Quantum Time
Quantum Time
IN PROCESS
LAST UPDATE 2010.04.28
David Finkelstein
School of Physics
Georgia Institute of Technology
Abstract
Classical infrastructures of gravity and the standard model are quantized,
including space-time and the imaginary i. If one regards the standard-model
vacuum and its space-time continuum as a large thin dome with classical con-
tinuous longitudinal dimensions and quantum transverse ones, it is resolved
here into a truss dome of generalized spins. This quantization preserves the
common Lie groups and conservation laws as accurately as experiment requires
but bounds all variables. Its stat(e)vectors come from a typed exterior algebra
Q of real spinors that merges the space-time and the Hilbert space of quan-
tum theories. Its dynamics is specified by a history statvector in Q, local in
a simplicial sense, not differentially. The classical space-time manifold and
the imaginary i arise in a singular organized limit as the history undergoes a
“superconducting” condensation.
Keywords: Quantum gravity, quantum logic, quantum pragmatics, quantum
set theory, quantum topology, standard model, superconducting vacuum
1
Contents
1 Infraquantization 5
1.1 Quantizing the infrastructure Dated 2010.04.25 . . . . . . . . . . . 5
1.2 Outline Dated 2010.04.25 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7
1.3 Infinity in, infinity out revised 2010.04.25 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
1.4 Eliminating the center Dated 2010.04.20 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10
1.5 Merging products Dated 2010.04.20 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
1.6 The sea of events Dated 2010.04.22 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
1.7 Atoms of time and energy Dated 2010.04.14 . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12
1.8 Asymptotic freedom? Dated 2010.04.16 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14
2 Prior studies 15
2.1 Space-time quantization Dated 2010.04.14 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15
2.2 Feynman, Yang, and Penrose quantum spaces Dated 2010.04.20 . . 17
2.3 The reform of the Heisenberg-Poincaré algebra . . . . . . . . . 17
2.4 The reform of Bose statistics revised 2010.04.17 . . . . . . . . . . . 19
2.5 The Umklapp problem Dated 2010.04.14 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
6 Quantization as quantification 35
6.1 Cellular locality Dated 2010.04.25 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
6.2 The spin tree Dated 2010.04.25 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
6.3 Infraquantum Pauli adjoints . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
6.4 Cumulation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42
6.5 Negative probability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43
2
7.4 Dynamics as ambience Dated 2010.04.21 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
7.5 Organizational entropy Dated 2010.04.23 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52
7.6 Infraquantum ground statvector . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 54
7.7 Infraquantum organization . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
7.8 Unbreaking symmetry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
8 Gauging as quantification 55
8.1 Gauge in infraquantum space-time . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57
9 Infraquantum space-times 59
9.1 The minimum black hole . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59
9.2 Infraquantum spin-orbit analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 60
9.3 Infraquantum chirality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61
9.4 The infraquantum dome . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62
10 Generations 63
11 Particle valence 65
11.1 Standard model valences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65
11.2 Q valence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67
12 Infraquantum fields 68
12.1 Q gaugeons . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69
12.2 The emergence of space-time . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 71
3
14.9 Dirac operator . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80
15 Discussion 81
15.1 Acknowledgements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 82
16 Appendices 82
4
1 Infraquantization
1.1 Quantizing the infrastructure 2010.04.25
Nature seems to exhibit more dimensions in the small than in the large. In
this respect it is a large thin dome of events, with some cosmic ”longitudinal”
dimensions, and some submicroscopic ”transverse” ones. Its long dimensions
support the orbital coordinates xµ , pµ of space-time position and momentum,
and have cosmic extent. Its short dimensions, for example spins, are short in
the absolute sense that their coordinates take on few values. Of these, the
spins are longitudinal in the sense that they take part in rotations and boosts
of the large dimensions. Isospins are transverse in the sense that they do not,
but have their own transformations.
In working theories today, the dome is a continuum with quantum variables
attached to each point. Its infinitude of degrees of freedom causes some sig-
nificant physical computations to diverge, but a finite discrete framework like
a lattice would generally violate important conservation and invariance laws.
Quantization is a way to repair divergent theories by simplifying their Lie
algebras, originally the commutative ones. It has already eliminated infini-
ties like the heat capacity of ovens and the ground energy of hydrogen atoms,
without violating conservation of energy or momentum. Quantizing the in-
frastructure by simplifying its Lie algebras—“infraquantization”— similarly
eliminates the remaining infinities.
It represents the dome as a finite network or complex composed of quan-
tum simplices. Its elementary events, the atomistic elements of history, are
now finite in number and quantum in nature, and connect into simplices with
familiar continuous symmetries.
This unification of the long and short is of a Feynman-Penrose kind rather
than a Kaluza kind, atomistic rather than continuous. It remodels the large
dimensions after the fashion of the small rather than conversely. This process
does not introduce manifold dimensions but removes them, replacing them by
many spinlike variables.
Experiment today, however, seems rather consistent with manifold theo-
ries like those of the canonical commutation relations and general relativity.
The main goal of this work is to find a crucial experiment for the quantum
infrastructure.
The present infraquantization [hopefully] accounts for the huge anisotropy
of the dome as one accounts for that of a soap bubble or a graphene: by
the way atomistic elements organize themselves into a coherent whole. Unlike
bubbles and graphene, however, the cosmic network does sit in a space-time
but replaces the space-time, as well as the observed short dimensions. As a
5
quantum system, the network dome is described statistically by a vector in a
many-dimensional vector space of other possible statistical descriptions, not
by a membrane in a larger classical space.
Such statistical vectors are often called “state vectors”. This term came
from a non-operational interpretation that doesn’t work. We interpret them
statistically and therefore call them “statvectors” or simply “statvectors” (§17).
The familiar axiomatization of quantum theory in Hilbert space omits an
indispensable construct, quantum statistics. Since quantum theory is statis-
tical, a one-quantum theory has little meaning. A quantum theory should
be able to construct descriptions of beams of quanta out of descriptions of its
quanta. Infraquantum statvectors are posited here to have a product represent-
ing the composition of quanta. They reside in a graded Lie algebra Q whose
grade counts quanta, and whose monadics—first-grade elements—represent in-
put or output processes for individual quanta. In the present infraquantization
the multiplication is exterior, so a product can be interpreted as a simplex, and
the addition is quantum superposition, so the simplex is a quantum simplex.
To form a complex of quantum simplices, one does not add them but braces
them and multiplies (§5). A quantum complex is a simplex of simplices, not a
sum of simplices.
The thread that leads us through the maze of possible simplicial complex
theories is a correspondence principle in the sense of Bohr. It is based like
Bohr’s on a Lie algebra homotopy that simplifies its Lie algebra, now of scale
parameters other than ~. This makes it a special case of the theory of group
deformation quantization. The general hypothesis that we adopt here is that
basically simple symmetries are deformed to compound ones, including gauge
symmetries, by singular organizing limits [16]. Examples:
• The group homotopies of Yang [48] and Segal [33] (§2.2).
• The group contraction of Inönü and Wigner [25].
• The symmetry rearrangement of Heisenberg, Umezawa [41], and Nambu-
Goldstone boson theory.
An infraquantization must undeform these deformations, or reform them.
Standard quantum field theories assume that there is a fixed dynamical
law, and that it is Poincaré invariant, unitary, and local. These seem to be
features of a singular limit. Infraquantization changes them all, slightly in the
usual experimental domain but eventually greatly.
Recall that the process of quantification converts a theory of an individual
to a theory of an unspecified quantity of similar individuals, and qualitative
yes-or-no predicates to quantitative how-many predicates. Here the individuals
are quantum. Quantum quantification is discussed in §6.
6
In most developments of physical theory, quantization and gauging are
separate and independent processes. Infraquantum theories carry out both by
iterated quantification.
In a canonical theory, field operators of quantum annihilation and creation
are functions on the domelike infrastructure, and so have a higher set-theoretic
(Quine) type than the dome events. To deal with such type-distinctions be-
tween quantum systems, infraquantization replaces Hilbert space H and its
dual Dual H by a finite-dimensional subalgebra FQ ⊂ Q of a typed exterior
algebra Q, defined in §5. FQ replaces H and Minkowski space-time too, which
return only as singular organized limits of Q. FQ also replaces Newton’s dif-
ferential calculus by a typed extension of Grassmann’s algebraic differential
calculus. Dynamical variables are finite matrices, hierarchically composed of
smaller finite matrices. The vertices of its simplicial complexes are lower-type
simplices, braced to serve as points.
The infrastructure of canonical quantum theories includes the complex
plane C of probability amplitudes as well as a classical space-time manifold.
While C is useful, it fails in structural stability and locality, two working prin-
ciples that seem indispensable. This is reason enough to consider seriously
whether a real quantum theory will not work better than a complex one.
It is proposed that the imaginary i of quantum theory is no more fun-
damental than that of Steinmetz’s electric network theory. The Steinmetz i
represents a quarter-wave phase shift of an external sine-wave generator, en-
abling us to replace d/dt by iω in the network differential equations. It loses
meaning if the external generator is significantly non-sinusoidal. Then one
returns to the more generally valid second-order differential equations. It is
proposed that the Heisenberg i likewise represents a symmetry of the ambience,
and that in a less symmetric ambience the first-order differential equations of
Heisenberg and Schrödinger must be replaced by one involving higher powers
of ∂t . The variable i [hopefully] becomes a Higgs field, imparting mass to
otherwise massless gaugeons that do not annul it.
7
§8 relates gauging to quantification.
§9 discusses infraquantum space-times, the Umklapp problem and the chiral
spinors of the standard model.
§10 formulates hypotheses for a microscopic quantum theory of the three
fermion generations.
§11 injects the chemical concept of valence and the covalent bond for the
binding of space-time on one type-level and of gaugeons on the next.
§12 composes the standard model gaugeons and gravitons out of four fermions
bound by deep covalent exchanges.
§13 relates the main condensates of the standard model to those of the in-
fraquantum dome.
§14 [hopefully] sets up a fermionic infraquantum dynamics that may suffice to
control the gaugeons too.
§15 sums up consequences of this theory so far, with grateful acknowledgments.
§16 consists of appendices on general quantum theory and on Clifford and
Fermi algebras, and a glossary.
8
language of quantum annihilation and creation processes, taking a phenomeno-
logical language as basic. The Lagrangian language is then merely a singular
limit, badly defined, no more “basic” for field theory than Newtonian mechan-
ics is for quantum mechanics.
The distinction between creation and annihilation, however, is defined rel-
ative to the ambience, including the arrow of the observer’s time. To overide
this distinction relativistically, let us call elementary creation and annihilation
operations, or input and output operations, and their superpositions, collec-
tively, io operations. Stats represent io operations. The most basic statvectors
are monadics, which generate a graded algebra in which the monadics have
grade 1. The monadics of a canonical quantum theory form a Heisenberg Lie
algebra for bosons and a Fermi Clifford algebra for fermions. Collectively these
algebras and their reforms, interpreted statistically, will be calledstatalgebras.
The statvectors of the usual Hilbert-space formulation of a generic quantum
theory are, in this view, elements of a statalgebra whose product is forgotten.
The infraquantum statvectors belong to a finite-dimensional algebra of io
operations, an operational language. In what follows, it is a Clifford algebra FQ
with additional type-structure, and its statvectors concern quantum particles,
space-time events, and sub-events of a lower type.
Quantum theories with finite-dimensional statalgebra (or Hilbert space)
are termed regular after [7]. For example, a theory of a googol spins is regular,
100
since its Hilbert space dimension is only 2(10 ) , but not the theory of one linear
harmonic oscillator, which has ∞ dimensions. To be more phenomenological
than canonical quantum theories, let us assume regularity:
9
The regularity postulate encourages us to quantize until we reach a regu-
lar physical theory. Singular limits like the Poincaré group are less physical
than their regular origins. Each quantization changes the working algebra,
with consequences that may be small in the current experimental domain but
ultimately become large.
A working physical theory must revise the structure of field theory at length
scales much larger than the atom. If the Maxwell action is used, the zero-
point energy of the electromagnetic field just for wavelengths larger than the
atom suffices to curve the universe to fit into a sublunary sphere. The normal
ordering that blocks this disaster is non-local from the viewpoint of field theory,
yet natural within the io language. Infraquantization replaces the differential
locality of field theory by a simplicial locality natural to Q. In this sense the
normal ordering is local and the field-theoretic action non-local.
10
simplification implies regularity. It also provides a correspondence principle:
The homotopies (3) correspond infraquantum constructs to singular. (4)
The familiar correspondence principle with ~ → 0 is a special case.
Any fermionic statvector algebra (see Appendix 17.4) is also a Clifford algebra.
The canonical Lie algebra of classical physics becomes a door to quantum me-
chanics when we identify it with the Bose statvector algebra of the constituent
quanta. Indeed, it is often called the Heisenberg Lie algebra, as though Hamil-
ton had nothing to do with it. Likewise one may use the Dirac Clifford algebra
of spin as a door to the lower quantum levels, by identifying it with the Fermi
algebra of sub-events, the quantum elements of quantum space-time events.
We assume that the Dirac Clifford elements too include not only spin opera-
tors but also fermionic statvectors, now for sub-events. Sub-events too have a
statvector algebra, for which the following notation is useful:
TQ is the subspace of Q of type T . The statvector algebras EQ1 for events,
DQ1 for event differences, and CQ1 for cell events, are constructed in §5.
Let us make the tentative assumption that the space-time tangent bundle is
a classical organized limit of a Fermi-Dirac system of infraquantum sub-events:
tan M ≺− Fermi EQ1 ; E
Q1 = ext(DQ1 ) = (ext)2 (CQ1 ). (5)
The term “vacuum” recalls the void of Newton, while classical field theory
recalls the plenum of Descartes. A quantum infrastructure, however, is neither
11
vacuum nor plenum, but may be called a “plexus”: a structure described by
a finitude of topological connections, here membership (ι) relations between
quantum simplices of several types.
A classical crystal has a discrete symmetry group. The quanta have a con-
tinuous one, however, currently including the Poincaré group and the standard-
model unitary groups. If the ambient medium is a crystal, as Newton and
Fresnel declared the ether to be, it must be a quantum and relativistic crystal,
a synthesis of the continuous and discrete. We model it as a quantum plexus.
Since this plexus does not collapse at once, even when it is cold, its elements
presumably obey Fermi statistics. They then may form a Fermi event sea .
This is our ambience. It [hopefully] becomes the standard-model vacuum in a
singular organized limit.
The hypothetical Dirac sea is made of particles with charge and mass,
resulting in infinite charge and mass density. We do not assign charge and mass
to events of the plexus. Charge and mass are, however, sources of curvatures
of different kinds. They are not properties of individual events but describe
defects in the organization of many events, like the Burgers(-Volterra) vector
of crystal physics. Events carry charge and mass no more than a gas atom
carries a Burgers vector.
While Aristotle assumed infinitely many infinitely small instants of time, with-
out beginning or end, and infinitely many points of space, this leads to noxious
divergences already mentioned. To avoid infinities, let us seek meanings for
the constructs of space and time that are more operational.
Einstein associated a space-time point, or event, with a smallest possible
occurrence, for example a collision of two small bodies. The standard model
and general relativity still use this classical event construct, but it is obsolete.
Today we analyze the collision of the smallest bodies into supposedly quan-
tum input-output operations represented in standard theories by arrows in a
Feynman diagram. Unlike the classical ideal event of Einstein, which has only
space-time position coordinates, physical operons also manifest space-time mo-
mentum, spin, hypercharge, isospin, color, and a generation number. These
are all quantum variables in the standard model, coordinates in a quantum
space.
Fermion theories can be finite-dimensional and bosonic ones cannot. Sim-
plicity therefore seems to favor fermionic operons over bosonic. To be sure,
Palev has reformed the bosonic statistics [29] and Palev statistics can be finite-
dimensional; but a pair of fermions obey Palev statistics exactly. Let us there-
fore attempt to express all quanta as aggregates of fermions.
12
A fermionic statvector is a monadic—first-grade element—of an exterior
algebra. Let us therefore call the operon it represents a monad, with apology
to Leibniz and Aristotle. What a monad creates or annihilates can then be
called a monon for the nonce. In brief: Monadics are mathematical vectors,
that represent physical monads, that input or output monons; and analogously
for g-adics, tensors of grade g. In the present application to quantum history,
a monad is a single event of history. What it inputs or outputs depends on its
type.
Leptons and quarks are presumably global defects, with strength measured
by the mass and charge they carry. We nevertheless explore the possibility
that they can be associated with individual monons, as global defects like
disclinations and dislocations can sometimes be attached to single atoms of a
crystal.
We draw our statvectors from a typed exterior algebra Q (§6.2). Q replaces
both differential manifold and Hilbert space as a mathematical framework for
the theory of the quantum plexus. The space-time and momentum-energy
spaces of special relativity, and the Hilbert space of quantum theory, all merge
into subspaces of Q and return as singular organized limits.
The typical canonical commutation relation (2), suitable for a particle on a
line or a boson mode, is a singular organized limit of the regular commutation
relations
q , pb] = bı, [bı, qb] = Q2 pb, [b
[b p,bı] = P2 qb (6)
in which Q, P > 0 are small structural constants like ~. Rescaled, these rela-
tions define skew-hermitian so(3) rotation generators
q p bı ~ ×L
~ = L.
~
Lx = , Ly = , Lz = , L (7)
Q P QP
If we introduce an auxiliary external imaginary constant i for the moment,
we may use it to construct hermitian operators iLx , iLy , iLz , dimensionless
angular momenta that can also be regarded as occupation numbers, positive
or negative, counting angular-momentum quanta of size 1, “rotons”, around
the three axes. Then Q is the quantum of q, P is the quantum of p, and QP is
the quantum of bı. The rotator algebra (6) approaches the oscillator algebra (2)
as the physical coefficients Q, P → 0, provided that there are enough rotons of
all three kinds to imitate a continuum, and the vast majority are z-rotons:
so(3; R) −
h(1, R). (8)
This Lie algebra can be applied to time and energy too, if we take q = t
and p = E. Their quantum units are designated by X and E. A sub-event
possessing one X of duration may be called a chronon To recover the complex
13
quantum theory in a singular limit, one goes to an aggregate of such oscillators
with a cumulative bı ≈ i.
The simple commutation relations (6) have been applied to particle coor-
dinates ([48], [43],[27], and others) and to Bose statistics [29].
The symplectic group Sp(2, R) = SL(2, R), mixing q and p and fixing i, is
a symmetry of (2), but not of (6). It is stable but infraquantization does not
preserve it. Infraquantization regularizes the commutation relations, not their
symmetry.
To recover the canonical quantum theory from such a simple theory, we
must perform a homotopy (3) of the group or Lie algebra, here letting Q, P → 0.
This centralizes the variable bı −
i. To justify (6) we must find bı in experiment.
14
to small values but leaves them variable. The singular organized limit shrinks
the three-dimensional p, q,bı-space to a two-dimensional p, q-phase space.
Let us refer to such a combined process of singular homotopy and organi-
zation as a singular organized limit or Limo . For example, we write schemat-
ically
qb −
q = Limo qb, pb − p = Limo pb, bı − hi = Limo r. (9)
In particular, the compound canonical commutation relations and Bose statis-
tics are singular organized limits of regular Lie algebras.
2 Prior studies
2.1 Space-time quantization 2010.04.14
15
15 dimensions. It uses quantum constants of speed c, action h, time X, and
energy E, to make the orbital variables dimensionless.
On another track, Segal [33], attempting to understand and forecast the
evolution of quantum physics, argued on Darwinian grounds that physics is
evolving toward simple Lie algebras: A compound Lie algebra has a singular
Killing form, and an arbitrarily small change in its structure tensor makes it
non-singular. As measurements of the structure constants improve, therefore,
a compound Lie algebra has survival probability 0 relative to its semi-simple
neighbors, which outnumber it ∞ to 1. Natural selection favors simple Lie
algebras.
Since the isometry group of the statvector space of a quantum theory is
one of these Lie algebras, simplicity in the sense of Segal implies regularity in
the sense of Bopp and Haag [7]:
16
Galiautdinov [22], Shiri-Garakani [34], Bayer ([5], and others have stud-
ied Yang-invariant physics in Q. Baugh [3] represented the Yang so(5, 1) Lie
algebra in sl(6R) much as we do here.
Let us compare the quantized orbital variables of the simple spaces mentioned,
using chEX units. Here x b is a quantized x; k ∈ 3; m ∈ 4; and δ indicates a
finite difference to be summed later:
Feynman [17] xm
δb ∼ γm, δpm
= ?
Yang [48] bm
x ∼ i(g mn η 5 ∂n − η m ∂5 ), ∼ i(η6 ∂m − ηm ∂6 ).
pbm
Penrose [30] xk
δb ∼ σk , δbpm
= ?
Present xm
δb ∼ γ m5 , ∼ γm6 .
δbpm
(11)
The Penrose and Feynman quantum spaces still assume an absolute space or
space-time, with coordinates corresponding to xµ but not pµ . Simplicity led
Yang to relativize space-time within a larger quantum phase space, Yang space,
including momenta, boosts and angular momenta, as well as a complex plane.
These spaces are inadequate today. Standard model operons carry a hyper-
charge y, a generation variable Γ, three isospin variables τ k , four space-time
position variables xm , four momentum-energy variables pm , four Dirac spin
variables γ m , and eight color charges χc . In addition there are bosonic fields:
12 gauge 4-vectors Γm A , a Higgs field φ, and gravity. Infraquantizations must fit
all these variables and their commutation relations into the operator algebra
Lin Q (§14).
Yang, like Snyder, represented his algebra by differential operators on an
infinite-dimensional function space, as shown in (11). Simplicity in the present
sense requires a finite-dimensional representation like Feynman’s and Pen-
rose’s. This is the bottom line of (11). These finite-dimensional representations
must have indefinite metrics, and so do not fit into Hilbert space. A physical
interpretation of indefinite metrics and negative probability was indicated by
Dirac [13].
17
with m, m0 , m”, m000 ∈ 6.
DO: Check signs.
The commutation relations of the Heisenberg-Poincaré Lie algebra of space-
time position xµ , momntum-energy pµ , and Lorentz generator Lµ0 µ , are
[Lµ000 µ00 , Lµ0 µ ] = gµ000 µ0 Lµ00 µ − gµ00 µ0 Lµ000 µ + gµ00 µ Lµ000 µ0 − gµ000 µ Lµ00 µ0 ,
[Lµ00 µ0 , xµ ] = gµ0 µ xµ00 − gµ00 µ xµ0 ,
[Lµ00 µ0 , pµ ] = gµ0 µ pµ00 − gµ00 µ pµ0 ,
[Lµ00 µ0 , i] = 0,
[xµ0 , pµ ] = igµ0 µ ,
[xµ , i] = 0,
[pµ , i] = 0. (13)
with µ, µ0 , µ”, µ000 ∈ 4 and ~ = 1.
To deform (12) − (13), one considers a representation of (12) on a statvec-
tor space V = 2(2N + 1)R with large dimension 2(2N + 1), so that the spectra
of the Lm0 m are quasicontinuous, and focuses attention on a polarized sector
Vpol ⊂ V , supposed to represent ordinary experience, in which |L65 | is close to
its maximum eigenvalue N and the other components of Lµ0 µ are much smaller,
though still quasicontinuous. Let us set
xµ = XLµ5 ,
pµ = ELµ6 ,
bı = EXL65 . (14)
Then X is the quantum of xµ , a natural unit of time; call it the chron. E is the
quantum of pµ , a natural unit of energy; N is the maximum magnitude of any
component of Lm0 m in this representation, and in that sense is the maximum
number of rotons; and bı2 ≈ −1 in Vpol . In the limit
E, X → 0, N → ∞, with NEX = 1, (15)
the Heisenberg-Poincaré relations (13) follow.
The Casimir operator for Yang so(6 − n, n) is then
0 bµ x
x bµ pbµ pbµ
0
Lm m Lm0 m = Lµ µ Lµ0 µ ++ 2 + g 66 g 55 N2 (bı)2 . (16)
X2 E
This approximates the square of the mass in E units if X E subject to (15).
DO: Classify representations of so(6 − n, n) as Wigner classified representa-
tions of the Poincaré group.
DO: Find a correspondence between the two families of representations. Note
that the dome breaks so(6−n, n), while the vacuum is invariant under iso(3, 1)
and that Wigner uses Heisenberg statvectors while infraquantization uses his-
tory statvectors.
18
2.4 The reform of Bose statistics revised 2010.04.17
The commutation relations for Bose statistics define a canonical Lie algebra,
and so require reform. Palev [29], also explicitly seeking simplicity, reformed
the canonical algebra of Bose statistics to a simple Lie algebra, such as so(N ).
Pairs of Q fermions do not exactly obey Bose statistics. It is easy to show
that they obey a Palev statistics [29] defining an so(N ) Lie algebra of which
the canonical Lie algebra of Bose statistics is a singular organized limit. In
infraquantum theories, therefore, it is natural to represent all empirical bosons
as even polyads, with fermionic hard cores. It is understood that this hard
core must show up in high-energy photon-photon collisions.
19
3 The cosmic dome 2010.04.08
The plenum of canonical field theory emerges from a plexus of fermionic sub-
events as a singular organized limit. We do not use this limit here since it
diverges. Instead we study a symmetry rearrangement [41] that preserves the
full Yang symmetry for the dome condensate. This keeps some dimensions of
the statvector space that are usually thrown away, but the total number is still
finite, while for the singular limit it is infinite.
The standard model and the semiclassical theory of gravity describe a dy-
namically variable cosmic dome. The continuous space-time coordinates of
field theory represent its longitudinal dimensions. The unitary charges rep-
resent its transverse dimensions. A quantum spin of the Lorentz group is
attached to each operon, and can be considered longitudinal but short, quan-
tum, and regular; in contrast to the orbital variables, which are longitudinal
and long, and presently singular, still undergoing the singular diffeomorphism
group of general relativity. Chamseddine, Connes, and Marcolli [11] work with
such a singular dome.
The Q language of §5 enables one to resolve this dome into a space truss
of variable topological structure, a typed simplicial complex, with similar spin
variables for both longitudinal and transverse struts, and no continuous vari-
ables.
The Yang SO(6) group (11) implies that in a singular organized limit bı −i
there is a symplectic symmetry between position xµ and momentum pµ . Our
ambient dome reduces the Yang symmetry. Its variables xµ vary over ranges
of cosmological magnitude, while momenta pµ , ordinarily undefined for the
empty manifold, may be taken to be 0 in the ambient “vacuum”.
Something similar occurs for a bubble or a graphene flake. Organized
into a graphene, carbon atoms collectively define a 2 + 1-dimensional quasi-
manifold. The manifold (x,y,t) coordinates range over macrocosmic ranges
defined by the graphene. The carbon momenta obey the constraint px , py ≈ 0
in the manifold coordinate system due to the same binding forces that define
the quasi-manifold (x, y, t) coordinate systems. One cannot carry such results
from a graphene to a quantum plexus because graphene theory assumes a
background space-time manifold; but they are suggestive.
It is natural to enlarge the Yang so(3, 3) Lie algebra with the unitary
charges. In the standard model each operon also has a Lorentz spin, here
termed longitudinal, and there is no symmetry between the longitudinal and
transverse spins. We suppose that such an extended symmetry exists for the
kinematics of the individual operon, and is badly broken as a symmetry by the
organization of the dome. Unitary charges remain after the dome organization,
as spins transverse to the dome, along its smallest dimensions. Lorentz spins,
20
similarly, survive as short longitudinal variables, of magnitude ∼ X. Orbital
dimensions (x, p) are longitudinal and long.
Standard theories, to be sure, assume that the proper times between phys-
ical operons depend solely on their orbital variables and not on their spins
or charges, longitudinal or transverse. Spins and charges are usually given
space-time length 0.
This assumption makes the chronometric form singular. Therefore the
theory is structurally unstable. There is a natural invariant metrical form
for a spin plexus, and it defines non-zero proper times for longitudinal and
transverse spins, though they seem to be too small to be detected yet. Then a
change in a longitudinal spin generally changes the proper time between two
operons, while a change in a transverse (unitary) spin does not.
The plexus then resembles a truss dome or graphene that is as wide and
old as the cosmos but too thin to measure as yet. In an infraquantum theory
the dome is a typed simplical complex, whose vertices are generated by the
membership operation ι and multiplicative composition ∨.
The imaginary spin dyad bı − i should be considered transverse but long,
since it is macrocosmic, involving many cells, but polarized and frozen. If the
longitudinal dimensions are regarded as angular or azimuthal, the transverse
dimension of bı is radial. We are to narrate the the structure and excitations
of the dome within Q as parsimoniously as possible.
In such theories, particles are propagating excitations of the dome. They
may define representations, not of the unstable Poincaré group, as Wigner
proposed, but of the symmetry Lie group G[E] of the dome. The possible Yang
groups SO(5, 1), SO(4, 2), SO(3, 3), are simple but mix space-time, momentum,
and complex-plane dimensions, and so are broken by the dome. One of them
may still serve as group G[C] of a generic cell of the dome, on a lower type-level
C < E that includes the standard model unitary charges. Then the casimir
(operator) of the Yang Lie algebra includes and unifies casimirs of the Lorentz
group, the complex-phase group U(1), and the infraquantized proper time and
proper mass. The casimir of the cell Lie algebra similarly unifies the casimirs
of the Yang group and the unitary charges.
The physical constants entering into the Feynman or Yang groups are the
speed and action units c, h of earlier groups, elementary time and energy units
X and E with XE = h, and a cosmological integer N. Under either group, time
is just energy measured in huge units. The vacuum is supposed to reduce the
Yang casimir to the Minkowski form in an singular organized limit X, E →
0, N → ∞.
