Kantianism - Britannica Online Encyclopedia
Kantianism - Britannica Online Encyclopedia
Kantianism - Britannica Online Encyclopedia
Kantianism
Kantianism,
either the TABLE OF CONTENTS
system of
Introduction
thought
contained in the Nature and types of Kantianism
A system such as the critical philosophy of Kant freely lends itself to reconstructions of its
synthesis according to whatever preferences the private philosophical inclinations of the
reader may impose or suggest. Kant’s system was a syncretism, or union, of British
empiricism (as in John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume) that stressed the role of
experience in the rise of knowledge; of the scienti c methodology of Isaac Newton; and of
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 1/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
the metaphysical apriorism (or rationalism) of Christian Wolff, who systematized the
philosophy of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, with its emphasis on mind. Thus, it constituted a
synthesis of elements very different in origin and nature, which tempted students to read
their own presuppositions into it.
The critical philosophy has been subjected to a variety of approaches and methods of
interpretation. These can be reduced to three fundamental types: those that conceive of
the critical philosophy as an epistemology or a pure theory of (scienti c) knowledge and
methodology, those that conceive of it as a critical theory of metaphysics or the nature of
being (ultimate reality), and those that conceive of it as a theory of normative or
valuational re ection parallel to that of ethics (in the eld of action). Each of these types—
known, respectively, as epistemological, metaphysical, and axiological Kantianism—can, in
turn, be subdivided into several secondary approaches. Historically, epistemological
Kantianism included such different attitudes as empirical Kantianism, rooted either in
physiological or psychological inquiries; the logistic Kantianism of the Marburg school,
which stressed essences and the use of logic; and the realistic Kantianism of the Austrian
Alois Riehl. Metaphysical Kantianism developed from the transcendental idealism of
German Romanticism to realism, a course followed by many speculative thinkers, who
saw in the critical philosophy the foundations of an essentially inductive metaphysics, in
accordance with the results of the modern sciences. Axiological Kantianism, concerned
with value theory, branched, rst, into an axiological approach (properly so-called), which
interpreted the methods of all three of Kant’s Critiques—Critik der reinen Vernunft (1781,
rev. ed. 1787; Critique of Pure Reason), Critik der practischen Vernunft (1788; Critique of
Practical Reason), and Critik der Urteilskraft (1790; Critique of Judgment)—as normative
disciplines of thought, and, second, into an eclectic or relativistic Kantianism, which
regarded the critical philosophy as a system of thought dependent upon social, cultural,
and historical conditions. The chief representatives of these submovements are identi ed
in the historical sections below.
It is essential to distinguish clearly between two periods within the Kantian movement:
rst, the period from 1790 to 1831 (the death of the German idealist G.W.F. Hegel) and,
second, the period from 1860 to the present—separated by a time when an
antiphilosophical positivism, a type of thought that supplanted metaphysics with science,
was predominant. The rst period began with the thorough study and emendation of
Kant’s chief theoretical work, the Critique of Pure Reason, but it soon became
intermingled with the romantic tendencies in German idealism. The second period, called
speci cally Neo-Kantianism, was rst of all a conscious reappraisal, in whole or in part, of
the theoretical Critique but was also, as a total system, a reaction against positivism.
Earlier Neo-Kantianism reduced philosophy to the theory of knowledge and scienti c
methodology; systematic Neo-Kantianism, arising at the beginning of the 20th century,
expressed itself in attempts at building metaphysical structures.
These transcendental elements are of three different orders: at the lowest level are the
forms of space and time (technically called intuitions); above these are the categories and
principles of human intelligence, among them substance, causality, and necessity; and at
the uppermost level of abstraction are the ideas of reason—the transcendental “I,” the
world as a whole, and God. It is through the encounter between the forms of human
sensory intuition (space and time) and perceptions that phenomena are formed. The
forms arise from the subject himself; the perceptions, however—or the data of experience
—have reference, ultimately, to things-in-themselves, which nevertheless remain
unknowable, inasmuch as, in order to be known at all, it is necessary for things to appear
clothed, as it were, in the forms of human intuition and, thenceforth, to present
themselves as phenomena and not as noumena. The thing-in-itself, accordingly, indicates
the limit and not the object of knowledge.
