Ph.D. Program in Political Science of The City University of New York
Ph.D. Program in Political Science of The City University of New York
Ph.D. Program in Political Science of The City University of New York
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Ph.D. Program in Political Science of the City University of New York is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to Comparative Politics.
http://www.jstor.org
Juan Linz, Presidentialism, and Democracy
A CriticalAppraisal
Since the 1960s Juan J. Linz has been one of the world's foremost contributorsto
our understandingof democracy, authoritarianism,and totalitarianism.Although
many of his contributionshave had a significant impact, few have been as far-
reaching as his essay "Presidentialor ParliamentaryDemocracy: Does It Make a
Difference?,"originally written in 1985. The essay argued that presidentialismis
less likely than parliamentarismto sustain stable democraticregimes. It became a
classic even in unpublished form. Among both policymakers and scholars it
spawneda broaddebate aboutthe meritsand especially the liabilities of presidential
government.Now that the definitive version of the essay has appeared,we believe
that a critical appraisalis timely. This task is especially importantbecause Linz's
argumentsagainst presidentialismhave gained widespreadcurrency.
This article critically assesses Linz's argumentsabout the perils of presidential-
ism. Although we agree with several of Linz's criticisms of presidentialism,we dis-
agree that presidentialismis particularlyorientedtowardswinner-takes-allresults.'
We argue that the superior record of parliamentarysystems has rested partly on
where parliamentarygovernmenthas been implemented,and we claim that presi-
dentialismhas some advantagesthatpartiallyoffset its drawbacks.These advantages
can be maximizedby paying carefulattentionto differences among presidentialsys-
tems. Otherthings being equal, presidentialismtends to functionbetter where pres-
idencies have weak legislative powers, parties are at least moderatelydisciplined,
and party systems are not highly fragmented.Finally, we argue that switching from
presidentialismto parliamentarismcould exacerbateproblems of governability in
countrieswith undisciplinedparties.Even if parliamentarygovernmentis more con-
ducive to stable democracy,much rests on what kind of parliamentarismand presi-
dentialism is implemented.2
By presidentialismwe mean a regime in which, first, the presidentis always the
chief executive and is elected by popularvote or, as in the U.S., by an electoral col-
lege with essentially no autonomywith respect to popularpreferencesand, second,
the terms of office for the presidentand the assembly are fixed. Under pure presi-
dentialism the president has the right to retain ministers of his or her choosing
regardlessof the composition of the congress.
449
ComparativePolitics July 1997
450
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
Finally, political outsiders are more likely to win the chief executive office in
presidential systems, with potentially destabilizing effects. Individuals elected by
directpopularvote are less dependenton and less beholden to political parties. Such
individualsare more likely to govern in a populist, antiinstitutionalistfashion.
We agree with the main thrustof four of Linz's five basic criticisms of presidential-
ism. We concur that the issue of dual legitimacy is nettlesome in presidentialsys-
tems, but we believe that his contrastbetween presidentialand parliamentarysys-
tems is too stark.To a lesser degree than in presidentialsystems, conflicting claims
to legitimacyalso exist in parliamentarysystems. Conflicts sometimes arise between
the lower and upper houses of a bicameral legislature, each claiming to exercise
legitimatepower. If both houses have the power of confidence over the cabinet, the
most likely outcome when the houses are controlledby differentmajoritiesis a com-
promise coalition cabinet.In this case dual legitimacy exists, not between executive
and assembly, but between the two chambers of the assembly. This arrangement
could be troublesome if the two chamberswere controlled by opposed parties or
blocs. In a few parliamentarysystems, including Canada, Germany, and Japan,
upperhouses have significantpowers over legislation but can not exercise a vote of
no confidence againstthe government.In some the upperhouse can not be dissolved
by the government.Then, there is a genuine dual legitimacy between the executive
and part of the legislature. Thus, dual democratic legitimacy is not exclusively a
problemof presidentialism,thoughit is more pronouncedwith it. A unicameralpar-
liament would avoid the potential of dual legitimacy under parliamentarism,but it
sacrifices the advantagesof bicameralism,especially for large, federal, and plural
countries.8
Another overlooked potential source of conflicting legitimacy in parliamentary
republicsis the role of the head of state, who is usually called "president"but tends
to be elected by parliament.The constitutions of parliamentaryrepublics usually
give the president several powers that are - or may be, subject to constitutional
interpretation- more than ceremonial.Examples include the president'sexclusive
discretion to dissolve parliament(Italy), the requirementof countersignaturesof
cabinetdecrees (Italy), suspensoryveto over legislation(Czech Republic,Slovakia),
the power to decree new laws (Greece for some time after 1975), and appointments
to high offices, sometimes (as in the Czech Republic and Slovakia) including min-
istries. Linz argues that the presidentin such systems "can play the role of adviser
or arbiterby bringingpartyleaderstogetherand facilitatingthe flow of information
among them."He also notes that "no one in a presidentialsystem is institutionally
entitled to such a role." He is quite right that political systems often face moments
451
ComparativePolitics July 1997
452
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
ing an executive; opponents must either wait out the term or else countenance
undemocraticrule. There may be cases when this higher thresholdfor government
change is desirable,as it could provide more predictabilityand stability to the poli-
cymaking process than the frequentdismantlingand reconstructingof cabinets that
afflict some parliamentarysystems.
Theoretically, the problem of fixed terms could be remedied without adopting
parliamentarismby permittingundercertainconditionsthe calling of early elections.
One way is to allow either the head of government or the assembly majority to
demandearly elections for both branches,as is the case undernewly adoptedIsraeli
rules. Such provisions representa deviation from presidentialism,which is defined
by its fixed terms. Nevertheless, as long as one branch can not dismiss the other
without standing for reelection itself, the principle of separationof powers is still
retainedto an extent not present in any variantof parliamentarism.
We take issue with Linz's assertionthatpresidentialisminducesmore of a winner-
takes-allapproachto politics thandoes parliamentarism.As we see it, parliamentary
systems do not afford an advantageon this point. The degree to which democracies
promotewinner-take-allrules dependsmostly on the electoral and partysystem and
on the federal or unitary nature of the system. Parliamentarysystems with disci-
plined partiesand a majoritypartyoffer the fewest checks on executive power, and
hence promote a winner-takes-allapproach more than presidential systems.'0 In
GreatBritain,for example, in the last two decades a partyhas often won a decisive
majorityof parliamentaryseats despite winning well under 50 percent of the votes.
Notwithstandingits lack of a decisive marginin popularvotes, the partycan control
the entire executive and the legislature for a protractedperiod of time. It can even
use its dissolutionpower strategicallyto renew its mandatefor anotherfive years by
calling a new election before its currentterm ends.
Because of the combinationof disciplined parties, single memberpluralityelec-
toral districts, and the prime minister's ability to dissolve the parliament,
Westminstersystems provide a very weak legislative check on the premier.In prin-
ciple, the MPs of the governingpartycontrolthe cabinet,but in practicethey usual-
ly supporttheir own party's legislative initiatives regardlessof the merits of partic-
ular proposals because their electoral fates are closely tied with that of the party
leadership.As a norm, a disciplined majority party leaves the executive virtually
unconstrainedbetween elections." Here, more than in any presidentialsystem, the
winnertakes all. Given the majorityof a single partyin parliament,it is unlikely that
a no confidence vote would prevail, so there is little or no opposition to check the
government.Early elections occur not as a flexible mechanismto rid the countryof
an ineffective government,but at the discretionof a ruling majorityusing its disso-
lution power strategicallyto renew its mandatefor anotherfive years by calling a
new election before its currentterm ends.12
Presidentialismis predicatedupon a system of checks and balances. Such checks
453
ComparativePolitics July 1997
454
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
Medium/ Colombia
Large DominicanRepublic
Small Botswana
Trinidadand Tobago
Medium/ Venezuela
Large
455
ComparativePolitics July 1997
Finally, we agree with Linz that presidentialismis more conducive than parlia-
mentarismto the election of a political outsideras head of governmentand that this
process can entail serious problems.But in presidentialdemocraciesthat have more
institutionalizedparty systems the election of political outsiders is the exception.
Costa Rica, Uruguay,Colombia, and Venezuela have not elected an outsider presi-
dent in recent decades, unless one counts Rafael Calderaof Venezuela in his latest
incarnation(1993). Argentinalast elected an outsiderpresidentin 1945, when Per6n
had not yet built a party.In Chile political outsiderswon the presidentialcampaigns
of 1952 and 1958, but they were exceptions ratherthan the norm. The most notable
recent cases of elections of political outsiders, FernandoCollor de Mello in Brazil
(1989) and Alberto Fujimoriin Peru (1990),owe much to the unravelingof the party
systems in both countriesand in Fujimori'scase also to the majorityrun-off system
that encouragedwidespreadparty system fragmentationin the first round.
456
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
457
ComparativePolitics July 1997
458
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
459
ComparativePolitics July 1997
Greater Choice for Voters Competingclaims to legitimacy are the flipside of one
advantage.The direct election of the chief executive gives the voters two electoral
choices instead of one - assuming unicameralism,for the sake of simplicity of
argument.Having both executive and legislative elections gives voters a freerrange
of choices. Voters can support one party or candidate at the legislative level but
anotherfor the head of government.
460
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
461
ComparativePolitics July 1997
predicteasily what the effect of their vote will be in terms of the composition of the
executive, either because postelection negotiationswill determinethe natureof the
executive, as occurs in multipartyparliamentarysystems, or because a large field of
contenders for a single office makes it difficult to discern where a vote may be
"wasted"and whethervoting for a "lesser-of-evils"might be an optimal strategy.
Strom's indicatorof "identifiability"runs from O to 1, with 1 indicating that in
100percentof a given nation's post-WorldWarII elections the resultinggovernment
was identifiableas a likely resultof the election at the time voters went to the polls.
The average of the sample of parliamentarynations in Western Europe from 1945
until 1987 is .39, that is, most of the time voters could not know for which govern-
ment they were voting. Yet undera parliamentaryregime voting for an MP or a party
list is the only way voters can influence the choice of executive. In some parlia-
mentarysystems, such as Belgium (.10), Israel (.14), nd Italy (.12), a voter could
rarelypredictthe impactof a vote in parliamentaryelections on the formationof the
executive. The formationof the executive is the resultof parliamentarynegotiations
among many participants.Therefore,it is virtuallyimpossible for the voter, to fore-
see how best to supporta particularexecutive.
In presidentialsystems with a pluralityone roundformat,identifiabilityis likely
to approach1.00 in most cases because voters cast ballots for the executive and the
numberof significant competitorsis likely to be small. Systems in which majority
run-off is used to elect the presidentare different,as three or more candidatesmay
be regardedpriorto the first roundas serious contenders.When pluralityis used to
elect the presidentand when congressionaland presidentialelections are held con-
currently,the norm is for "serious"competition to be restrictedto two candidates
even when there is multipartycompetition in congressional elections. Especially
when the electoral method is not majorityrun-off, presidentialismtends to encour-
age coalition buildingbefore elections, thus clarifyingthe basic policy options being
presentedto voters in executive elections and simplifying the voting calculus.
Linz has respondedto the argumentthatpresidentialismengendersgreateridenti-
fiabilityby arguingthatvoters in most parliamentarysystems can indeed identify the
likely prime ministers and cabinet ministers."9By the time individuals approach
leadershipstatus, they are well known to voters. While his rejoinderis valid on its
face, Linz is using the term "identifiability"in a differentmannerfrom Stromor us.
He is speakingof voters' ability to identify personnelratherthangovernmentteams,
which, as we have noted, may not be at all identifiable.
462
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
on legislative matters.Of course, this independenceof the assembly from the exec-
utive can generatethe problemof immobilism.This legislative independenceis par-
ticularlyproblematicwith highly fragmentedmultipartysystems, where presidents'
parties typically are in the minority and legislative deadlock more easily ensues.
However, where presidentsenjoy substantialassembly support,congressionaloppo-
sition to executive initiativescan promoteconsensus building and can avoid the pas-
sage of ill-consideredlegislation simply to preventa crisis of confidence. The immo-
bilism feared by presidentialism'sdetractorsis the flip side of the checks and bal-
ances desiredby the United States' founding fathers.
Congressionalindependencecan encouragebroadcoalition buildingbecause even
a majority president is not guaranteed the unreserved support of partisans in
congress. In contrast,when a prime minister's party enjoys a majority,parliamen-
tary systems exhibit highly majoritariancharacteristics.Even a party with less than
a majorityof votes can rule almost uncheckedif the electoralsystem "manufactures"
a majorityof seats for the party. The incentive not to jeopardize the survival of the
governmentpressures members of parliamentwhose parties hold executive office
not to buck cabinetdirectives.Thus, presidentialismis arguablybetterable thanpar-
liamentarismto combine the independenceof legislators with an accountableand
identifiable executive. If one desires the consensual and often painstakingtask of
coalition building to be undertakenon each major legislative initiative, ratherthan
only on the formationof a government,then presidentialismhas an advantage.
463
ComparativePolitics July 1997
example is decree power. Those that allow the president to defend the status quo
against attempts by the legislative majority to change it may be termed reactive
powers.
The veto is a reactive legislative power thatallows the presidentto defend the sta-
tus quo by reactingto the legislature's attemptto alter it, but it does not enable the
presidentto alter the status quo. Provisions for overridingpresidentialvetoes vary
from a simple majority,in which case the veto is very weak, to the almost absolute
veto of Ecuador,where no bill other than the budget can become law without pres-
idential assent (but congress can demanda referendumon a vetoed bill).
In a few constitutionsthe presidentmay veto specific provisions within a bill. In
a truepartialveto, also known as an item veto, presidentsmay promulgatethe items
or articles of the bill with which they agree, while vetoing and returningto congress
for reconsiderationonly the vetoed portions. A partialveto strengthenspresidents
vis-ai-viscongress by allowing them to block the parts of a bill they oppose while
passing those parts they favor; the presidents need not make a difficult choice of
whetherto accept a whole bill in orderto win approvalfor those partsthey favor.
Severalpresidentshave the rightof exclusive introductionof legislative proposals
in certainpolicy areas. Often this exclusive power extends to some critical matters,
most notably budgets, but also military policy, the creation of new bureaucratic
offices, and laws concerningtariff and creditpolicies. This power is also reactive. If
presidentspreferthe statusquo to outcomes likely to win the supportof a veto-proof
majorityin congress, they can preventchanges simply by not initiatinga bill.
A proactivepower lets presidentsestablisha new statusquo. If presidentscan sign
a decree thatbecomes law the momentit is signed, they have effectively established
a new statusquo. Relatively few democraticconstitutionsallow presidentsto estab-
lish new legislation without first having been delegated explicit authorityto do so.
Those that confer this authoritypotentiallyallow presidentsto be very powerful.
Decree power alone does not let presidentsdominatethe legislative process. They
can not emit just any decree, confident that it will survive in congress. But it lets
them shape legislation and obtain laws that congress on its own would not have
passed. Even though a congressional majority can usually rescind decrees, presi-
dents can still play a majorrole in shaping legislation for three reasons:unlike a bill
passed by congress, a presidentialdecree is alreadylaw, not a mere proposal,before
the other branch has an opportunityto react to it; presidents can overwhelm the
congressional agenda with a flood of decrees, making it difficult for congress to
considermeasuresbefore theireffects may be difficult to reverse;and presidentscan
use the decree power strategically,at a point in the policy space where a congres-
sional majorityis indifferentbetween the status quo and the decree:
A case can be made thatpresidentialsystems generally functionbetterif the pres-
ident has relatively limited powers over legislation. When the congress is powerful
relativeto the president,situationsin which the presidentis shortof a majorityin the
464
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
congress need not be crisis-ridden.If the presidenthas great legislative powers, the
ability of the congressto debate,logroll, and offer compromiseson conflictualissues
is constrained.The presidency takes on enormous legislative importance,and the
incumbenthas formidableweapons with which to fine tune legislation and limit con-
sensus building in the assembly. It is probably no accident that some of the most
obvious failures among presidential democracies have been systems with strong
presidentialpowers.
Party Systems and Presidentialism Linz notes that the problemsof presidential-
ism are compoundedin nationswith deep political cleavages and numerouspolitical
parties. This argumentcould be taken further:the perils of presidentialismpertain
largely to countrieswith deep political cleavages and/ornumerouspolitical parties.
In countrieswhere political cleavages are less profoundand where the party system
is not particularlyfragmented,the problemsof presidentialismare attenuated.Many
presidentialdemocracieseitherhave deep political cleavages or many parties;hence
Linz's arguments about the problems of presidentialismare often pertinent. But
some presidentialsystems have less indelibly engravedcleavages and less partysys-
tem fragmentation.In these cases, presidentialismoften functions reasonablywell,
as the United States, Costa Rica, and Venezuela suggest. One way of easing the
strainson presidentialsystems is to take steps to avoid high party system fragmen-
tation.21
465
ComparativePolitics July 1997
466
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
The problems of the fixed term of office are also mitigatedby limited party sys-
tem fragmentation.The fixed termof office is particularlyperniciouswhen the pres-
ident can not get legislation passed. This problem is more likely when the presi-
dent's party is in a distinct minority. It is no coincidence that the oldest and most
establishedpresidentialdemocracies- the U.S., Costa Rica, and Venezuela (from
1973 to 1993) - have two or two-and-one-halfpartysystems. Six of the seven pres-
idential democracies that have lasted at least twenty-five consecutive years (Uru-
guay, Colombia, and the Philippines, in addition to the three already mentioned
cases) have had under three effective parties. Chile is the sole exception. Extreme
multipartismdoes not doom presidentialdemocracies,but it does make their func-
tioning more difficult.
467
ComparativePolitics July 1997
468
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
Conclusion
NOTES
We are grateful to Michael Coppedge, Steve Levitsky, Arend Lijphart,Timothy Scully, and two
anonymousreviewers for helpful criticisms of earlierdraftsof this article.
1. We follow Lijphart'sunderstandingof a Westminster(British) style democracy.Arend Lijphart,
Democracies.: Patterns of Majoritarian and Consensus Governmentin Twenty-OneCountries (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1984), esp. pp. 1-20. For our purposes, the most importantfeaturesof a
469
ComparativePolitics July 1997
470
Scott Mainwaringand MatthewJ. Shugart
471