0% found this document useful (0 votes)
227 views

CHAP10 Ordinal Numbers

The document discusses transitive sets and ordinal numbers. Some key points: - Ordinal numbers describe the structure of well-ordered sets, while cardinal numbers simply measure size. - A set is transitive if every element within an element is also an element of the set. The natural numbers are transitive. - An ordinal number is a transitive set that is well-ordered by the membership relation. Ordinal arithmetic is defined by transfinite induction. - The class of all ordinals cannot be a set, according to the Burali-Forti paradox. This leads to the definition of cardinal numbers as ordinals that are not equivalent to any predecessors.

Uploaded by

Ronaldo Manaoat
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
227 views

CHAP10 Ordinal Numbers

The document discusses transitive sets and ordinal numbers. Some key points: - Ordinal numbers describe the structure of well-ordered sets, while cardinal numbers simply measure size. - A set is transitive if every element within an element is also an element of the set. The natural numbers are transitive. - An ordinal number is a transitive set that is well-ordered by the membership relation. Ordinal arithmetic is defined by transfinite induction. - The class of all ordinals cannot be a set, according to the Burali-Forti paradox. This leads to the definition of cardinal numbers as ordinals that are not equivalent to any predecessors.

Uploaded by

Ronaldo Manaoat
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 6

10.

ORDINAL NUMBERS
§10.1 Transitive Sets
We turn our attention to ordinal numbers. With finite numbers the cardinal
numbers, apart from zero, are 1, 2, 3, … while the ordinal numbers are 1st, 2nd, 3rd, …
There is really very little difference. For infinite sets there’s a big difference. While
cardinal numbers simply measure the size of a set, ordinal numbers describe the structure
of a well-ordered set.
Consider the well-ordered set {1, 2, 3, … , 0}. As a set this is no bigger than
{1, 2, 3, …}. But as well-ordered sets the ordering is quite different. One set has a
largest while the other does not.

A set x is transitive if x  x, that is, if every element of an element of x is


itself an element of x.

Example 1: Recall that (1, 2) = {{1}, {1, 2}}.


x = {0, 1, 2, {2}, {1, 2}, (1, 2)} is not transitive since x = {0, 1, 2, {1}, {1, 2}}  x.
However y = {0, 1, 2, {2}, {1, 2}, (2, 1)} is since y = {0, 1, 2, {2}, {1, 2}}  x.

The natural numbers are transitive, and the set of natural numbers itself is
transitive.

Theorem 1: A set x is transitive if and only if x x.


Proof: Suppose x is transitive. We must show that x  x, that is, every element of x is
a subset of x. Let y  x. If z  y then z  x and so z  x. Hence y  x, as required.
Now suppose x  x. Let y  x. Then for some z, y  z and z  x.
Since x  x, z  x, that is, z  x. Since y  z, y  x. We have therefore shown that
x  x.

Example 1 (continued): Observe that every element of y is a subset of y, since


y = {0, {0}, {0, 1}, {2}, {1, 2}, {{2}, {1, 2}}}.

Theorem 2: If the elements of x are transitive then so are x and x.


Proof: Suppose that the elements of x are transitive.
(1) Let y  x. We must show that y  x, that is y  u for all u  x.
Let u  x. Then u is transitive. Since y  x, y  z for some z  x.
 z  u. Since y  z  u, y  u.
(2) Let y  x. Then for some z, y  z  x. Then z  u for some u  x.
Since y  z  u and u is transitive, y  u. Thus y  x. Hence x is transitive.

Example 2: The sets x = {{1, {1}}, {1}, 0, 1, 2} and y = {{2, {1}}, {1}, 0, 1, 2} are
transitive. Let u = {x, y}.
Then u = x  y = {{1}, 0, 1, 2} and x = {{1, {1}}, {2, {1}},{1}, 0, 1, 2}, both of
which are transitive.

73
§10.2 Ordinal Numbers
An ordinal number is a transitive set that is well-ordered by the relation
“ or =”. So, for ordinals, < and  are equivalent. We denote the class of ordinals by
Ord.

Examples 2: Ordinal numbers include all the natural numbers, as well as  and +.

If (X, ) is a well-ordered set X and is similar to the ordinal  we say that  is its
ordinal number. We shall show that this is uniquely defined. We denote the ordinal of
X by ord (X, ). If the ordering is understood we can write ord(X).

