Bu Kovan Sky 2006
Bu Kovan Sky 2006
Bu Kovan Sky 2006
To cite this article: Mlada Bukovansky (2006) The hollowness of anti-corruption discourse, Review of International
Political Economy, 13:2, 181-209
Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the Content) contained
in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no
representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of
the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,
and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied
upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall
not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other
liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or
arising out of the use of the Content.
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic
reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any
form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://
www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions
Review of International Political Economy 13:2 May 2006: 181209
ABSTRACT
As part of an overall focus on governance in international political econ-
omy, the corruption issue has catapulted from the margins of academic and
policy discourse on international affairs to a position as one of the central
problems facing transition economies and the developing world today. But
the irreducibly normative character of anti-corruption discourse is in tension
with the predominantly rationalist, technical and instrumental justifications
for open markets which have long dominated the academic and institutional
discourse on international political economy. A survey of the anti-corruption
consensus reveals omissions and oversights which cause analysts to evade
and obscure, rather than directly engage, core problems of politics and ethics;
this may have practical consequences for anti-corruption efforts. Republican
political thought, though not without its own risks and flaws, may balance
and correct some of the omissions and oversights of liberal and rationalist
discourse on corruption.
KEYWORDS
Corruption; governance; republicanism; International Monetary Fund;
World Bank; Transparency International
I. INTRODUCTION
In the last decade, international organizations have increasingly publicized
their concerns about political corruption (commonly defined as the use of
public office for private gain, or the illegitimate purchase by private actors
of political consideration), primarily as a negative influence on economic
development but also as the source of a host of other ills ranging from loss
of democratic legitimacy to terrorism. The corruption issue has catapulted
from the margins of academic and policy discourse to a position as one of
the central problems facing transition economies and the developing world
today. Moreover, international organizations and donor states, as well as
Review of International Political Economy
ISSN 0969-2290 print/ISSN 1466-4526 online C 2006 Taylor & Francis
http://www.tandf.co.uk
DOI: 10.1080/09692290600625413
R E V I E W O F I N T E R N AT I O N A L P O L I T I C A L E C O N O M Y
norms of modern market society, would also recognize their historical and
sociological contingency.
The ethical problem in the liberal-rationalist approach to corruption has
to do with the external imposition of contingent standards on societies that
are not fully participating in defining those standards. This problem needs
to be faced not only for moral reasons but for pragmatic ones as well;
arguably the moral reasons partly constitute the pragmatic reasons. Ex-
ternally imposed standards will lack legitimacy unless they are embraced
and internalized by the culture on which they are imposed. Legitimacy
of a law or standard is at least in part an ethical problem; a standard
must be embraced as right or fair by a social actor to be considered
legitimate. Standards that lack legitimacy (the ethical problem) are less
likely than legitimate standards to be effectively enforced (the pragmatic
problem).
An alternative discourse on corruption, one which does not take the
ends of modernity as unproblematic and given, might well correct some
of the evasions and omissions of the current anti-corruption consensus,
and may perhaps even begin to address some of its practical and ethical
problems. Fuel for such a discourse may be found in the republican tra-
dition of political thought. Republican discourse offers richer and more
normative notions of political agency, institutions, and public good than
are available in neo-liberal discourse. It also offers more in the way of a
self-determined notion of public good, and in a highly heterogeneous in-
ternational system, this may render its contributions particularly salient,
though also problematic and perhaps unsettling.
The first sections of this essay lay out a critique of the anti-corruption
discourse in its institutional and academic manifestations, and the final sec-
tion explores how our understanding of the corruption problem might be
deepened by attending to the republican tradition; the conclusion suggests
some practical consequences of the analysis.
184
B U K O VA N S K Y: T H E H O L L O W N E S S O F A N T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
I I . T H E A NT I - C O R R U P T I O N C O N S E N S U S
The turn in international organizations concerned with development to-
ward addressing corruption and governance more generally is one symp-
tom of the perceived inadequacy of narrowly economic approaches to the
problem of economic development. In the dominant lending institutions
and the academic discourse they draw on and generate, the overall goal re-
mains the same as that articulated by classical economic theory: economic
growth is the engine of economic development. How the means to at-
tain that goal are conceptualized has broadened, however, to include such
things as institutions, governance, human capital, and social capital.
Because the modernization that was anticipated after decolonization did
not produce the hoped-for results stable market economies and democ-
Downloaded by [University of Alberta] at 21:37 29 December 2014
ratization in many parts of the world, the search for relevant variables
that may have been overlooked in the first waves of development litera-
ture has drawn scholars and policy-makers to the study of institutions and
governance. This focus has in turn unveiled the problem of corruption.
For decades, international institutions had little if anything to say about
corruption. Silence signified complacency, or at least unwillingness to con-
front the issue. Confronting the issue, on the other hand, means speaking
publicly about it. Publicly calling a person or government corrupt is a polit-
ical act. During the mid to late 1990s the United Nations, the International
Monetary Fund, the World Bank, the Organization for Economic Cooper-
ation and Development, and a number of regional institutions, business
organizations, and non-governmental organizations brought the corrup-
tion issue to the forefront of their agendas and began to lobby for measures
intended to curb corruption. The nongovernmental organization Trans-
parency International (TI) has played a central role in putting the corrup-
tion issue on the international agenda, through its field programs and lob-
bying efforts, and through its publication of the Corruption Perceptions
Index and the newer Bribe Payers Index (Transparency International,
2003). These policy developments have been informed and buttressed by
a growing scholarly literature focusing on corruption and its effects, par-
ticularly its effects on economic development (Hopkin, 2002).
The international realm has traditionally been viewed as highly permis-
sive with respect to bribery and other transactions that would be deemed
corrupt in a domestic context. Only 20 years ago it was considered per-
fectly acceptable and in many states tax deductible to bribe foreigners
if not ones own nationals. This is no longer the case in one small sense:
although such activities still routinely occur, they are no longer openly,
publicly justifiable (Noonan, 1984: 65255). This aligns with a more general
trend: the growth of a comprehensive governance agenda within interna-
tional institutions and across a broader swath of non-governmental and
trans-governmental networks, wherein the structure and implementation
185
R E V I E W O F I N T E R N AT I O N A L P O L I T I C A L E C O N O M Y
vate gain, and/or the exercise of inappropriate (i.e. private sector) influ-
ence over the decisions of public officials. Yet almost none actually explore
where the line between public and private should be drawn. Corruption is
treated like pornography people are expected to know it when they see
it. The key focus in the documents surveyed is on articulating a rationale
for fighting corruption, not defining corruption as such.
Examining public rationales for fighting corruption in the texts of key
international resolutions, treaties and commentaries helps us to interpret
the significance people are publicly willing to give the corruption issue.
Just as secrecy is a defining component of corrupt practices, publicity is
a defining component of anti-corruption campaigns. Public rationales for
anti-corruption efforts are worth studying precisely because they help to
constitute such efforts.
The OECD
The OECDs Convention on Combating Bribery of Foreign Public Officials
in International Business Transactions was the result of efforts and con-
sultations by a Working Group on Bribery which convened in 1989 and
presented its first recommendations in 1994. The United States played a
significant role in furthering the initiative to develop an OECD instru-
ment, based on US domestic debates about whether the Foreign Corrupt
Practices Act of 1977 (which prohibits US companies from bribing foreign
public officials) was making it difficult for US companies to compete in
gaining access to contracts and other competitive advantages in interna-
tional markets (Pieth, 1997). But US pressure alone cannot fully explain the
adoption of the Convention, if only because if it had been up to the US
alone, such a Convention would have been adopted much earlier. NGOs
and a growing consensus among academics, especially economists, about
the relationship between corruption and economic growth most probably
facilitated the adoption of the Convention. In addition, the corrupt nature
of much of the privatization process that followed the opening up of the
former Soviet Union and Eastern Europe to international capitalism surely
helped to bring the Europeans around to the idea that corruption was a
significant problem worthy of concerted counter-measures.
The Convention was adopted on 21 November 1997 and entered into
force on 15 February 1999 (OECD, 1997). As of January 2005, 36 states had
ratified the convention. It requires parties to enact domestic legislation
criminalizing bribery of foreign public officials (including legislative, ad-
ministrative, and judicial officials, whether appointed or elected), and to
impose strong sanctions against this crime. Such legislation and penalties
are required to match those imposed against bribery of domestic public of-
ficials. The Convention further contains money laundering provisions and
191
R E V I E W O F I N T E R N AT I O N A L P O L I T I C A L E C O N O M Y
But as TI notes in a recent Corruption Survey, the budget for the Group is
inadequate to the task at hand (Transparency International, 2004).