These theses of Kant provoked criticism among the followers of Christian Wolff, the
Leibnizian rationalist, and doubts among the disciples of Kant, which, as they further
developed into systems, marked the rst period of Kantianism. Inasmuch as these
disciples took the Critique of Pure Reason to be a “preface” to the study of pure reason or
of the transcendental system and not the system itself, they saw in this interpretation an
explanation for the ambiguities to which the Critique (as they felt) was subject. Their
doubts revolved around two points: rst, Kant had erroneously distinguished three kinds
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 3/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
This function of human thought (the transcendental subject), which serves as the
absolute source of the a priori, was variously designated by different early Kantian
thinkers: for the German realist Karl L. Reinhold, it constituted the faculty of
representation; for the Lithuanian idealist Salomon Maimon, it was a mental capacity for
constructing objects; for the idealist Jakob S. Beck, a protégé of Kant, it was the act of
synthesis; for the empirical critic of Kantianism G.E. Schulze, it was experience in the sense
intended by Hume, a volley of discrete sense impressions; for the theory of knowledge of
the outstanding ethical idealist Johann G. Fichte, it was the original positing of the Ego
and the non-Ego, which meant, in turn, in the case of the aesthetic idealist F.W.J. von
Schelling, the “absolute self,” in the case of Hegel, the Geist, or “absolute Spirit,” and nally,
in the case of the pessimistic Romanticist Arthur Schopenhauer, the “absolute Will.” In
each case (excepting Schulze) the interpretation of the thing-in-itself in a realistic
metaphysical sense was rejected in favour of various degrees of transcendental idealism.
Removed from the main current of Kantianism was the empirically oriented thinker Jakob
Friedrich Fries (the one gure in this group who was not an idealist in the true sense), who
interpreted the a priori in terms of psychological faculties and elements.
Having earlier renounced these apostates on a large scale, Kant, at the end of his life,
prepared a new exposition of the transcendental philosophy (the second part of his Opus
Postumum), which showed that he was ready tacitly to accede to the criticisms of his
adversaries.
NINETEENTH-CENTURY NEO-KANTIANISM
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 4/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
The rejection of all of philosophy by positivism had the anomalous effect of evoking an
awakening of Kantianism, for many thinkers wished to give to positivism itself a
philosophical foundation that, while respecting the phenomenological attitude, would yet
be hostile to the metaphysics of positivism, which was usually a tacit, but inconsequential,
materialism. It was justi ably held that Kant could provide such a foundation because of
his opposition to metaphysics and his limitation of scienti c knowledge to the sphere of
phenomena. The complexity of the critical philosophy was such that the theoretical
criticism could be approached in diverse ways and that, through the facts themselves,
diverse interpretations of the Critique of Pure Reason could be obtained. In the order of
their origin (though not of their worth or importance), there thus arose currents of
Kantianism that were empiricist, logicist, realist, metaphysical, axiological, and
psychological—of which the most important survived into the 20th century.
The return to Kant was determined by the historical fresco of the incomparable historian
of philosophy Kuno Fischer titled Kants Leben und die Grundlagen seiner Lehre (1860;
“Kant’s Life and the Foundations of his Teaching”), which replaced the earlier work of the
semi-Kantian Ernst Reinhold, son of the more notable Jena scholar mentioned above
(published 1828–30), and especially that of the outstanding historian of philosophy Johann
Eduard Erdmann (published 1834–53). In 1865 the imperative “Zurück nach Kant!” (“Back
to Kant!”) reverberated through the celebrated work of the young epistemologist Otto
Liebmann, Kant und die Epigonen (“Kant and his Followers”), which was destined to
extricate their spirits from the positivistic morass and, at the same time, to divert the
Germans from Romantic idealism.
EPISTEMOLOGICAL NEO-KANTIANISM
The empiricist, logistic, and realistic schools can be classed as epistemological.
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 5/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
when, in the in nitesimal calculus, the analyst generates motion by imagining thin slices
of space and time and adding up their areas. Hence, experience is a perfect construction
of humankind’s logical spirit. Cohen’s example inspired many authors, among them
Cohen’s colleague at Marburg Paul Natorp, who, in his work on the logical foundations of
the exact sciences, integrated even psychology into the Marburgian transcendentalism;
and Ernst Cassirer, best known for stressing the symbolizing capacities of human beings,
who, in his memorable work Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft
der neueren Zeit (1906–20; The Problem of Knowledge: Philosophy, Science, and History
since Hegel), transposed this same logisticism into a form that illumines the history of
modern philosophy.
METAPHYSICAL NEO-KANTIANISM
Ten years after the appearance of the aforementioned groundbreaking book Kant und die
Epigonen, its author, Otto Liebmann, introduced the new metaphysical approach in his
book Zu Analysis der Wirklichkeit (1876; “On the Analysis of Reality”), which came near to
the Kantianism of Marburg. The Romanticist Johannes Volkelt, in turn, took up the theme
of a critical metaphysics and expressed his persisting aspirations toward the Absolute in
the claim that, beyond the certainties of subjective consciousness, there exists a new kind
of certainty in a transsubjective realm. Subjectivity is, thus, inevitably transcended, just as
the sciences are surmounted when they presuppose a metaphysics. The in uential
spiritual moralist Friedrich Paulsen defended the claim that Kant had always behaved as a
metaphysician, even in the Critique of Pure Reason, in spite of the epistemological
restrictions that he imposed upon himself—a claim that made an impact that was felt
throughout the following century.
AXIOLOGICAL NEO-KANTIANISM
Inasmuch as the two principal representatives of the axiological interpretation both
taught at the University of Heidelberg, this branch is also known as the Southwest
German or Baden school. Its initiator was Wilhelm Windelband, esteemed for his
“problems” approach to the history of philosophy. The scholar who systematized this
position was his successor Heinrich Rickert, who had come from the tradition of Kuno
Fischer. Drawing a parallel between the constraints that logic exerts upon thought and
those that the sense of ought exerts upon ethical action, these thinkers argued that, while
human action must answer to an absolute value (the Good), human thought must answer
to a regulative value (the True), which imposes the duty of conforming to it. The Critique
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 6/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
PSYCHOLOGICAL NEO-KANTIANISM
A discipline known as the Kant Philologie, concerned with the history, development, and
works of Kant, preempted a considerable portion of philosophical historiography after
1860. These studies began with the immense commentary on the Critique of Pure Reason
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 7/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
produced in 1881–92 by Hans Vaihinger, known for his philosophy of the “As If” (which
stresses human reliance on pragmatic ctions), and with the founding in 1896 of the new
journal Kantstudien (“Kant Studies”) and in 1904 of the Kant-Gesellschaft (“Kant Society”)
—both still extant. The most conspicuous result of this philological movement, however,
was undeniably the monumental edition of all of Kant’s available works prepared (1900 ff.)
by the Academy of Sciences at Berlin, initially under the editorship of the champion of
humanistic studies, Wilhelm Dilthey.
NON-GERMAN KANTIANISM
The English-speaking countries, on the other hand, were not disposed to assimilate the
critical philosophy as they did Hegelian idealism. Except for the Scottish religious
absolutist Edward Caird (The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant, 1889), who was chie y
a Hegelian, there was in Britain at the close of the 19th century only another Scot, the
critical realist Robert Adamson, who was a Kantian. After him, however, can be cited the
commentary, published in 1918, of Norman Kemp Smith, producer of the standard English
translation of Kant’s rst Critique, and later the remarkable exposition by the Oxford
Kantian Herbert J. Paton, Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience (1936). Kantian methods could
also be discerned in a later work of the prominent Oxford philosopher Peter F. Strawson,
titled Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (1959).
