him looking at it
before, but in fact, the desire only took shape at the point of receiving it.
(De Jaegher, 2009, p. 549)
A similar example5 involves a tired couple at a party that has been
going on for a long time. Across the distance they regard each other
and at one point she raises her arm and with a finger touches her wrist
close to her watch to alleviate some discomfort. Interpreting her
move, he says: Youre right, its rather late and maybe we should
leave, to which, looking back at her watch, she readily agrees
realizing that she had been trying to convey the very message her part-
ner interpreted in her move. A third example is what reportedly hap-
pens occasionally between experienced tango dancers which they
describe as an experience of deep connection during the dance or as
dancing as one. The leader sees his moves interpreted correctly by
the follower before they even have a chance to start forming. This
could happen because the experienced follower is reading the
leaders body better or faster than he himself is. Before the founded
[5] I first heard Sanneke de Haan describe this example in a talk. The situation is a reworking
of an example by Pierre Jacob and Marc Jeannerod.
INTERACTIVE TIME-TRAVEL 69
changed by the further act of owning ones part in a social act. A deed
becomes an action because it does follow reasons, only not our know-
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
possibly that I had a desire for it before, but not an explicit one. But in
general we cannot say that the act was aimed at obtaining this effect. If
in some circumstances we could affirm this, it would still be a case of
realizing something I secretly intended, i.e. a narrowly epistemic ret-
rospection. In contrast, what occurs in participatory sense-making is
that individual acts run as it were along two braiding intentional paths,
those of the individuals involved and those of the interactive autono-
mous dynamics, and there is an ongoing tension and ambiguity
between these domains. The retroactive modulation of intentions is
simply one particularly unintuitive way in which this ambiguity can
get resolved. The event that triggers a retro-modulation of intentions
is not simply an unexpected consequence of my action on the other,
but an unresolved interactive tension that literally moves me to seek a
resolution in how my intentions, in their virtual aspects, are retroac-
tively coherent with the others response.
In summary, the retroactive and intercorporeal determination of an
individual intention is not just narrowly epistemic, even though it
involves phases of reflection, re-signification, and appropriation.
Here we reiterate that our departure point is twice removed from tradi-
tional analyses. Firstly, we start from a past state rich in virtual possi-
bilities for regulation, not a void, intention-less state. Secondly, we
consider the body as participant: its resources used in co-regulating
engagement in interaction. It is the heteronomy to which we submit
while we interact that (often literally) moves us. These moves them-
selves find a place within the multiple virtual tendencies that inform
and shape regulation and simultaneously, after the fact, change their
status from foreign into ours by becoming acts first and then inscrib-
ing an intention in the past.
INTERACTIVE TIME-TRAVEL 71
5. Conclusion
If we accept the possibility that interactive processes can (sometimes)
play constitutive roles in social cognition and participatory forms of
sense-making in general (De Jaegher, Di Paolo and Gallagher, 2010),
then we must admit that it is possible for such processes to intervene in
the complex constraining relations between individual actions and
intentions. This possibility implies the definitive abandonment of the
linear-causal model of intentionality in favour of the enactive model
sketched above.
While this may look like a lost battle for the autonomy of individual
agency (we may be more determined even in our personal intentions
by our social world than we care to admit), the intersubjective modu-
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
lation of intentions that can take place in the thick, tentative present is
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
the bodys precarious existence and feed its needs (in both senses: sat-
isfying and perpetuating them) by altering it, moving it, and delimit-
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
ing it, but also by enabling its biology, scaffolding it, and accompany-
ing it.
The retroactive modulation of intentions in participatory sense-
making, whether rare and merely a conceptual marker in the logical
space of enactive theory or frequent and deserving of further study,
would always involve an individual gesture of acceptance and appro-
priation of this relational social flow. The result can empower our own
personal projects as well as constrain them.
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Hanne De Jaegher, Elena Cuffari, and two anonymous
reviewers for comments that helped improve this paper. This work is
supported by the Marie-Curie Initial Training Network, TESIS:
Towards an Embodied Science of InterSubjectivity (FP7-PEO-
PLE-2010-ITN, 264828).
References
Bavelas, J.B., Coates, L. & Johnson, T. (2000) Listeners as co-narrators, Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, pp. 941952.
Beer, R.D. (2003) The dynamics of active categorical perception in an evolved
model agent, Adaptive Behavior, 11 (4), pp. 209243.
Bergson, H. (1934) La pense en le mouvant. Essais et conferences, Paris: Flix
Alcan.
Buhrmann, T., Di Paolo, E.A. & Barandiaran, X. (2013) A dynamical systems
account of sensorimotor contingencies, Frontiers in Psychology, 4, p. 285.
[6] Heidegger arguably does see the world of social practices as constitutive of individual
meaning, and in consequence has a good claim as having avoided transcendental solip-
sism. But too much focus on the dangers of social conformity and too individualistic a rec-
ipe for overcoming them has made many thinkers sometimes miss this important move
(see, for example, discussion in Dreyfus, 1991).
INTERACTIVE TIME-TRAVEL 73
Macmillan.
Ravaisson, F. (1838/2008) Of Habit, Carlisle, C. & Sinclair, M. (trans.), London:
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013
Continuum.
Reed, K., Peshkin, M., Hartmann, M.J., Grabowecky, M., Patton, J. & Vishton,
P.M. (2006) Haptically linked dyads: Are two motor-control systems better than
one?, Psychological Science, 17, pp. 365366.
Taylor, C. (1985) Hegels philosophy of mind, in Taylor, C., Human Agency and
Language: Philosophical Papers, vol. 1, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Thompson, E. (2007) Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology and the Sciences of
Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Varela, F.J. (1979) Principles of Biological Autonomy, New York: Elsevier/North
Holland.
Varela, F.J. (1991) Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves, in Tauber, A.I. (ed.)
Organisms and the Origins of Self, pp. 79107, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers.
Varela, F.J. (1997) Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition, Brain and
Cognition, 34 (1), pp. 7287.
Varela, F.J., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. (1991) The Embodied Mind: Cognitive
Science and Human Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Von Kleist, H. (1951) On the gradual construction of thoughts during speech, Ger-
man Life and Letters, 5, pp. 4246.
Weber, A. & Varela, F.J. (2002) Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the
autopoietic foundations of biological individuality, Phenomenology and the
Cognitive Sciences, 1 (2), pp. 97125.