Term Paper Philo
Term Paper Philo
Term Paper Philo
IS THE
HANDMAID OF
THEOLOGY
Justin Palenzuela
St. Benedict’s academy
Guinobatan, Albay
INTRODUCTION:
How does philosophy become the handmaiden of theology? What is the connection of
independent of theology, and based on its own principles. A philosophy that was neither
independent nor truly and totally rational could not be an aid to theology, because it wouldn’t
exist at all, much less help anything. Philosophy’s independence constitutes an essential part of
It does not follow from this that philosophy is any less rational because it borrows various theses
from revealed theology and then establishes them on rational grounds. This is in fact a rather
unremarkable thing: just another instance of starting with something unknown and then finding a
Philosophy’s place as handmaiden does not come as a result of the categorization of thought, but
in order of human fulfillment. Prayerful union of the soul with God is the end toward which
philosophizing is ordered. Since before the fall of Rome, monks had been spending great deals of
time copying, studying, and meditating on text as an aid to contemplation. St. Augustine, in de
doctrina christiana, argued that the preacher should take the best from all the sciences, like the
Israelites plundered Egypt, in order to further their study with God. He claimed that knowledge
of natural sciences and philosophy had a limited intrinsic value, but showed a great amount of
usefulness when used as an aid to the knowledge of God. As a result, philosophy is the
“handmaid” that prepares the human mind for contemplation – or theology, viewed not strictly as
a scientific examination of religious truths, but as prayerful meditation upon God Himself.
It’s important to understand that, for medieval, there is no strong distinction between scientific
theology, prayer, liturgy, and moral living. Evagrius ponticus, for example, wrote “if you are a
theologian, you will pray truly. And if you pray truly, you are a theologian.” Theologians like
Bonaventure, Aquinas, and many others of the scholastics would continue to emphasize the
centrally of prayer in theological study, even after the great age of the contemplative monk had
ended.
CHAPTER 1: DUALISM
Dualism is the concept that our mind is more than just our brain. This concept entails that our
mind has a non-material, spiritual dimension that includes consciousness and possibly an eternal
attribute. One way to understand this concept is to consider our self as a container including our
physical body and physical brain along with a separate non-physical mind, spirit, or soul. The
mind, spirit, or soul is considered the conscious part that manifests itself through the brain in a
similar way that picture waves and sound waves manifest themselves through a television set.
The picture and sound waves are also non-material just like the mind, spirit, or soul.
The alternative concept is materialism. Materialism holds that everything in our universe is made
from physical materials including the human mind or brain and that spiritual attributes do not
exist in the universe. This concept holds that our mind and brain are one and the same.
If dualism is not true, the mind is limited to the physical brain. Assuming this scenario, what
kind of a mind would we expect? We certainly would not expect to have consciousness strictly
from materials. Perhaps we could expect to see a mechanical mind similar to a computer that is
run by a program. We would not expect things like consciousness, sensations, thoughts,
emotions, desires, beliefs, and free choice. Such a mind would behave in a deterministic way
based upon the laws of matter. Many scientists and philosophers are now concluding that the
laws of chemistry and physics cannot explain the experience of consciousness in human beings.
We would not expect people with such a mind to be responsible for their behavior because
everything they do is determined by the attributes of matter. We all know that is absurd. Also, we
could not trust our minds since they are just a random collection of materials not produced by an
intelligent mind.
with dualism we would expect the spiritual mind to have similar attributes to that of its source. If
the source is the God of the Bible, the concept of dualism is consistent with the Bible. Genesis
1:26 states, “Then God said, ‘let Us make man in our image, according to our
likeness...’” Genesis 2:7 states, “And the Lord God formed man of the dust of the ground, and
breathed into his nostrils the breath of life; and man became a living being.” Luke 23:46 states,
“And when Jesus had cried out with a loud voice, He said, ‘Father, into your hands I commend
my spirit.’”
A British study published by the journal “Resuscitation” provided evidence that consciousness
continues after a person’s brain has stopped functioning and he or she has been declared dead
supports the truth of dualism. In their journal article, physician Sam Parnia and Peter Fenwick, a
neuropsychiatrist, describe their study of sixty-three heart attack victims who were declared
clinically dead but were later revived and interviewed. About ten percent reported having well-
structured, lucid thought processes, with memory formation and reasoning during the time that
their brains were not functioning. The effects of starvation of oxygen or drugs were ruled out as
J. P. Moreland, PhD, author and theologian states during an interview with Lee Strobel, “People
are clinically dead, but sometimes they have a vantage point from above, where they look down
at the operating table that their body is on. Sometimes they gain information that they couldn’t
have known if this were just an illusion happening in their brain. One woman died and she saw a
tennis shoe that was on top of the hospital.” This is strong scientific evidence for the validity of
her experience and the existence of a conscience mind that separates from the body at death.
There is no place in the brain where electric stimulation can cause a person to believe or decide.
When Roger Sperry and his team studied the differences between the brain’s right and left
hemispheres, they discovered the mind has a causal power independent of the brain’s activities.
Our thoughts can be true or false. However, brain states cannot be true or false.
Nobody can tell what we are thinking by measuring brain waves. We must be asked what we are
thinking.
When empirical information is used to as a basis for validating dualism, we can come to a
consensus that it is true. However, dualism vs. materialism is tied to the creation vs. evolution
debate. Consequently, evolutionists need to take unrealistic positions against dualism to defend
In a similar way, if only the objective scientific empirical facts are considered, evolution has no
The mind-body problem is the problem: what is the relationship between mind and body? Or
alternatively: what is the relationship between mental properties and physical properties?
Humans have (or seem to have) both physical properties and mental properties. People have (or
seem to have) the sort of properties attributed in the physical sciences. These physical properties
include size, weight, shape, colour, motion through space and time, etc. But they also have (or
seem to have) mental properties, which we do not attribute to typical physical objects these
much else), intentionality (including beliefs, desires, and much else), and they are possessed by a
subject or a self.
Physical properties are public, in the sense that they are, in principle, equally observable by
anyone. Some physical properties—like those of an electron—are not directly observable at all,
but they are equally available to all, to the same degree, with scientific equipment and
techniques. The same is not true of mental properties. I may be able to tell that you are in pain by
your behaviour, but only you can feel it directly. Similarly, you just know how something looks
to you, and I can only surmise. Conscious mental events are private to the subject, who has a
The mind-body problem concerns the relationship between these two sets of properties. The
1. The ontological question: what are mental states and what are physical states? Is one
class a subclass of the other, so that all mental states are physical, or vice versa? Or are
Different aspects of the mind-body problem arise for different aspects of the mental, such as
3. The problem of consciousness: what is consciousness? How is it related to the brain and
the body?
4. The problem of intentionality: what is intentionality? How is it related to the brain and
the body?
5. The problem of the self: what is the self? How is it related to the brain and the body?
Other aspects of the mind-body problem arise for aspects of the physical. For example:
6. The problem of embodiment: what is it for the mind to be housed in a body? What is it
The seemingly intractable nature of these problems have given rise to many different
philosophical views.
Materialist views say that, despite appearances to the contrary, mental states are just physical
states. Behaviourism, functionalism, mind-brain identity theory and the computational theory of
mind are examples of how materialists attempt to explain how this can be so. The most common
factor in such theories is the attempt to explicate the nature of mind and consciousness in terms
of their ability to directly or indirectly modify behaviour, but there are versions of materialism
that try to tie the mental to the physical without explicitly explaining the mental in terms of its
behaviour-modifying role. The latter are often grouped together under the label ‘non-reductive
physicalism’, though this label is itself rendered elusive because of the controversial nature of
Idealist views say that physical states are really mental. This is because the physical world is
an empirical world and, as such, it is the intersubjective product of our collective experience.
Dualist views (the subject of this entry) say that the mental and the physical are both real and
neither can be assimilated to the other. For the various forms that dualism can take and the
In sum, we can say that there is a mind-body problem because both consciousness and thought,
broadly construed, seem very different from anything physical and there is no convincing
consensus on how to build a satisfactorily unified picture of creatures possessed of both a mind
and a body.
DUALISM
I said above that predicate dualism might seem to have no ontological consequences, because it
is concerned only with the different way things can be described within the contexts of the
different sciences, not with any real difference in the things themselves. This, however, can be
disputed.
The argument from predicate to property dualism moves in two steps, both controversial. The
first claims that the irreducible special sciences, which are the sources of irreducible predicates,
are not wholly objective in the way that physics is, but depend for their subject matter upon
interest-relative perspectives on the world. This means that they, and the predicates special to
them, depend on the existence of minds and mental states, for only minds have interest-relative
perspectives. The second claim is that psychology—the science of the mental—is itself an
irreducible special science, and so it, too, presupposes the existence of the mental. Mental
predicates therefore presuppose the mentality that creates them: mentality cannot consist simply
First, let us consider the claim that the special sciences are not fully objective, but are interest-
relative.
No-one would deny, of course, that the very same subject matter or ‘hunk of reality’ can be
described in irreducibly different ways and it still be just that subject matter or piece of reality. A
as mass of sub-atomic particles, and there be only the one mass of matter. But such different
This is where basic physics, and perhaps those sciences reducible to basic physics, differ from
irreducible special sciences. On a realist construal, the completed physics cuts physical reality up
at its ultimate joints: any special science which is nominally strictly reducible to physics also, in
virtue of this reduction, it could be argued, cuts reality at its joints, but not at its minutest ones. If
scientific realism is true, a completed physics will tell one how the world is, independently of
any special interest or concern: it is just how the world is. It would seem that, by contrast, a
science which is not nominally reducible to physics does not take its legitimation from the
underlying reality in this direct way. Rather, such a science is formed from the collaboration
between, on the one hand, objective similarities in the world and, on the other, perspectives and
interests of those who devise the science. The concept of hurricane is brought to bear from the
perspective of creatures concerned about the weather. Creatures totally indifferent to the weather
would have no reason to take the real patterns of phenomena that hurricanes share as constituting
a single kind of thing. With the irreducible special sciences, there is an issue of salience, which
required before their structures or patterns are reified. The entities of meteorology or biology are,
Even accepting this, why might it be thought that the perspectivality of the special sciences leads
to a genuine property dualism in the philosophy of mind? It might seem to do so for the
psychological state. So the irreducible special sciences presuppose the existence of mind. If one
is to avoid an ontological dualism, the mind that has this perspective must be part of the physical
reality on which it has its perspective. But psychology, it seems to be almost universally agreed,
is one of those special sciences that is not reducible to physics, so if its subject matter is to be
physical, it itself presupposes a perspective and, hence, the existence of a mind to see matter
as psychological. If this mind is physical and irreducible, it presupposes mind to see it as such.
We can now understand the motivation for full-blown reduction. A true basic physics represents
the world as it is in itself, and if the special sciences were reducible, then the existence of their
ontologies would make sense as expressions of the physical, not just as ways of seeing or
interpreting it. They could be understood ‘from the bottom up’, not from top down. The
irreducibility of the special sciences creates no problem for the dualist, who sees the explanatory
outside of the physical world. Nor need this worry a physicalist, if he can reduce psychology, for
then he could understand ‘from the bottom up’ the acts (with their internal, intentional contents)
which created the irreducible ontologies of the other sciences. But psychology is one of the least
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) argued that the supreme principle of morality is a standard of
rationality that he dubbed the “Categorical Imperative” (CI). Kant characterized the CI as an
objective, rationally necessary and unconditional principle that we must always follow despite
any natural desires or inclinations we may have to the contrary. All specific moral requirements,
according to Kant, are justified by this principle, which means that all immoral actions are
irrational because they violate the CI. Other philosophers, such as Hobbes, Locke and Aquinas,
had also argued that moral requirements are based on standards of rationality. However, these
standards were either instrumental principles of rationality for satisfying one’s desires, as in
Hobbes, or external rational principles that are discoverable by reason, as in Locke and Aquinas.