Although the OECD Convention highlights a number of instrumental
economic reasons to be concerned about bribery, the Preamble to the Con-
vention clearly articulates moral concerns along with concerns about gov-
ernance, economic development, and international competitiveness. The
Preamble to the OECD Convention uses the term moral in the first sen-
tence: Considering that bribery is a widespread phenomenon in interna-
tional business transactions, including trade and investment, which raises
serious moral and political concerns, undermines good governance and eco-
nomic development, and distorts international competitive conditions; . . .
(OECD, 1997). Currently the OECD is engaged in work on public sector
ethics and corruption which aims to help countries review and reform
their ethics infrastructures (the institutions, systems and mechanisms
they have for promoting ethics and countering corruption in the public ser-
vice, and exchange experience on recent initiatives (OECD, 2004). There is
good reason to be skeptical about the implementation of these grand de-
signs. A survey accompanying the 2002 Transparency International Bribe
Payers Index showed that a majority of multinational corporations based
in OECD countries are not even aware of the treaty and the relevant im-
plementing legislation (Transparency International, 2002d). Nevertheless,
the rhetoric of the OECD Convention clearly echoes the turn toward a
comprehensive concern with governance and the ethics of governance as
a legitimate objective of international institutions.
Transparency International
The most visible non-governmental player in the anti-corruption move-
ment has been Transparency International, a non-profit organization orig-
inally based in Germany, with regional chapters and field offices prolifer-
ating world-wide. TI characterizes itself as a broad civil society movement
192
B U K O VA N S K Y: T H E H O L L O W N E S S O F A N T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
side as well as the demand side of the international bribery equation, and
the publication of two Bribe Payers Indices (in 1999 and 2002) has shown
which wealthy countries are perceived to host corporations most likely to
pay bribes, as well as which economic sectors are perceived as the most cor-
rupt. In the 2002 BPI, Russia, China, Taiwan, and South Korea were the host
countries whose corporations are perceived as most likely to pay bribes to
secure contracts, but OECD countries (and signatories to the OECD anti-
bribery convention) such as Italy, Japan, the United States, France, and
Spain were also perceived to host corporations highly likely to pay bribes;
the fact that US corporations are perceived as having a relatively high
propensity to bribe raises questions about the efficacy of the Foreign Cor-
rupt Practices Act. The worst sectors are, unsurprisingly, the construction
and arms industries (Transparency International, 2002c). The BPI evidence
suggests that the OECD country efforts to combat corruption may either be
interpreted as embodying weak implementation, empty rhetoric, or double
standards. By paying lip service to anti-corruption efforts OECD countries
have made themselves vulnerable to public disapproval, especially when
NGOs such as TI take up and publicize the cause, but so far that seems to
be the extent of it.
TIs operations focus on bringing together and disseminating research
and information on corruption, publishing codes of conduct, holding con-
ferences, and networking with private and public-sector parties concerned
about corruption. TI can thus be seen as a moral entrepreneur, actively
publicizing and preaching its cause (Nadelmann, 1990). TI has gained the
acceptance and cooperation of the IMF and World Bank insofar as these
institutions have worked closely with TI to develop good governance poli-
cies. But much of TIs work has also been concentrated at the grass-roots
level, with a proliferation of national chapters organizing actions targeted
toward specific national and local communities. This is in recognition of
the idea that: In order to be meaningful and hold promise of real change,
the debate on corruption must be held internally, within the community
193
R E V I E W O F I N T E R N AT I O N A L P O L I T I C A L E C O N O M Y
I I I . E C O NOM I C A N D I N S T I T U T I O N A L R AT I O N A L E S
IN ANTI-CORRUPTION DISCOURSE
Downloaded by [University of Alberta] at 21:37 29 December 2014
Although the evidence just presented shows that ethical terms and refer-
ences to good governance are peppered throughout the key anti-corruption
documents put out by institutions such as the UN, the IMF, the World
Bank, and the OECD, in those institutions, as in contemporary academic
discourse, the dominant rationale for the anti-corruption consensus has
been economic, and to a lesser extent institutional (deploying a thin con-
ception of institutions as incentive structures), rather than normative: the
argument is that corruption hurts economic development either by siphon-
ing off resources and discouraging foreign investment, or because corrupt
elites select public financing projects in order to maximize their opportu-
nities for monopoly rents rather than encourage sustainable growth. The
discourse constituting this rationale articulates a sense of complementarity
between institutional effectiveness and economic performance (Davis and
Trebilcock, 1999; Keefer, 2004; La Porta et al., 1999). Economists and polit-
ical scientists using the methods of economics (especially rational choice
theory) dominate this discursive territory (Keefer, 2004; Rose-Ackerman,
1978, 1999; Treisman, 2000).
The main consensus in recent economic studies is that corruption
hurts foreign investment and economic growth (Ades and Di Tella, 1997;
Kaufmann, 1997; Mauro, 1995, 1997, 2004; Rose-Ackerman, 1997, 1999;
Shleifer and Vishny, 1993; Tanzi and Davoodi, 1998). As Paolo Mauro sum-
marizes: A consensus seems to have emerged that corruption and other
aspects of poor governance and weak institutions have substantial, adverse
effects on economic growth (Mauro, 2004: 1). Although many studies of
corruption have focused on its effects on foreign direct investment (FDI),
and although debate continues among economists as to the harmful or
beneficial effects of FDI (see Kapstein, 2002), economic growth remains the
primary measure of development, and more open markets are widely seen
as the best way to achieve such growth. Although one can find plenty of
references to such governance ideals as the rule of law and its impartial
application and enforcement, and protection of individual rights, in the
194
B U K O VA N S K Y: T H E H O L L O W N E S S O F A N T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
the public sector can just as easily inhibit as encourage the development
of democratic institutions of governance (Hopkin, 2002; Khan, 2002). In-
ternational financial institutions and big aid donor states may want less
corruption, but by advocating smaller government they are not doing much
to contribute to and may inadvertently be undercutting the positive
development of good government.
The insight that less government is better government can also be de-
rived from an earlier strain of economic and political science literature that
was more sanguine about corruption. Prior to the anti-corruption consen-
sus, corruption was frequently seen as a way for multinational corporations
to gain footholds in developing country markets. With this in mind, schol-
ars have in the past argued (and a minority still do argue) that some forms
of corruption may not necessarily be a bad thing. Corrupt practices may
cut red tape and facilitate the smoother operation of markets, especially
where governments are not subject to checks and balances, accountability,
and transparency, and where they hold disproportionate power over state
resources. Thus, corruption could help rather than hurt development by
allowing investors to elude inefficient laws and deny greedy officials the
proceeds of legal but onerous tax revenues (substituting illegal but presum-
ably smaller side-payments) (Cheung, 1996; Lui, 1996; Olsen, 1998). Samuel
Huntington has further argued that corruption is an inevitable by-product
of the modernization process; hence advocating modernization and anti-
corruption measures at the same is self-contradictory (Huntington, 1987).
Much of this literature thus dovetails nicely with the market-friendly no-
tion that less government is better government, since corruption involves
bypassing the inefficient public sector (Hayek, 1960).
Despite the plethora of economic studies of governance and institutions,
in their methodological individualism and rationalism such studies do
not leave much room for the possibility that politics could be an ethical
endeavor grounded in commitment to a substantive public good. In the
1960s, Joseph Nye defined corruption as follows:
196
B U K O VA N S K Y: T H E H O L L O W N E S S O F A N T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
individual behavior.
But anti-corruption laws vary widely in different societies. Distinguish-
ing between a gift and a bribe requires thick cultural knowledge of the
particular society in question (Husted, 1999; Offer, 1997; Smart, 1993). Fur-
ther, many of the societies at which the new anti-corruption discourse is
aimed do not have clear cut rules delimiting the boundary between public
good and private interest in specific transactions; judging such societies
as corrupt means deploying standards drawn from the more developed
world (de Sardan, 1999; Szeftel, 1998).
As Peter Euben has pointed out in a critique, Nyes discussion of the costs
and benefits of corruption for development carries with it an implicit nor-
mative judgment about the desirability of modernization. A good society
is a modernizing one; a corrupt society is one that inhibits development.
But because the ends of modernity are regarded as inevitable, impersonal,
and/or rational, they cannot themselves be the subject of rational dispute
or subjective prescriptions (Euben, 1989: 244). The dominant values of
modernity become reified. In the anti-corruption discourse, and in the gov-
ernance discourse more generally, this often boils down to valorizing eco-
nomic growth measured in terms of gross domestic product as the end
toward which public officials must strive. This not only inhibits critical
political debate over the ends of the political community, but also leaves
little room for agency as the conscious, willed reproduction of those values
in daily life, and the moral self-restraint that this would imply.
These two problems the reification of dominant (liberal) values and
the neglect of moral and political agency are at the heart of the elisions
and omissions of the liberal-rationalist modes of anti-corruption discourse.
Confronting these problems means bringing politics back into the dis-
course in such a way that it is not treated simply as a market-distorting
or externality-alleviating exogenous constraint, but rather as a process en-
tailing the production of, and struggle over, collective identities and goals
the coercive and consensual process by which political communities are
197
R E V I E W O F I N T E R N AT I O N A L P O L I T I C A L E C O N O M Y
constructed and maintained. Only by confronting this process and its ir-
reducibly political, normative, and contestable contours can we come to
an understanding of corruption as something more than a transgression of
arbitrary or exogenously imposed rules.
By linking the problem of corruption to the problem of under-
development, advanced industrial countries implicitly and unjustifiably
claim the moral high ground for themselves, and ascribe to the develop-
ing world the status of the moral reprobate while simultaneously mak-
ing vague and possibly unworkable governance demands on developing
country governments and societies. Further, by advocating pressure from
outside as a primary mechanism for curbing corruption, we deny the ca-
pacity and agency of the actors in developing countries to determine for
themselves the contours of political authority and the distinctions between
Downloaded by [University of Alberta] at 21:37 29 December 2014
public good and private interests, between gifts and bribes, between legiti-
mate and illegitimate patronage. This may arguably be appropriate in some
cases from a purely practical standpoint (as in so-called failed states),
though I believe further discussion is warranted even on this point. But
as a matter of principle, and given that the economic framework of global
capitalism is interwoven with a political framework of nominal sovereign
equality, we should strive to develop anti-corruption discourse in such a
way as to leave the question of the proper goal of political and even eco-
nomic development open to discussion and critique, rather than treating
it as a given.
Finally, pitching the anti-corruption discourse as a diagnosis for un-
derdevelopment also absolves those living in liberal capitalist states from
scrutinizing their own polities in terms of a discourse of corruption. But
there is a long history in political thought of engaging in just such scrutiny
(Arendt, 1958; Habermas, 1989; Pocock, 1975; Shumer, 1979), and as the
lobby for campaign finance reform in the US shows, for example, there
is little reason to believe that critical scrutiny of the health of the modern
liberal polity is no longer warranted.
I V. C L A R I F Y I NG T H E M O R A L A N D P O L I T I C A L
DI M E NS I ONS OF AN T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
While there may be a number of institutional ways to check corrupt behav-
ior, anti-corruption efforts ultimately require a vision of good governance
which carries enough moral weight to motivate people, since moral behav-
ior on the part of at least some individual human beings usually the focus
is on public officials, but clearly private actors and community leaders of
all sorts may be involved as well is part and parcel of good governance.
Although Susan Rose-Ackerman is an economist firmly grounded in the
rational choice tradition, even she concludes her systematic discussion of
the political economy of corruption by noting that, institutional incentives
198
B U K O VA N S K Y: T H E H O L L O W N E S S O F A N T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
Shumer, 1979). The problem with this, from the point of view of republican
theorists, is that such pursuit of immediate advantage can lead a commu-
nity to ruin. The ruin or corruption of a political community entails a loss
of liberty, and a slide into dependency. In Machiavellis Discourses, which
states the republican position clearly and forcefully, a free state is one in
which people legislate for themselves, with an eye toward the good of the
community as a whole. By contrast, the corrupt state has lost its liberty
and is in a state of dependency and bondage: either it is dependent upon a
foreign power, or in bondage to a tyrant or a governing party which rules
tyrannically only for its own advantage, or it may be subject to the brief
anarchic rule of the mob (Machiavelli, 1950: I xvi). None of these corrupt
forms of rule is stable or secure.
In contrast to the often asocial individualism of liberal discourse (as
Downloaded by [University of Alberta] at 21:37 29 December 2014
135). Such moral impetus ultimately springs from love of ones country,
the patria of the Renaissance humanists (Skinner, 1978).
Unlike earlier republican theorists, those of Machiavellis time, and es-
pecially Machiavelli himself, were not optimistic about the capacity of hu-
man beings to sustain civic virtue based on love of country. As Machiavelli
notes:
. . . men act rightly only upon compulsion; but from the moment that
they have the option and liberty to commit wrong with impunity,
then they never fail to carry confusion and disorder everywhere. It is
this that has caused it to be said that poverty and hunger make men
industrious, and that the law makes men good . . . (Machiavelli, 1950:
I iii)
Downloaded by [University of Alberta] at 21:37 29 December 2014
agency, where the terms moral and political may be construed as comple-
mentary rather than contradictory concepts. Here the difference between
republicanism and the liberal discourse is stark, because the latter dis-
course for the most part adopts a Hobbesian view of man as naturally
selfish (which the republicans do not deny) and asocial (which the republi-
cans vehemently deny). It is worth noting as an aside that contemporary
realisms tendency to tout both Hobbes and Machiavelli as founding fa-
thers totally obscures this important distinction between them, and that
Hobbes belongs much more to the liberal tradition than most contempo-
rary international relations theorists allow.
Corruption in republican discourse can also connote a structural condi-
tion, a sickness of the polity which at worst can mean its destruction as
a cohesive whole, or a loss of identity and definition (Euben, 1989: 222).
Downloaded by [University of Alberta] at 21:37 29 December 2014
Peter Euben points out that one of the most exemplary historical cases of
a polity that has become corrupt to the point of disintegration is Thucy-
dides account of the civil war in Corcyra; the term used in describing this
disintegration is stasis:
Under such conditions religion, family, and morality become in-
struments in their own destruction. Oaths are temporary strategies
adopted only when one is outmaneuvered or outmanned by an op-
ponent . . . Morality and justice are rhetorical diversions which dis-
guise secret hatreds and excuse private revenge . . . Since everyone
is a potential enemy, isolation is the only guarantee against surprise
attack. In the beginning of civil war, men killed their enemies with
the assistance of their party. But as the stasis intensified the number
of potential enemies increased and the number of possible friends
decreased until the only trustworthy friend was oneself and the only
safe party was a party of one. (Euben, 1989: 225)
It does not require a huge stretch of the imagination to apply this picture of a
totally corrupted polity to some of the areas that have been and continue to
be devastated by civil wars in our time. Corruption in republican discourse
thus connotes loss of liberty, self-determination, and identity as a political
entity; the corrupt state may break down, first into warring factions, and
then warring individuals; it is not unlike the Hobbesian state of nature.
The republican discourse thus offers a richer and more resonant con-
ception of corruption than does liberal-rationalist discourse. Richer, in its
conception of institutions as organic entities whose norms are capable of
being internalized, and which are capable of evoking emotional attach-
ment and moral commitment, rather than merely exogenous incentive
structures channeling the activity of narrowly self-interested actors. Cor-
ruption means that the institutions constituting the political community
have decayed and no longer provide liberty and security. More resonant,
in that it evokes the human capacity for moral agency in civic life. Corrupt
202
B U K O VA N S K Y: T H E H O L L O W N E S S O F A N T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
fers fuel for debate and communicative action. Some of the other limits of
republican discourse are more problematic. Grounding political morality
in a love of country can be seen as antithetical to the development of a cos-
mopolitan morality that is dear to the normative liberalism of Immanuel
Kant and his successors (Kant, 1998). Machiavellis advice to leaders does
not include an ethic of caring about what happens to those who live outside
the polity, except insofar as they may pose a threat (in which case they need
to be neutralized). Despite his preference for a republican form of govern-
ment, Machiavelli was not above advocating violence and princely rule to
correct the problem of corruption in certain situations. And finally, republi-
canism is often deeply cynical about the possibility that good, non-corrupt
governance can actually be realized.
This latter problem was to some extent addressed by the Federalists in
the US, who sought to overcome the weaknesses of human nature by con-
structing institutions which would assure the survival of republican values
without requiring the active deployment of republican virtues (Appleby,
1992; Onuf and Onuf, 1993; Shklar, 1990). But that turning point in repub-
lican thought is what fueled the liberal conception of institutions as exoge-
nous constraints on selfish human behavior a conception I have argued
neglects the normative, motivational appeal of a more organic conception
of institutions, one that recognizes their capacity to be internalized as mo-
tivators of moral and political (i.e. civic-minded) human action. One way
in which such internalization works is through that seemingly out-dated
republican notion of love of country; commitment to the public good has
moral appeal if it is underpinned by that sort of civic-minded sentiment.
In the absence of such a normative motivation, moral behavior can only
be induced by the exogenous constraint of institutions, which then raises
the age-old question of who will construct such institutions where they
do not exist already. And that is precisely the problem repeatedly faced
in the anti-corruption discourse and the broader governance agenda in
international political economy.
203
R E V I E W O F I N T E R N AT I O N A L P O L I T I C A L E C O N O M Y
V. C O N C L U S I O N
The emergence of corruption as a core issue in the governance agenda
of multilateral institutions, and in the academic discourse informing the
policies of such institutions, raises important questions of political agency
and moral action in politics, but up to this point these questions have been
obscured by the technical-instrumental approach to institutions and the
rationalist economic methods deployed in the prevailing liberal discourse
constituting the anti-corruption consensus. Rather than assume that the
ends of modernity can be gracefully bequeathed to the developing world
and transition economies of the former communist countries via the ex-
tension of a global market economy, the anti-corruption discourse would
benefit from an injection of alternative modes of deliberating about what
corruption actually means, and what needs to be done to engage leaders
and citizens in deliberation about the substance of the public good, and the
pursuit of collective ends. That such pursuit involves some self restraint
and sacrifice cannot be plausibly denied. The motivation for such sacrifice
must be normative and come from within individuals and societies, rather
than being imposed from without. Normative motivations in pursuit of
the public good are the result of moral commitments by human beings,
commitments grounded in a devotion to ones political community.
It hardly seems likely that international institutions would be willing to
leave the question of good governance entirely to the patriotism and self-
determination of publics and political leaders in the various countries with
whom they deal. After all, they do not hand out resources unconditionally,
and as we have seen, the democratization process does not always yield
results that are palatable to the west. Nevertheless, the governance dis-
course emanating from institutions like the IMF, the World Bank, and even
the United Nations, is likely to remain relatively anemic and ineffectual (not
to say hypocritical) without the active, committed, self-determining par-
ticipation of the people toward whom the governance agenda is directed.
204
B U K O VA N S K Y: T H E H O L L O W N E S S O F A N T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The author wishes to thank Chris Reus-Smit, Len Seabrooke, Greg White,
participants at seminars at the Australian National Universitys Research
School of Pacific and Asian Studies and at the International Studies Associ-
ation Conference in 2002, and two anonymous reviewers, for their valuable
comments on this paper.
NOTE
1 I owe this insight to one of the anonymous reviewers of this essay.
REFERENCES
Ades, Alberto and Di Tella, Rafael (1997) The New Economics of Corruption: A
Survey and Some New Results, Political Studies, XLV: 496515.
205
R E V I E W O F I N T E R N AT I O N A L P O L I T I C A L E C O N O M Y
Appleby, Joyce (1992) Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination, Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Arendt, Hannah (1958) The Human Condition, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
Press.
Best, Jacqueline (2002) Civilizing Globalization? The New Financial Architecture
and the Re-Embedding of Global Finance, Paper presented at the International
Studies Association Conference, New Orleans, LA, March 2427.
Brademas, John and Heimann, Fritz (1998) Tackling International Corruption: No
Longer Taboo, Foreign Affairs, 77:5.
Bratsis, Peter (2003) The Construction of Corruption, or Rules of Separation and
Illusions of Purity in Bourgeois Societies, Social Text 77, 21(4):99133.
Camdessus, Michael (1998) The IMF and Good Governance, Address by the Man-
aging Director of the IMF at Transparency International, Paris, France, 21 Jan-
uary 21 [www.imf.org/external/np/speeches/1998/012198.HTM].
Cheung, Steven N. S. (1996) A Simplistic General Equilibrium Theory of Corrup-
Downloaded by [University of Alberta] at 21:37 29 December 2014
36(2):379415.
de Sardan, J. P. Olivier (1999) A Moral Economy of Corruption in Africa? Journal
of Modern African Studies 37(1):2552.
Shklar, Judith N. (1990) Montesquieu and the New Republicanism, in Gisela Bock,
Quentin Skinner and Maurizio Viroli (eds) Machiavelli and Republicanism, Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Shleifer, Andrei and Robert W. Vishny (1993) Corruption, Quarterly Journal of Eco-
nomics, 108(3):599617.
Shumer, S. M. (1979) Machiavelli: Republican Politics and its Corruption, Political
Theory 7(1):534.
Skinner, Quentin (1978) The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, Vol 1, The Re-
naissance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, Quentin (1990) The Republican Ideal of Political Liberty, in Gisela Bock,
Quentin Skinner and Maurizio Viroli (eds) Machiavelli and Republicanism, Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Slaughter, Anne-Marie (1997) The Real New World Order, Foreign Affairs,
76(5):18397.
Smart, Alan (1993) Gifts, Bribes, and Guanxi: A Reconsideration of Bourdieus
Social Capital, Cultural Anthropology, 8(3):388408.
Szeftel, Morris (1998) Misunderstanding African Politics: Corruption and
the Governance Agenda, Review of African Political Economy, 25(76):221
40.
Tanzi, Vito (1995) Corruption, Governmental Activities, and Markets, Finance and
Development, 32:4.
Tanzi, Vito and Davoodi, Hamid (1998) Roads to Nowhere: How Corruption in Public
Investment Hurts Growth, Economic Issues Series #12. Washington, DC: Inter-
national Monetary Fund.
Theobald, Robin (1990) Corruption, Development, and Underdevelopment, London:
Macmillan.
Transparency International (2002a) Press release announcing the 2002 CPI,
www.transparency.org/pressreleases archive/2002/2002.08.28.cpi.en.html.
Transparency International (2002b) Bribe Payers Index documentation, available
at www.transparency.org/cpi/index.html#bpi.
Transparency International (2002c) Press release, 14 May. www.transparency.
org/pressreleases archive/2002/2002.05.14.bpi.en.html.
Transparency International (2002d) Bribe Payers Index 2002, Explanatory Notes
and Comparative Tables. Available on the Transparency International Website:
www.transparency.org.
208
B U K O VA N S K Y: T H E H O L L O W N E S S O F A N T I - C O R R U P T I O N D I S C O U R S E
53/176, 25 January.
United Nations General Assembly (2001) General Assembly Resolution A/RES/
55/188, 25 January.
United Nations General Assembly (2002) General Assembly Resolution
A/RES/56/186, 31 January.
United Nations General Assembly (2003) Ad Hoc Committee for the Negotiation
of a Convention against Corruption, Draft text of the UN Convention Against
Corruption, A/AC.261/3/Rev.4, 12 May 2003, accessed at www.unodc.
org/unodc/en/crime cicp committee corruption session 9.html
United Nations (2003) United Nations Convention against Corruption.
Available for download at: www.unodc.org/unodc/en/crime convention
corruption.html
Vogl, Frank (1998) The Supply Side of Global Bribery, Finance and Development,
35:2.
Walzer, Michael (1983) Spheres of Justice, NY: Basic Books.
Weintraub, Jeff and Kumar, Krishan (eds) (1997) Public and Private in Thought and
Practice, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
World Bank (1997a) Poverty Reduction and Economic Management Section, Help-
ing Countries Combat Corruption: the Role of the World Bank, September, available
at <www1.worldbank.org/publicsector/anticorrupt/corruptn/coridx.htm>.
World Bank (1997b) World Development Report 1997, Washington, DC: World Bank
Group.
World Bank (2004) The New Anti-Corruption Homepage, www1.worldbank.org/
publicsector/anticorrupt/index.cfm, accessed on 19 June.
209