Theorem 3: If  is an ordinal number, then so is +.

Theorem 4: Elements of ordinals are ordinals.


Proof: Elements of ordinals are subsets and so are well-ordered. Let x  y  z  ,
where  is an ordinal. Then since  is transitive, x, y, z are elements of . Since  is
transitive on , x  z.

Theorem 5: Similar ordinals are equal.


Proof: Let f:  be a similarity. Suppose x is the smallest element of  such that
f(x)  x. If y < x then y = f(y) < f(x), whence x  f(x). Now suppose y < f(x).
Then, since f1 is a similarity, f1(y) < x. Hence y = f(f1(y)) = f f1(y) < x. So f(x)  x, a
contradiction. Hence there is no such x.

Theorem 6: If  and  are ordinal numbers and    then  is an element of .


Proof: Suppose ,  are ordinals such that   . Let x be the least element of   .
Since x   and  is transitive, x  .
Since (  )  x = 0, x  . Let y  . Then y  .
Since {x, y} has a least, either x  y or x = y or y  x. If x  y or x = y, then x  ,
contradicting the fact that x    . Thus y  x and so   x. But x  . Hence x = .
As x  ,   .

Theorem 7: Transitive subsets of ordinals are ordinals.


Proof: Suppose there is an ordinal  having a transitive subset which is not itself an
ordinal, and suppose  is the least element of + which has such a subset. Then there is
some X   which is transitive but not an ordinal. Then X is not well-ordered by . Let
0  Y  X have no least. Now the elements of Y are elements of the ordinal  and so are
ordinals, and hence transitive. Hence Y is transitive.
Let y  Y. Then Y  y  Y  X  . Hence y  . Thus y is an ordinal, and
being less than , the transitive subset Y must be an ordinal. By Theorem 6, Y  Y.
But clearly Y is the least element of Y, a contradiction.

74
Theorem 8: If X is a set of ordinals then X is an ordinal.
Proof: Suppose X is a set of ordinals. Then X is transitive. Let 0  Y  X. Then the
elements of Y are ordinals and so Y is transitive. Let   Y. Then Y  . Thus Y
is an ordinal. Hence Y   or Y =   Y. Hence if Y  Y, Y  Y, a
contradiction. Thus Y is the least element of Y. Hence X is well-ordered by . Thus
X is an ordinal.

Theorem 9 (Burali-Forti Paradox): The class of ordinals is not a set.


Proof: Suppose Ord is a set. Then Ord  Ord and so Ord  (Ord)+  Ord so
Ord  Ord, a contradiction.

§10.3 Transfinite Induction


The method of Proofs by Induction is very useful in mathematics. It works
because every non-empty set of natural numbers has a least, that is, the set of natural
numbers is well-ordered by the usual ordering. Finite induction can be extended to
infinite sets, provided we can well-order them.

Theorem 10 (Proof by Transfinite Induction): Suppose W is a well-ordered set and X


is a subset of W. Suppose that X has the property that whenever all the predecessors of
x are in X then so is x. Then X = W.
Proof: Suppose X  W. Then m = min(W  X)  C!

We can also define things by transfinite induction. The following is a special case.

Theorem 11: Suppose G is a generalized function whose domain is S, a subset of Ord


with no maximum. Then there exists a unique function f on S such that f(x +) = G(f(x))
for all x  S and f(x) = {f(y) | y < x} if x has no predecessor.

§10.4 The Arithmetic of Ordinal Numbers


A non-zero ordinal is a limit ordinal if it has no immediate predecessor. An
obvious example is .
We define addition of ordinals by transfinite induction as follows:
(A0)  + 0 = ;
(A1)  + + = ( + )+;
(A2)  +  =  { +  |  < } if  is a limit ordinal.

Example 3: Successively adding 1 to  we get the sequence  + 1,  + 2, …

We define multiplication of ordinals by transfinite induction as follows:


(M0) 0 = 0;
(M1) + = () + ;
(M2)  =  { |  < } if  is a limit ordinal.

We define exponentiation of ordinals by transfinite induction as follows:

75
(E0) 0 = 1;
(E1)  = .;
+

(E2)  = { +  |  < } if  is a limit ordinal and   0;


(E3) 0 = 0 if  is a limit ordinal.