Kant agreed with many of his predecessors that an analysis of practical reason reveals the
requirement that rational agents must conform to instrumental principles. Yet he also argued that
can nevertheless be shown to be essential to rational agency. This argument was based on his
striking doctrine that a rational will must be regarded as autonomous, or free, in the sense of
being the author of the law that binds it. The fundamental principle of morality — the CI — is
none other than the law of an autonomous will. Thus, at the heart of Kant’s moral philosophy is a
conception of reason whose reach in practical affairs goes well beyond that of a Humean ‘slave’
to the passions. Moreover, it is the presence of this self-governing reason in each person that
Kant thought offered decisive grounds for viewing each as possessed of equal worth and
The most basic aim of moral philosophy, and so also of the Groundwork, is, in Kant’s view, to
“seek out” the foundational principle of a “metaphysics of morals,” which Kant understands as a
system of a priori moral principles that apply the CI to human persons in all times and cultures.
Kant pursues this project through the first two chapters of the Groundwork. He proceeds by
analyzing and elucidating common sense ideas about morality, including the ideas of a “good
will” and “duty”. The point of this first project is to come up with a precise statement of the
principle or principles on which all of our ordinary moral judgments are based. The judgments in
question are supposed to be those that any normal, sane, adult human being would accept on due
rational reflection. Nowadays, however, many would regard Kant as being overly optimistic
about the depth and extent of moral agreement. But perhaps he is best thought of as drawing on a
moral viewpoint that is very widely shared and which contains some general judgments that are
very deeply held. In any case, he does not appear to take himself to be primarily addressing a
genuine moral skeptic such as those who often populate the works of moral philosophers, that is,
someone who doubts that she has any reason to act morally and whose moral behavior hinges on
a rational proof that philosophers might try to give. For instance, when, in the third and final
chapter of the Groundwork, Kant takes up his second fundamental aim, to “establish” this
foundational moral principle as a demand of each person’s own rational will, his conclusion
apparently falls short of answering those who want a proof that we really are bound by moral
requirements. He rests this second project on the position that we — or at least creatures with
rational wills — possess autonomy. The argument of this second project does often appear to try
to reach out to a metaphysical fact about our wills. This has led some readers to the conclusion
that he is, after all, trying to justify moral requirements by appealing to a fact — our autonomy
Kant’s analysis of the common moral concepts of “duty” and “good will” led him to believe that
we are free and autonomous as long as morality, itself, is not an illusion. Yet in the Critique of
Pure Reason, Kant also tried to show that every event has a cause. Kant recognized that there
seems to be a deep tension between these two claims: If causal determinism is true then, it
seems, we cannot have the kind of freedom that morality presupposes, which is “a kind of
causality” that “can be active, independently of alien causes determining it” (G 4:446)
Kant thought that the only way to resolve this apparent conflict is to distinguish
between phenomena, which is what we know through experience, and noumena, which we can
consistently think but not know through experience. Our knowledge and understanding of the
empirical world, Kant argued, can only arise within the limits of our perceptual and cognitive
powers. We should not assume, however, that we know all that may be true about “things in
themselves,” although we lack the “intellectual intuition” that would be needed to learn about
such things.
These distinctions, according to Kant, allow us to resolve the “antinomy” about free will by
interpreting the “thesis” that free will is possible as about noumena and the “antithesis” that
every event has a cause as about phenomena. Morality thus presupposes that agents, in an
incomprehensible “intelligible world,” are able to make things happen by their own free choices
Many of Kant’s commentators, who are skeptical about these apparently exorbitant metaphysical
claims, have attempted to make sense of his discussions of the intelligible and sensible worlds in
less metaphysically demanding ways. On one interpretation (Hudson 1994), one and the same act
can be described in wholly physical terms (as an appearance) and also in irreducibly mental
terms (as a thing in itself). On this compatibilist picture, all acts are causally determined, but a
free act is one that can be described as determined by irreducibly mental causes, and in particular
by the causality of reason. A second interpretation holds that the intelligible and sensible worlds
are used as metaphors for two ways of conceiving of one and the same world (Korsgaard 1996;
Allison 1990; Hill 1989a, 1989b). When we are engaging in scientific or empirical
causation, but when we deliberate, act, reason and judge, we often take up a different
perspective, in which we think of ourselves and others as agents who are not determined by
natural causes. When we take up this latter, practical, standpoint, we need not believe that we or
others really are free, in any deep metaphysical sense; we need only operate “under the idea of
freedom” (G 4:448). Controversy persists, however, about whether Kant’s conception of freedom
requires a “two worlds” or “two perspectives” account of the sensible and intelligible worlds.
Although the two most basic aims Kant saw for moral philosophy are to seek out and establish
the supreme principle of morality, they are not, in Kant’s view, its only aims. Moral philosophy,
for Kant, is most fundamentally addressed to the first-person, deliberative question, “What ought
I to do?”, and an answer to that question requires much more than delivering or justifying the
fundamental principle of morality. We also need some account, based on this principle, of the
nature and extent of the specific moral duties that apply to us. To this end, Kant employs his
findings from the Groundwork in The Metaphysics of Morals, and offers a categorization of our
basic moral duties to ourselves and others. In addition, Kant thought that moral philosophy
should characterize and explain the demands that morality makes on human psychology and
forms of human social interaction. These topics, among others, are addressed in central chapters
of the second Critique, the Religion and again in the Metaphysics of Morals, and are perhaps
satisfying answer to the question of what one ought to do would have to take into account any
political and religious requirements there are. Each of these requirement turn out to be, indirectly
at least, also moral obligations for Kant, and are discussed in the Metaphysics of Morals and
in Religion. Finally, moral philosophy should say something about the ultimate end of human
endeavor, the Highest Good, and its relationship to the moral life. In the Critique of Practical
Reason, Kant argued that this Highest Good for humanity is complete moral virtue together with
complete happiness, the former being the condition of our deserving the latter. Unfortunately,
Kant noted, virtue does not insure wellbeing and may even conflict with it. Further, he thought
that there is no real possibility of moral perfection in this life and indeed few of us fully deserve
the happiness we are lucky enough to enjoy. Reason cannot prove or disprove the existence of
Divine Providence, on Kant’s view, nor the immortality of the soul, which seem necessary to
rectify these things. Nevertheless, Kant argued, an unlimited amount of time to perfect ourselves
philosophy should employ when pursuing these aims. A basic theme of these discussions is that
the fundamental philosophical issues of morality must be addressed a priori, that is, without
priori method to seek out and establish fundamental moral principles, however, does not always
appear to be matched by his own practice. The Metaphysics of Morals, for instance, is meant to
be based on a priori rational principles, but many of the specific duties that Kant describes, along
with some of the arguments he gives in support of them, rely on general facts about human
In one sense, it might seem obvious why Kant insists on an a priori method. A “metaphysics of
morals” would be, more or less, an account of the nature and structure of moral requirements —
in effect, a categorization of duties and values. Such a project would address such questions as,
what is a duty. What kinds of duties are there? What is the good? What kinds of goods are there?,
and so on. These appear to be metaphysical questions. Any principle used to provide such
categorizations appears to be a principle of metaphysics, in a sense, but Kant did not see them as
external moral truths that exist independently of rational agents. Moral requirements, instead, are
rational principles that tell us what we have overriding reason to do. Metaphysical principles of
this sort are always sought out and established by a priori methods.
Perhaps something like this was behind Kant’s thinking. However, the considerations he offers
for an a priori method do not all obviously draw on this sort of rationale. The following are three
The first is that, as Kant and others have conceived of it, ethics initially requires an analysis of
our moral concepts. We must understand the concepts of a “good will”, “obligation”, “duty” and
so on, as well as their logical relationships to one another, before we can determine whether our
use of these concepts is justified. Given that the analysis of concepts is an a priori matter, to the
Of course, even were we to agree with Kant that ethics should begin with analysis, and that
analysis is or should be an entirely a priori undertaking, this would not explain why all of the
fundamental questions of moral philosophy must be pursued a priori. Indeed, one of the most
important projects of moral philosophy, for Kant, is to show that we, as rational agents, are
bound by moral requirements and that fully rational agents would necessarily comply with them.
Kant admits that his analytical arguments for the CI are inadequate on their own because the
most they can show is that the CI is the supreme principle of morality if there is such a principle.
Kant must therefore address the possibility that morality itself is an illusion by showing that the
CI really is an unconditional requirement of reason that applies to us. Even though Kant thought
that this project of “establishing” the CI must also be carried out a priori, he did not think we
could pursue this project simply by analyzing our moral concepts or examining the actual
behavior of others. What is needed, instead, is a “synthetic”, but still a priori, kind of argument
that starts from ideas of freedom and rational agency and critically examines the nature and
This is the second reason Kant held that fundamental issues in ethics must be addressed with
an a priori method: The ultimate subject matter of ethics is the nature and content of the
Fundamental issues in moral philosophy must also be settled a priori because of the nature of
moral requirements themselves, or so Kant thought. This is a third reason he gives for an a
priori method, and it appears to have been of great importance to Kant: Moral requirements
present themselves as being unconditionally necessary. But an a posteriori method seems ill-
suited to discovering and establishing what we must do whether we feel like doing it or not;
surely such a method could only tell us what we actually do. So an a posteriori method of
seeking out and establishing the principle that generates such requirements will not support the
observations could only deliver conclusions about, for instance, the relative advantages of moral
behavior in various circumstances or how pleasing it might be in our own eyes or the eyes of
others. Such findings clearly would not support the unconditional necessity of moral
of moral requirements. It would view them as demands for which compliance is not
advantageous, optimific or in some other way felicitous. Thus, Kant argued that if moral
analysis and defense of moral thought, it must be carried out entirely a priori.
REFLECTION
based on its own principles. A philosophy that was neither independent nor truly and totally
rational could not be an aid to theology, because it wouldn’t exist at all, much less help anything.
in order of human fulfillment. Prayerful union of the soul with God is the end toward which
philosophizing is ordered. Since before the fall of Rome, monks had been spending great deals of
time copying, studying, and meditating on text as an aid to contemplation. St. Augustine, in de
doctrina christiana, argued that the preacher should take the best from all the sciences, like the
Israelites plundered Egypt, in order to further their study with God. He claimed that knowledge
of natural sciences and philosophy had a limited intrinsic value, but showed a great amount of
usefulness when used as an aid to the knowledge of God. As a result, philosophy is the
“handmaid” that prepares the human mind for contemplation – or theology, viewed not strictly as
a scientific examination of religious truths, but as prayerful meditation upon God Himself.
Dualism is the concept that our mind is more than just our brain. This concept entails that our
mind has a non-material, spiritual dimension that includes consciousness and possibly an eternal
attribute. One way to understand this concept is to consider our self as a container including our
physical body and physical brain along with a separate non-physical mind, spirit, or soul. The
mind, spirit, or soul is considered the conscious part that manifests itself through the brain in a
similar way that picture waves and sound waves manifest themselves through a television set.
The picture and sound waves are also non-material just like the mind, spirit, or soul.
If dualism is not true, the mind is limited to the physical brain. Assuming this scenario, what
kind of a mind would we expect? We certainly would not expect to have consciousness strictly
from materials. Perhaps we could expect to see a mechanical mind similar to a computer that is
run by a program. We would not expect things like consciousness, sensations, thoughts,
emotions, desires, beliefs, and free choice. Such a mind would behave in a deterministic way
based upon the laws of matter. Many scientists and philosophers are now concluding that the
laws of chemistry and physics cannot explain the experience of consciousness in human beings.
With dualism we would expect the spiritual mind to have similar attributes to that of its source. If
the source is the God of the Bible, the concept of dualism is consistent with the Bible.
. In their journal article, physician Sam Parnia and Peter Fenwick, a neuropsychiatrist, describe
their study of sixty-three heart attack victims who were declared clinically dead but were later
revived and interviewed. About ten percent reported having well-structured, lucid thought
processes, with memory formation and reasoning during the time that their brains were not
functioning. The effects of starvation of oxygen or drugs were ruled out as factors. Researchers
consensus that it is true. However, dualism vs. materialism is tied to the creation vs. evolution
debate. Consequently, evolutionists need to take unrealistic positions against dualism to defend
In a similar way, if only the objective scientific empirical facts are considered, evolution has no
The mind-body problem is the problem: what is the relationship between mind and body? Or
alternatively: what is the relationship between mental properties and physical properties?
Humans have (or seem to have) both physical properties and mental properties. People have (or
seem to have) the sort of properties attributed in the physical sciences. These physical properties
include size, weight, shape, colour, motion through space and time, etc. But they also have (or
seem to have) mental properties, which we do not attribute to typical physical objects these
much else), intentionality (including beliefs, desires, and much else), and they are possessed by a
subject or a self.
Physical properties are public, in the sense that they are, in principle, equally observable by
anyone. Some physical properties—like those of an electron—are not directly observable at all,
but they are equally available to all, to the same degree, with scientific equipment and
techniques. The same is not true of mental properties. I may be able to tell that you are in pain by
your behaviour, but only you can feel it directly. Similarly, you just know how something looks
to you, and I can only surmise. Conscious mental events are private to the subject, who has a
The mind-body problem concerns the relationship between these two sets of properties. The
Materialist views say that, despite appearances to the contrary, mental states are just physical
states. Behaviourism, functionalism, mind-brain identity theory and the computational theory of
mind are examples of how materialists attempt to explain how this can be so. The most common
factor in such theories is the attempt to explicate the nature of mind and consciousness in terms
of their ability to directly or indirectly modify behaviour, but there are versions of materialism
that try to tie the mental to the physical without explicitly explaining the mental in terms of its
behaviour-modifying role. The latter are often grouped together under the label ‘non-reductive
physicalism’, though this label is itself rendered elusive because of the controversial nature of
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) argued that the supreme principle of morality is a standard of
rationality that he dubbed the “Categorical Imperative” (CI). Kant characterized the CI as an
objective, rationally necessary and unconditional principle that we must always follow despite
any natural desires or inclinations we may have to the contrary. All specific moral requirements,
according to Kant, are justified by this principle, which means that all immoral actions are
irrational because they violate the CI. Other philosophers, such as Hobbes, Locke and Aquinas,
had also argued that moral requirements are based on standards of rationality. However, these
standards were either instrumental principles of rationality for satisfying one’s desires, as in
Hobbes, or external rational principles that are discoverable by reason, as in Locke and Aquinas.
Kant agreed with many of his predecessors that an analysis of practical reason reveals the
requirement that rational agents must conform to instrumental principles. Yet he also argued that
can nevertheless be shown to be essential to rational agency. This argument was based on his
striking doctrine that a rational will must be regarded as autonomous, or free, in the sense of
being the author of the law that binds it. The fundamental principle of morality — the CI — is
none other than the law of an autonomous will. Thus, at the heart of Kant’s moral philosophy is a
conception of reason whose reach in practical affairs goes well beyond that of a Humean ‘slave’
to the passions. Moreover, it is the presence of this self-governing reason in each person that
Kant thought offered decisive grounds for viewing each as possessed of equal worth and
The most basic aim of moral philosophy, and so also of the Groundwork, is, in Kant’s view, to
“seek out” the foundational principle of a “metaphysics of morals,” which Kant understands as a
system of a priori moral principles that apply the CI to human persons in all times and cultures.
Kant pursues this project through the first two chapters of the Groundwork. He proceeds by
analyzing and elucidating common sense ideas about morality, including the ideas of a “good
will” and “duty”. The point of this first project is to come up with a precise statement of the
principle or principles on which all of our ordinary moral judgments are based. The judgments in
question are supposed to be those that any normal, sane, adult human being would accept on due
rational reflection. Nowadays, however, many would regard Kant as being overly optimistic
about the depth and extent of moral agreement. But perhaps he is best thought of as drawing on a
moral viewpoint that is very widely shared and which contains some general judgments that are
very deeply held. In any case, he does not appear to take himself to be primarily addressing a
genuine moral skeptic such as those who often populate the works of moral philosophers, that is,
someone who doubts that she has any reason to act morally and whose moral behavior hinges on
a rational proof that philosophers might try to give. For instance, when, in the third and final
chapter of the Groundwork, Kant takes up his second fundamental aim, to “establish” this
foundational moral principle as a demand of each person’s own rational will, his conclusion
apparently falls short of answering those who want a proof that we really are bound by moral
requirements. He rests this second project on the position that we — or at least creatures with
rational wills — possess autonomy. The argument of this second project does often appear to try
to reach out to a metaphysical fact about our wills. This has led some readers to the conclusion
that he is, after all, trying to justify moral requirements by appealing to a fact — our autonomy
Throughout his moral works, Kant returns time and again to the question of the method moral
philosophy should employ when pursuing these aims. A basic theme of these discussions is that
the fundamental philosophical issues of morality must be addressed a priori, that is, without
priori method to seek out and establish fundamental moral principles, however, does not always
appear to be matched by his own practice. The Metaphysics of Morals, for instance, is meant to
be based on a priori rational principles, but many of the specific duties that Kant describes, along
with some of the arguments he gives in support of them, rely on general facts about human
In one sense, it might seem obvious why Kant insists on an a priori method. A “metaphysics of
morals” would be, more or less, an account of the nature and structure of moral requirements —
in effect, a categorization of duties and values. Such a project would address such questions as,
what is a duty. What kinds of duties are there? What is the good? What kinds of goods are there?,
and so on. These appear to be metaphysical questions. Any principle used to provide such
categorizations appears to be a principle of metaphysics, in a sense, but Kant did not see them as
external moral truths that exist independently of rational agents. Moral requirements, instead, are
rational principles that tell us what we have overriding reason to do. Metaphysical principles of
this sort are always sought out and established by a priori methods.
Fundamental issues in moral philosophy must also be settled a priori because of the nature of
moral requirements themselves, or so Kant thought. This is a third reason he gives for an a
priori method, and it appears to have been of great importance to Kant: Moral requirements
present themselves as being unconditionally necessary. But an a posteriori method seems ill-
suited to discovering and establishing what we must do whether we feel like doing it or not;
surely such a method could only tell us what we actually do. So an a posteriori method of
seeking out and establishing the principle that generates such requirements will not support the
observations could only deliver conclusions about, for instance, the relative advantages of moral
behavior in various circumstances or how pleasing it might be in our own eyes or the eyes of
others. Such findings clearly would not support the unconditional necessity of moral
of moral requirements. It would view them as demands for which compliance is not
advantageous, optimific or in some other way felicitous. Thus, Kant argued that if moral
analysis and defense of moral thought, it must be carried out entirely a priori.
johnson, r. (2004, february 23). stanford.edu. Retrieved from stanford encyclopedia of philosophy:
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/