Infraquantization iterates Fermi quantification, which is represented by the
functor ext, forming the exterior algebra of a statvector space. Quantization,
general relativization, and gauging then become special cases of quantification.
21
Multiple Bose quantification has also been proposed [40, 46].
Nowadays there seem to be three variables with important non-zero vacuum
values:
• Gravity’s gµν breaks space-time sl(4R).
• Higgs hi breaks weak su(2).
• The quantized imaginary bı breaks complex-plane sl(2R) and time reversal
T ∈ SL(2R).
Let us designate the regional mean values by g, h, ı. There may be close func-
tional relations among these three varables. Both i and gνµ distinguish time
from space in their way; i responds to time reversal but not to space-reflection,
while gνµ responds to neither. Particle masses may derive from couplings to
h, but are defined as couplings to g.
It has been supposed that g and h are statistical parameters of the vacuum
statvector of the system ([38], for h). The global concept of a vacuum statvec-
tor, however, depends on the assumption that the dynamics is homogeneous
under time translation. This assumption may not work for time-shifts that
are too small or too large. In an infraquantum theory it may be impossible in
principle to carry out time translations by 10100 s or 10−100 s, as assumed in
canonical theories.
More conservatively, let us replace “vacuum” by a regional description of
the dome, which is mostly metasystem, and has only approximate symmetries,
to be determined experimentally.
The special relativity group ISO(3, 1) reduces the observer to but 10 degrees
of freedom, like a speck of crystal adrift in Minkowski space-time M. This
group is simplistic but not simple.
General relativity over-compensates. While it works empirically in the
classical macrocosmic realm, its gauge group Diff represents observers with
a continuous infinity of degrees of freedom, as if they were infinitely elastic
22
organisms, cosmic super-squids, unaffected by gravity or distortion, crossing
light-cones freely in both directions. General relativity is even more singu-
lar than special relativity. But it is also points toward simplicity, in that it
eliminates the toxic commutativity of the covariant or kinetic momentum com-
ponents. And it inspired the Yang-Mills theory of gauge and thus the standard
model.
In standard quantum theory there is a unitary relativity group U(∞) re-
lating different frames in Hilbert space. Usually the quantization of gravity is
taken to require representing Diff within U(∞).
Let us seek a still better form of relativity, with observer somewhere be-
tween infinitesimal speck and infinite squid, that supports an infraquantum
regularization of the standard model. The strategy is to morph our theo-
ries from the language of H and M to that of some finite-dimensional “field
type” FQ ⊂ Q, without changing them drastically. This is the project of an
infraquantum relativity, with memorandum
23
condensate is indeed important for gentle measurements on large blocks of the
plexus, but it is disorganized at the zero point of energy.
24
of two statvectors seem to form a two-real-parameter family of statvectors.
This indicates C; a one-parameter family implies R, a four-parameter family
H. If there are violations of i symmetry in nature, they hide even better than
violations of parity and time symmetry did.
As long as time is continuous, moreover, any discrete variable that is con-
tinuous must be constant. The choice between i and −i could propagate
throughout the connected universe in this way. But here we consider space-
times that are quantum, not continuous, and cannot use that argument. And
as an operator with i2 = −1, i has a continuous infinity of possibilities, not
just two.
Another difficulty of principle with an absolute i is that the centrality
assumption [i, o] = 0 is structurally unstable. A stabler condition is that the
commutator Lie algebra of the operator i and present observables o is simple,
but the commutators with i are small. This instability, however, seems to lead
to no infinities, and could be tolerated. We can muster no hard evidence that
i is not an absolute.
Nevertheless it moves: Assuming a fixed i throughout the cosmos vio-
lates Einstein locality, one of the most fruitful principles of the last century of
physics.
Therefore we continue the construction of a real quantum theory with a
quantized i. This includes replacing the Heisenberg Lie algebras by orthogonal
Lie algebras, which replaces Bose statistics by Palev statistics (§2.4). As (6)
illustrates, simplification may require a quantized imaginary bı − i.
One especially simple way to quantize i is to imbed it in the quaternions,
where it is no longer central. This idea was put forward by Yang at a Rochester
Conference in 1959. The proper framework for it seems to be a real quantum
theory with an SO(3) gauge group and a dynamical i-field replacing the con-
stant i, defining the electric axis in electroweak isospin space. (One first effort
explored a quaternion quantum theory, which seems to be less relevant to par-
ticle physics.) The quantized i-field of the so(3) gauge theory then turns out to
be a Higgs field [39, 1]. This is the closest we come so far to a phenomenological
justification for quantizing i.
More generally, to correspond with the standard complex theory, a real
quantum theory will have an infraquantized imaginary bı in its operator algebra,
with a correspondent i ≺− bı, possibly depending on the reference frame, as
with the relativization of time. Yang’s bı = L65 [48], suitably normalized, is
such an operator.
bı, the quantized i, has a universal direct coupling to all the other basic
fields, appearing as a multiplier for their action operators (§9.3); unlike the
Higgs field, which is not assumed to couple directly to the strong interactions.
The quantization bı ∼ Σ2 γ 65 also recalls the proposal i = γ 4321 of Hestenes
25
[24].
bı enters into the quantum skew-action operator with any action operator
δA:
δΦ = bı δA/h. (20)
Like angular momentum and energy, bı is a sum of contributions from every
system, including the metasystem. Let us hypothesize an organization akin to
polarization that centralizes (“superselects”) the resultant bı and results in the
imaginary unit of complex quantum theory: bı − i.
The Heisenberg relation [xm , pm ] = ~i returns in a singular organized limit
but cannot hold for one cell, where the Yang relation is more accurate. There-
fore canonical quantum theory grossly overestimates zero-point energies in the
small, and the vacuum energy density. The coordinates, momenta, and bı are
now cumulated spins, of finite spectra. Measuring a cumulated spin does not
take indefinitely great momentum-energy in the way that measuring a position
coordinate is supposed to. It may merely incur a space-time meltdown.
Each subsystem contributes to bı as it does to the total angular momentum
tensor. When the system is gauged for the sake of locality, bı acts as a Stückel-
berg or Higgs field in giving mass to some components of the gauge field;
namely, those in the plane normal to bı. bı thus serves to define the electric
direction in isospin space. First noted for the quaternions, this feature of the
quantized imaginary generalizes to any Clifford algebra, including Q, and to
any gauge field.
An absolute i seems almost indispensable today because it was assumed
quite early that basic quantum equations like the Heisenberg Equation of Mo-
tion have to be of first order in ∂t , a formally skew-hermitian operator on
functions of time, and the Hamiltonian provided by classical mechanics is her-
mitian. In Dirac’s development, the Equation of Motion has to be first-order
because by definition a state gives complete information, and so should deter-
mine its own future uniquely. The development equation for the state must
then contain no derivatives higher than the first.
But a statvector is not a state. It does not give complete information, only
maximal information, almost all statistical. There is no compelling reason why
a statvector should determine its own development. The concept of history is
more general than the concept of a first-order differential equation. It puts the
construct of Lagrangian before that of Hamiltonian, and Lagrange’s theory is
not partial to first order equations. In a quantum history theory the basic
dynamical equations of quantum physics could be of higher degree than the
first. Then one could reduce them to the first degree by introducing new
variables and an i, but this could be done in many ways, and the differences
among them need have no physical significance.
26
The imaginary is then needed mainly for correspondence: between the gen-
erator of ∂t and the Hamiltonian; between commutators and Poisson Brackets;
and so forth. But then it may be a product of the classical limit, like corre-
spondence itself.
In the existing complex quantum theory, i is central and therefore strictly
conserved. This has non-trivial experimental consequences. Since this central-
ity assumption is not local, let us assume that i is only approximately central,
like the coordinates of a baseball or the components of the metric tensor, as
a consequence of a singular organizing classical limit. Then all singlets of the
complex quantum theory must in principle be resolved into doublets when the
organization of i is broken and the underlying real theory peeps through.
Absent a fixed i, we must give up the Heisenberg first-order form of dy-
namics (19). In a quantum history theory, Lagrange’s equations of motion are
more natural than Hamilton’s and are typically real second-order equations.
For example, Lagrange’s equation for a quantum oscillator takes the valid form
d dq
+ ω 2 q : (4∂bt )2 q + ω 2 q = 0 (21)
dt dt
(using the commutator symbol 4 of §17.4).
In canonical quantum theories assume time coordinates from the start. The
history statvector space V of a canonical quantum theory is then a tensor
product of time slices Vt O
V= Vt (22)
t
The canonical form form for a history dynamics statvector is a tensor product
E = UT, T −1 ⊗ UT −1, T −2 ⊗ . . . ⊗ U−T +1,−T (23)
in which each time t appears twice, for input and output.
If an infraquantum theory an event may still have a time coordinate opera-
tor b
t. Then its statvector space is a direct sum of b
t-eigenspaces, and its exterior
algebra is an exterior product of time slices. Several such slices may be needed
to determine the rest of the history statvector, subject to the dynamics. For
example a second-order theory can relate two final slices t, t − 1 to two earlier
ones t − 2, t − 3. A history quantum theory of order o is one whose dynamical
statvector can be factored into sub-complexes of
An example of a covariant Killing form of Lagrange’s equations of degree
2 in ∂t is
0
4Lm0 m 4Lm m q = M 2 q (24)
27
where Lm0 m is the tensor of generators of a supposed symmetry group, like
the Yang Lie algebra (12), and M 2 is a squared-rest-mass, or an operator
generalization.
In circuit theory one might define i as the operator
This could work for the quantum theory too, but it does not look relativisti-
cally invariant. Theories like the Yang theory provide a covariant quantized
tensor that includes i as one component. Such theories have a tensor Lm0 m
of Lie-algebra symmetry generators, with a Lorentz subalgebra. The famil-
iar translation generators ∂µ are approximations to some of its components.
Lm0 m is supposed to have a non-zero vacuum expectation Lm0 m dominated in
an adapted frame by one enormous component, so that under ambient condi-
tions
Lm0 m = Lm0 m + δLm0 m , δLm0 m Lm0 m (26)
0
For a covariant formulation, let the dominant component be θm m Lm0 m . Then
0
θm m Lm0 m
bı := m0 m . (27)
|θ Lm0 m |
—compare (25).
To account for the fact that the i-trick works so spectacularly well, we
should return to Einstein once again:
28
over R, the modification for complex vector spaces being trivial. The functor
ext, by definition, converts the statvector space F to the exterior algebra
Q1 (F) := ext F, said to be the statvector space for the quantum set of type 1
over F. Thus a quantum set is simply an aggregate with Fermi statistics.
We apply ext T times to form the statvector space
for quantum sets of type T over F. Since (ext)0 := Id, F itself is the statvector
space for type 0. R, the statvector space for the empty set only, can be
regarded as the statvector space of type −1.
The types form a nested sequence. The limit T → ∞, which is merely their
union, is the statvector space for the generic quantum set founded on F:
The set y whose element is x (and x alone) is usually written as {x}. Peano
wrote it as
y = ιx, (33)
both in his theory of the natural numbers, where he called ιx the successor
of x, and in his set theory. His functional notation is more convenient for
iteration than braces, and we adopt it here, but continue to call the operation
of ι bracing.
Leptons and quarks have significant structure, described by their spins
and charges. Their statvector spaces are tensor products of statvector spaces
associated with each of these properties. Tensor products are how parts are
assembled into wholes in quantum theory; one may therefore call the spin of an
29
electron a part of the electron. This does not imply that one can disassemble
the electron into such parts. We may see a particle without a spin, but we
never see a spin without a particle.
Such a structured but indivisible unit can be represented by a unit set =
singleton = monad whose fine structure is in its second members, the members
of its sole member.
We construct a typed quantum set algebra Q suitable for framing a finite
quantum theory by enriching a classical set algebra C with quantum super-
position so that it becomes an exterior algebra Q. The exterior product cor-
responds to the disjoint union. The grade-g subspace of Q is written Qg . ι
becomes a linear operator
ι : Q 7→ Q1 (34)
Q is a real exterior algebra over itself, and minimal in that respect:
(1) Q = ext ι’ Q;
(2) If P = ext P, (35)
then P ⊃ Q.
30
5.1 Spin-statistics equality
A useful clue to this quantization is the observed spin-statistics equality
W = X; (36)
W being the spin parity, a homotopy that rotates the system continuously
.
through 2π. W = +1 for even spin, −1 for odd (in units of h/2). And X being
the statistics parity, interchanging two statvectors of the system: Xψφ = φψX.
.
X = +1 for even (Bose) statistics, −1 for odd (Fermi).
Since monadics x ∈ Q1 , the first grade of Q, obey x2 = 0, the monads they
describe statistically have fermionic statistics, X ≡ −1. We may infer from
(36) that monadics are to serve as spinors, with W = −1.
The quadratic space W[T ] of its orthogonal group SO(W[T ]) will be defined
(in (53)). All bosons must be pseudo-bosons composed of fermions in Q theory,
obeying a Palev statistics [29], which is tautologically simple, with a Lie algebra
such as so(n + 2) instead of the canonical Lie algebra H(n). The Q operators
for orbital variables (§8), isospin, color, hypercharge, generation, gaugeons,
and the higgs are in the Lie algebra sl(EQ) ⊂ sl(Q) (not in Q) and sums of
atomic terms of a cellular level sl(CQ) ⊂ sl(E)
The typed exterior algebra has a long beard [19, 21]. The present work
uses a simplicity principle (3) and a correspondence principle (4) lacking in
those first efforts.
One disturbing feature of the ι operator is that it forgets the statistics of
its operand. Whether x has odd or even statistics, ιx has odd statistics.
Fortunately we encounter a similar anomaly daily in particle physics. The
statistics of a particle forgets all its parts except its spin—for example, its
isospin, color, and flavor.
Again, in the standard constriction of a spinor space as the exterior algebra
over a semivector space, both odd-grade and even-grade exterior products
constitute spinors and are subject to Fermi statistics.
We may represent this feature of nature by a difference in type. The prop-
erties of a particle that do not matter for its statistics are internal in the sense
that they act on the contents of the outermost ι defining a particle statvector.
They operate on a lower type than spin.
In the topological theory of quantum statistics, one expresses an exchange
of a pair in terms of a macroscopic continuous rotation of the pair through π. In
this infraquantum theory, the explanatory direction is reversed. A macroscopic
rotation of a spin is composed of microscopic input-output operations on the
31
semivectorial parts of the spin. For spin 1/2, the the statvectors are the factors
0 0
γ µ in γ µ µ = [γ µ , γ µ ]/2.
To incorporate the spin-statistics equation, we assume:
All quantum histories are assembled from monads described by spinors. (38)
32
6 ...
26 ...
5 ...
25 ...
4 ...
16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 ...
3
4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15
2
2 3
1
1
0
T 0
(40)
33
L 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15
L
1(2 )
(41)
Table. The 16 basic monadics of type 4.
34
frame where iE = ∂t ≺− L46 and i ≺− L56 /N, a natural approximate energy is
{L46 , L45 }
E≈ . (42)
N
6 Quantization as quantification
It is well known that “second quantization” is not a quantization proper but a
quantification, passing from one-quantum to many-quantum properties. Here
we reformulate canonical quantization too in terms of quantification, and use
it as a pattern for infraquantization. Canonical quantization in a Hilbert space
H will be referred to as H quantization. It has two steps:
35
1. Atomize. Select a canonical Lie algebra V of basic system variables.
2. Quantify. Form a linear algebra H generated by V .
Step 1 amounts to guessing the atom of the quantized system. It passes from
the classical system to a quantum atom. Step 2 clones that atom many times
using Bose statistics.
For a linear harmonic oscillator, for example, V is spanned by three vectors
q, p, i, and is also the statvector space of one phonon. The quantized oscillator
is then a bosonic assembly of such phonons.
The corresponding steps of infraquantization are:
One extends canonical quantization to allow graded Lie algebras, such as ex-
terior algebras, as well as Lie algebras proper, in order to construct variables
without classical correspondents, like spins and fermion annihilators, as well
as those that have classical correspondents. We will assume that V and its
algebra are finite-dimensional subalgebras of Q.
36
and
Dim E−1Q is microcosmic but Dim EQ is cosmological. (50)
Therefore Dim E−1Q must be so large that we can leap from E−1Q to the
macrocosmic in a single quantification. This is the cosmological leap, from
microcosm to macrocosm.
If N is the number of possible quantum monads in a system history, the
dimension of the level E monadics must obey
37
algebra by a formal sum of the simplices, but in Q addition + is mere quantum
superposition, not aggregation. A multiplicity of g Q simplices is represented
by a g-adic, a higher-level simplex. A general simplicial complex is then merely
a general simplex or polyad. To emphasize that we deal with a simplex of
simplices, we sometimes call it a meta-simplex .
We may express the two main hypotheses as one:
We write the type level of Q within which the history statvector is represented
as EQ. Classical homology works with simplices of one level, that of its vertices.
Infraquantum simplices of levels 1 – 6 are convenient and apparently sufficient
for field theory.
For any v ∈ Q, L v : Q → Q, u 7→ v ∨ u is the linear operator of left exterior
multiplication by v; R v : Q → Q, u 7→ u ∨ v, that of right multiplication by v
(Appendix 17.4). The duplex space W[T ]
Q : W → R, Q(w) = w2 . (54)
38
creators, and allow both symmetric or skew-symmetric swaps, corresponding
0
to (γc0 c)2 = ±1, then the swaps generate SO(2C , 2C ). Then Lc c represents
the swap γc0 c on Dual EQ1 , of the event level E.
The statvector algebra of level T is TQ = (ext)T R. Any infraquantum
operon is composed of lower level ones, in the way that sets and simplices
are composed of lower level sets and simplices. Q has commuting operators
Grade and Level, corresponding to classical cardinality and level. A g-adic is
an element of Q of grade g, corresponding to a set of cardinality g. The operon
it describes is called a g-ad or g-simplex.
Well before Einstein, Newton doubted his law of gravity on the basis of a lo-
cality principle that has become an indispensable guide for theoretical physics:
All action is by contact.
In the standard model, the theories of the space-time structure of special rel-
ativity and the complex-phase structure of quantum theory, remain global
rather than local, and the theories of the hypercharge, electroweak, and strong
interactions are local gauge theories built on this global structure. Classi-
cal locality requires the Lagrangian to couple only field variables at the same
space-time point; not, say, at the same momentum-energy point in the Fourier-
transform space; and with time derivatives of bounded order. Diffeomorphisms
respect such locality, but the canonical group violates it. The conflicting alge-
bras of general relativity and canonical quantum theory must blend into one
in a simple theory, for they both work too well to be merely suppressed. Let
us suppose that a reformed version of locality will survive infraquantization.
In a topological quantum theory like that developed here, two cells shall be
defined to be in contact not by coordinate relations but by shared elements,
simplicial vertices. This permits one to sharpen the locality principle to cellular
locality:
The action swaps elements between cells in contact. (56)
Then the fundamental operations are not true spins, which assume an external
quadratic classical space, but swaps, which do not. When Cartan represented
rotations by their action on spinors [9], Schur and others had already repre-
sented swaps in that way [32].
Infraquantum theories are naturally local in this sense. One sees this as
follows.
The action of gauge theories is built up from gauge differentiators Dµ (x).
Its locality depends on the action having a low polynomial degree in the D0 s,
since an infinite power series eiaD is a no-local translation.
39
Infraquantization replaces these differentiators by orthogonal-group gener-
ators Lm0 m , represented by dyadics γm0 γm ∈ Q. Their monadic factors γm are
io operators, creating and annihilating vertices of the complex on which they
act. While the D’s are represented in an orthogonal group of huge dimension,
they are formed by cumulation from the vertices of a simplex of low type with
fewer than 16 vertices. Then the vertices m, m0 being swapped belong to an
image of this basic cell.
A product like Dm000 m00 Dm0 m in the dynamical phase statvector would be
non-local, if it coupled vertices m and m00 that are not in contact. But such
0
products actually appear in the context of connecting tensors γ m”m that locate
m0 and m” in the standard cell of CQ. They are then local in the cellular sense.
with its natural, neutral quadratic form and orthogonal group. In this context,
elements of V and W are called semivectors and vectors, respectively. The
spinors of SO(W ) are then multi-semivectors, the multivectors over V . Their
exterior product violates SO(W ) and is ultimately forgotten in the standard
quantum theory.
The spin tree, the central column of (58), is constructed inductively, by
iterating ext, beginning with the trivial exterior algebra R, of grade and level
≡ 0. A spinor space of any level is the exterior algebra over the spinor space of
the previous level. We may readily reconstruct the orthogonal group of which
this is a spinor space. The spinor space of level T is defined to be the vector
space TQ ∼ = T +1Q1 . Its semivector space is the space V [T − 1] := T −1Q1 , which
is an isotropic (= null) subspace of the neutral vector space W[T − 1] of (53),
and SO(W[T − 1]) is its orthogonal group [10, 8, 12].
Orthogonal groups and Clifford-Fermi algebras sit on each rung of the spin
40
tree:
.. .. .. .. ..
. . . . .
↑ext
3 Fermi 4R 16R 32R SO(16, 16)
↑ext
2 Fermi 2R 4R 8R SO(4, 4)
↑ext (58)
1 Fermi R 2R 4R SO(2, 2)
↑ext
0 Fermi 0 R 0 1
T Lin TQ TQ W[T ] SO(W[T ])
Level Algebra Spinors Vectors Group
Ψ = 2V . (60)
The orthogonal group associated with this spinor space is SO(W) where W =
Dup V. If V ⊂ Q then Ψ ⊂ Q.
The distinction between spinors of SL(n) and vectors of SO(m) is rela-
tivized in Q. Namely, one and the same space TQ1 of any level T is a spinor
space relative to the orthogonal group SO(W[T − 1]) = SO(Dup T −1Q1 ) of the
previous level T − 1, and is a semivector space relative to the orthogonal group
SO(W[T ]) of its own level. Therefore the operator ι can be spinor-valued or
vector-valued depending on context.
Because of their spinorial statvectors, let us represent leptons and quarks as
monons. Their statvectors are monadics of the event type EQ1 . Then gaugeons
and gravitons are tetrons, with statvectors in EQ4 .
41
The case p = p[2] for four-dimensional spinors, usually designated by p =
β, is special in being skew-symmetric; the higher Pauli forms can be made
symmetric. This requires
[T ] 0 [T ] 0
∀ω ∈ so(TQ) : pq00 q0 ω q q + pq0 q00 ω q q = 0. (62)
6.4 Cumulation
A monadic of any level embraces parts of the level below. Lower-level operators
induce higher-level ones; in particular, quantum spin operators induce classical
orbital operators as follows.
Q theories represent the statvectors of simplices of simplices by multivectors
of multivectors, polyadics of polyadics. Each polyadic in level Q[T + 1] is a
unique exterior polynomial in insertions of the basic polyadics of the previous
level TQ, as in (40). Any transformation of one level thus extends naturally
42
to monadics of the next level, and thence to polyadics. This defines a unique
exponentiation
representing each orthogonal Lie algebra within the next. Iteration results in
an nth exponential representation
43
These have nothing to do with the so-called negative probabilities some-
times used to describe ordinary quantum interference of probability ampli-
tudes.
Negative probabilities have a useful physical interpretation [13]. They are
no more problematical than a negative bank deposit or a negative energy.
The number is the change in population of the system, positive for input and
negative for output. This permits us to use a single vector space V for both
input and output operations, instead of V and Dual V , and distinguish input
from output statvectors in V by the signs of their norms.
The Dirac form kψk of (69) as written is not definite. Its density is the
product of a current vector jµ (x) of the electron with a normal vector nµ (x) to
the surface S. If both point everywhere into the future, kψk is positive. But
by the fermionic symmetry between input and output, such a statvector has a
partner whose current vector points everywhere into the past and whose norm
is negative. This is not considered a problem. We interpret such statvectors ψ
of negative norm as describing an output rather than an input. Under further
inspection of this example, especially of the electric charges, we see that if the
input is an electron, the partner output is a positon. We adopt the Dirac rule
in general [13]:
44
The probability of a transition ψ → ψ 0 defined by two monadics depends
on the Fermi sea in which the experiment is carried out. An experimenter can
borrow from the sea; the resulting vacancy in the sea counts as −1 event. A
transition that has negative probability is also one that would be impossible
if the sea were empty.
From the one-quantum viewpoint the Fermi sea is part of the metasystem,
the ambient environment, not the system. It has too many variables to be
the system of any experimenter that the universe can accommodate. In the
many-quantum or field-theoretic viewpoint, however, the system can include
at least a droplet of the Dirac sea, described by a fiduciary polyadic. It then
has entropy 0, and so is highly ordered, frozen stiff, like the ether of Newton
and Fresnel, who may have wondered about how we and the planets move so
freely through such a crystal.
In the standard theories the polyadic statvector EDirac of the Dirac sea is
too divergent to be of much use. For example, its grade, the number of events
in the history of the sea, is infinite. It is usually taken into account roughly
by subtracting an infinite constant from the Hamiltonian that is said to make
the vacuum energy expectation zero, although experimentally it is not exactly
zero, and mathematically neither is ∞ − ∞. Since the subtraction requires a
Fourier transform, it is non-local as well as infinite. In infraquantum theories
the grade of the event sea E is no longer infinite but merely too large to be
counted as yet, and the vacuum energy is finite.
45
7.1 History statvectors 2010.04.29
The Feynman path integral theory would describe this dynamics by the diag-
onalized product
connects the atoms of D and provides input and output at the ends of the
process. The two together define a path amplitude
46
The limit as N → ∞ may not exist. Infraquantum theory is finite-
dimensional, and so has no such divergence problem, but it may still give
absurdly large theoretical values for quantities that are experimentally small.
The relativistic covariance of the canonical theory cannot be taken for granted,
since the time slice is not a covariant construct. But we can assure that the
infraquantum theory is covariant under a given simple group by building it
with covariant processes from covariant atoms. To guarantee Lorentz invari-
ance exactly, we choose the group of the infraquantum theory to include the
Lorentz group. To approximate Poincar’e invariance, we choose the group of
the infraquantum theory to have the Poincaré group as a singular organized
limit, as the Yang group SO(3, 3) does.
Let us suppose for now that an infraquantum system history is maximally
described by a history statvector E in a finite-dimensional subspace V ⊂ Q.
This means that V , and hence Q, contains correspondents of both input and
output statvectors of the canonical theory. A classical history is a singular
organized limit.
The correspondence between inputs and outputs that make up an assured
transition is now represented by a linear operator h : V → V , interchanging
creators and annihilators, and reversing order of products. When φ = hψ, this
means that the transition ψ → φ goes on every trial.
Canonical quantum dynamics permits us to measure the energy by measur-
ing a Hamiltonian operator H constructed from canonical variables; perhaps
by weighing the system. But the quantum energy can also be measured by
measuring a frequency, as symbolized by the definition E := i~∂t . This does
not work in the classical limit ~ → 0, where for finite energy the frequency
→ ∞. Nevertheless this conception of energy, based on frequency, seems more
fundamental than the classical notion, based on work; but it is the frequency
of a statvector, a statistical construct. The dynamical equation equates energy
to a Hamiltonian, which can be measured on one system, but is not always
the energy. Weighing the system seems to be a way to determine its energy
non-statistically.
47
groups like isospin and Lorentz spin, and ψ0 is a singular “seed” statvector of
momentum eigenvalue pm = 0. ψ(k) is made from ψ0 by a translation in mo-
mentum space generated by ix. Metaphorically, ψ0 is the principal statvector
of a position basis.
Infraquantization need not modify χ but simply takes it to be a statvector
in CQ .
Infraquantization plausibly replaces the exponential by a normalized or-
thogonal transformation:
mL
ψ)(k) = e−ik·x ≺− N −1 eX k m5
= ψ(k). (78)
Although the norm of the usual exponential is infinite, that of its reform is
finite, and designated by N 2 .
To deal with the “seed” statvector ψ0 , let us first replace it by a projector
on momentum p = 0, designated by δ(p). The probability operator for the
incoming quantum is then
Specifying both the time and the energy of one event is impossible due
to complementarity. One evades this problem in the canonical theory by al-
lowing an infinite time to prepare the system, requiring only that the task be
completed by a specified time t. The time t may then be continuously varied
to define a sharp frequency. In this way time and the energy can both be
known with arbitrarily small indeterminacy product ∆t∆E. Canonical quan-
tization corresponds a classical infinitesimal transformation to a quantum one
by a Lie-algebra homomorphism, and then uses i to correspond observables to
observables.
In an infraquantum theory, we do not have forever to prepare an energy, we
cannot vary the time continuously, and we do not have an absolute i. Never-
theless a correspondence survives between such skew-hermitian operators, not
hermitian operators. A skew-symmetric correspondent ∂bt = E is assumed to
time-translation ∂t , and a skew-symmetric correspondent t to energy transla-
tion it.
Since the correspondent bı of i is not central, we cannot form correspondents
of t and E from those of t and E by simple multiplication. The factor-ordering
problem is even greater for infraquantization than for canonical quantization.
If we have made a time operator b t, we may define an instant by the pro-
jection operator Pt0 on a specific eigenvalue t0 of the operator b t. Since none
of the spatial coordinates x k
b commute with t = x b 4
b , Pt0 has little resemblance
to the classical or canonical-quantum instants.
48
It is axiomatic in classical physics that all instants include the same infinite
number of events. This is incompatible with regularity, which permits only a
finite number of independent events in each time slice. Infraquantum theories
typically describe histories with time-slices that grow and then shrink with
time. This impairs the correspondence between infraquantum dynamics and
the Hamiltonian dynamics of canonical theories. We assume that Hamiltonian
dynamics applies to middle age, t/NX → 0 in the singular limit NX → ∞, X →
0. To extend dynamics to periods comparable to the total time NX, we must
allow for information increase and decrease, for example by replacing some
statvectors by probability operators.
Infraquantization admits a more pragmatic construct of dynamical law than
classical physics. Classical physics traditionally took the “perspective of eter-
nity”, excluding Observer and Law from the physical universe, and imagining
them to be fixed apriori instead. The Law was given much symmetry, the
Observer none. Special relativity and quantum theory pluralized, naturalized,
and activated the Observer, by accepting observers into the physical universe,
relating us by a relativity group, and predicting that our determinations of
a system variable changes some unobserved variable by a finite unpredictable
amount.
In a typical quantum experiment, the experimenter inputs a beam of sys-
tems undergoing the experimental process. Therefore we may represent the
metasystem for this purpose by a virtual population or reservoir of replicas of
the system, and represent an input operation by a selection from this reser-
voir. Then the ideal quantum experimenter, while no longer infinite, is still
exponentially larger than the system, which is therefore a logarithmically small
part of the universe. A quantum theory does not require a universal ontol-
ogy and a deterministic law; a manual of feasible experiments to be done in
a rather coarsely specified ambience, and a statistical prediction of their out-
comes will suffice. The dynamics of the system includes the influence of the
mostly unobserved metasystem on the system undergoing experiment. This
influence is sometimes expressed by external fields or sources. The ambience
may have a finite temperature, but here we approximate it as cold, coherent
in the quantum sense.
h xn . . . x1 i0 = Tr xn . . . x1 D = E ◦ D, E := xn . . . x1 . (80)
49
These become propagators when the variables are monadic statvectors, com-
monly associated with specified space-time points. Let us retain this form in
the infraquantum theory and merely reform D. E is now a statvector speci-
fying an experiment and E ◦ D is the amplitude for E under the dynamical
statvector D.
To reform the usual dynamics, let us absorb the usual imaginary factor
i/h into the action A, which then becomes a dimensionless skew-symmetric
real skew-action operator Φ − iA/h on history statvectors, representing an
imaginary phase:
R
D = eΦ −
eiA/h = ei (dx)L/h
, Φ ∈ Lin Q[E]. (81)
The history amplitude D is used to compute propagators as in (80). They in
0
turn define the time-translation operator W t t connecting an input statvector
for one time-slice t with that for a later time-slice t0 . Choose independent
variables st making up a complete set with time t, and basic eigenstatvectors est
with the indicated eigenvalues. Then the transition amplitude can be written
as h 00 i
0 0
W s t st := Tr es t est D . (82)
In the continuum theory there is supposed to be a limiting case t0 = t + dt, of
the form
0
ws (t+dt) st = [δ 0 (t) + H(s
e 0 , s, t)]dt. (83)
This defines the skew-Hamiltonian operator H(t). e
Today the term “vacuum” has been thoroughly relativized [41]. It stands
for the part of the universe that is relegated to the metasystem, which is
observed only coarsely. To escape the preconception of a uniquely defined,
absolutely empty, physical vacuum, let us speak of an ambient medium or
ambience rather than “the vacuum”. The ambience enters the theory in the
determination of the physical input/output statvectors and in the dynamical
law of the system.
Sometimes the ambience is supposed to have some great symmetry, and
sometimes a temperature. Such assumptions must be used with some dis-
cretion, since the metasystem includes the experimenter, who breaks all ob-
servable symmetries and is not in thermal equilibrium. The cosmos exhibits
little symmetry, and the symmetry near the Big Bang is less than that of our
ambience today. A vacuum symmetry is an approximation to the universe in
the way that a tangent is an approximation to a curve. It extrapolates local
conditions to the rest of the universe.
To study the quantum structure of space-time we we must include some
of it in the system. We also must have a still greater place to stand, how-
ever; to satisfy the postulates of quantum kinematics, the metasystem must
50
be exponentially larger than the system. So we must leave most of space-time
structure in the metasystem.
If a quantum description of our metasystem would require a statvector
space of (say) 10100 ∼ 2300 dimensions, the largest system we can fully observe
has only about 300 dimensions in its statvector space. Since 3001/4 ∼ 4, this
would restrict the system to a microcosmic space-time cell only 4X on each
edge, imbedded in the ambient space-time. Like an ice-cube in a glacier, its
quantum structure will then be mainly determined by its ambience.
Let us assume that the standard model spins and charges originate as spin-
like operators on a monadic statvector space CQ1 of some “cell type” C within
the typed statvector algebra Q of §5. We require that C = 4 accommodates
not only the Yang Lie algebra so(6 − n, n), which reforms the Poincaré and
canonical Lie algebras, but also the unitary charges of the standard model,
which are already semisimple:
51
7.5 Organizational entropy 2010.04.23
in a way compatible with the dynamical statvector D. Let us assume that this
defines a factorization of EQ into factor spaces Qt [E]:
_
E
Q= Qt [E] (87)
t
52
Each space has its own operator algebra and trace operation Trt . Given pro-
jectors P and Pt for the history and one instant t, the marginal distribution
ρnot t for the rest of history is defined by
Φ describes a union of n bosons all associated with the same statvector φ. The
associated one-boson marginal probability operator is
Its entropy is
S = − Tr ρ ln ρ (91)
in units of k. This is 0, while the marginal entropy of a random aggregate is
ln D, infinitely greater in the limit of large D.
The entropy of the marginal one-quantum probability operator is defined
for the diachronic quantum theory as simply as for the synchronic, thanks
to the finiteness of the theory. In an infraquantum theory the assembly is
carried out by ext, the quantum correspondent of power-set formation or set-
exponentiation. The trace is over all histories, that is, over all simplicial com-
plexes, which are finite in number.
In some cases of physical interest, the condensation is not of individual
quanta but of Cooper pairs, or tetrads, or of polyads of some even grade g
that is held fixed as n, D → ∞. Then the condensation shows up as a polyad
entropy that is bounded as n, D → ∞.
53
7.6 Infraquantum ground statvector
The ground statvector ψ is usually defined by Hψ = Emin ψ where Emin is the
minimum eigenvalue of the Hamiltonian H. While there is no Hamiltonian
in an infraquantum theory, there is the propagator W c between two adjacent
time-slices. This is given by (82) with the infraquantized dynamical statvec-
tor Db for D. (82) includes a kinematic transformation t → t0 besides the
induced dynamical transformation s → s0 . There seems to be no reason in
an infraquantum theory, which has a first time and a last, for W c to define a
one-parameter group of time translations. The existence of such a group is
likely a consequence of organization and limited to a middle range of temporal
resolution, much longer than X and much shorter than the age of the universe.
The infinitesimal generator of this limiting group is the Hamiltonian operator
of the time slice.
The Hamiltonian mode of description singles out a rest frame and a time
variable. This is harmless when the condensate also defines a rest frame, as
does a superconducting crystal. But our goal is to describe the ambient “vac-
uum” condensate, which is Lorentz covariant. A description that is transpar-
ently Lorentz covariant will sometimes be more useful than one which masks
this covariance.
We must describe how the diachronic dynamics D enters into a condensate
statvector E. We review the canonical theory to guide the infraquantum one.
In the canonical theory, an input process ψ is carried out over a long interval
in the remote past, −T ≥ t > −∞, and its totally time-reversed output process
ψ T in the remote future, ∞ > t ≥ T . If ψ is an energy eigenstatvector, a shift
δt in the time between ψ and ψ T changes the history amplitude by a phase-
shifting factor e±iωδt , and ~ω is the energy eigenvalue of the system.
The infraquantum theory has an operator corresponding to the time shift-
ing operator ∂t , namely the Yang skew-energy L64 =: ∂bt . And one correspond-
ing to the i of the phase-shifting factor, namely bı = L65 /N. However bı is not
central until an appropriate condensation occurs and a singular organized limit
is taken.
It seems that the usual energy construct requires a limit process T → ∞
for its definition. If we copy this in the infraquantum theory, we invalidate the
guarantee of finiteness; the limit may diverge. Instead we choose an appropri-
ate finite time interval for the experiment such as
√ √
NX > t > − NX. (92)
This is short enough to be far from the beginning and end of time, and so
approximate translational invariance. It is long enough to include a great
many X’s and so approximate continuity.
54
7.7 Infraquantum organization
7.8 Unbreaking symmetry
The problem is to describe Nambu-Goldstone symmetry transformations on a
condensate without breaking the simple symmetry of the pre-condensate. Let
us tackle the example of an organization of many spins 1/2.
Symbols: The individual spin vector is s. The statvectors for an individual
spin are spinors ψ, ψ h . The collective spin is S = ψ h s ψ. For a set of N spins
with statvector Ψ, the mean value of the collective spin is S := Ψh S Ψ. This
is normalized to unit length to define the mean spin direction
Ψh S Ψ
e := . (93)
|Ψh S Ψ|
Therefore the collective spin about the mean collective spin is
S · S := S · Ψh S Ψ. (94)
It is plausible to identify s with the generator of the unbroken symmetry.
This leaves two Nambu-Goldstone symmetries, usually approximated by two
translations of the NG boson, a singular limit of the regular symmetry we
seek. More accurately they are two rotations about axes normal to S. They
can be approximated well by translations because they are usually restricted
to small rotations of a long vector. Rotating one spin s through a full 2π turns
S only through 2π/N. It is only when we unthinkingly use the translational
approximation for large rotations that infinities creep in.
The NG rotations are generated by two components of S orthogonal to S;
let us designate them by S1 and S2 .
The three generators S1 , S2 , S have well-defined physical meaning for the
ensemble of ensembles of spins statistically described by the statvector Ψ. They
do not have the usual form of observables. They are certainly not observables
of one spin, since they involve many. And they are not observables of the
collective, since they involve the statvectors Ψ, Ψh of the collective. They may
be interpreted as joint observables of one spin and one collective of spins.
8 Gauging as quantification
The Yang simplification adjoins dimensions to the usual (x, y, z, t). A Yang-
space point y, relative to any frame, carries a space-time point x, a cotangent
vector p, an element a of an so(n), and an infinitesimal complex-plane rotation
0 −φ
∈ so(2), (95)
φ 0
55
in the array
0 −φ −x1 . . . −xn
φ 0 −p1 . . . −pn
x 1 p1 0 . . . an1
y= .. .. . (96)
. . a12 ... a n2
.. .. .. ..
. . . .
xn pn a1n ... 0
Thus y includes the elements of a gauge connection, which associates a Lie
algebra element a with a direction p (or its dual) at a point x. This suggests
that a singular quantum gauge field might actually be a limo of a regular sea
of events, taken from a quantum space like a Yang space with an appropriate
orthogonal group.
The spin group represented within the Clifford algebra Cliff W[4] of level
4 is the double covering Cov SO(4, 4). This contains no SO(5, 1) subgroup.
Instead let us adopt SO(3, 3) ⊂ SO(4, 4) for the Yang group for now. SO(4, 2)
would also fit into SO(4, 4). The spinors of Yang SO(3, 3) with 8 real dimen-
sions fit into the 16 dimensions of 4Q1 , but not into the monadics of a lower
level.
Q grade counts vertices of the cell, Q level counts nested iotas, and the
basic Q dynamical operators LC ∈ so(W[C]) of the cell level C count com-
ponents of generalized angular momentum in units of the roots of this Lie
algebra. The eight spin-like atoms of orbital angular momentum x bm and pbm
(m ∈ 6), and the quantized imaginary bı, are among the 15 generators γ C of a
Yang so(3, 3) Lie algebra, forming a Lie subalgebra of the 120-dimensional Lie
algebra so(W[C] ⊂ Lin 4Q1 ∼ = Cliff W[C] of level C
The unitary charges of the standard model can be represented using another
6 real dimensions and the quantized imaginary bı already constructed. This still
fits into the 16-dimensional spinor space CQ1 with C = 4.
The matrices of so(W[C]) are too small to usefully approximate our usual
orbital variables. They best represent spins, the “atoms” of the orbital vari-
ables. The orbital variables are cumulants of such spins. A Yang so(3, 3) of
level C is faithfully represented on level E by second cumulants of its gener-
ators LC (§6.4). The LC in one Q frame are, up to constant multipliers, the
operators
xm
δb = X γ m5 , m, n = 1, 2, 3, 4,
δb
pm = E γm6 ,
δ bı = N−1 γ 65 , (97)
δLb nm = hγnm ,
as h(4) ≺− so(3, 3) ≺− sl(6)
56
The infraquantized imaginary bı is normalized to unit magnitude with a factor
N−1 . To form macrocosmic monad coordinates, we must cumulate these atomic
16
cell variables at least twice, to reach at least level 6, with 26 = 2(2 ) points,
ample for a quasi-continuum.
The statvectors for the atoms of momentum do not commute. Neither do
their cumulants, the quantified momenta, which correspond to infinitesimal
translations. This quantum non-commutativity survives into general relativity
as part of the curvature, perhaps including a cosmologically constant part.
Let us posit spontaneous polarizations of bı = Σ2 γ 65 − i and of a Pauli
form βc0 c = −βcc0 that makes γ 4321 β-symmetric:
The form β is a special case of the Pauli metric β T of level T , for which see
(63). β singles out the first-grade γ c : they are the elements of Lin 4Q1 that
anticommute with γ 4321 and are β-skewsymmetric. These γ c in turn define the
Minkowski space-time, as a singular organized limit of cumulants of second-
0
grade products γ c c . Thus the Pauli form determines the Minkowski form and
space-time in this context.
While de Sitter relativity can be a useful approximation for patches of
physical space-time the Yang SO(3, 3) relativity is badly broken by the ambient
dome, which is anisotropic, but it can still apply to a quantum cell of the dome.
57
We must then transfer the main ideas of Bardeen-Cooper-Schrieffer super-
conductivity theory from classical Minkowski space-time to an infraquantized
space-time like Yang space. Many of the necessary ingredients for a gauge the-
ory of the Yang-Mills kind are already present in the Yang space (96. A gauge
theory associates a Lie algebra element a(x, v) with each infinitesimal tangent
vector v at each point x of space-time, depending linearly on v. δu = a(x, v)u
represents the change in a vector u due to transport of u from x to x + v.
Points of Yang space, however, have even statistics, wrong for a Fermi sea.
Therefore we take for the statvector space of a fermionic sub-event the spinor
space R8 underlying the Yang so(3, 3) space, with odd statistics. The sub-
event variables fulfilling the Yang commutation relations are then the dyadic
0
spin components γ c c of this event. To form an event of Yang space, many
such spinorial sub-events have to pair off and condense, like Cooper pairs.
This raises the question of how the fermion interactions are to be described,
before and after the organization of the ambient dome. Since the coupling of
events is to have as its singular organized limit the dynamics of the standard
model and gravity, our first approach is to infraquantize that dynamics.
It is parsimonious to surmise that all arise in a singular organized limit
from one bosonic condensation of the plexus, with one critical temperature
Tc , and can all be expressed in terms of one order parameter; rather than a
sequence of condensations with distinct critical temperatures Tc n , one for each
of these vacuum mean values.
In support of the single-condensate notion, we first note that
Proof The Clifford algebra associated with Yang so(6) has six monadic gener-
ators γ y (y = 1, . . . , 6). The Clifford element defining the quantized imaginary
bı is γ 65 in the Yang frame. To be specific let us assume that
(γ 4 )2 = (γ 5 )2 = (γ 6 )2 = −1, (99)
so that the Yang group is SO(3, 3). Then the Clifford complement of γ 65 is
γ > γ 65 where γ > := −γ 654321 . Clearly
is the top element of the Minkowski Clifford algebra (not to be designated here
by γ 5 for obvious reasons). Thus bı determines γ 4321 .
But γ 4321 in turn determines the subspace of Minkowskian generators γ µ
(µ = 1, 2, 3, 4). They are the monadic generators among the γ y that anticom-
mute with γ 4321 .
58
As usual, the γ µ in turn determine the Minkowski metric by their anticom-
mutators:
0 0
{γ µ , γ µ } = 2g µ µ . (101)
To develop this proposal into a microscopic theory, we must propose a trial
statvector analogous to the Cooper pair of superconductivity. The classical
Dirac vector field γ µ (x) is not one operator but four. We may without loss of
generality regard it as a surrogate for a more accurate, though more singular,
two-point dyadic γ(x0 , x) ≈ γ µ (x)δxµ , where δx := x0 − x. This in turn is
supposed to be the ambient mean of a dyadic
b ∈ Cliff 2 W[E]
γ (102)
b is second-grade in Cliff W,
of higher type, containing events as well as spins. γ
and therefore fourth-grade in Dup Q, and may be diagramed as an X. The
relevance of two-point fields was pointed out by Einstein and Mayer [14, 15].
0
The angular momentum operator γ c c is then a concomitant of γ b. It pro-
vides the Q representation (97) of the Yang SO(3, 3) group that reforms the
canonical Lie algebra h(4) ≺− sl(R). It thus provides each frame with an in-
fraquantized imaginary bı, a local variant of the global constant i of complex
quantum theory, in the way that general relativity localized the global constant
gnm of special relativity to the local form gnm (x).
9 Infraquantum space-times
9.1 The minimum black hole
Infraquantization modifies the usual estimate of the minimum black hole size.
To review the standard heuristic argument, consider a body of mass M local-
ized within a ball of radius R for a time much greater than R/c. Let us assume
for the moment that Newton’s law of gravity is still approximately valid for
lengths as small as R. If the body is not to disappear into a black hole, it should
be able to reflect light. The kinetic energy mc2 of a photon at its boundary R
must exceed the photon’s gravitational binding energy −V = GmM/R:
> GM m
mc2 ∼ −V = , (103)
R
where G is the (unrationalized) gravitational constant.
If the Heisenberg determinacy limit holds for lengths as small as r, the
body has a root-mean-square momentum
> h
Mc ∼ . (104)
R
59
(103) and (104) imply the Planck-length bound,
r
> 2hG
r∼ =: RP . (105)
c3
Newton’s law of gravity presumably does not hold on the scale of X. Its
error could be enormous if, as infraquantization suggests, there is a short-range
fermionic hard core of repulsion within the long-range attraction of gravity.
The following crude argument uses the Newton law anyway, so it does not
give an estimate but merely invalidates one of the usual arguments that the
observed elementary particles cannot be quantum black holes, and so reopens
the question.
The Yang indeterminacy relation implies not (104) but
> h
r∼ |hbı i|. (106)
2mc
Then, still assuming Newton’s law of gravity,
r
> 2hG
r∼ |hbı i| = |hbı i|RP . (107)
c3
Since bı is the sum of an even number of spins, its spectrum includes 0. If
hbı i → 0, the black hole radius and mass can approach 0. Quantum black holes
much lighter than the Planck mass become possible below the time scale of
the ambient dome organization.
Suppose now that there is a potential energy minimum V instead of the
unbounded Newtonian potential −GmM/R, but equivalence is still approxi-
mately valid. Then V is proportional to both masses:
GmM
V ≈− (108)
R0
with a new physical constant R0 . Then instead of (103) one has
> GM m < R0 c2
mc2 ∼ −V = , M∼ . (109)
R0 G
60
For example, the monadic statvector
∈ 6Q1 (111)
61
spinors. That is, when Yang SO(3, 3) is reduced to the Lorenz group, the Yang
spinors are reduced to chiral Lorentz spinors.
xm ∼
The atoms of the quantized orbital operators may be represented by δb
m
γ , δbpm = γ 4321 γm , as was suggested also by Marks [28].
Present experience, where
p the canonical relations work, is with a part of
the spectrum of |bı| = + −Qi2 so near to the maximum value N as to be
indistinguishable from it. Yet this narrow band must have a multiplicity that
passes today for infinite. For example the band
62
Infraquantization quantizes the orbital variables left classical in the stan-
dard model and SCCM , using similar atomic quantum elements for orbital, spin,
and charge variables. Flipping the spin of an electron annihilator is supposed
to change the proper time between it and another electron annihilator, possibly
by too little to resolve with present experimental space-time resolution.
Let us assume that the dome has a simple Lie algebra
to be found.
The Poincaré relativity group does not fit into the groups of EQ. It is a
singular approximation to the Yang relativity group SO(3, 3) at the cellular
level.
DO: Show this.
Since the Poincaré Lie algebra is a reduction of diff, the Yang Lie algebra in
turn is assumed to be a reduction of a higher-level relativity gauge Lie algebra
suitable for quantum gravity and the other gauge forces too:
d = sl(EQ) ⊂ sl(Q).
diff ≺− diff (116)
10 Generations
Empirically, the fermion spectrum is unexpectedly divided into three genera-
tions differing only in their masses, their coupling to gravity. Properly under-
stood, this must tell us something equally peculiar about the fine structure of
the quantum plexus.
The division into generations is not quite unique. One basis diagonalizes
the fermion mass operator M , another the weak charge operator QW , another
the coupling coefficient gH of the Yukawa coupling to the Higgs field. The
unitary transformation from the charge basis to the mass basis is fermion
mixing. It reduces to a lepton-mixing part UW M , the PMNS (Pontecorvo-Maki-
63
with angular momentum. On the other hand, there are remarkable violations
of this analogy in the relation of Γ to multiplicities and to couplings. The
multiplicities of the standard model group representations are independent of
Γ, while those of the atomic rotation group depend markedly on n, namely
quadratically. For example, the multiplicity Mn of hydrogen shells changes
from M1 = 2 for the K shell to M2 = 6 for the L shell. There seems to be a
unitary operator connecting the generations, but not the shells of hydrogen.
In the limit of very large radius n → ∞, however, the fractional change
from one hydrogenic radial shell to the next becomes small:
Mn+1 − Mn
→ 0. (117)
Mn
As n → ∞, neighboring shells of hydrogen then become approximately isomor-
phic, in that their differences are small fractions of the total. Γ still resembles
a radial variable, but a very large one, compared to the radial distance between
shells. The generations are shells that are flat and isomorphic on the scale of
particle physics.
This fits the dome model reasonably well, for the dome has a cosmic radius
and a subparticle thickness, and so its strata can be practically flat. On the
other hand, instead of one transverse dimension the dome has one for every
standard-model charge.
What singles out the generation coordinate Γ? And why do fermion masses,
to a crude approximation, seem to vary geometrically with Γ? Roughly speak-
ing,
M (Γ) ∼ M (0)eΛΓ , (118)
with a large inter-generational mass ratio eΛ ∼ 102±1 . No radial variable
of elementary quantum mechanics effects the particle energy so powerfully.
Perhaps this is a clue.
Some speculations are obvious in an infraquantum perspective. Though
still poorly founded, they might be worth future study:
The Higgs field singles out one direction in the dome at each event, and
determines some gaugeon masses. Parsimony suggests that Γ indexes eigenval-
ues of the quantized Higgs field. In the infraquantum theory, correspondingly,
it is conceivable that Γ indexes the spectrum of (bı)2 .
One familiar exponential process in superconductors is shielding or pene-
tration. In a boundary layer the electric vector potential falls off as A ∼ e−µξ
with penetration ξ into the superconductor. Here µ is a measure of photon
rest mass hµ/c within the superconductor. In a bulk superconductor the skin
depth λ is a small part of the bulk, and the mass shift of the Cooper pair is a
small part of its mass, so superconducting generations, with various values for
64
the Cooper-pair mass, have not been observed, as far as I know. If this analogy
has some validity, generations of Cooper pairs would be seen more clearly in
a superconducting film or graphene several atoms thick. What is the mass of
Cooper pairs in the boundary layer of a superconductor? Let us return to the
more exact considerations necessary to solidify such conjectures.]
11 Particle valence
11.1 Standard model valences
In this section we use a terminology for the standard model taken from chem-
istry. Each quantum of the standard model has a single-particle Hilbert space
that is a product of several factor spaces on which act orbital, spin, and charge
operators. The factor spaces provide the indices on the statvectors of the par-
ticle, describe formal parts of the particle, and are transported by the gauge
connections, so they have some semblance of physical existence. Yet they are
not quanta in space-time, which is only one of these parts. We may call these
phenomenological parts of the quanta valences. In an infraquantum theory
valences arise naturally as entities of lower type than particles and space-time.
What is known of the valences of the quantum particles today is summed
up in the Feynman vertices of the standard model, such as the electron-photon
vertex
e
γ ∼∼∼• or γ → e + e. (119)
e
In an infraquantum theory this must be a singular organized limit of the actual
process. Photons are at least dyadic, and should be represented by at least
two lines More generally, Q bosons have statvectors of even grade, and are
composed of an even number of fermions. Furthermore, the components of the
momentum do not commute, and cannot all be assigned eigenvalues at once.
De Broglie and Feynman tried assembling photons and gravitons (respectively)
from fermions, without positive results. They worked in a classical space-time
with quanta, subject to the Heisenberg indeterminacy principle, which requires
strong forces for close binding.
But Q weakens the Heisenberg indeterminacy principle at small range, and
simultaneously provides another way to bind monads into polyads: covalent
bonding below the event level. Polyadics cannot be bound with an ι since suc-
cession results in a monadic, but can be bound by sharing second, third, or n-th
65
members of lower type, which may be valences. Let us call this phenomenon
deep covalent bonding.
It results in pseudo-bosons with hard fermionic cores. The dyadics
ψ = abc ± ab c =:
◦ ±
◦
,
(120)
φ = ab cd ± ac bd =:
•
◦ ±
◦
•,
are simple examples of deep covalent bonds within Q. In the example ψ, the
leftmost circle represents a, the inner circle b, and the rightmost c.
One candidate for the photon of (119) under Q resolution might be
γ ==== γ → e + e− (121)
e.
in which the horizontal lines represent two electron processes held together by
deep covalent bonds like those of (120). This model cannot be right. It would
not account for direct photon emission by particles other than the electron.
The standard model gauge group itself suggests a more complex structure
for the leptons, and a simpler structure for the gaugeons. In the standard
model kinematics, the chiral lepton and quark and the gaugeon have tensor-
product statvector spaces, which can also be written as exterior products:
66
Each gaugeon of the standard model relates an orbital direction and a pair
of valences (G, W, or S). The orbital direction can itself be identified with
a pair of G valences, spins. Thus the gaugeon has a tetrad of valences of
appropriate kinds. The diagram (121) is replaced by the finer structure
γ ==== γ → e + e− (123)
The electron line has been broken into a thinner line standing for an inner
valence and a thicker line that carries everything else including the spin. The
gaugeon line is now composed of two valence lines rather than two electron
lines. It can interact with any fermion carrying an appropriate valence, not
only with an electron.
11.2 Q valence
To form a Q correspondent of the valence concept, let us assume tentatively
that each fermion is a product of its valences, held together by deep covalent
bonding.
This raises the question of whether the dynamics can effect such binding.
The relevant pre-reformation skew-action is the fermionic term ΦF of (139).
According to the standard model, W and S gaugeons map external (orbital)
Lie algebra elements into internal ones. Allowing two valences to define a Lie
algebra element, they have the structure L2 T 2 . According to canonically quan-
tized general relativity, G gaugeons have the valence L4 . In a pre-organization
theory, whose symmetry is not yet broken by the split into L and T statvectors,
the three gaugeons merge into one.
At present, however, superselection rules separate the G, W, and S valences.
Superpositions of different valences do not seem to occur. A superselection
rule, like a selection rule, implies a symmetry, but also implies decoherence.
Decoherence can be due to random disturbances that destroy phase relations
between two terms in a direct sum. They occur, for example, when each of
the terms in question is itself a sum of too many sub-terms for us to resolve
their phases accurately. In Q dynamics, the large numbers involved seem to
be the number of paths joining two events, and the number of steps along the
transport path. Too many steps make the space-time coordinates central. It
is possible that too many paths result in the superselection rules between G,
S, and W.
67
The gauge Lie algebra of the standard model is a direct sum of the gauge
Lie algebras of hypercharge Y , isospin I, and color C, of the kind
u(1)Y
gS = su(2)I = u(1) ⊕ su(2) ⊕ su(3). (124)
su(3)S
This is not the invariance Lie algebra of any quantum entity supposed to exist
in the standard model. Its defining representation acts on a 6-dimensional
direct-sum complex vector space
not the direct sum (125). The quark theory is invariant under the charge Lie
group
GQ := U(1) ⊗ SU(2) ⊗ SU(3). (127)
To infraquantize the three interactions involves representing these groups in
SO(EQ1 ), along with the groups of general relativity.
12 Infraquantum fields
We express the usual construct of a spinorial quantum field over classical
Minkowski space-time M operating on a Hilbert space H as a singular or-
ganized limit of a polyad with statvectors in EQ. The constructs of field space,
space-time, and Hilbert space thus merge into the typed exterior algebra Q.
The correspondence between the canonical and infraquantum field con-
structs is crucial for a Q theory. It arises from the dome structure of the
ambient plexus as follows.
In a completely classical model with field values in a linear space F and
space-time events in a finite set X , the field state space is the power-set F X .
Its multiplicity is
|F X | = |F||X | . (128)
A Lagrangian dynamical theory then uses the dual linear space F 0 for the
canonical conjugate of the F field. In the canonical quantization, (F ⊕ F 0 )X is
68
used as statvector space for one quantum. Its vectors represent input-output
processes for the quantum.
When Xb is a quantum space, however, as in an infraquantum theory, there
is no satisfactory power-set construct (F ⊕ F 0 )X . There is the binary expo-
b
2Y∨X ∼
2 Y∨X − = (2Y )X := ZbX , (131)
b b b b
b
space-time X .
This limits us to field spaces that have logarithm spaces. It is convenient
therefore that a spinor space Ψ = ext V has a logarithm, namely its semivector
space V (§6.2).
Thus even though there is no natural Q construct of a quantum function
on a quantum space-time, the dome organization naturally provides such a
construct as a singular organized limit of a quantum set of monads; and the
field so defined can be a spinor field, or any polyadic product of monadic spinor
fields. It is so far merely plausible that this path can be retraced to recover
the spinor field on classical space-time from the infraquantum theory in Q.
12.1 Q gaugeons
We turn now to infraquantum gauge theory. The central object of the standard
gauge theory, following Einstein and Weyl, is a gauge differentiator, a reformed
69
version of the Lie partial differentiator ∂µ . Three known gauges, gravitational
(G), electroweak (W), and strong (S), combine without unification into a grand
gauge differentiator
with grand vector potentials Gµ that act on each tensor according to its nature
and degree. We have absorbed the relevant coupling constants and current
operators into the grand vector potentials Gµ . Then all the coupling constants
appear as appropriate “fine-structure constants” αG , αS , αW standing before
the respective gaugeon skew-action operators, yet to be written.
The infraquantum correspondent of Dµ is the tensor Lc0 c [E] of cumulated
generators of the reformed simple gauge Lie algebra so(CQ1 ). Lc0 c [E] also
includes correspondents of the space-time coordinates, angular momenta, and
the infraquantized imaginary bı.
Since the kinetic energy of a test particle is part of Dm and the potential
energy is part of G m , let us speak of the three terms in any gauge differentiator
Dµ = ∂µ − G µ (133)
as kinetic (D) , total (∂), and potential (G). The gauge invariant one is
the kinetic, Dµ . Einstein’s principle of local equivalence implies three local
equivalence conditions on Dµ :
1. Dµ respects the tetrad vectors γ µ and so the metric tensor.
2. Dµ is atorsional, respects the coordinate tangent vector fields en (x).
3. Dµ agrees with the Lie derivative ∂µ on the scalars xν :
ΦF Φ G Φ WS ΦH
z }| { z }| { z }| { z }| {
Φ = iψγDψ + αG iγγ[D, D] + αW,S i[D, D]γγ[D, D] + i(φD2 φ − W(φ)) . (135)
70
The fermion term is linear in Dµ . The gravitational skew-action operator
ΦG is the term quadratic in D, and involves only DµG , the G part of Dµ .
The electroweak term ΦWS is quartic in the grand differentiator Dµ . The
standard-model Higgs term ΦH involves a colorless isospinor spinless scalar φ
in a W-shaped potential, a source of G and W gaugeons but not S. Yang space
provides an isovector scalar bi −
i instead.
It has often been suggested, since Kaluza, that some of these gaugeons are
expressible in terms of the others. In an infraquantum theory based on Q, the
gaugeons are associated with polyadics of even grade, composed of an even
number of monadics, representing fermions. We should therefore explore the
possibility that all the skew-action operators might be effective surrogates for
the fermion one. Specifically, we have ordered the terms on the right-hand
side of (135) so that each might be a manifestation of the ones preceding it, all
ultimately flowing from the fermion skew-action operator, the only one that
contains all the fields ordinarily considered to be independent.
bı −
i, pµ , Lµ0 µ −
0, (136)
the first to recover the canonical commutation relations for orbital variables
and field variables, the rest is to reduce the x, p-phase space to x-space-time.
It is implicit that the variables xµ , which commute in this limit, are not con-
strained; that the plenum is four-dimensional, not a lower-dimensional quasi-
manifold like a wire or a bubble. In §13 we review how a condensate is described
in a history-based quantum theory.
71
13.1 Infraquantum fermions
Let us begin by infraquantizing the fermion skew-action operator ΦF of (139).
Prior to infraquantization, but after a canonical quantization that includes
gravity, the variables in ΦF represent tensors of the valences shown first in
(122), rendered contravariant for convenience. We write x for the coordinates
of a point in space-time, s for the spins-and-unitary-charges of the fermion
annihilated by ψ, µ for a Minkowski vector index, f for the fermion quantum
occupation numbers and g for gaugeon occupation numbers connected by ψ.
Then simplification results in the valences shown on the right-hand sides of
these equations. It replaces each Minkowski index and event µx of Dµ by a
pair of event indices e0 e, suitably extended to represent the standard model
internal unitary charges as well, and undergoing a split into spin and orbit
in the limo. Let us write the resulting “cell” orthogonal group of the sub-
event as SO[C]. its vector indices as c, c0 , and its Q spinor indices still as
s, s0 . In a canonical theory, ∂µ and xµ are canonically conjugate as single-
0
event operators (Le e ) on the event type level E. Probably E = C + 2 will
suffice. While c need assume but 16 values or fewer, after infraquantization
the spinor index s ranges over cosmologically values, perhaps 26 = 264K . Then
0
covariance requires a corresponding conversion γ µ (x) ≺− γ e e . We designate
fermion occupation quantum numbers by f, f 0 , and infraquantum numbers by
fb, fb0 ; and analogously for gaugeons g and gb. In sum,
0 b0 b
ψ = (ψ xs|f f ) ≺− ψ e|f f ,
xµ|s 0 s|g 0 g 0 0
γ = (γ ) ≺− γ e e|bg gb, (137)
0 0 0 0
D = (Dxµ|s s|g g ) ≺− Le e|bg gb.
Let us also continue to suppose that all forces are ultimately exchange
forces, differing in what is exchanged:
72
of skew-symmetric operators. The Dirac spin operator field γ µ (x) and the
differentiator Dµ can be regarded as field operators for gravitons. Then the
usual skew-action operator coupling them is
Z
ΦF = i (dx) ψγ µ Dµ ψ. (139)
A Q reformation replaces:
• ψ(x) by an operator Lψ where now ψ ∈ EQ1 .
R
• i (dx) ψ . . . ψ by a cumulation ΣL65 (§6.4).
• Dµ (x) by Lc0 c .
0
• γ µ (therefore) by γ c c .
Due to the hanging indices of L65 the result is not yet a tensor.
In classical gauge theory the gauge derivative coincides with the Lie deriva-
tive for coordinate functions:
73
For gravity all four monads in the tetrad are longitudinal to the dome. For
the other gauge interactions, two are transverse to the dome.
Spin and orbit variables undergo the same group ISO(3, 1) in special rela-
tivity, but not in general relativity. Unlike the vector representation, the spinor
representation of so(3, 1) does not extend to one of sl(4R), whose irreducible
unitary double-valued representations are infinite-dimensional. Therefore, to
general-relativize the construct of spinor, Cartan introduced a mobile frame,
a field of tangent-vector quadruples γ 0 (x), . . . , γ 3 (x) with a fixed Minkowski
inner product γm (x)·γn (x) = gnm . This defines a Lorentz group SO(3, 1; x) on
each tangent space, but events transform under Diff. A Cartan vector-sextuple
would appear in a theory of Yang so(3, 3).
The Dirac spin operators γ µ have had several metamorphoses since their
conception:
1. In gravity theory the Cartan vector-quadruple γ µ (x) becomes the dynam-
ical variable for gravity. The classical gravitational metric at x, described
in the mobile frame, is then the tensor
0 1 0
g m m (x) := {γ m (x), γ m (x)}, (143)
2
which is arbitrarily fixed to be a constant Minkowskian form in the mobile
frame.
2. In Dirac’s theory of the single electron, the γ µ become monadics of a
Clifford algebra and represent physical quantum variables of the electron.
3. In the Yang space-time the coefficient γ µ in the Dirac equation become
a sector γ µ6 of the generator γ nm of Yang so(3, 3), contragredient to the
momentum:
pµ ≺− Lµ6 , γ µ ≺− γ µ6 . (144)
4. In Q the single-electron γ µ become annihilators of type B, the predecessor
of spin.
5. In standard quantum field theory the γ µ are constant coefficients of the
electron wave equation, not dynamical variables.
6. In canonical quantum gravity, the matrix elements of the γ µ (x) become
graviton annihilators.
7. Q gravity uses the cumulant spin operators
0 0
γ c c (E) := ΣE−C γ c c (C). (145)
The Dirac operator becomes
0
γ c c (E)Lc0 c (E) −
γ µ ∂µ (146)
74
0
The Q operators γ c c (E) act on the spinors ψ ∈ Q(E), which carry both
spin and orbital information (§9.2). Therefore each γ c carries information
about two spins and two orbital variables, input and output. The Q gravita-
tional metric corresponding to (143) is evidently the numerical tensor
0 1 0
g c c := {γ c , γ c }, (147)
2
involving four spin and orbital variables. It will be symmetric in its spin
variables if it is skew-symmetric in its orbital variables. It is simply the natural
neutral metric on W(E), referred to a mobile frame. The variability of this
metrical structure derives from the variability of the Q simplicial complex to
which it is applied, in the way that a variable curved surface in a flat space of
constant metric has a variable metrical structure.
The Q correspondent of the gauge covariant differentiator Dµ is the genera-
tor on the field level F induced by the cell Lie algebra generator LC of level C.
It requires F − C iterations of cumulation Σ. The resulting correspondences
are:
tangent space ≺− Q simplex of level C
Cartan n−ad γ n (x) ≺− Q n-adic in EQn
diff ≺− sl(EQ1 )
Dµ (x) ≺− ΣE−C LC =: LC [E]
s0
Ksm 0m ≺− [LC 0 [E], LC [E]] (148)
Because the cell map is an orthogonal transformation, the local equivalence
principle is automatically satisfied.
A Q quantum theory has no supersymmetry between bosons and fermions.
Even operons are composed of odd, and not conversely. The generating vari-
ables obey a Fermi statistics, not a Bose.
The atomistic analysis of the other gauge fields can be modeled on that of
gravity. One adjoins to the six cellular CQ dimensions required for Yang so(5, 1)
as many more dimensions as needed for the unitary groups of the standard
model, raising the cell level C if necessary. This enlarges the generator LC of
sl(CQ1 ) accordingly. The induced generator LE F −C L then includes all
C := Σ C
the coordinate and momentum variables of the full gauge field.
Near the singular organized limit, where one can speak of space-time points,
we have supposed that the gravitational field variable γb is not attached to one
event but two (§8.1). This makes it possible to form a pseudo-boson from
the basic fermions. The field tensor can be symmetric in its space-time indices
because it is skew-symmetric in its space-time points, although these points are
so closely bound that they presently pass for one point. All apparent bosons
are hard-core pseudo-bosons in this model.
75
The four flat-space Dirac γ m ’s of standard spin 1/2 theory have been as-
sumed to be what remains of the cell operators γ w ∈ W[C] after the dome
organizes itself. The γ w transform as so(3, 1) vectors when 4Q1 transforms as
a spinor space:
0
Λγ c Λ−1 = Lc c0 γ c , Λ ∈ sl(4Q1 ) = sl(16R), L ∈ so(3, 1). (149)
γ m (x) ≺− L ee , (151)
5
where the ee are the basis elements of Q.
We will use γ rather than L to remind us that we are using its spinor repre-
sentation. Then the core of the fermion skew-action operator simplifies to
0 00 g 0 0 0
γ · D ≺− γ e e|g γ ee |g g . (153)
76
≺− Φ
bF
h 00 00 00
∼ Tr ψbf ”e” f ”00 e”00 c”00 Lf ” e” c” f ”0 e”0 c”0
0 0 0 00 0 0 0
i
× γ f ” e” c” f ”e”c” Lf ”e”c f 0 e0 c0 ψbf e c f e
∈ Lin FQ. (154)
77
13.5 Constructing the strong gaugeon field
DO: Do this.
78
The Higgs field has been left out for now because [hopefully] it is a cluster of Q
fermions with deep covalent binding, arising from the infraquantized fermion
dynamical statvector D b F.
In the standard theory DF describes a field of spin-1/2 free fermions propa-
gating with the usual spin-orbit coupling γD between the spin of each fermion
and its kinetic momentum. It includes no direct interaction between fermions.
The fermion field operators act as a quantifier, summing over the individual
fermions in the many-fermion field theory. All interactions between fermions
arise from their coupling to the collective gauge fields of D. To describe the
propagation of the gaugeons requires gaugeon skew-action operators ΦG,W,S .
In the Q theory the fermion field operators still form a quantifier, summing
over individual fermions. The gaugeons. however, have to be replaced by
polyadics in the fermions, say of grade g, if only to fit their observed spin and
statistics. The fermion skew-action operator then couples not two fermions,
but g+2 fermions. It describes interaction as well as propagation. The gaugeon
propagator is then no longer separate from the fermion propagator, but derives
from it algebraically. It is then conceivable that ΦF is the entire skew-action
operator.
1 Differentiator
0
Dm ≺− ΣE−C γ c c ∈ EQ1 , (156)
a cumulant kinetic energy-momentum operator.
79
14.4 Pauli form
β implicit in ψ ≺− the Pauli form p[E] of EQ.
14.6 Sources ξ, ξ.
Part of item (14.6). R
An exterior integration [dψdψ] over fermionic histories. This is part of a
Fourier transform, a mere change of frame that can be omitted.
80
spin
∂
z}|{
00 0
= ι Σ2 γ c c0 × γ c c × Σ2 γ c c00 (157)
| {z } | {z } ∂ιo
imaginary orbit
with the indicated correspondences. A peels one outer ι from its operand, ap-
plies the bracketed coupling, and then restores the ι. The “imaginary” factor
bı is needed for skew-symmetry, just as the standard Dirac action requires a
factor i. Infraquantization incorporates gauging, and thus raises the grade of
the Dirac propagator from the usual two to six, describing physical interaction
as well as propagation. The Q Dirac equation is a specific topological relation
between quantum operons, relating the edges of connected cells. The reduc-
tion γ 6...1 = ±1 (§9.3) results in chiral operon spinors analogous to the chiral
fermion spinors of the standard model.
The standard model algebra s[u(2)×u(3)] of charges becomes s[u(2)×u(4)].
All the physical monads support one representation of this algebra. Black
monads actually happen while colorful monads are individually only virtual.
This is suggestively similar to the way timelike displacements actually happen
while spacelike ones are virtual [31].
While every basic standard fermion has the same spin 1/2, they do not all
have the same color representation, which acts on 1C for leptons and 3C for
quarks; nor the same isospin representation, which acts on 1C for right-handed
leptons and 2C for quarks and left-handed leptons.
This part of the exploration has analyzed the standard singular description
into atoms. This has to be worked out further for gauge variables. Then will
come a largely synthetic task of a rather different character, reassembling the
parts into a coherent whole.
15 Discussion
DO: ... Finish this section.
One possibility among many is that the generations represent three strata
within the transverse structure of the dome. It is well known that particle
masses represent shielding lengths, analogous to the Debye length of an elec-
trolyte. In a continuum, shielding proceeds continuously, Is it conceivable that
in a quantum plexus shielding proceeds in quantum jumps, the generations?
Or is it possible that the difference between the generations can be expressed
as a difference in type? I cannot formulate these questions algebraically yet.
81
15.1 Acknowledgements
I am indebted to James Baugh, Shlomit Ritz Finkelstein, Andry Galiautdinov,
Dennis Marks, Zbigniew Oziewicz, Heinrich Saller, and Sarang Shah for recent
helpful discussions and corrections.
16 Appendices
17 Quantum pragmatics 2010.04.28
82
The quantum mode of reasoning is based on operations or actions and so is
aptly termed pragmatic by Stapp [36]. Let us speak of quantum pragmat-
ics rather than quantum logics, to avoid the misconceptions mentioned and
emphasize the empirical nature of the study in question.
The system under study is taken here to be specified by how experimenters
can produce it, act on it, and register it; by their input, throughflow, and
output actions. The rest of nature, including the experimenter, instruments,
and life support, constitute the metasystem.
Historically the metasystem was known only coarsely and described in nat-
ural language. Now it is possible to operate at least on a logarithmically small
part of it with quantum precision. If this part can still serve as a metasystem
for a still smaller system, then it may be considered to be a quantum meta-
system. The possibility that such extensions of quantum theory might become
necessary was anticipated by Bohr [6]. But then the rest of nature, including
ourselves as experimenters on this metasystem, remains coarsely resolved, and
can be regarded as meta-metasystem, or meta2 system.
In the present study, space-time coordinate variables are quantized. Space-
time variables of canonical quantum field theory are not measured on the
field system but on individual quanta, one type lower. Their quantization is
therefore an infraquantization.
Let us reserve the term state as in classical mechanics for an observable
property of the isolated system that determines all others. For an isolated
system, knowing the state is complete knowledge of the system, by definition.
When we sharply determine any property of a physical system, however, it
seems that we change other properties of the same system, which are not be-
ing determined, greatly and uncontrollably. Therefore physical systems do not
seem to have states. In quantum pragmatics a ray in a Hilbert space H pro-
vides a maximally informative—sharp—statistical description of a population
of systems, certainly not a state. A ray is conveniently specified by one of its
vectors, which therefore is also not a state.
Formulations of quantum theory using the term “state vector” often say
that every quantum system has a state vector. This assumption seems mean-
ingless or false, but is so widespread that the only practical way to evade it
to drop the term. Here a non-zero vector in the ray describing a sharp input-
output process is called a statistical vector or statvector . Statvectors and their
duals represent sharply defined input and output quantum operations. The
individual system does not “have” a statvector in the sense that it has a mo-
mentum, or in the sense that a classical system has a state. Statvectors also
have a product, by which aggregates are formed from individuals.
The Hilbert space arises because physical filtration operations that are
crisp—meaning P 2 = P —seem to form a projective geometry. The sharp
83
projectors are its points or rays, the next sharpest are its lines, and so on. The
incidence relation defining this projective geometry is easily expressed in terms
of the inclusion relation A ⊂ B, and this is defined in terms of a statistical
null relation AøB meaning that “every” beam that passes the A test entirely
fails the B test, and conversely. Then
Two points fix a line, and two lines in a plane fix a point, just as in classical
logic. But many points lie on every line, as in projective geometry, not classical
logic. They are all called superpositions of two points that fix the line, and
this is the superposition principle, the feature peculiar to quantum pragmatics
and alien to classical logic. What is often called a quantum logic is a Galois
lattice of the null relation.
To be quite explicit:
84
set theory as a theory of transformations. His quantum logic was also a the-
ory of transformations, namely projection operators, and he later mentioned
“quantum set theory”, but apparently never constructed one. The quantum
set theory Q is a specially simple and limited quantization of classical set
theory, replacing classical logic by a quantum pragmatics, and retaining the
transformational interpretation of Boole and von Neumann.
In quantum theory it is especially important to distinguish mathematical
objects from physical, since they are handled with different logics. In classical
mechanics one may relate mathematical to physical objects by a generalized
commutative diagram:
computation
M0 → M1
85
The vacuum too is full of connections, but they may be inactive on the scale
of current measurements. And we must leave enough metasystem outside the
system to carry out the study.
\ i b
[a, b]P = [b
a, b]. (162)
~
It converts the Hamiltonian dynamical equation into the Heisenberg dy-
namical equation
dq i
= [H, q]. (163)
dt ~
For fermions this i can be cancelled by one in the Hamiltonian, though not for
bosons.
In the present infraquantization, the imaginary i emerges in a singular
organizing limit. This is consistent with its use in the correspondence relation
(162), which also refers to such a limo.
86
of the cosmos, not including ourselves, that can have experimental meaning.
The use of cosmic statvectors does not seem to be intrinsically more absurd
than the use of cosmic states. One must not take it literally, and must exercise
due caution for features peculiar to the quantum case, like non-commutativity.
∀v ∈ C 1 : v 2 = kvk =: v · v ∈ C 0 . (164)
87
multiplication operation x ∨ y (∨yx in prefix notation), a free monadic oper-
ation ιx, read successor of x, and the empty set 1, a constant. The classical
product ∨ is the disjoint union, obeying ιx ∨ ιx = 0. Peano’s ι operation is
better suited to an algebraic theory than Cantor’s ∈ relation. ιx = {x} = x is
the set whose only element is x. The familiar set notation {x, y, . . . , z} is here
an abbreviation for ιx ∨ ιy ∨ . . . ∨ ιz.
A quantum variant of ι serves as the microcosmic strut of which a quantum
system history is constructed, an iota indeed. 0 ∈ C serves as a space-holder,
marking the absence of a meaningful expression; a back-formation from the
quantum theory, where 0 ∈ Q is the sole vector that defines no ray and no
physical process, synonymous with the ∞ of C. S. Pierce and the om (omega)
of SETL.
C[T ] ⊂ C is the level-T part of C, the subset of C whose sets can be written
with 1, ∨ and ≤ T nested ι’s. Levels nest: T < T 0 :⊂: C[T ] ⊂ C[T 0 ]. Let
C g denote the subset of C of grade (:=cardinality) g, the g-ads, products of g
monads. Let the (binary) exponential exp2 X be the set of finite subsets of
any set X. Then C is its own exponential: C = exp2 C. Define the random
(finite) set as the mathematical object with state space C.
Now for the quantum set or polyad. This is associated in quantum fashion
with the vector space Q. Vectors with the statistical interpretation of quantum
theory are called statistical vectors or statvectors to distinguish them from
states in the classical sense (Appendix 17). Any non-zero statvectors in Q
statistically described a polyad.
Q is a real exterior algebra generated, by analogy with C, by the associative
exterior product ∨, an injective linear operator ι : Q → Q, the constant
identity 1 for the empty set, and the constant 0 for the undefined. In an
exterior algebra, monadics anti-commute.
Operations that in classical logic were considered mental or mathematical
correspond in quantum pragmatics to physical operations. The Q monadics
represent operations of individual quantum annihilation, monads. The Q prod-
uct b ∨ a means doing a and then b; ιx means annihilating an annihilator. In
the present application let us suppose that annihilations of first-generation
leptons and quarks are near-monads. The higher generations are taken up in
§10.
Q is the exterior algebra over itself:
Q = ext Q. (166)
A certain sequence of rays in Q illustrated in (40) is isomorphic to C. The levels
TQ and Q[≤ T ] are defined analogously to C[T ] and C[≤ T ]. The inclusive levels
Q[≤ T ] are nested exterior subalgebras of Q.
Q has a natural Hilbert space metric, defined inductively:
88
• R = Q[1] is a one-dimensional Hilbert space with norm h0 xx = x2 for
x ∈ R ⊂ Q.
• If H is a Hilbert space then ext H has a unique natural Hilbert space
form extending H.
• Therefore Q =∼ Limo n→∞ (ext)n R has a unique natural Hilbert space
metrical form h extending h0 .
89
17.4 Glossary 2010.04.25
90
References
[1] Stephen L. Adler. Quaternionic quantum mechanics and quantum fields.
Oxford University Press, 1995.
[2] V. Ambarzumian and D. Iwanenko. Zur frage nach vermeidung des un-
endliche selbstrückwirkung des elektrons. Zeitschrift für Physik, 64:563–
567, 1930.
[3] J. Baugh. Regular Quantum Dynamics. PhD thesis, School of Physics,
Georgia Institute of Technology, 2004.
[4] F. Bayen, M. Flato, C. Fronsdal, A. Lichnerowicz, and D. Sternheimer.
Quantum mechanics as a deformation of classical mechanics. Letters in
Mathematical Physics, 1:521–530, 1977.
[5] Gregor W. Bayer. Theory of the cut-off. Symmetry, to appear, 2009.
[6] N. Bohr. Causality and complementarity. Philosophy of Science, 4:293–4,
1936.
[7] F. Bopp and R. Haag. Über die möglichkeit von spinmodellen. Zeitschrift
fr Naturforschung, 5a:644, 1950.
[8] R. Brauer and H. Weyl. Spinors in n dimensions. American Journal of
Mathematics, 57:425, 1935.
[9] E Cartan. Les groupes projectifs qui ne laissent invariante aucune multi-
plicit plane. Bull. Soc. Math. France, 41:53–96, 1913.
[10] E. Cartan. Leçons sur la theorie des spineurs. Hermann, Paris, 1938.
[11] A. H. Chamseddine, A. Connes, and M. Marcolli. Gravity and the stan-
dard model with neutrino mixing. Adv. Theor. Math. Phys., 11:991–1089,
2007.
[12] C. Chevalley. The construction and study of certain important algebras.
The Mathematical Society of Japan, Tokyo, 1955.
[13] P. A. M. Dirac. Spinors in Hilbert Space. Plenum, New York, 1974.
[14] A. Einstein and V. Bargmann. Bivector fields. Annals of Mathematics,
43:1–14, 1943.
[15] A. Einstein and V. Bargmann. Bivector fields II. Annals of Mathematics,
43:15–23, 1943.
[16] L. D. Faddeev. How we understand “quantization” a hundred years after
Max Planck. Physikalische Blätter, 52:689, 1996.
[17] R. P. Feynman, 1941. Personal communication ca 1961. Feynman began
this line of thought in about 1941, before his work on the Lamb shift, and
may have published a similar formula.
91
[18] D. Finkelstein. Space-time code. Physical Review, 184:1261–1271, 1969.
[19] D. Finkelstein, J.M. Jauch, and D. Speiser. Notes on quaternion quantum
mechanics I, II, III. Report CERN 59–7, 59–11, 59–17, CERN, Geneva,
1959.
[20] D. R. Finkelstein. Space–time structure in high energy interactions. In
T. Gudehus, G. Kaiser, and A. Perlmutter, editors, Coral Gables Confer-
ence on Fundamental Interactions at High Energy. Center of Theoretical
Studies January 22—24, 1969. University of Miami, pages 324–343, New
York, 1969. Gordon and Breach.
[21] D. R. Finkelstein. Quantum Relativity. Springer, Heidelberg, 1996.
[22] A. Galiautdinov and D. R. Finkelstein. Chronon corrections to the Dirac
equation. JMP, 43:4741, 2002.
[23] M. Gerstenhaber. On the deformation of rings and algebras. Annals of
Mathematics, 32:472, 1964.
[24] D. Hestenes. Space-time algebra. Gordon and Breach, New York, 1966.
[25] E. Inönü and E.P. Wigner. On the contraction of groups and their repre-
sentations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 39:510–524,
1953.
[26] B. Kostant. Lie algebra cohomology and the generalized Borel–Weil the-
orem. Annals of Mathematics, 74:329–387, 1961.
[27] A. Kuzmich, N. P. Bigelow, and L. Mandel. Europhysics Letters, A 42:481,
1998.
[28] Dennis Marks, 2008. Private communication.
[29] T. D. Palev. Lie algebraical aspects of the quantum statistics. Unitary
quantization (A-quantization). Preprint JINR E17-10550, Joint Institute
for Nuclear Research, Dubna, 1977. hep-th/9705032.
[30] R. Penrose. Angular momentum: an approach to combinatorial space-
time. In T. Bastin, editor, Quantum Theory and Beyond, pages 151–
180. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1971. Also available at
http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/penrose/. Penrose kindly shared some
of this seminal work with me as his theory of ‘mops’, in 1960.
[31] H. Saller. Operational Quantum Theory I. Nonrelativistic Structures.
Springer, New York, 2006.
[32] I. Schur. Über die Darstellung der symmetrischen und der alternierenden
Gruppen durch gebrochene lineare substitutionen. Journal für die reine
und angewandte Mathematik, 139:155–250, 1911. Translation: On the
92
representation of the symmetric and alternating groups by fractional lin-
ear substitutions. Transl. M-F Otto. International Journal of Theoretical
Physics 40:413–458 (2001).
[33] I. E. Segal. A class of operator algebras which are determined by groups.
Duke Mathematical Journal, 18:221–265, 1951. Especially §6A.
[34] M. Shiri-Garakani and D. R. Finkelstein. Finite quantum kinematics of
the harmonic oscillator. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 2006.
[35] H.P. Snyder. Quantized space-time. Physical Review, 71:38, 1947.
[36] H. P. Stapp. The copenhagen interpretation. American Journal of
Physics, 40:1098–1116, 1972.
[37] E. C. G. Stückelberg. Quantum theory in real Hilbert space. Helvetica
Physica Acta, 33:727–752, 1960.
[38] L. Susskind. Dynamics of spontaneous symmetry breaking in the
weinberg–salam theory. Physical Review D, 20:2619, 1979.
[39] M. Tavel, D. Finkelstein, and S. Schiminovich. Weak and electromagnetic
interactions in quaternion quantum mechanics. Bulletin of the American
Physical Society, 9:435, 1965.
[40] Armin Uhlmann. State vector and quantization in an over-all space-time
view. Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift der Karl-Marx-Universität Leipzig,
Mathematische-Naturwissenschaftliche Reihe, 2/3:115–123, 1957/58.
[41] H. Umezawa. Advanced field theory: micro, macro, and thermal physics.
American Institute of Physics, 1993.
[42] R. M. UNGER. THE SELF AWAKENED: PRAGMATISM UNBOUND.
Harvard, 2007.
[43] R. Vilela-Mendes. Deformations, stable theories and fundamental con-
stants. Journal of Physics A, 27:8091–8104, 1994.
[44] John von Neumann. Mathematische Begrundung der Quantenmechanik.
Nachr. Ges. Wiss. Göttingen, pages 1–57, 1927. Also in J. von Neumann,
Collected Works, volume 1.
[45] S Weinberg. Implications of dynamical symmetry breaking: An adden-
dum. Physical Review D, 19:1277, 1979.
[46] C. F. v. Weizsäcker, E. Scheibe, and G. Sussmann. Komplementarität und
Logik III. Mehrfache Quantelung. Naturwissenschaften, 13a:705, 1955.
[47] J. Wess. Gauge theories on noncommutative spacetime treated by the
Seiberg-Witten method. In U. Carow-Watamura, Y. Maeda, and S. Wata-
mura, editors, Quantum Field Theory and Noncommutative Geometry,
page 177. Springer, Berlin, 2005.
93
[48] C. N. Yang. On quantized spacetime. Physical Review, 72:874, 1947.
94