Alpers Schiller Pastoral
Alpers Schiller Pastoral
Alpers Schiller Pastoral
UC Berkeley
Peer Reviewed
Title:
Schiller's Naive and Sentimental Poetry and the Modern Idea of Pastoral
Author:
Alpers, Paul, University of California, Berkeley
Publication Date:
04-01-1990
Series:
Cabinet of the Muses: Rosenmeyer Festschrift
Permalink:
http://escholarship.org/uc/item/25986405
Keywords:
Schiller, pastoral poetry, Empson
Abstract:
Pages 319-331 of Cabinet of the Muses: essays on classical and comparative literature in honor
of Thomas G. Rosenmeyer, edited by Mark Griffith and Donald J. Mastronarde (Atlanta 1990).
Copyright Information:
All rights reserved unless otherwise indicated. Contact the author or original publisher for any
necessary permissions. eScholarship is not the copyright owner for deposited works. Learn more
at http://www.escholarship.org/help_copyright.html#reuse
Paul Alpers
University of California, Berkeley
the elegy in the narrower sense, and the second the idyll.
(200)
On Naive and Sentimental Poetry has been said to “constitute the
intellectual foundation for all modern approaches to pastoral,” on the grounds
that it established modal (as opposed to traditional generic) definitions of the
various kinds of poetry.2 But the essay is more specifically a “mirror for
[321]modern critics,” as the Elizabethans might have said, because Schiller’s
categories of sentimental poetry correspond remarkably to what many critics
still describe as the uses of pastoral. Like Schiller, these critics consider a
longing for the ideal, prompted by a reaction against the ways of civilization, to
be at the heart of (pastoral) poetry. Hence when not indulging in pure
representations of the ideal (Schiller’s idyll), the pastoral sensibility will either
turn to criticism of corrupt or sophisticated ways of life (Schiller’s satire) or
will look back nostalgically to a simpler, vanished past (Schiller’s elegy). The
satiric potentialities of pastoral are a commonplace—to the extent that in some
accounts, satire is not simply an aspect or potential use of pastoral but its main
motive. And the extraordinary emphasis on the Golden Age in modern
accounts of pastoral—far beyond what is justified by ancient or even
Renaissance writers—is due to critics’ accepting a structure of relationships
which makes the elegy, in Schiller’s sense, a definitive manifestation of the
impulse at the heart of this kind of poetry.
However powerful and suggestive Schiller’s theory of modern poetry, it is
unlikely that we would accept the specific terms in which he frames it. But
pastoral still seems to us to be defined by the problem of man’s relation to
nature and the phenomena and issues which Schiller derives from it. Hence we
find modern critics channeling the general issues of On Naive and Sentimental
Poetry into the specific problematic of pastoral. Adam Parry’s well known
essay, “Landscape in Greek Poetry,” develops a framework almost identical to
Schiller’s:
Man in the youth of a culture possesses a kind of confidence
which does not allow him to feel alien from the world about
him. … As long as man, though different from the rest of
nature (using the word in a wider sense), is not of another
world from it, he will not choose nature as a whole, or
nature in a multiple aspect, to figure something of himself.
For this would involve his conceiving nature as something
other.3
Having outlined this version of the naive, Parry goes on to define the later stage
of culture and poetry:
Interest in landscape, or nature, for its own sake could be
best understood as applying to that literary art wherein man
looks to nature for something which he has not within
himself or which exists in an imperfect and adulterated
manner in his daily life. … Nature no longer tells us what
we are: it tells us what we are not but yearn to be. Pastoral
322 Paul Alpers
Hence the value of these poems is at the same time their limitation: “We can
love them and seek them out only when we stand in need of peace, but not
when our forces are striving for motion and activity. Only for the sick in spirit
can they provide healing, but no nourishment for the healthy; they cannot
vivify, only assuage” (211).
Schiller’s analysis has a clarity and authority unmatched by any later critic
in his tradition. He gives a persuasive account of the appeal of pastoral, to
which he in no way suggests he is immune, while at the same time his sense of
its spiritual debility is as urgent, broadly based, and decisive as Dr. Johnson’s.
It is also less easily discounted than Johnson’s. Schiller’s argument brings out
and helps us understand the fact that many modern critics of pastoral find it
difficult to take their subject seriously. Bruno Snell represents Vergil’s
pastorals as “the discovery of a spiritual landscape,” prompted by the loss of the
[324]connection, which existed in the Greek city-state, between poetry and the
world of experience and action. This analysis derives, whether consciously or
not, from On Naive and Sentimental Poetry. (The second half of Snell’s essay
is devoted to Horace, whom Schiller called “the founder of this sentimental
mode of poetry” [190]). It is Schiller’s critique of the idyll which explains why
Snell does not treat the Eclogues simply as a form of modern poetry, but makes
them sound peculiarly feeble and self-indulgent:
Virgil needed a new home for his herdsmen, a land far
distant from the sordid realities of the present. … He needed
a far-away land overlaid with the golden haze of unreality.
… [Theocritus] still shows some interest in realistic detail.
Virgil has ceased to see anything but what is important to
him: tenderness and warmth and delicacy of feeling.8
Renato Poggioli, who expended so much wit and intelligence on analyzing the
pastoral ideal, had no qualms about saying that it “shifts on the quicksands of
wishful thought”:
The psychological root of the pastoral is a double longing
after innocence and happiness, to be recovered not through
conversion or regeneration but merely through a retreat
….The pastoral longing is but the wishful dream of a
happiness to be gained without effort, of an erotic bliss
made absolute by its own irresponsibility.9
Rosalie Colie praises Marvell’s “Mower” poems in the same vein:
The pastoral cannot provide a satisfactory working-model
for lives as men and women must live them, complicated
beyond help from the pastoral paradigm. Just because the
pastoral is so “useless” in interpreting human life, it is
important for its recreative, dreaming beauty all the same.10
These uneasy and condescending accounts can be referred to and explained by
Schiller not only because we still discern in pastoral the features of the
sentimental idyll, but also because we measure them by similar criteria. We
share with Schiller ideas of psychological integrity and fullness of experience
Schiller and the Modern Idea of Pastoral 325
that make pastoral appear callow or self-indulgent, and we share a sense of the
necessities of history that makes it appear escapist.
Modern critics are of course aware that pastoral writing is urban and
sophisticated. But by accepting a Schillerian account of the essential
ingenuousness and debility of “pure” pastoral, they can speak of its
sophistication not as one of its properties, but only as a conflict with itself. One
reason for emphasizing the satiric potentialities of pastoral is to associate it with
a stronger form of poetry that is explicitly ironic and schooled by experience.
But the characteristic way of making pastoral interesting is to claim that it
undermines or criticizes or transcends itself. Thus Harry Berger speaks of
Spenser’s Shepheardes Calender as a critique of “the paradise principle.” In
terms that again remind us of Schiller, he argues that Spenser represents “the
longing for paradise as the psychological basis of the pastoral retreat from life.
This longing may be inflected toward wish-fulfilling fantasy or toward bitter
rejection of the world that falls short of such fantasy.”11 What makes The
[325]Shepheardes Calender worth our attention, in Berger’s view, is that it
takes as jaundiced a view of the paradise principle as we do and proves to be
“an ironic portrait of the tradition it claims for itself.”12 Irony is not the only
way in which pastoral can be interpreted as something other than it seems.
Allegory too has been much favored by modern critics, who often invoke the
tradition that Vergil’s Fourth Eclogue prophesied the birth of Christ in order to
justify their own abstruse or high-minded interpretations.
Such attempts to transcend the felt limitations of pastoral are once again
anticipated and prospectively analyzed in On Naive and Sentimental Poetry.
The contradiction in sentimental idylls, Schiller says, is that they “implement an
ideal, and yet retain the narrower indigent pastoral world” (212). In traditional
pastoral, the poetic value of this world derives solely from the naive mode of
representation. The writer of modern idylls therefore “should absolutely have
chosen another world for the ideal” (212), which he should represent in wholly
other terms:
Let him not lead us backwards into our childhood in order
to secure to us with the most precious acquisitions of the
understanding a peace which cannot last longer than the
slumber of our spiritual faculties, but rather lead us forward
into our maturity in order to permit us to perceive that
higher harmony which rewards the combatant and gratifies
the conqueror. Let him undertake the task of idyll so as to
display that pastoral innocence even in creatures of
civilisation and under all the conditions of the most active
and vigorous life, of expansive thought, of the subtlest art,
the highest social refinement, which, in a word, leads man
who cannot now go back to Arcady forward to Elysium.
(213)
This is a call for what our leading witness of Romantic prophecy calls “strong”
poetry. Schiller’s terms are less ironized and embattled than Harold Bloom’s,
326 Paul Alpers
but his words bring to mind such Bloomian heroes as Blake, Wordsworth,
Shelley and Whitman, and he looks back to the same historical antecedent: “A
loftier satisfaction is aroused by Milton’s superb representation of the first
human couple and the state of innocence in paradise: the most beautiful idyll
known to me of the sentimental type” (212). When modern critics of pastoral
emphasize allegorical interpretation, the theme of art and nature, Edenic motifs,
and the higher flights of irony and self-reflexiveness, they assume the authority
of Romantic poetry in its heroic aspect and seek to make pastoral interesting to
it. Not all continue the Romantic tradition as frankly and grandly as Northrop
Frye, who assimilates pastoral to the mode of romance,13 and not all are as self-
aware as Harry Berger, who explicitly seeks a “strong” version of pastoral to
recuperate the “weak”;14 others, like Renato Poggioli and Frank Kermode, have
their own interesting quarrels with Romanticism. But just as accepting a
Schillerian account of pastoral leads to dissatisfaction with it, so embracing
Schillerian solutions leads to implausible claims. If “strong” poetry is our
criterion, there is no avoiding the conclusion that pastoral is “weak.”
*****
[326]The alternative to calling pastoral “weak” is to say, with William
Empson, that “the pastoral process” consists of “putting the complex into the
simple.”15 Though Some Versions of Pastoral is widely recognized as the
profoundest treatment of the subject, its coruscating brilliance and
idiosyncracies of manner have made it as difficult to use as it is easy to admire.
Empson’s view of pastoral has been regarded as either unmanageably inclusive
or narrowly social and political. It in fact lies between these extremes, wide-
ranging indeed but consistent. Empson develops an account of the central and
defining simplicity of pastoral not from the natural model of childhood and
maturity, but from a basic social situation—the encounter of “high” and “low”
persons, the sophisticated and socially privileged confronting (as courtiers and
rustics meet in Renaissance pastorals) the socially and economically humble.
Empson’s view that poetry is rhetorical and social—its permanent forces
unavoidably mediated by the realities of given societies and historical
moments—offers an alternative to Schiller’s view of poetry as psychological
and universal.
One finds ethical, social, and rhetorical emphases in some of the most
valuable interpretations of pastoral written since Empson—notably Thomas G.
Rosenmeyer’s The Green Cabinet (1969) and Richard Cody’s The Landscape
of the Mind (1969). (Note the concession to Schillerian poetics in these titles,
both of which, as Rosenmeyer in his case frankly admits, are irrelevant to the
arguments of the books.) By grounding their accounts of pastoral in intellectual
history—Epicureanism, in Rosenmeyer’s case, and Renaissance Neo-
Platonism, in Cody’s—both these studies imply a pre-Romantic poetics of
pastoral, to which not nature but certain kinds of human beings and human
experience are central. Neither of these studies considers itself “Empsonian.”
But it is Empson who provides a modern poetics that explains why attending to
the human figures of pastoral leads one to find its identifying features in
Schiller and the Modern Idea of Pastoral 327
The difference between Empson and Schiller comes out most pertinently
in the ways they construe simplicity and hence the idea that pastoral writing
puts “the complex into the simple.” Schiller speaks of the simplicity [Einfalt]
of naive poetry, but the element of the paradoxical or problematic in Empson’s
formula—its consciousness that “in pastoral you take a limited life and pretend
it is the full and normal one” (110)—does not come into play, since by
definition the naive as a mode of representation is expressive of full human
experience. The tension between the complex and the simple emerges when
Schiller considers simplicity in real life, in a discussion of what he calls
“childish” (kindisch) and “childlike” (kindlich) temperaments and behavior
(182ff.). “Childish” behavior and character cannot compel our unreserved
assent, he says, for they are at the expense of a mature and cultured sense of
reality. Certain individuals, however, have an inner strength and innocence that
enable them to transcend considerations of the world and its ways; in their
presence, our “mockery of ingenuousness [Einfältigkeit] yields to admiration of
simplicity [Einfachheit]” (182). In a rather tortuous discussion, Schiller tries to
reserve the honorific term “naive” for those persons who are genuinely
childlike, and at one point, he represents them as pastoral figures: in their
ignoring of “the artificial circumstances of fashionable society,” he says, they
“comport themselves even at the courts of kings with the same ingenuousness
and innocence that one would find only in a pastoral society [Schäferwelt]”
(184). But his main emphasis is on heroically naive individuals—poets, artists,
even statesmen and generals; the childlike then becomes a characteristic of
genius, whose expressions are “the utterances of a god in the mouth of a child”
(187). This is as paradoxical as Empson’s “complex in simple,” but the terms
are too [329]extreme to have the humbler pole modulate the style of life or art
that expresses it. Schiller’s attitude towards human simplicity is divided
exactly as is his attitude towards the literary idyll—between uneasiness at the
limitations of the childish and admiration of the genuinely childlike, which
proves to be heroic and godlike.
Empson’s idea of simplicity in social presence and behavior has some
superficial similarities to Schiller’s. A defence of the courtly pastoralist’s
pretence of humility—that “in its full form” it is not “merely snobbish”—
sounds some Schillerian notes:
The simple man becomes a clumsy fool who yet has better
“sense” than his betters and can say things more
fundamentally true; he is “in contact with nature,” which the
complex man needs to be, so that Bottom is not afraid of the
fairies; he is in contact with the mysterious forces of our
own nature, so that the clown has the wit of the
Unconscious; he can speak the truth because he has nothing
to lose. (14)
This could be squared with Schiller’s statement that “we ascribe a naive
temperament to a person if he, in his judgement of things, overlooks their
artificial and contrived aspects and heeds only their simple nature” (184). But
330 Paul Alpers
NOTES
1. “On Naive and Sentimental Poetry,” in H. B. Nisbet, ed., German Aesthetic and
Literary Criticism: Winckelmann, Lessing, Hamann, Herder, Schiller, Goethe
(Cambridge 1985). Nisbet reprints in full (slightly modified) the translation by Julius A.
Elias (New York 1966). Parenthetical page references in the text to “Naive and
Sentimental Poetry” are to Nisbet’s volume.
2. David M. Halperin, Before Pastoral: Theocritus and the Ancient Tradition of
Bucolic Poetry (New Haven 1983) 43.
Schiller and the Modern Idea of Pastoral 331