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 8/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
Public Domain however, was the realist Carlo Cantoni, who took an
anti-positivist stance. Later, in the period from 1900 to
1918, Kantianism was represented by the extreme realism of the theist Francesco
Orestano. A school of Kantian philology formed at Turin around the erudite Christian
idealist Augusto Guzzo and his journal Filoso a. More independent in spirit was the work
of the critical ontologist Pantaleo Carabellese, Giovanni Gentile’s successor at Rome.
ASSESSMENT OF KANTIANISM
PROBLEMS OF KANTIANISM
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 9/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
that afforded a realist alternative to the a priori but above all to re ect the distinctly
logistic position regarding the foundations of mathematics to which he adhered.
Although discussion of the status of the thing-in-itself in human knowledge of the real
remained on the philosophical agenda both during and after Hartmann’s time, it invoked
the same indecision as it always had. At a time when Hartmann was accepting the thing-
in-itself almost naïvely, empiricism (in all its forms) rejected it categorically and attempted
to construe the real in terms merely of what Kant had called phenomena. In the realm of
ethics, phenomenologists and existentialists were dissatis ed with the purely formal
character of Kant’s ethics—i.e., with its lack of speci city—and substituted a “material”
ethic, of concrete duties, which was no less absolute than that of Kant. Meanwhile, logical
empiricists (or logical positivists) were interested only in the analysis of expressions of
moral judgment, which they reduced to imperative statements that are emotive and
aimed at winning adherents.
OBJECTIONS TO KANTIANISM
It must be acknowledged that Kant has furnished many of the most signi cant themes
that are found in the currents of contemporary philosophy, even in the forms that they
still assume today. Yet, as compared with the state of affairs that existed from 1860 to 1918,
Kantianism suffered an impressive decline that continued until approximately the third
quarter of the 20th century.
What were the reasons for this decline? In general, after World War I the reduction of
philosophy to the philosophy of science was no longer accepted, though logical
empiricism offered hardly any objection to it. The philosophy of science comprises, in fact,
only one problem area, not the entire assemblage of philosophical problems. From this a
second objection arose: Kantianism in general is too formalistic to satisfy human
inquisitiveness, which inclines more and more toward concrete concerns. Kantianism
restricts itself to examining the a priori forms of thought and cares little for its diverse
contents. Were this objection pertinent only to the exact sciences, it would not be serious,
for these sciences attend to their own applications, but the objection becomes very grave
for the eld of ethics. For this reason, the objection against Kant’s formalism has been
raised most passionately against his ethical treatise, the Critique of Practical Reason—as
by Hartmann, by the phenomenologist Max Scheler, and by others. This transcendental
formalism immediately encounters the further objection of subjectivism—in spite of
efforts (from the side of logic) to evade it—i.e., it is blamed for obstructing the
apprehension of the real universality of the Ego, of the thinking subject, and for inexorably
impelling the scholar to the view that human knowledge is merely the product of
subjective construction. This subjectivistic transcendentalism, by its intrinsic logic, denies
humans access to the external world. Not only does it debar them from the world of
things-in-themselves but it also prevents them from granting objective reality to
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 10/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
These three major objections, which stand out in the midst of many criticisms of minor
details, recur constantly in the Kantian literature. The result of these objections, as far as
the evaluation of the critical philosophy is concerned, is that it is repudiated by some
philosophers in its entirety—without, however, being thereby considered barred by
limitation. Kant thus remains, in spite of everything, an inexhaustible source of problems
and ideas, comparable in this respect to Plato and Aristotle, with whom he forms the
great triad of Western philosophical thought.
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 11/12
27.11.2017 Kantianism -- Britannica Online Encyclopedia
https://www.britannica.com/print/article/311522 12/12