Examples 4:
 + 1 =  + 0+ = ( + 0)+ by (A1) = + by (A0)  .
1 +  = {1 + n | n < } = .
2 = {2n | n < } by (M2) = .
2 = 1+ = 1 +  by (M1) = 0+ +  = (0 + ) +  by (M1)
= (0 + ) +  by (M0) = {0 + n | n < } +  =  +  =  { + n | n < } by (A2).
2 = {2n | n < } by (E2) = 

§10.5 Further Arithmetic of Cardinal Numbers


Theorem 12:If a, b are cardinal numbers and a is finite and b is infinite then a + b = b.
Proof: Choose A, B disjoint so #A = a, #B = b.
Let C  B such that #C = 0 and let D = B  C. Let #D = d.
Then b = 0 + d so a + b = a + 0 + d = 0 + d = b.

Theorem 13: If a is an infinite cardinal number then a + a = a.


Proof: Choose A so that #A = a.
Let F = {bijections f : X  2  X | X  A}.
F  0 (take X with #X = 0).
F is partially ordered by extension.
By Zorn’s Lemma  maximal f: X  2  X for some X  A.
If A  X is infinite we contradict the maximality of f so A  X is finite.
#X + #X = #X and #A = #X + #(A  X) so
#A + #A = #X + #X + 2#(A  X)
= #A + #(A  X)
= #A.

Theorem 14: If a  b are cardinal numbers and b is infinite then a + b = b.


Proof: Choose A, B with #A = a, #B = b.
Since a  b, a + b  b + b = b.
But b  a + b so a + b = b.

Theorem 15: If a is an infinite cardinal number then a.a = a.


Proof: Choose A so #A = a.
Let F = {bijections f : X  X  X | X  A}.
F  0 (take X with #X = 0).
F is partially ordered by extension.
By Zorn’s Lemma  maximal f: X  X  X for some X  A.
Let #X = x. Then x.x = x.
Suppose x < a.

76
Then #(A  X) = a and so A  X has a subset, Y with #Y = x.
Then #[(X  Y) + (Y  X) + (Y  Y)] = 3x.x
= x so
there exists a bijection from (X  Y) + (Y  X) + (Y  Y) to Y.
We can thus extend f to a bijection g: (X + Y)  (X + Y)  X + Y, a contradiction.
Hence x = a and so a.a = a.

At long last we can define a cardinal number as a set. A cardinal number is


simply an ordinal number that is not equivalent to any of its predecessors.

Theorem 16: The class of ordinals, C, equivalent to a set S is itself a set.


Proof: Well order (S) and let  be the corresponding ordinal.
Then   C   <     .
So C = {   |   S}.
Now that we have established that the set of ordinals equivalent to S is a set we
can define, for any set S #S to be the smallest ordinal equivalent to S. Clearly it is a
cardinal number.
We are now in a position to properly define the alephs, that is, to write every
infinite cardinal as  for some ordinal . Let  be an infinite cardinal number.
Let S be the set of infinite cardinal numbers that are less than  (less than in the sense
of cardinal numbers). S is well-ordered by .
Let  be the ordinal number of this well-ordered set.
Then we denote  by .

Example 5: Let  = . Then S = {0, 1, 2, …} with


0 < 1 < 2 < …
The ordinal number of this well-ordered set is , which justifies the use of the notation
.

Example 6: Let  = +1. Then S = {0, 1, 2, …, } with


0 < 1 < 2 < … < 
The ordinal number of this well-ordered set is  + 1, which justifies the use of the
notation +1.

Theorem 17: If  is an ordinal number and # =  then    < +1.


Proof:    by definition of cardinals.
If +1   then +1  , a contradiction.

Theorem 18:  = { |  < } is a cardinal number.


Proof:  is an ordinal number.
Suppose  = # and  < .
Then   , so    for some  < .
Then  <   , a contradiction.

77
Theorem 19: { |  < +} = .
Proof: If  < + then    and so   .

Theorem 20: If  has no predecessor then { |  < } = .


Proof: Let  = { |  < }.
For all  < ,    and so   .
Hence   .
If  < ,  + 1 <  so +1  , a contradiction.

78

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy