Springer Philosophical Studies: An International Journal For Philosophy in The Analytic Tradition
Springer Philosophical Studies: An International Journal For Philosophy in The Analytic Tradition
Springer Philosophical Studies: An International Journal For Philosophy in The Analytic Tradition
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical
Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PETER KIVY
I want to argue here in exactly the opposite way: that one of the
features of ethical emotivism is completely lacking in the aesthetic
will not, I want to make clear, be arguing that the emotive theory o
a plausible theory. To the contrary, I am convinced (as are a lot
people) that it is not. Nor will I be arguing that aesthetic emotivis
plausible theory (although I am convinced it isn't). I am arguing, me
there is one plausible feature of ethical emotivism which fails to be
in the corresponding aesthetic formulation of the doctrine.
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
352 PETER KIVY
seems, in fact, to be as
morals. This is a 'given'
It is obvious, therefore, that any aesthetic theory sophisticated enough to
be worthy of notice must somehow leave room for real aesthetic disagree-
ment; or at least bring us to understanding what we are really doing when we
seem to be disagreeing. It is the same requirement that Charles Stevenson laid
down for ethical analysis: "In the first place, we must be able sensibly to
disagree about whether something is 'good"'3. And we cannot plausibly
accept the requirement in the moral sphere and dismiss it unreflectively in the
aesthetic without manifestly begging a very important question.
The heroic line would be, I suppose, to dismiss questions of aesthetic
(artistic) value as pseudo-questions. There was a time when many kinds of
questions were sent to Coventry in this way. But it was the result, so to
speak, of arguing from above. As J. 0. Urmson has pointed out, the early
emotive theory of value emerged from "considerations... of a very general
epistemological character and did not arise out of a careful and close reflec-
tion on the nature of value judgments"4. Today, however, these consider-
ations, once so compelling, have rather evaporated away. Nor do there seem
now to be any other arguments of a general philosophical kind to take their
place.
We must turn, therefore, to some other, less simple-minded form of emo-
tivism than the kind which sees aesthetic value judgments as instances of
personal preference expressions, pure and simple, if we are to have a hope of
finding a successful account of them in that direction. The emotivism of
Stevenson and A. J. Ayer provides such a model. But I will argue, the account
of ethical disagreement cannot be plausibly translated into aesthetic terms;
and that is the substance of my claim that one attractive feature of ethical
emotivism dissipates in the aesthetic atmosphere.
II
Ayer's emotive theory of ethics was born, as Urmson has remarked, not of
any real philosophical interest in ethical judgment but out of a need to
defend an epistemological theory against a threat from that direction. And if
his interest in ethics was ancillary, his interest in aesthetics was even further
from the center of his philosophical attention. Mention of it only comes in
offhand way, it being felt that what applies to ethical discourse "will be
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A FAILURE OF AESTHETIC EMOTIVISM 353
the man who is ostensibly contradicting me is merely expressing his moral sentiments. So
that there is plainly no sense in asking which of us is in the right. For neither of us is
asserting a genuine proposition.8
What, then, is going on when two apparently intelligent agents engage in what
we are all used to calling ethical disagreement? There is, Ayer insists, no real
disagreement at all; or, rather, no real disagreement about value, only a
dispute about fact, disguised by ethical language. That is how we save the
appearance of ethical discourse.
For we certainly do engage in disputes which are ordinarily regarded as disputes about
questions of value. But, in all such cases, we find, if we consider the matter closely, that
the dispute is not really about a question of value, but about a question of fact. When
someone disagrees with us about the moral value of a certain action or type of action, we
do admittedly resort to argument in order to win him over to our way of thinking. But
we do not attempt to show by our arguments that he has the 'wrong' ethical feeling
towards a situation whose nature he has correctly apprehended. What we attempt to
show is that he is mistaken about the facts of the case.9
It is Ayer's claim, as we have seen, that this view of ethical discourse can
be fitted, point for point, to aesthetic discourse. To that claim we now turn.
Ayer's discussion of aesthetics is extremely brief, and I shall quote it almost
in full. Ayer writes:
our conclusions about the nature of ethics apply to aesthetics also. Aesthetic terms are
used in exactly the same way as ethical terms. Such aesthetic words as 'beautiful' and
'hidious' are employed, as ethical words are employed, not to make statements of fact,
but simply to express certain feelings and evoke a certain response. It follows, as in
ethics, that there is no sense in attributing objective validity to aesthetic judgments, and
no possibility of arguing about questions of value in aesthetics, but only about questions
of fact.... [Tihe purpose of aesthetic criticism is not so much to give knowledge as to
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
354 PETER KIVY
communicate emotion. The critic, by calling attention to certain features of the work
under review, and expressing his own feelings about them, endeavours to make us share
his attitude towards the work as a whole. The only relevant propositions that he formu-
lates are propositions describing the nature of the work. And these are plain records of
fact.'0
III
Stevenson expounded over the years what he called two 'patterns of ana
for ethical terms. I intend to discuss both of them here, as each provi
possible analysis of aesthetic terms as well.
The first pattern of analysis takes as its 'working model' an explicatio
the proposition 'X is good'. According to Stevenson it "has something l
the meaning of 'I do like this; do so as well"' 1. In a later formulation,
rendered: "I approve of this, do so as well"12. The analysis certainly be
affinities with Ayer's. But there are noteworthy differences.
To begin with, Stevenson appears to construe 'I do like this', or 'I appr
descriptively. Unlike Ayer, he takes expressing, it would seem, as describ
state of mind. Second, the state of mind expressed, which Ayer usually
describes as an 'emotion' or 'feeling' (and only infrequently as an 'attitude'),
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A FAILURE OF AESTHETIC EMOTIVISM 355
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
356 PETER KIV'Y
IV
We have, then, three emotive analyses of 'beautiful' before us. Taking the
general sense of 'beautiful', something like 'aesthetically good', we have, first,
Ayer's analysis, in which, when I say 'X is beautiful', I am expressing or
evincing (but not describing) my positive emotive response toward X and
urging my hearers to adopt a like one. We have, secondly, the Stevensonian
analysis in which 'X is aesthetically good' can be understood to mean 'I
approve of X, do so as well', 'I approve' being construed as a description of
the speaker's state of mind, and 'do so as well' as the appeal to the attitudes
and interests of others. Finally, we have the more specific sense of 'beautiful',
with its more palpable descriptive content, such that we can distinguish,
among those things we want to call 'beautiful' in the sense of 'aesthetically
good', those that are 'pretty', those that are 'sublime', etc., and, of course,
those that are 'beautiful'. This second sense of 'beautiful' will be involved, at
times, in persuasive defmitions. At these times, it will, like the general sense,
be expressive of attitudes rather than beliefs.
With these three analyses of the term 'beautiful' laid out, I want now to
turn to three serious objections. The first two constitute what the title of my
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A FAILURE OF AESTHETIC EMOTIVISM 357
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
358 PETER KIVY
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A FAILURE OF AESTHETIC EMOTIVISM 359
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
360 PETER KIVY
to judgments of aesthe
imperative element hel
aesthetic disagreement
themselves in ethical d
not exist; and the aesth
have no raison d'etre. T
expressions of approva
the capability of the theory to give an adequate account of disagreement.
(More of that in a moment.) And to construe them as quasi-imperatives
makes little sense. So what is a distinct virtue in emotivism as an ethical
theory turns out, in aesthetics, to be a palpable vice.
At this point the aesthetic emotivist may have to concede that aesthetic value
judgments, unlike ethical ones, lack an imperative force and amount only to
expressions of approval. This means, as I suggested above, that their account
of aesthetic disagreement will be greatly impoverished. What will be left will
be the ploy that apparent disagreements in aesthetic value are in reality only
disagreements in aesthetic 'facts'. And this brings me to my second objection.
I do not believe this strategy can possibly have the same success in aesthetics
that it at least initially has in ethics.
What 'facts' could be in aesthetic dispute? They are, one assumes, the
features that characterize aesthetic objects. As Ayer says, the "only relevant
propositions" that the critic formulates - i.e. the only propositions properly
so called - "are propositions describing the nature of the [art] work. And
these", he concludes, "are plain records of fact". What might the disputed
facts be in an ethical argument? Clearly, two major kinds would be the
possible consequences of actions and the motives behind them. And when
we think about how complicated the causal chains are in this world, even in
the ordinary cases, how dark and hidden from scrutiny the motives of men,
we see that just deciding on consequences and motives can provide a rich field
for genuine disagreement. But what about aesthetic 'facts'? Do they really
leave that kind of room for debate? The painting is before us. How can there
be any real disagreement about what its features are, disagreement complex
enough to account for our protracted critical debates? It is square or round,
red or blue; a cow (or is it a horse?) in the lower right, a tree in the back-
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A FAILURE OF AESTHETIC EMOTIVISM 361
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
362 PETER KIVY
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A FAILURE OF AESTHETIC EMOTIVISM 363
VI
My fmal point takes its departure from a general criticism of the concept
emotive meaning to be found in Urmson's Emotive Theory of Ethics. I hav
no doubt that this line of argument will be a familiar one. My excuse fo
putting it through its paces again is to draw from it a result for aesthetics
that might, perhaps, be novel.
Consider the provocoteur who harrangues a crowd with 'Yankee go hom
We can, following Austin, distinguish between its illocutionary force and
perlocutionary effect: that is, essentially, we can distinguish between wha
is and what it does. 'Yankee go home!' is an incitement to rebellion; and i
illocutionary force it has by way of meaning convention. If a person does
know that 'Yankee go home!' is an incitement to rebellion, his knowledge
its meaning is to that extent defective. But the utterance of 'Yankee go
home!' may do various things. It may indeed incite to rebellion; but it may
also arouse fear, or loathing, or feelings of patriotism, or nothing at all. And
these perlocutionary effects are contingent: they cannot be part of the
meaning of 'Yankee go home!' In short, illocutionary force is a meaning
concept, perlocutionary effect is not.
Now in that the emotive theory, in ascribing emotive meaning to value
terms, ascribes it in virtue of the perlocutionary effect of uttering these
terms, it is making a basic conceptual error. For perlocutionary effect, unlike
illocutionary force, cannot be a matter of meaning. To quote Urmson,
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
364 PETER KIV'Y
It would seem, then, that 'attitudes' are more likely candidates than
emotions. And so the emotivist might argue that the illocutionary force of
ethical terms is to incite or recommend attitudes of certain kinds. But if this
seems like a plausible view of ethical discourse (I do not say it is), it seems so,
to begin with, because, as we have argued before, ethics has intimately to do
with action and action is at least in part contingent on attitudes. However,
when we attempt to give a similar analysis of the illocutionary force of
aesthetic value terms, that prima facie plausibility, as we have seen, evaporates.
That all, or most aesthetic value terms should have the recommending of atti-
tudes as their sole or major illocutionary force seems odd; for it is difficult to
understand what possible purpose such illocutionary force could serve in the
context of aesthetic discourse. Why should I want to recommend attitudes to
no further purpose of action? That surely would be language on holiday.
There must, one assumes, be some kind of connection between illocutionary
force and the use to which language is customarily put.
What, then, are we about when we make aesthetic value judgments? Some
linguistic utterances are made in contexts in which the purpose of moving to
action is absent; and their illocutionary force is at least in large part descriptive.
We tell the truth as we see it, sometimes, often in fact, to no further end: that
is a characteristic of truth-telling. Describing is, often, though not always, an
end unto itself. Ifjudgments of aesthetic value are themselves uttered character-
istically in contexts which preclude the further purpose of excitation to action,
are they not, at least in this respect, more like statements of what is the case
than incitements or imperatives or recommendations; and is this not at least
some grounds for taking their illocutionary force to be describing rather than
these other things? I am far from suggesting that this consideration alone
compels us to take such a line. I do suggest that it is a prima facie reason for
calling into question the all-too-familiar claim that disagreements over the
goodness and badness of works of art are clearly disagreements in attitude
rather than belief.
It is one of the ironies of intellectual history that aesthetics has, at least
since the seventeenth century, been a philosophical breeding ground for
'subjectivist' theories of value. It is no accident, for example, that Francis
Hutcheson introduced his moral sense philosophy with a treatise - perhaps
the first - on aesthetics: in other words, essentially 'aestheticizing' morality
with the emotive virus of 'taste'. But if I am right, the aesthetic soil is far less
hospitable to the subjective virus than the ethical. So it is high time, it seems
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A FAILURE OF AESTHETIC EMOTIVISM 365
NOTES
This content downloaded from 77.111.246.95 on Sat, 20 Jul 2019 16:31:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms