Fear and Death in Plato
Fear and Death in Plato
Fear and Death in Plato
Louis
Washington University Open Scholarship
All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs)
January 2009
Recommended Citation
Austin, Emily, "Fear and Death in Plato" (2009). All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs). 27.
https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd/27
This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in All
Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact
digital@wumail.wustl.edu.
WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY IN ST. LOUIS
Department of Philosophy
by
Emily A. Austin
August 2009
This dissertation would have never come to fruition without the help of many
people. First, I thank my advisor, Eric Brown, whose exuberant teaching persona and
keen intellect motivated me to make the radical shift from the study of Wittgenstein and
Quine to the study of Plato. I thank him especially for his unflagging efforts to help me
focus my wide-ranging thoughts and his consistent enthusiasm about the project. To
Second, I thank John Doris, who has kept me level-headed and confident, and
who continues to keep me focused on where the project needs to go next. Though he
Des Chene, Cathy Keane, and George Pepe—both for their willingness to serve in that
The fact that I have so many great friends who are also wonderful colleagues has
made it possible to get through this long process. They have helped me talk through and
muscle through some of these ideas in the office, in their homes, and in bars. In
particular, I thank Sarah Robins, Clerk Shaw, Mariska Leunissen, and Emily Crookston.
initiated my death obsession. If I had not taken his seminar on the history of death in
America, I would neither benefit nor suffer from this morbid curiosity.
Washington University in St. Louis, which has provided outstanding support during my
ii
graduate career. I thank the graduate school for my first-year fellowship and the Dean’s
Dissertation Fellowship. I thank Mark Rollins for his impressive skills as chair of the
philosophy department and his consistent advocacy for graduate students. He saved me
Finally, I thank my husband, Brian, who more than anyone else, has sustained me
through the ups and downs of this project and life at-large. Above all, though, I thank my
iii
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Acknowledgements 2
Introduction 6
iv
ABBREVIATIONS OF ANCIENT WORKS AND AUTHORS
PLATO
Ap. Apology
[Ax.]* Axiochus
Chrm. Charmides
Cri. Crito
Epin. Epinomis
Euthphr. Euthyphro
Grg. Gorgias
Hp. Ma. Hippias Major
La. Laches
Lg. Laws
Men. Meno
Mx. Menexenus
Phd. Phaedo
Phdr. Phaedrus
Ptr. Protagoras
R. Republic
Smp. Symposium
Tht. Theatetus
*Dialogues in brackets indicate that scholars generally agree that Plato is not the author of the dialogue.
ARISTOTLE
EN Nichomachean Ethics
Pol. Politics
HOMER
Il. Iliad
Od. Odyssey
EPICURUS
KD Key Doctrines
Ep. Men. Letter to Menoeceus
v
WELL, YOU JUST WELL TO GET READY, YOU GOT TO DIE.
Plato should have something to say about the fear of death. First, Plato intends to
offer an account of how to live well, and it does not take much imagination to see that the
fear of death can affect the course of one’s life. Second, for Plato, courage is a necessary
condition for living well, and the courageous person is distinguished by her ability to
stand firm in the face of death. Finally, courage is as necessary for a well-ordered polis
and the imminent possibility of violent regime change, death is an ever-present concern.
Any polis with a hope of survival must reckon with death in order to preserve itself.
Once one recognizes that Plato should say something about the fear of death, one
will discover that he says quite a lot, and what he says is interesting and contentious. At
the most general level, Plato consistently argues the following: 1) a virtuous person will
not fear her own death; 1 2) a virtuous person will not fear or grieve the death of her
family and friends; 2 and 3) a virtuous political organization will train its citizens not to
fear death and will prohibit public manifestations of grief. 3 It is by no means self-
evident, however, that ridding oneself of the fear of death, even if possible, is ethically or
1
Ap. 28b-29b, 35a-b, 37b, 40a-42a; Phd. 63e-64a, 67e, 68b, 68a-69a, 84d-85b, 117a;
Grg. 522de; R. 3: 386ab, 6:486a
2
Phd. 116a; 115e-116a; 117d-e; R. 3:387c-388d; 3:397d-e, 10:603e-606c
3
R. 3: 387c-388d, 9: 578a, 10:603e-606c; Ap. 35ab; Mx. 247c; Lg. 12: 958c-960b,
12:949b, 7: 732c, 7:800c-e,
2
1. Why does Plato think that the fear of death is ethically
inappropriate?
circumstances?
I address these questions within the individual context of three dialogues—the Apology,
Phaedo, and Republic. In this introduction, I briefly motivate the questions at a more
Plato’s dialogues.
The fear of death is an ethical concern for Plato for two reasons. First, Plato, like
most ancient ethicists, thinks the aim of a good life is achieving a harmonious soul, which
is comprised of a coherent set of beliefs and desires that manifest themselves in action. It
depends, in short, on psychological health. Thus, our contemporary thought that one’s
attitudes towards death are a matter of psychological health makes it de facto an ethical
Second, an inharmonious soul is an unvirtuous soul. The fear of death not only
threatens the unity of the soul, then, but it makes agents prone to unvirtuous acts. For
Plato, I argue, the fear of death makes unjust activities appear prudent, as injustices both
great and small can prove sufficient to save one’s own life or the lives of those for whom
3
one cares. In addition, since the traditional conception of courage involves standing firm
in the face of death, an extreme fear of death compromises one’s ability to act
courageously, whether in battle, in sickness, or on the sea. The fear of death can also
foster intemperance, since life’s finitude tempts individuals to maximize pleasures, and
one might seek to unjustly amass wealth and power with the hopes that they will protect
one against violence. Finally, for Plato, the fear of death keeps one from gaining
wisdom, not only because wisdom rises and falls with the other virtues, but also because
the avid pursuit of goods and security cuts in on time that should be spent in study.
Even if the fear of death compromises virtue, however, one might nevertheless
contend that it is hard-wired into our psychology and that many manifestations of the fear
of death are not open to alteration. In this dissertation, I argue that Plato believes that the
fear of death, though it can be masterfully controlled, can never be eliminated, because it
feeds on two desires that are beyond the reach of rational persuasion. First, human
beings have a natural desire for protection against the violence of others. Second, we
foster and enjoy attachments to people and projects, and death serves as the ultimate
accompany efforts to defend oneself and those for whom one cares against violence and
to extend the length of one’s life for the sake continuing one’s relationships. Success
Thus, I argue that Plato organizes the Republic’s ideal city with these two
ineliminable desires in mind. First, the ideal city is distinguished by its freedom from
faction—it is perfectly safe and secure. Citizens do not fight or seek protection against
4
one another’s violence. Second, individuals are educated from the outset in a way that
fosters the appropriate attitudes towards death. The educational program conditions
children’s emotions and teaches them that they should not fear death or grieve the death
of others. I offer a novel interpretation of the material conditions of the upper classes,
under which the collective possession of children and the absolute prohibition against
possessing any money ensure political stability and diffuse emotional attachments,
thereby lessening the fear of death and diminishing the desire to grieve.
OUTLINE OF CHAPTERS
The first two chapters take the Apology as their principal text. In Chapter One, I
examine Socrates’ two attempts to convince his audience that they should not fear death.
I argue that Socrates does not intend to convince his audience that they can eliminate
their fear. Rather, he intends to lessen the extent to which they fear death and to
convince them that risking death is always better than committing injustice. He argues
that the greater a person’s fear of death, the more willing she is to commit unjust or
the problem. First, some commentators argue that Socrates’ two arguments are
inconsistent, and I show that they are not inconsistent; second, many commentators argue
that the second argument is a dismal failure, and I show that it does not fail.
audience that a minor injustice is worse than risking death are seriously challenged by
two powerful human desires. First, most people desire security against violence. I show
5
that Socrates believes that gaining security requires injustice, so according to his
argument, making oneself an easy target for violence is better than the injustice required
to protect oneself. Second, most people desire to form and sustain intimate relationships
with friends and family, to whom they grow emotionally attached. This attachment
increases their fear of death, Socrates suggests, because death serves as the ultimate
threat to the continuation of personal relationships. In addition, the greater the emotional
attachment, the more injustice one is willing to commit to continue enjoying one’s
relationships. Socrates, I contend, indicates through the course of his defense that he has
left these two desires unsatisfied, and that it has led to his unjust prosecution and his
inability and unwillingness to protect himself and his family. I conclude that most of
Socrates’ audience prefers to satisfy these desires, even though it will increase their fear
In Chapter Three, I turn to the Phaedo. In the Phaedo, Socrates addresses a group
of philosophically-minded youth, all of whom admire his way of life and grieve his
impending death. I challenge the standard interpretation that Socrates is fearless before
death, and I contend that the antagonism between the body and the soul makes it
impossible for any embodied human to be fearless. For this reason, Socrates employs a
set of strategies to control his fear of death rather than eliminate it, and he recommends
each strategy to his distressed friends. First, he claims that the philosopher must
completely avoid some external goods (money and power) and strongly devalue others
(relationships with friends and family). Second, he believes one should regularly
rehearse arguments in support of the soul’s immortality, preferably until one truly
6
believes them. Third, one should speculate about the benefits of the afterlife by telling
myths and stories. Without all three strategies, Socrates would be unable to minimize
and control his fear. If his young interlocutors fail to reduce their worldly attachments or
remain unconvinced about the soul’s immortality, their fear will intensify. I argue that
The final two chapters concern the Republic. In the fourth chapter, I address the
attitudes towards death of the auxiliary, or second, class in the ideal city, who are
required to prepare themselves to die early on the battlefield. I argue that the
mechanisms by which auxiliaries control their fear of death are largely social in nature, or
features about the political organization that are external to them and mostly beyond their
control. First, I point out the elements of the educational program that foster the
appropriate attitudes towards the fear of death, especially the religious education, which
encourages hope for a desirable afterlife. Second, I argue that the most important
mechanism for controlling the auxiliaries’ fear of death and desire to grieve, somewhat
surprisingly, is the prohibition against possessing private external goods like children and
property. Since Plato thinks private property leads to faction and political instability,
providing the community with a sense of security from violence significantly lessens the
desire to seek protection through unjust means. The community of wives and children
keeps any soldier from leaving behind an orphan or widow, and the death of a child is
never a private misfortune and does not leave anyone childless. Without these political
mechanisms in place, I argue that the childhood education of the auxiliaries would prove
insufficient to control their fear of death and their temptation to act cowardly and
7
unjustly.
auxiliaries, are able to eliminate rather than simply control their fear of death. I argue
that the philosophers, too, cannot eliminate negative emotions like grief and fear. My
in Book IX. I use these two passages to set up my argument that the desire to grieve is a
ineliminable against two competing conceptions. I then turn to the philosopher’s fear of
death. I argue that philosophers control their fear by hoping for an afterlife, and they,
like the auxiliaries, desire immortal honor from the ideal city. Thus, I offer a somewhat
However, I concede that the philosophers, with one significant exception, exercise perfect
control over their emotions, even if the ideal city crumbles. I close by considering the
METHODOLOGY
to some extent a thematic enterprise, I cannot fully skirt the methodological issues. My
substantive reason, then, to jump into the fray concerning background issues that arise
from other ways of connecting Plato’s dialogues. To borrow from Chris Bobonich [2002:
8
483n8], “my claims about the content of particular dialogues are argued for on their own
merits, and do not depend on a specific chronological order.” I will also not be
concerned with whether Plato may have changed his mind, and if so, when he might have
done so. I remain agnostic about the extent to which the protagonist Socrates resembles
his historical counterpart and about the relationship between the protagonist Socrates and
the beliefs of Plato himself. None of the questions of my dissertation turn on these
standard Oxford Classical Texts. For Vol. 1, I use the revised text by Duke, et. al.
[1995]. For all other references to the Platonic corpus, I use the Burnet volumes [1900-
1907]. I have availed myself of a number of excellent commentaries. For the Apology, I
primarily consulted Burnet [1924], Strycker and Slings [1994], Adam [1910], and Dyer
[1893]. For the Phaedo, I consulted Burnet [1911], Geddes [1885], and Wagner [1894].
For the Republic, I used Adam [1894]. I supply the Greek in the notes, though short
9
CHAPTER ONE
In Plato’s Apology, Socrates argues that the members of the Athenian jury could
greatly benefit from fearing death less. He is especially concerned with the effect of an
marked fear of death makes cowardice and injustice tempting, as a petty injustice can
fend off threats to one’s person and may at times prove sufficient to save one’s life.
Socrates, then, in order to explain his current predicament and justify his refusal to save
himself by committing injustice, must convince his audience that risking death is a better
choice than committing a minor injustice. He must convince them that they should
imperil themselves in similar fashion. This is no small task. Socrates offers two
arguments for this effort. The first I call the “Argument from Uncertainty” (29a5-b6) and
At the most general level, commentators have raised two objections to Socrates’
arguments regarding the fear of death. First, they seem mutually inconsistent, since the
second argument breaches the epistemic modesty upon which the first argument depends.
Second, the “Two Things Argument” is a mess, leading scholars to judge it either a very
bad argument or no argument at all. Instead of an argument, those donning the banner of
∗
All references in chapters one and two in which the dialogue is unspecified refer to the
Apology.
10
charity argue that Socrates intends only to offer his audience “consolation” or “reasons
for hope.”4 Thus, the standard means for resolving the inconsistency is to undermine
epistemic modesty and protecting him from the charge of arguing poorly. I argue that the
arguments are in no way inconsistent, since Socrates is entitled to his breach of the
epistemic modesty of the first argument. In addition, I argue that he is fully committed to
First, though, it is useful to see how Socrates appears to contradict himself. The
crucial premise of Socrates’ “Argument from Uncertainty” is that no one knows whether
death is a harm rather than a benefit. He offers the argument in response to an imaginary
objector, who wonders why Socrates is not “ashamed” [αἰσχύνῃ, 28b3] to continue
oneself wise when one is not, to think one knows what one
does not know. For no one knows whether death might not
4
Among those who argue that the “Two Things Argument” is not intended to be read
critically as an argument are Brickhouse and Smith [1989: 260-1, 267] and [1989b 156-
57], Reeve [1989: 182], Armleder [1966: 46], and Strycker and Slings [1994: 216-7].
Roochnik [1985, 219-20] concludes that Socrates willfully offers his audience a bad
argument with the intent of duping the less-philosophical among them in order to comfort
them (falsely, it seems).
5
My allies in principle are McPherran [1996] and Rudebusch [1999]. The details and
extent of our differences will become clear in the course of the paper.
11
And how is this not the most blameworthy ignorance to
believe one knows what one does not know? On this point
In other words, Socrates suspects that he is wiser than his fellow death-fearing citizens
However, in his parting speech to those who voted to acquit him, it seems he
reneges on his claim of ignorance by arguing that death is a benefit. First, he reflects on
the silence of his spiritual guide, or daimonion, in the proceedings that have led to his
death sentence:7
6
τὸ
γάρ
τοι
θάνατον
δεδιέναι,
ὦ
ἄνδρες,
οὐδὲν
ἄλλο
ἐστὶν
ἢ
δοκεῖν
σοφὸν
εἶναι
μὴ
ὄντα·
δοκεῖν
γὰρ
εἰδέναι
ἐστὶν
ἃ
οὐκ
οἶδεν.
οἶδε
μὲν
γὰρ
οὐδεὶς
τὸν
θάνατον
οὐδ
εἰ
τυγχάνει
τῷ
ἀνθρώπῳ
πάντων
μέγιστον
ὂν
τῶν
ἀγαθῶν,
δεδίασι
δ
ὡς
εὖ
εἰδότες
ὅτι
μέγιστον
τῶν
κακῶν
ἐστι.
καίτοι
πῶς
οὐκ
ἀμαθία
ἐστὶν
αὕτη
ἡ
ἐπονείδιστος,
ἡ
τοῦ
οἴεσθαι
εἰδέναι
ἃ
οὐκ
οἶδεν;
ἐγὼ
δ ,
ὦ
ἄνδρες,
τούτῳ
καὶ
ἐνταῦθα
ἴσως
διαφέρω
τῶν
πολλῶν
ἀνθρώπων,
καὶ
εἰ
δή
τῳ
σοφώτερός
του
φαίην
εἶναι,
τούτῳ
ἄν,
ὅτι
οὐκ
εἰδὼς
ἱκανῶς
περὶ
τῶν
ἐν
Ἅιδου
οὕτω
καὶ
οἴομαι
οὐκ
εἰδέναι·
7
There is no easy way to deal with the daimonion, but the fact is that, whatever it is, it
plays an essential role in Socratic ethics and piety. I am not wedded to any particular
conception of the daimonion, so long as the basic details remain: with respect to morality,
it has an evaluative component, and Socrates considers its evaluations to be true and
thereby action-guiding. For a sustained treatment of the daimonion and Plato’s reliance
on other sorts of religious divination, see Vlastos [1999], especially “Socratic Piety,” and
the special issue of Apeiron, 48/2 [2005].
12
This thing that has happened to me is likely to be a good
With this conclusion in hand, Socrates offers his audience the “Two Things Argument,”
in which he contends that regardless of what happens when one dies, death will be a
far from claiming ignorance about the value of death, and it would seem that he is
and his changing predicament. I contend that both arguments should be read as
prudential in nature, meant to explain and justify Socrates’ dedication to choosing justice
8
κινδυνεύει
γάρ
μοι
τὸ
συμβεβηκὸς
τοῦτο
ἀγαθὸν
γεγονέναι,
καὶ
οὐκ
ἔσθ
ὅπως
ἡμεῖς
ὀρθῶς
ὑπολαμβάνομεν,
ὅσοι
οἰόμεθα
κακὸν
εἶναι
τὸ
τεθνάναι.
μέγα
μοι
τεκμήριον
τούτου
γέγονεν·
οὐ
γὰρ
ἔσθ
ὅπως
οὐκ
ἠναντιώθη
ἄν
μοι
τὸ
εἰωθὸς
σημεῖον,
εἰ
μή
τι
ἔμελλον
ἐγὼ
ἀγαθὸν
πράξειν.
There are some who would contest my translation of τεκµήριον as proof (cf. Strycker and
Slings [1994: 383] and Vlastos [1991: 283-4n2]). I side with Brickhouse and Smith
[1989: 237] and McPherran [1996: 255]. For the most part, those who want to downplay
the strength of τεκμήριον
do so because they prefer that Socrates have a confidence that
depends upon a transparant, rational argument, or they seek to lessen his confidence in
order to save him from a breach of epistemic modesty. As I argue that the strength of the
daimonic warrant gives Socrates the right to breach his earlier epistemic modesty, I am
content to render what I take to be appropriate power to his epistemic confidence.
Regarding the role of the daimonion, see n.3.
13
at the risk of death.9 The first is a prudential argument to the effect that it is best for one
to choose justice when doing so puts one at risk of death, even if one does not know
whether death is beneficial. Death is the better bet. The second argument follows three
marked changes in Socrates’ circumstances. First, instead of risking death, he faces it.
Second, he directs his statements to a smaller audience that is composed of those who
voted to acquit him. Third, he has new evidence from his daimonion. His new
circumstances and new evidence enable him to argue that if one faces death as a result of
consistently just action, even though one does not know the nature of death (annihilation
vs. immortality), one can see death as a benefit. Choosing justice gives one the
advantage of facing death confidently, while choosing injustice does not. For Socrates,
acquiring and acting in light of reasonable attitudes towards death makes one less anxious
must know that death is a harm. Since no one has sufficient knowledge that death is
harmful, no one is justifiably afraid. However, knowledge that death is a benefit is also
unattainable. If death were a benefit, especially if it were the “greatest of benefits,” then
one might justifiably look forward to death, as one looks forward to receiving tenure or
finishing the day with a tumbler of whisky. According to Socrates’ argument, though, we
are not entitled to make any claim about what death is or whether it is good for us. To
9
This prudential interpretation is dismissed by Rudebusch [1999: 66].
14
believe that we can make such claims, and that such claims are the justifiable bases for
Though one might think that Socrates aims to convince the jurors that they should
not fear death, this cannot be his aim. If it were, his argument would be a dreadful failure
for two reasons. First, for Socrates, fear is the anticipation of harm; people fear those
things they believe to be future harms.11 To convince his audience that their fear of death
is unjustified, Socrates needs to convince them that death is not a harm. However,
Socrates insists that no one knows or can know whether death is a harm or a benefit. The
only way he could convince the jurors that they have no reason to fear death is to prove to
them something that would undermine his claim of ignorance. Socrates is not, one hopes,
Second, the jurors may heartily admit their uncertainty about whether death is a
harm, yet consider this uncertainty further reason to fear and avoid death. Given a choice
between certain and uncertain results, if I place high value on the certain results (life is
overall pretty good), and have no desire to discover the uncertain results (death is
possibly very bad), I may have little desire to venture into the unknown. When the loss
of life is at stake, risk aversion generally passes for prudence. If you tell me that an
10
Throughout this paper, I treat Socrates as a cognitivist about emotion (in the sense that
emotions depend on judgments), who also believes that one’s judgments about death are
open to revision in light of reasoned argument. This is, I think, in line with the standard
view that in the “Socratic dialogues,” Socrates denies the existence of an irrational part of
the soul that cannot (at least in some instances) be altered via a change in beliefs alone.
11
I use fear and anxiety interchangeably in this discussion, since the Apology does not
necessitate any distinction, but it should not be overlooked that the distinction can be
usefully employed and, I argue elsewhere, is useful when working with later Platonic
works which feature an irrational element of the soul.
15
elective medical procedure might benefit me or it might kill me, it would be strange for
satisfied if I stay alive (i.e. raising my children, finishing my book). If I choose the
Socrates’ argument, then, does not aim to convince his audience not to fear death.
It does, however, challenge the Athenian jurors’ blind assumption that death is harmful,
and, more importantly, it undermines the degree to which they fear it. Though Socrates
consistently refers to his own death as a risk, he thinks others tend to view death not
merely as a risk or a possible harm, but as the “greatest of evils” or the “ultimate risk”
(Ap. 29a9-b1, 34c7, 40a9-b1; cp. Grg. 522de). He thinks this is a grievous mistake. For
if death really were the worst thing that can happen to one, everything else that is bad
pales in comparison. The greater one’s fear of death, then, the greater the injustice one is
willing to commit in order to avoid it. If an agent believes death is the worst thing, even
if she grants that it is indubitably bad to heedlessly kill her enemies, betray her city, or
bribe the jury, then she should prefer to kill, betray, or bribe in order to avoid death.
Such is the ordinary prudence of opting for the lesser evil (cp. Phd. 68d5-9). On this
view, anyone who pursues any number of activities at the risk of death seems perversely
imprudent. This, of course, is exactly the way Socrates seems to his imaginary objector.
If one cannot be certain that death is even a harm, however, much less the greatest
of harms, then the demands of prudence change. Provided an opportunity to avoid death
by betraying her city to the enemy or bribing the jury, it is no longer clear that she should
err on the side of injustice. Before, when her options were to suffer the greatest of evils
16
or do something unjust, injustice was the lesser evil. Now, however, she is certain that
injustice is bad but recognizes her uncertainty about death. In this circumstance, Socrates
avoid something that could be good. He chooses an ethical certainty over a metaphysical
uncertainty.
audience’s conception of what counts as prudent action when death is a risk. Socrates’
numerous anecdotes in which he is forced to decide between justice and risking death
make it clear that he understands the argument’s objective in this way. He introduces the
(32a5-8).12
At the close of his first anecdote, in which he resists the demands of the Council
to unjustly prosecute the generals from the battle of Arginusae for not retrieving the dead,
he reiterates:
…but I thought I should run any risk on the side of the law
and justice rather than join you, for fear of prison or death,
12
ἀκούσατε
δή
μοι
τὰ
συμβεβηκότα,
ἵνα
εἰδῆτε
ὅτι
οὐδ
ἂν
ἑνὶ
ὑπεικάθοιμι
παρὰ
τὸ
δίκαιον
δείσας
θάνατον,
μὴ
ὑπείκων
δὲ
ἀλλὰ
κἂν
ἀπολοίμην.
17
when you were engaged in an unjust course. (32b9-c2).13
In the second anecdote, Socrates is ordered to unjustly deliver Leon of Salamis to the
not fairly crude to say, death is not a concern for me, but
(32d1-d4).14
In later passages, Socrates reiterates the theme. He recognizes that he might save
himself if he resorted to begging for his life by crying and parading his family and friends
before the court. He thinks doing such things is at odds with the justice of the courts, so
he refuses to secure his release from death in that fashion: “but I will do none of these
things, even though I may seem to be running the ultimate risk” (34c5-7).15 And finally,
after he is sentenced to death, he justifies his decision not to beg for his life, saying, “I
did not think it necessary to do anything unfit for a free man because of the danger”
(38e2-3).16 In none of these passages does Socrates deny that death might be harmful.
13
μετὰ
τοῦ
νόμου
καὶ
τοῦ
δικαίου
ᾤμην
μᾶλλόν
με
δεῖν
διακινδυνεύειν
ἢ
μεθ
ὑμῶν
γενέσθαι
μὴ
δίκαια
βουλευομένων,
φοβηθέντα
δεσμὸν
ἢ
θάνατον.
14
τότε
μέντοι
ἐγὼ
οὐ
λόγῳ
ἀλλ
ἔργῳ
αὖ
ἐνεδειξάμην
ὅτι
ἐμοὶ
θανάτου
μὲν
μέλει,
εἰ
μὴ
ἀγροικότερον
ἦν
εἰπεῖν,
οὐδ
ὁτιοῦν,
τοῦ
δὲ
μηδὲν
ἄδικον
μηδ
ἀνόσιον
ἐργάζεσθαι,
τούτου
δὲ
τὸ
πᾶν
μέλει.
15
ἐγὼ
δὲ
οὐδὲν
ἄρα
τούτων
ποιήσω,
καὶ
ταῦτα
κινδυνεύων,
ὡς
ἂν
δόξαιμι,
τὸν
ἔσχατον
κίνδυνον.
16
ἀλλ
οὔτε
τότε
ᾠήθην
δεῖν
ἕνεκα
τοῦ
κινδύνου
πρᾶξαι
οὐδὲν
ἀνελεύθερον
18
III. Beyond Epistemic Modesty?
At the end of the dialogue, however, Socrates is not risking death. The sentence
has been handed down, and he is given no choice but to confront death. He now sheds
his epistemic modesty. Instead of claiming that death is a known unknown, Socrates
argues that it is “something good,” perhaps the greatest benefit. Before, he claimed that
one should not let one’s fear of death outweigh one’s dedication to justice. Now,
Still, I maintain that he is not contradicting himself, nor should a reader resolve
the conflict by lessening Socrates epistemic confidence. He has new evidence and a new
audience. Justice in the face of death is now prudent for another reason. I contend that
his new evidence permits the claim that death is a benefit for the just. It does not warrant
any claims about what happens when one dies, but Socrates does not make any claims of
that sort. Instead, Socrates aims to convince a subset of the jurors that the best way to
deal with death is to do as he has done, to choose justice, because only the just face death
with the same equanimity with which he faces it. The borders of his epistemic limitations
that he risks suffering “what one might think, what is commonly thought to be, the worst
of evils” (40a9-b1).17 Yet his daimonic sign has not opposed any of the actions that have
17
ταυτὶ
ἅ
γε
δὴ
οἰηθείη
ἄν
τις
καὶ
νομίζεται
ἔσχατα
κακῶν
εἶναι·
19
led to his death. Since his daimonion reliably prevents Socrates from doing something
unwise, he concludes that he has done nothing unwise, even though he has brought on his
death sentence. His death must not be a bad thing, so he has no reason to fear it. 18
significantly reduces his audience for his final speech. He directs the earlier argument to
the entirety of the Athenian jury, whereas he now addresses only those who voted to
acquit him, whom he can “rightly call judges” (40a3) and “friends” (40a1). This is no
small point. For instance, when Socrates tells the jurors that “those of us who consider
death to be a bad thing are clearly mistaken” (40b8-c1), there is good reason to interpret
‘those of us’ to refer only to the people Socrates is addressing. 19 Socrates does not say
that it is a mistake for anyone to consider death a bad thing. He says that those who have
acquitted him, whom he has reason to believe are disposed to choose justly, have no
18
There is a sizable literature that seeks to walk a fine line concerning the epistemic
warrant of the daimonion. On the one hand, if it always stops Socrates from doing what
is wrong, then Socrates must know more than he claims to know. At the least, he would
have ready knowledge of what is wrong simply by trying to do it and knowledge of what
is right on the basis of its noninterference. Many, if not all, of his claims to ignorance,
then, would be false or ironic. However, if the daimonion does not always tell Socrates
what is wrong, then it seems he cannot be confident of his conclusions based on daimonic
silence in any particular instance. It could simply be taking the day off. In the case at
hand, then, Socrates would not be entitled to his claim that death is not bad for him.
Brickhouse and Smith [1989: 250-57] argue that the number of unchecked steps required
for Socrates to complete the very complex action of offering a defense provides sufficient
inductive grounds for concluding that his death will not be a bad thing. For them, the
complexity and particularly of Socrates action also prohibits him from generalizing to
other cases; thus, he does not undermine his disavowal of knowledge. Reeve [1989: 181-
2] argues that, though the daimonion might overlook small evils, it would certainly
intervene if Socrates were about to experience “the greatest of evils.”
19
οὐκ
ἔσθ'
ὄπως
ἡμεῖς
ὀρθῶς
ὑπολαμβάνομεν,
ὅσοι
οἰόμεθα
κακὸν
εἶναι
τὸ
τεθνάναι
20
reason to consider death harmful.
While speaking to this audience, then, Socrates claims that death is a benefit, and
he offers two nested arguments. The first is his argument from daimonic silence, and the
second is the “Two Things” argument. I contend that both arguments are of a piece
because Socrates’ evidence from the daimonion is necessary to explain his confidence in
the success of the “two things” argument. So, his increased confidence in the final
speech is tied closely to his changed epistemic standpoint and his new audience, and his
claims about the benefits of death do not contradict the limited confidence of his earlier
discussion.
But I need to do some work to sustain this reading of the later passage. Most
scholars distinguish sharply between Socrates’ appeal to his daimonion and his “Two
Things” argument, and they do not think that both arguments represent Socrates’
considered views.
There are a number of reasons commentators are eager to separate the arguments.
Perhaps the chief argument against generalizing Socrates’ lessons is that the daimonion is
private. Privacy poses two difficulties. First, since the audience has no direct access to
Socrates’ daimonion, they might require more convincing evidence in order to accept
Socrates’ claims about death. Thus, Roochnik contends that “since no one else is privy
to its messages,” the “two things” argument is required in order for “his audience to think
through the situation logically with him.”20 Other commentators are not particularly
concerned with who has access to the daimonion’s prohibitions; they are concerned to
20
Roochnik [1985: 212]; also McPherran [1996: 255].
21
establish only that its lesson, at least in this instance, is restricted to Socrates alone. Thus,
the resounding silence daimonic silence offers Socrates a proof or indication that his own
death will be good, but it has no bearing on whether the death of others will be good.
According to Reeve, since the conclusion applies to Socrates alone, the second argument
is unconnected. It is also less compelling, as Socrates can only offer his audience “good
The second reason the arguments are separated is that, while some have defended
Socrates’ conclusion in the argument from daimonic silence, the “two things” passage
troubles most commentators, and not only because it threatens to cast Socrates into a
contradiction that is the focus of this paper. It is so difficult to render the “two things”
argument respectable that many readers pursue a charitable route by claiming that it is
meant merely as consolation to his sympathetic, distressed audience. In short, they are
willing to cede the failure of the “two things” argument, and they hope to isolate it from
evidently believes that the conclusion to be drawn from his daimonion applies to all those
listening, at least, as I have argued, to those with a penchant for justice. Remember that
the take-home lesson from his daimonion’s silence is that “those of us” who think death
is bad are wrong. Though charity may be the reason motivating some commentators to
scrap the “two things” argument, they do so at the risk of undermining Socrates’ belief
that his first argument applies generally. They swap one brand of charity for another.
21
Strycker [1994: 216-7]; Reeve [1989: 182]; Brickhouse and Smith [1989: 258].
22
Second, the transition from the daimonion argument to the “Two Things
differentiation, I contend this phrase does not do as much work as they might intend.22
Commentators contend that the silence of Socrates’ daimonion provides him with a
“proof” [τεκμήριον] that death will not be bad for him, whereas the “good hope” he
offers his audience is significantly less weighty. However, those who separate the
argument on these grounds need to account for the body of evidence that Socrates
himself, even with his proof in hand, never claims to face death with anything more than
“good hope.” Throughout the Platonic corpus, regardless of the presumed date of the
dialogues, Socrates describes his own attitude towards death as one of “good hope”
[πολλὴ ἐλπις, Phd. 67b8, 70b1; εὔελπις, Phd. 63c5; ἡ ἐλπὶς μεγάλη, Phd. 114c9; μετὰ
22
ἐλπις is a relatively rare word for Plato. He uses some form of ἐλπις about 30 times,
and a majority of the instances refer to some relation a person holds towards death as a
future state. It is unclear, however, how much epistemic strength is involved in Plato’s
conception of “hope.” It is clearly not an idle wish. However, he offers only one
sustained definition of ἐλπις, (L. 1: 644c10-d4), and he uses it to cover all beliefs about
the future [δόξας
μελλόντων]. When one has a belief that something will be bad, one
fears it, and when one has a belief that something will be good, one is “confident,”
“courageous,” or even “without fear.” [θάρος, 1: 644d1]. It is quite bizarre, though, that
both states would be a variety of ἐλπις, and the epistemic strength involved remains
unclear.
23
ἀγαθῆς
ἐλπίδος, Phd. 67c1; μετὰ
καλῆς
ἐλπιίδος, R. 496e2].23 There is reason to think,
then, that in his second argument, he is boarding the same boat as his audience.
Finally, though this may be a bit of a stretch for some readers, there is reason to
think that many in the audience would take seriously the lessons of Socrates’ daimonion
from piety. If we were to follow the wealth of testimony that Socrates was brought up on
charges of impiety at least in part because of the daimonion, then the audience to whom
he is speaking has acquitted him of the charge.24 The daimonion, then, does not conflict
with their established religious beliefs. They need not be Socrates’ followers, they may
not even like him, yet they still might think that he could be some sort of mantic,
especially at the end of his life, when “men prophesy most” (39c2-4). One should by no
means doubt that Athenians believed in prophets, even in the most unlikely form.
Still, those scholars who want to distinguish sharply between Socrates’ two
arguments and downplay his commitment to the “two things” argument have charity on
their side so long as the “two things” argument appears unredeemable. In what follows,
then, I will recast the “two things” argument as a successful prudential argument in light
sound, but I can defend it from the major objections raised by detractors.
23
Though it is not in the mouth of Socrates, the Athenian in Epinomis (973c) notes that a
good person cannot expect much to go well in life, but can, if she has lived well, face
death with “good hope” [καλὴ
δὲ
ἐλπὶς, Epin. 973c6].
24
For evidence that Socrates’ impiety involves or is exhausted by his daimonion, see Ap.
31c8-d2, Euthphr. 3b5-7, and Xenephon’s Apology. Burnet [1924], on the other hand,
believes Socrates is brought up on charges of impiety because of his involvement in the
Orphic cults.
24
The structure of the “two things” argument is simple and formally valid. It begins
with a disjunction: “to be dead is one of two things: either the dead person is nothing and
relocation or the soul from this place here to another place” (40c6-9).25 Socrates next
aims to establish two conditionals, one for each disjunct: (1) if there is no afterlife, then
afterlife, then death will be the greatest benefit (40e6-7). If the disjunctive premise and
the two conditionals are true, then Socrates is entitled to conclude that death will be
Against the disjunctive premise, Roochnik argues that Socrates’ two options are
not exhaustive. When Socrates contends that death is either a dreamless sleep or a
departure for somewhere else, he overlooks options. At the most general level, though, it
should be clear that the disjunction holds: there is an afterlife, or there is not. As for the
possibilities Socrates considers, I cannot imagine what the absence of an afterlife would
be except the absence of perception, so I consider him safe on that score. However, there
These problems threaten not the disjunctive premise itself so much as the second
conditional that assumes the afterlife is a benefit. Roochnik suggests that, far from being
good, the afterlife could consist in pushing rocks up hills or having one’s liver eaten daily
25
δυοῖν
γὰρ
θάτερόν
ἐστιν
τὸ
τεθνάναι·
ἢ
γὰρ
οἷον
μηδὲν
εἶναι
μηδὲ
αἴσθησιν
μηδεμίαν
μηδενὸς
ἔχειν
τὸν
τεθνεῶτα,
ἢ
κατὰ
τὰ
λεγόμενα
μεταβολή
τις
τυγχάνει
οὖσα
καὶ
μετοίκησις
τῇ
ψυχῇ
τοῦ
τόπου
τοῦ
ἐνθένδε
εἰς
ἄλλον
τόπον.
25
by vultures.26 Indeed, the possibilities are endless. Setting aside the details, why should
Socrates, I argue, assumes the afterlife will be good because to think otherwise
would be at odds with his conception of piety. If there are gods, they are good by
definition, and that is his guiding constraint. In addition, he believes that he is addressing
the limited audience of the ostensibly pious, and thus, he likely believes that they agree.27
Socrates believes, then, that the gods would not force a good person to have her liver
eaten over and over by vultures. It is an unresolved and troubling question whether
Socrates believes these might be worries for an unjust person, and I will address that
worry below. However, Socrates clearly does not believe the afterlife would be unjust
and heedlessly cruel. So, although this conditional premise is not unassailable, Socrates
has good reason to accept it, and his limited audience could hardly deny it except by
making wholesale changes in their core commitments to the goodness of the gods.
something like “a dreamless sleep,” then death is a benefit. Socrates here draws on a
26
Roochnik, 213
27
There is some concern that jury members who accept a number of traditional myths
might be unable to believe the gods are good or just. The myths that are at the center of
Greek religion include tales of gods harming humans for spite or fun. Presumably,
however, Socrates thinks the acceptance of these stories is at odds with more central
beliefs that the gods are good. Think, for instance, of the trouble Euthyphro makes for
himself. If I am correct that for Socrates, pious beliefs are integral in facing death
fearlessly, then he believes no one will gain the appropriate attitudes toward death
without resolving this tension. Those who believe the stories of the gods acting unjustly
cannot properly rid themselves of the fear of death.
26
traditional conception of “the slumber of death,”28 and he says,
putting the other nights and days of his life next to that
night, he had to inquire and say how many nights and days
that not only a private citizen but also the Great King
night (40c10-e30).29
The problem with this argument concerns the relationship between pleasure and
28
Both Homer and Hesiod use the word ‘slumber’ [ὕπνος] to describe death. (See Il. XI
and Hesiod fr. 160). In Hesiod’s Theogony, Sleep and Death are twins born of Night. In
the Iliad, these twins carry Sarpedon’s body off at the behest of Zeus.
29
καὶ
εἴτε
δὴ
μηδεμία
αἴσθησίς
ἐστιν
ἀλλ
οἷον
ὕπνος
ἐπειδάν
τις
καθεύδων
μηδ
ὄναρ
μηδὲν
ὁρᾷ,
θαυμάσιον
κέρδος
ἂν
εἴη
ὁ
θάνατος̶ἐγὼ
γὰρ
ἂν
οἶμαι,
εἴ
τινα
ἐκλεξάμενον
δέοι
ταύτην
τὴν
νύκτα
ἐν
ᾗ
οὕτω
κατέδαρθεν
ὥστε
μηδὲ
ὄναρ
ἰδεῖν,
καὶ
τὰς
ἄλλας
νύκτας
τε
καὶ
ἡμέρας
τὰς
τοῦ
βίου
τοῦ
ἑαυτοῦ
ἀντιπαραθέντα
ταύτῃ
τῇ
νυκτὶ
δέοι
σκεψάμενον
εἰπεῖν
πόσας
ἄμεινον
καὶ
ἥδιον
ἡμέρας
καὶ
νύκτας
ταύτης
τῆς
νυκτὸς
βεβίωκεν
ἐν
τῷ
ἑαυτοῦ
βίῳ,
οἶμαι
ἂν
μὴ
ὅτι
ἰδιώτην
τινά,
ἀλλὰ
τὸν
μέγαν
βασιλέα
εὐαριθμήτους
ἂν
εὑρεῖν
αὐτὸν
ταύτας
πρὸς
τὰς
ἄλλας
ἡμέρας
καὶ
νύκτας̶εἰ
οὖν
τοιοῦτον
ὁ
θάνατός
ἐστιν,
κέρδος
ἔγωγε
λέγω·
καὶ
γὰρ
οὐδὲν
πλείων
ὁ
πᾶς
χρόνος
φαίνεται
οὕτω
δὴ
εἶναι
ἢ
μία
νύξ.
27
perception. It is somewhat standard fare that pleasure requires perception, when
like a dreamless sleep, and a dreamless sleep entails the absence of perception, then it
cannot be pleasant.30 It would seem that if Socrates is to argue that the lack of perception
George Rudebusch steps in to offer Socrates a new variety of pleasure that does
not depend upon perception. He imports an Aristotelian distinction between two types of
pleasures, “modal” and “sensate” pleasures. The pleasures that would render Socrates’
Rudebusch grants, then, that dreamless sleep cannot be pleasant in this sense. “Modal”
pleasures, on the other hand, are pleasures that are not experienced in particular
instances; rather, they “happen in a certain way.” Marks of this sort of pleasure include
activities that (1) “are done or happen effortlessly or without boredom, or (2) are
His key example of a “modal” pleasure is borrowed from Gilbert Ryle and
involves a golfer who spends the day on the course. Though the golfer may experience a
number of “sensate” pleasures during his game (for instance, when he sinks a difficult
30
The claim that pleasure and pain require perception is the chief premise in Epicurus’
argument that death is nothing to fear. (KD 2, Ep. Men. 124-5). This premise, however,
leads Aristotle to the opposite conclusion, namely that if there is no benefit or harm once
a person is dead, then we have every reason to fear death (EN 3:6: 1115a25-27).
31
Rudebusch [1999: 68].
28
putt), his experience of the game or activity as a whole is a “modal” pleasure. Likewise,
the “modal” pleasure can obtain even if the agent experiences a number of “sensate”
pains (for instance, if his partner were responsible for their loss to some professors from a
different department). In either case, the golfer can experience “modal” pleasure
throughout the course of the game without being aware of the activity as a pleasure, while
supplements Ryle’s example with one of an avid reader of fiction who becomes so
absorbed in her novel that she is “barely aware” of the world around her, perhaps even
Socrates. First, there is scant evidence that Socrates ever recognized such a distinction,
and those ancients who did recognize such a distinction would likely object to
Rudebusch’s use of it. Rudebusch gets his textual evidence for the modal/sensate
pleasure distinction from Aristotle, primarily because neither Socrates nor Plato ever
draws such a distinction. Aristotle himself uses the distinction to talk about two different
kinds of activity, and those familiar with Aristotle’s conception of a life of virtuous
activity must know that Aristotle’s primary example of a life that is not active is a life
One might think, though, that even if Socrates did not intend to speak of “modal
pleasure,” and even if Aristotle would object to sleep as a “modal pleasure,” we should
be in favor of the distinction in order to make the argument work. However, I argue that
32
Ibid. 69-70
29
the distinction is unconvincing as a solution to the problem and that we can get Socrates
out of this puzzle without talking about the pleasures of sleep at all.
Rudebusch makes a convincing case that there are a number of pleasures of which
we are not aware, many of them taking place over a significant expanse of time. It would
“preconscious,” and we might even be willing to grant Rudebusch the idea that some
pleasure to the “sleep of death.” For, in each example of subconscious pleasure offered
by Rudebusch, there is at least the possibility that one could become aware of one’s past
pleasure. One finishes the novel or someone asks whether one enjoyed one’s golf game.
Even in the case of the most subconscious of pleasures, there is the possibility that those
death, however, there is no affirming or denying the status of one’s pleasure. There is not
even the possibility of becoming aware of the pleasure of one’s golf game or novel
reading. In each of Rudebusch’s examples, the agent is conscious, she is just not
new conception of pleasure at all, for I contend that Socrates does not claim that the lack
40e2-3] and that most of one’s days and nights are not better and more pleasant than
being dead. These claims do not require the thought that a dreamless sleep or a state of
30
lacking perception is pleasant. Socrates need only think that most days and nights are
Though this offers a dismal view on the quality of human life, it is not out of tune
with conceptions of the value of life in other Platonic dialogues,34 and it is certainly a fair
representation of the picture painted by the epic poets, tragedians, and historians.35 As
cultural background to this evaluative stance towards life, one can easily go as far back as
Hesiod, but the paradigmatic account of the dismal view is in the first book of Herodotus.
In his famed discussion with Croesus, Solon claims the second happiest life is
exemplified by two brothers, Cleobis and Biton. On the day that they received fame
because of their devotion to their mother, she asked the gods to reward them with
33
The choice of κέρδος here is a bit puzzling, as one might expect ᾽όφελος.
κέρδος is
rarely used by Plato, and almost always in the context of deriding individuals who
organize their lives around external goods—lovers of money or profit. In the corpus, the
great majority of instances appear in the spurious dialogue Hipparchus, in which Socrates
and Hipparchus attempt to define greed. However, in the Gorgias, Socrates and Gorgias
agree that being refuted if one holds a false view is κέρδος (461a), which clearly has
more of a positive, Socratic ring to it.
34
In the Platonic corpus, this dark sentiment is most clearly displayed in the Epinomis, in
which the Athenian claims that life is full of sorrows from beginning to end. That is,
excepting one point in the middle of life in which the pains are “tolerable” [μέτριον,
974a3] for a few people. This rare period, however, is fleeting and followed by old age,
which is the worst of all. No one, he concludes, “would want to come to life again,
unless he happens to be full of childish belief” [ὅστις
μὴ
τυγχάνει
παιδικῆς
δόξης
μεστὸς
ὤν, 974a5-7]. Though the Epinomis is thought to be dubious by some and spurious by
others (see introduction to the dialogue in Cooper’s Complete Works, 16-17), I follow the
arguments for its authenticity offered by A.E. Taylor [1927: 497-8]. One should also not
think this view of life is merely ancient. For a very elegant and very dark contemporary
defense of this view, see Benatar [2006], Better Never to Have Been.
35
I share this reading of Socrates’ claims about the relative pleasure of sleep when
compared with the sorrows of life with McPherran [1996: 257-8].
31
“whatever is best for a man to win”. They were rewarded evening feasting, after which
they fell asleep and never awoke. With this reward, Solon says, “the god showed
thoroughly how much better it is for a man to be dead than alive.”36 The misfortunes of
life make death an advantage. The only life better, according to Solon, is to live a long,
unremarkable life, raise a lot of children, and then die courageously in battle.
Socrates might provide a bit more content to this thought by reflecting on the
painful effects of desires, especially unsatisfied desires. A desire manifests the lack of
some object that is perceived as good, and the lack of the desired object is a sort of pain.
Thus, “the pain of desire.” The more desires one has, the more pain one experiences. In
addition, the more one worries about one’s ability to satisfy those desires in the future,
the greater one’s anxiety. As anxiety, like fear, is another species of pain, one is pained
not only by one’s desire, but also by one’s insecurity about consistently procuring even
the most basic of one’s desires. In sleep, on the other hand, especially dreamless sleep,
one experiences no sense of pain at all, no need for anything. Death, if it were a
dreamless sleep, would be perennially free of desire, thus perennially free of pain and
anxiety (cp. Grg. 492e-494b; Phd. 66b-67b). This removal of pain, then, would itself be
It is true that the amount of pain that desire causes for each individual depends
upon, among other things, the degree to which an individual is temperate. The more
desires she has, the more unfilled desires she is likely to have at any given time; thus, the
more pains she experiences at any given time. On this model of desire, it is advantageous
36
I. 31, trans. Greene [1987]
32
while living to pare down the demands of one’s desires in order to decrease one’s pain,
and there is also reason to limit one’s desires to those that are easily attainable in order to
have more unfulfilled desires than others. Those with wildest and most untamed desires,
like perhaps the King of Persia, may stand to benefit the most from death, for they will be
relieved of the most pain (cp. Phd. 107cd). We can make sense, then, of the idea that
death is better than most of the days of one’s life, regardless of whether one is a common
Thus far, I have defended the first conditional by showing how death as a
dreamless sleep could be construed as beneficial, and I have defended the expected
benefit of the second conditional on grounds of piety. In addition, I contended that once
one recognizes the changes in Socrates’ circumstances, the “two things” argument agrees
with his earlier insistence that no one knows whether death is a harm or a benefit. But it
might nevertheless seem that Socrates flouts his earlier epistemic modesty not by
insisting that death is a benefit for the just—for this, he has the new evidence provided by
his daimonion’s silence—but by insisting that death is a harm for the unjust. Socrates
another place, and if the things that are said are true,
namely that all who have died are there, what greater
33
themselves judges here, and will find those true judges who
It seems that the afterlife brings a desirable change in judges only for those who are just.
“Those who call themselves judges here” and embrace their injustice will not be so keen
on facing Minos and his fellow true judges. Such is the clear implication of Socrates’
words. But how does he have new evidence for this? He has evidence for benefit, not for
First, it is evident that Socrates is committed to the spirit of his sketch of his
afterlife, not to the letter. Socrates’ strings together his conception of the afterlife with a
says “If, though, death is some sort of change from here to another place, and if the things
that are said are true, namely that all who have died are there, what greater blessing could
there be, jurymen?” (40e4-7). His further statements regarding the judgment of just gods
are likewise conditional, as is his notion that he will be able to continue his philosophical
examination of those who claim to know things which they do not know. Socrates does
34
Nevertheless, even if the spirit is all to which we need pay attention, it might be
objected that there is plenty for the unjust to worry about in the spirit alone, and if so,
Socrates oversteps his bounds. In other words, it might be overstating the conditional
nature of Socrates’ picture of the afterlife to think he is not committed to the claim that
someone who is unjust, should the afterlife be just, is in a worse position than someone
who enters the afterlife having lived her life as justly as she could (cp. Phd 107c; Grg.
523a-524b; Tht. 176a-177b). Surely, if the afterlife is ordered and just, there is
something to fear for the unjust in the idea that they could be treated as they deserve.
One might think, as Brickhouse and Smith have argued [1989b], that in the same
way that the King of Persia could stand to benefit most from the removal of the pain
caused by his excessive desires, the unjust who enter the afterlife may stand to benefit the
most from the true justice of the afterlife. If we are to take seriously the solidly Socratic
commitment that just punishment is beneficial to the one receiving the punishment, then
the unjust person stands to benefit quite a lot from the judgment of Minos et. al. (cf. Grg.
525b, 478d-480e).38 It might seem odd, but this could very well commit Socrates to the
idea that the more unjust one is, the more one stands to benefit from just punishment.
The King of Persia, or some other paradigmatically wicked tyrant like Archelaus, benefits
from the cessation of his excessive desires and from whatever corrective treatment might
alter his beliefs and desires in accord with temperance and justice. Thus, Socrates is not
committed to the idea that the unjust are harmed in the afterlife, since they benefit at least
38
The most systematic treatment of Socrates’ claim that punishment benefits the
punished is Mackenzie’s Plato on Punishment [1985].
35
Now, however, we might wonder why Socrates singles out those individuals who
voted for his acquittal when he claims that it is mistake to think death is a bad thing. I
have argued that Socrates chooses a particular audience and that his choice of audience is
crucial for understanding his argument. If everyone stands to benefit from death, and the
unjust may stand to benefit the most, why choose justice over injustice while living? If I
can live recklessly and nevertheless stand to benefit regardless of whether the soul is
I argue that the primary advantage of choosing justice is that regardless of what
death offers, the just can face death without fear, in the same way that Socrates faces
death without fear. The just not only benefit from death, but they are able to see death as
a benefit, at least to some degree. The unjust, on the other hand, even if they too benefit
from death, will be unable to face death fearlessly, and this, I contend, has all sorts of
To illustrate the point, let’s revisit the first prong of the “two things” argument.
Though death removes the pain caused by the King of Persia’s excessive desires, as well
as his anxiety about continuing to secure the objects of those desires, there is reason to
think his unruly desires will leave him with a much greater fear of death than those who
are more temperate. Since the principal aim of his life is to continue securing the objects
of his many desires, he will fear death as the ultimate threat to his ability to obtain those
pleasures. As he takes himself to have more pleasures to lose by dying than others have
to lose, he takes himself to be more justified in fearing death. Death, then, as the
cessation of his ability to achieve the objects of his many, many desires, is a terrible
36
prospect.39 In addition, the tyrant’s ability to secure his pleasures likely increases his
anxiety about death at the hands of others who desire his resources in order to secure the
objects of their own desires. So he fears losing his many pleasures by death, whether that
The second prong of the “two things” argument should cause the unjust individual
even greater consternation, as it is likely that the prospect of punishment is not something
she happily contemplates. If there is an afterlife, despite the Socratic claim that she
might be most improved by just punishment, there is little reason to think she would look
upon any of the variations of the afterlife Socrates might entertain with anything less than
resistance and fear. Simply being rebuked and corrected might cause a wealth of anxiety.
Regardless of the outcome of death, then, the average unjust and intemperate individual
recognizes little reason to think her death will be beneficial and a host of reasons to fear
it.
A significant fear of death, though, causes all sorts of problems. If one assents to
Socrates’ first argument about the fear of death and prudence, then the fear of death
undercuts one’s ability to choose justice when doing so requires that one risk one’s life. If
the unjust and intemperate have a greater fear of death, they will be more likely continue
acting unjustly in order to avoid death. Belief that death is a great harm, if not even the
“the greatest of harms,” makes choosing to act unjustly in order to secure pleasures or
39
The argument that death is bad, as it deprives a person of her many pleasures and
projects, has been recently defended by Nagel [1979] and Williams [1973], but less
recently by Aristotle (EN 3:9: 1117b). Those who do not believe this is a reason to think
death is bad include Rosenbaum [1986, 1989], Nussbaum [1994], Epicurus, and now, it
seems, Plato.
37
safety seem the best option. Choosing injustice, in turn, makes death more fearsome by
introducing a feedback mechanism. The fear of death motivates one to choose injustice,
but choosing injustice increases one’s fear of death. Most importantly, since anxiety
indubitably compromises one’s ability to live a good life, and the unjust and intemperate
will be rife with anxiety, they have greatly diminished their chances for living a good life.
Those who choose to act justly, on the other hand, gain two advantages. They are
better able to face death confidently, and because of this, they are better able to
consistently choose justice at the risk of death. Their ability to choose justice in the face
of death institutes a feedback mechanism that helps undercut the fear of death. The just,
then, can face death with the same equanimity with which Socrates faces death. Most
seems that the just individual is better off in life regardless of whether death is the loss of
perception or holds the promise of an afterlife. She acknowledges the relative benefits of
However, a final objection to Socrates’ argument remains: why does Socrates not
consider the possibility of an afterlife in which none of the “things that are said” are true,
an afterlife in which there is no justice, no gods, or in which the gods torment the just
exactly as they are tormented by the unjust in this life?40 If this were the case, there
40
Rudebusch responds to this objection by arguing that Socrates need not be committed
to the justice of the afterlife. Even if the afterlife is not just, the good man will still be
fine because Socrates believes “no harm can come to a good man.” Thus, if the afterlife
is filled with pain, the good man will experience “no harm.” It is difficult to believe this
is what Socrates intends, though, when he contends the afterlife is a great benefit. One
might doubt that surviving a host of torments, even if the good man may do so with
aplomb, would be that great a benefit.
38
would be reason for everyone, just or unjust, to fear the afterlife. It should be clear now
that the answer must be the same as it was to Roochnik’s objection to the disjunction.
Any sketch of the afterlife would be acceptable insofar as it did not deviate from
Socrates’ pious commitment to the goodness of the gods, a commitment he believes his
audience shares. If there is an afterlife, then justice will reign there, as it does not in
Athens, primarily because the gods rule justly, and the gods rule the afterlife.
Socrates’ commitment to piety is in fact the chord that runs through both passages
concerning the fear of death, as neither argument gets off the ground if the gods are
patently unjust. As I have argued, the justice of the gods is a necessary assumption
driving Socrates’ conception of the afterlife in the “two things” argument. It is clear,
though, that the first argument must depend on an implicit commitment about the gods as
well. For the fear arising from the uncertainty of death could very well override the call
to justice if there were not good reason to think that it is the gods who require one to act
justly, and that what the gods require is what is best. Socrates makes this explicit
immediately after he insists on his ignorance about death, for he adds, by way of contrast,
“I do know that this is unjust and shameful, to do what is unjust and to disobey one’s
superior, whether god or human” (29b6-7).41 It may be that the gods require one to act
justly without a reward, and that doing so may get one killed. It cannot, however, be that
the gods call on one to act in accordance with virtue because they want to torment
41
τὸ
δὲ
ἀδικεῖν
καὶ
ἀπειθεῖν
τῷ
βελτίονι
καὶ
θεῷ
καὶ
ἀνθρώπῳ,
ὅτι
κακὸν
καὶ
αἰσχρόν
ἐστιν
οἶδα.
39
In conclusion, I contend that the upshot of Socrates’ arguments is that those who
choose injustice cause themselves a wealth of anxiety in the course of their life and in the
what is fearful, with the result that they do themselves a great deal of psychological harm.
The fact that acting unjustly is self-harm is perhaps the most paradigmatically Socratic of
claims, and in this instance, Socrates argues that unjust individuals harm themselves by
increasing their fear of death exponentially. On the other hand, those who choose justice
live less anxious, less painful lives, and they have reason to see death as a benefit. For
40
CHAPTER TWO
In the previous chapter, I argued that Socrates aims to convince the jury that they
should always risk death rather than commit an unjust act. In this chapter, though, I
contend that Socrates recognizes that his arguments run up against two extremely
powerful human desires that must remain unsatisfied if one intends to control one’s fear
of death in the way he recommends. First, one cannot satisfy a desire for physical safety
and protection from unjust violence, either for oneself or for those one loves. Second,
one must avoid forming strong emotional attachments to people and projects, since
nothing human has true value, and attachments increase one’s fear of death.
These two desires share a common denominator, since both illustrate a link
between external goods and the fear of death. First, security is an external good, and the
desire for security against a violent death is arguably the most basic manifestation of the
fear of death. Since gaining security often depends on acquiring other external goods
(money, allies, walls, and weapons), the desire for security can be readily linked to the
desire for many other external goods as well. Second, both desires indicate the human
relationships and life projects. The desire to ensure safety for those one loves and the
desire to stay alive long enough to enjoy relationships and complete projects increase the
fear of death, since death threatens to deprive one of all external goods irreparably.
41
First, then, I show that the desire for security and protection from unjust violence
is indeed a concern for Socrates in the Apology and that he believes certain external
goods are conducive to providing security from unjust violence. However, he also thinks
that obtaining these goods of security and protection requires injustice, and I offer an
account of why he likely believes this is the case. Since Socrates refuses to commit
injustice, he admits that he has left himself and his family without sufficient defense
However, in the third section, I note that Socrates thinks that some external goods
having a family do not generally necessitate unjust actions. Nevertheless, I argue that
Socrates thinks emotional attachment to these relationships increases the fear of death,
which then increases the temptation act unjustly in order to avoid losing the relationship
at death. During the course of his defense, Socrates expresses disdain for such people,
since committing even a minor injustice is, again, worse than acting in a way that permits
In the final section, I argue that leaving their desires for security and for personal
attachments intentionally unsatisfied will be impossible for most, if not all, of Socrates’
audience. These desires are too powerful to ignore without extreme difficulty, and, more
importantly, it remains unclear that they are best eliminated. If Socrates thinks one must
fight them in order to convince oneself that risking death is better than a minor injustice
and that death is even a benefit, then some people may quite reasonably prefer to engage
42
SECURITY AND EXTERNAL GOODS
In this section, I marshal the textual evidence that indicates that Socrates links the
fear of death and the desire for security. I highlight passages in which Socrates claims
that the pursuit of a certain class of scarce and competitive external goods is conducive to
protection against death, and I tease out his three basic commitments:
requires injustice.
injustice.
Given (C2), those invested in staying alive have a vested interest in procuring some
external goods, and fast. The problem for Socrates, who might otherwise prefer to stay
alive, is posed by (C1) and (C3); one cannot acquire and use external goods to avoid
death without injustice. One must be willing to commit injustice to acquire goods one
needs for protection, and one must be willing to use external goods unjustly in order to
stay alive. An individual who insists on justice, then, must avoid the pursuit of protective
external goods and prepare to be killed. I argue, then, that Socrates believes a certain
class of external goods, in particular goods that are scarce and competitive, is off-limits to
anyone who wants to be just, and that same class of external goods is desirable to those
43
(C1)
In the course of his defense, Socrates repeatedly justifies his lack of political
involvement and his disinterest in pursuing economic and social gain. He claims, in short,
that if he had pursued external goods, he would have long been dead. Since he is a “good
pursued external goods without being killed. Given that he addresses a body of people
who have pursued those external goods without as yet meeting a bad end, his self-
assessment suggests he does not consider his audience particularly good or honest.
Socrates fails to endear himself to the jury in many ways, but one might think this a
Three passages show that Socrates believes attempts to gain external goods justly
would eventually result in an unjust death. The first passage is one of the most famous in
the dialogue. Having just reminded the jury that he has a “divine sign,” which he claims
has prohibited him from taking part in public affairs, he provides a rationale for the
daimonion’s prohibition:
For know well, men of Athens, that if I had long ago tried
44
either you or any other crowd and prevents many unjust
himself from death for a little time, to live a private life, not
Socrates does not think his daimonion’s prohibition against political action applies to
himself alone. First, Socrates does not believe he would survive, but he also does not
think any other human being would survive under similar political circumstances. Second,
he allows that others might be “really fighting for justice,” and he believes they, too,
would meet the same end if they sought political influence. The lesson of the daimonion
is that anyone who refuses to commit injustice or to sit idly by while others commit
Socrates follows this claim with a few examples of his dedication to justice despite
the risk of death. The first anecdote concerns his refusal to try the generals from the
battle of Arguinusae, and the second anecdote narrates his refusal to deliver Leon of
Salamis to his death at the hands of the Thirty. Both anecdotes featured in the previous
chapter, but what matters for the moment is the conclusion he draws as a result of the
42
εὖ
γὰρ
ἴστε,
ὦ
ἄνδρες
Ἀθηναῖοι,
εἰ
ἐγὼ
πάλαι
ἐπεχείρησα
πράττειν
τὰ
πολιτικὰ
πράγματα,
πάλαι
ἂν
ἀπολώλη
καὶ
οὔτ
ἂν
ὑμᾶς
ὠφελήκη
οὐδὲν
οὔτ
ἂν
ἐμαυτόν.
καί
μοι
μὴ
ἄχθεσθε
λέγοντι
τἀληθῆ·οὐ
γὰρ
ἔστιν
ὅστις
ἀνθρώπων
σωθήσεται
οὔτε
ὑμῖν
οὔτε
ἄλλῳ
πλήθει
οὐδενὶ
γνησίως
ἐναντιούμενος
καὶ
διακωλύων
πολλὰ
ἄδικα
καὶ
παράνομα
ἐν
τῇ
πόλει
γίγνεσθαι,
ἀλλ
ἀναγκαῖόν
ἐστι
τὸν
τῷ
ὄντι
μαχούμενον
ὑπὲρ
τοῦ
δικαίου,
καὶ
εἰ
μέλλει
ὀλίγον
χρόνον
σωθήσεσθαι,
ἰδιωτεύειν
ἀλλὰ
μὴ
δημοσιεύειν.
45
anecdotes. Specifically, he reiterates his claim that any person who aims to be just cannot
(32e2-33a1).43
These passages demonstrate that Socrates believes any effort to pursue political power or
engage in political affairs justly would result in his death and the death of anyone else like
him.
Socrates, though, does not think that the pursuit of political influence is the only
external good that would lead to his death. Later in the trial, the list of life-threatening
activities increases significantly. After the jury finds Socrates guilty, Meletus requests
that they sentence him to die (36b). Socrates is then called upon, as is customary, to
propose a counter penalty, after which the jury must decide which of the two
43
Ἆρ
οὖν
ἄν
με
οἴεσθε
τοσάδε
ἔτη
διαγενέσθαι
εἰ
ἔπραττον
τὰ
δημόσια,
καὶ
πράττων
ἀξίως
ἀνδρὸς
ἀγαθοῦ
ἐβοήθουν
τοῖς
δικαίοις
καὶ
ὥσπερ
χρὴ
τοῦτο
περὶ
πλείστου
ἐποιούμην;
πολλοῦ
γε
δεῖ,
ὦ
ἄνδρες
Ἀθηναῖοι·
οὐδὲ
γὰρ
ἂν
ἄλλος
ἀνθρώπων
οὐδείς.
46
deliberately not kept quiet during my life and did not care
Thus, Socrates believes someone who pursues external goods justly or honestly can have
little confidence that he will not die at the hands of others. External goods of this sort
include (but are not limited to) political power, military leadership, wealth, maintaining a
What, though, makes Socrates believe that such goods cannot be pursued justly
without risking death? The clearest reason is that a just person will always meet with, in
44
τί
ἄξιός
εἰμι
παθεῖν
ἢ
ἀποτεῖσαι,
ὅτι
μαθὼν
ἐν
τῷ
βίῳ
οὐχ
ἡσυχίαν
ἦγον,
ἀλλ
ἀμελήσας
ὧνπερ
οἱ
πολλοί,
χρηματισμοῦ
τε
καὶ
οἰκονομίας
καὶ
στρατηγιῶν
καὶ
δημηγοριῶν
καὶ
τῶν
ἄλλων
ἀρχῶν
καὶ
συνωμοσιῶν
καὶ
στάσεων
τῶν
ἐν
τῇ
πόλει
γιγνομένων,
ἡγησάμενος
ἐμαυτὸν
τῷ
ὄντι
ἐπιεικέστερον
εἶναι
ἢ
ὥστε
εἰς
ταῦτ
ἰόντα
σῴζεσθαι
I follow Burnet [1924: 154] in the translation of εἰς
ταῦτ'
ἰόντα
σῴζεσθαι as “to have
recourse to them” as opposed to Strycker, who suggests “take to” or “engage in.”
Strycker [1994: 153] objects to Burnet’s rendering, claiming that “Socrates dos not mean
that he is too honest to have recourse to either economic or political activities in order to
remain safe, as if such pursuits were a means to an end, namely safety; they are ends in
themselves.” This, I think, begs the question. That they can be ends in themselves does
not mean that they are not often pursued for instrumental purposes, and Burnet is right to
point out that some of these items, especially “political clubs and factions,” have an
express purpose of helping one escape prosecution and death.
47
Strycker’s words, “unscrupulous adversaries.” 45 This is inevitable, I argue, because
goods like power and money are scarce and competitive, so one must be willing and
prepared to commit injustice to get one’s share. When resources are limited, someone
who refuses to use deadly force is defenseless against someone willing to shed some blood
if necessary. Those who pursue competitive external goods will inevitably be required to
commit injustice simply to protect themselves from unjust competitors. Even individuals
who succeed in procuring external goods without committing injustice will have trouble
(C2)
Not only can the just pursuit of such goods lead to death, but lacking them also
leaves one prey to unjust violence. It does not require a reconstruction of the mores and
goods increases one’s ability to escape threatening jams. People with money and allies
can use those external goods to escape death or punishment. Money still pays lawyers’
45
Strycker [1994: 368].
46
Strycker claims that there is no evidence that it would be difficult to avoid death as a
just businessman in Athens [1994: 368]. However, I think that the presence of
“unscrupulous adversaries” is just as likely in business as in the political arena. And
protecting one’s money would likely require injustice, since people like rich foreigners
had a tendency to end up dead with their fortunes confiscated.
48
fees, power can get one’s son out of combat, and the temptation to bribe judges and
Socrates lacks these resources, and he makes sure everyone present knows it. He
begins his defense by admitting that he lacks the rhetorical ability possessed by his
accusers (17b). In fact, on a literal reading of the passage, he claims never to have even
visited a law court, a place where oratorical ability is the coin of the realm (17d).47 Since
gaining and exercising oratorical skill is a skill of the political arena, his lack of experience
no doubt tracks his belief that political involvement would prove lethal. Socrates grants
that proficiency in oratory would offer him an advantage, as orators are much more likely
to secure an acquittal for the falsely accused. In fact, guilt and innocence need not concern
a true orator, since the distinguishing mark of an excellent orator is his ability to argue
external good of public speaking and cares more for truth than style, is at a much greater
47
As Burnet [1924: 73] rightly notes, “this is not be taken too seriously.” Brickhouse and
Smith object that Socrates must have visited a law court, if only because he later says he
has seen other people parade their children before the court in order to secure their
acquittal [1989: 49-59]. I see no reason to insist on anything stronger than that he has
never practiced what he is currently doing. One might suppose he has at least been called
up for jury duty. Yet those who prefer a Socrates who is never “ironic” must explain this
away.
48
A key theme in Socrates’ discussion with Callicles in the Gorgias is Socrates’ inability
to protect himself from unjust violence due to his refusal to, among other things, practice
oratory. Callicles repeatedly insists that this is a failure of prudence, while Socrates
repeatedly insists that avoiding injustice is far more important than securing one’s life
(see esp. Grg. 508c-509c, 511b-d, 521b-e).
49
risk of being killed unjustly, and he knows it. 49
Money is another external good that would be helpful for saving Socrates’ life.
By the standards of an Athenian citizen, though, Socrates was poor, and he admits this
quite openly (31c, 36d). For example, he offers his poverty as evidence against his
accusers’ claim that he takes money from the young men who study with him (31c). As
Though one mina is not a ludicrously small amount of money, it is nevertheless woefully
49
I was asked at one point whether rhetorical skill qualifies as an external good. There is
a sense in which it is not, since it is not an object or person that is external to the
possessor of the skill. However, if education is an external good, then an education in
rhetoric is an external good. Or, if an external good is something that is only good when
used by a virtuous person, then rhetorical skill is an external good. Perhaps my best reply
is to borrow the rhetorical response to the question offered by a classicist friend of mine:
“Is a gun an external good?”
50
εἰ
μὲν
γὰρ
ἦν
μοι
χρήματα,
ἐτιμησάμην
ἂν
χρημάτων
ὅσα
ἔμελλον
ἐκτείσειν,
οὐδὲν
γὰρ
ἂν
ἐβλάβην·
νῦν
δὲ
οὐ
γὰρ
ἔστιν,
εἰ
μὴ
ἄρα
ὅσον
ἂν
ἐγὼ
δυναίμην
ἐκτεῖσαι,
τοσούτου
βούλεσθέ
μοι
τιμῆσαι.
ἴσως
δ
ἂν
δυναίμην
ἐκτεῖσαι
ὑμῖν
που
μνᾶν
ἀργυρίου·
τοσούτου
οὖν
τιμῶμαι.
50
insufficient to placate the jurors.51 Granted, a fine of one mina is less ridiculous than his
εὐεργέτῃ, 36d4; cp. R. 5:465d]. However, it is still only a fraction of the amount that
might be a reasonable alternative to the death penalty. Both proposals—free meals at the
public expense or a paltry fine—highlight Socrates’ belief that the life he leads is
incongruous with making and possessing wealth. Without money, though, he again finds
Thus, Socrates’ lack of political and military power, allies, money, and oratorical
skill leave him prey to unjust violence and with few resources to defend himself.
(C3)
Obviously, Socrates cannot use the goods he does not possess to escape unjust
violence. Some goods, though, are not scarce and competitive, and one need not commit
injustice in order to attain or maintain them. Though Socrates lacks oratorical flair,
power, and money, he does have two external goods that appear on many standard lists
of desirable external goods—friends and family (cf. EN 1:8: 1099b; 1:7: 1097b). He has a
wife, three sons, two of them young, and he reminds the jurors that he is a family man
51
Burnet [1924: 160] cautions against thinking of a mina as the equivalent of £4 in 1924.
Instead, one might appeal to Aristotle to establish that it “was recognized as a fair ransom
for a prisoner of war” (EN 5: 7: 1134b21).
51
(34d3-8). His friendship with and influence over numerous young men is a chief reason
he has been indicted in the first place. Since one can, under most circumstances, have a
family and friends without committing injustice, Socrates lacks principled reason to avoid
pursuing them.
It may seem unclear, though, that family and friends (not factious political allies)
can play a role in the quest to stay secure and avoid unjust violence. Socrates notes
twice, though, that when one is on trial for one’s life, friends and family can be handy for
the jurors, he notes his unwillingness to use his friends and family for advantage, even in
The “ultimate risk” is Socrates’ recurring reference to the risk of death (Ap. 29a9-b1,
52
τάχα
δ
ἄν
τις
ὑμῶν
ἀγανακτήσειεν
ἀναμνησθεὶς
ἑαυτοῦ,
εἰ
ὁ
μὲν
καὶ
ἐλάττω
τουτουῒ
τοῦ
ἀγῶνος
ἀγῶνα
ἀγωνιζόμενος
ἐδεήθη
τε
καὶ
ἱκέτευσε
τοὺς
δικαστὰς
μετὰ
πολλῶν
δακρύων,
παιδία
τε
αὑτοῦ
ἀναβιβασάμενος
ἵνα
ὅτι
μάλιστα
ἐλεηθείη,
καὶ
ἄλλους
τῶν
οἰκείων
καὶ
φίλων
πολλούς,
ἐγὼ
δὲ
οὐδὲν
ἄρα
τούτων
ποιήσω,
καὶ
ταῦτα
κινδυνεύων,
ὡς
ἂν
δόξαιμι,
τὸν
ἔσχατον
κίνδυνον
52
34c7, 40a9-b1; cp. Grg. 522d-e). Many people who stand trial for their life, Socrates
suggests, are willing to use their family to protect themselves from death by arousing pity
for the wife they will widow and the children they will orphan. They hope that the jury
will also pity the accused, who will be deprived of his close personal relationship and
Socrates, though, is not a man of pity or a man who wants pity. Defendents who
attempt to use their children to avoid a death sentence, for Socrates, behave unjustly
because they fear death. He claims that they are a “shame” [αἰσχρὸν, 35a3] and “no
“disgrace”:
Yet I have often seen some who act just like this when on
Socrates echoes this claim when he addresses those who voted to put him to death. He
accuses them of killing him because he refused appeal to their pity, or “to say or do
53
οἵουσπερ
ἐγὼ
πολλάκις
ἑώρακά
τινας
ὅταν
κρίνωνται,
δοκοῦντας
μέν
τι
εἶναι,
θαυμάσια
δὲ
ἐργαζομένους,
ὡς
δεινόν
τι
οἰομένους
πείσεσθαι
εἰ
ἀποθανοῦνται,
ὥσπερ
ἀθανάτων
ἐσομένων
ἂν
ὑμεῖς
αὐτοὺς
μὴ
ἀποκτείνητε·
53
everything necessary to avoid my sentence” (38d4-5).54 They wanted him to see him, he
says, “lamenting and mourning and my other things that are, as I say, unworthy of me,
but that you have been accustomed to hear from others” (38d9-e2).55
These passages may at first suggest that Socrates merely thinks that appeals to
pity are unseemly or shameful rather than that that he condemns them as unjust or
unvirtous in some other respect. However, first, and most simply, one might think it
maybe, but not ashamed. Second, and on textual grounds, Socrates follows his claim that
such displays are shameful with the judgment that they are “not fine or just or pious”
lessen the sentence of anyone because of pity, since to judge on the basis of emotional
encouragement would itself be unjust and impious. Thus, appeals to pity are not only
or obscure the truth, or as placating the jury by offering money in exchange for justice.
He lacks money, and he lacks the requisite oratorical skill, but he does not lack the means
54
δεῖν
ἅπαντα
ποιεῖν
καὶ
λέγειν
ὥστε
ἀποφυγεῖν
τὴν
δίκην
55
θρηνοῦντός
τέ
μου
καὶ
ὀδυρομένου
καὶ
ἄλλα
ποιοῦντος
καὶ
λέγοντος
πολλὰ
καὶ
ἀνάξια
ἐμοῦ,
ὡς
ἐγώ
φημι,
οἷα
δὴ
καὶ
εἴθισθε
ὑμεῖς
τῶν
ἄλλων
ἀκούειν.
54
In the course of his defense, then, Socrates makes a set of claims about his refusal
to gain the means with which he could protect himself and his refusal use his available
goods to fend off an unjust death. This dogged determination to avoid injustice, he thinks,
explains to his audience why he appears so willfully imprudent and so unable to secure
his own safety. In the course of this explanation, he accuses those who protect
In the final section of this chapter, I consider to what extent he can reasonably
expect people to ignore their own physical security and, perhaps more importantly, the
security of their friends and family. One might, for instance, wonder why emotional
appeals in service of a fair verdict are prohibited, even if one concedes the injustice of
emotional appeals in order to secure a false acquittal. A reader should never lose sight of
the possibility that Socrates may not always be a character worth emulating. For now,
though, I set aside the question of protection from unjust or violent death in order to
explore Socrates’ connection between the fear of death and emotional attachment to
external goods.
As I mentioned in the previous section, some external goods are open to those
who refuse to commit injustice. Personal relationships with friends and family, for
instance, are not generally pursued solely for the sake of security. This is not to say that
55
they could not be pursued solely as instrumental to security, like cohorts in a political
faction.56 Children can provide some economic security through their free labor and their
protection when one grows old and weak. Socrates clearly thinks children can be helpful
when on trial for one’s life, at least if one is willing to parade those children through court,
wring one’s hands, and weep. When used for such purposes, children can be remarkably
instrumental to security, and one could theoretically have children for this reason alone.
We tend to think there are some personal relationships that we pursue with an
understanding that they are part of living a good life or because they offer opportunities
for exercising some variety of virtuous behavior (generosity, for instance). Socrates
presumably has children and friends for something like this reason. He does not befriend
Crito and Plato for the sake of security, even if they could be used that way. So, perhaps
he does not think goods pursued from motives other than security contribute to the fear
of death.
children and family with their fear of death in a different way. Strong attachment to any
56
There was a raging Hellenistic debate about friendship. One worry was whether
hedonists like the Epicureans could be friends without one of them abandoning the other
whenever the other became no longer pleasant. So, opponents claimed, Epicureans were
only fair weather friends. On one common reading of the Epicureans, they formed
friendships for the sake of mutual security and stayed friends with people who caused
them displeasure because to abandon these friends would make them insecure in the
future. Many authors, especially Cicero, quite reasonably objected that friendship only
for mutual advantage seems a poor sort of friendship. Evans [2004] has defended it as a
very reasonable way of thinking about friendship.
56
external good breeds the fear of death, because death is the greatest threat to the continued
enjoyment of those things to which one is attached. The greater one’s attachment to the
goods of this life, the more one resents and fears death. If one wants to minimize one’s
fear of death, then, a prescription might be to lessen one’s attachment to relationships and
other external goods. Socrates, it seems, recommends precisely this strategy, not merely
because it is a handy trick for combating the fear of death, but because, I argue, he truly
Think, first, of the defense I offered in Chapter One of the first prong of
Socrates’ claim that a “dreamless sleep” would be better than almost all of the days and
night of one’s life requires the background assumption that life is overall really bad. Life
is full of pain, and death serves as a release from that pain. Some of life’s pain,
presumably, comes from physical suffering and misfortune, but I suggested that the
consistent, daily pain of life must arise from unsatisfied desires for pleasure. An
unsatisfied desire causes pain and anxiety, and the more unsatisfied desires one has at any
given time, the greater the pain. In addition, the desire to continue to satisfy one’s desires
in the future, as well as the worry that one will be unable to satisfy them, increases the
pain. Death, for Socrates, is a release from this pain and worry.
Socrates’ reasoning, then, rests on the assumption that death does not deprive one
of anything of significant, positive value. Instead death frees one from a lot of pain. We
may falsely believe, as the tyrant does, that certain objects of desire have positive value,
and so we may resent and fear death as a deprivation of our ability to enjoy them.
57
Convincing people that their desire for a well-stocked wine cellar and a long life to empty
it is a questionable reason to fear death, though, might be significantly less difficult than
convincing them that they should rid themselves of a desire to establish and maintain
lasting personal relationships that would be cut short by the death of either partner.
Socrates could be correct that human desires are trivial and painful and that life is full of
suffering—but it is worth noting that desires for and attachments to personal relationships
There are four straightforward ways that attachment to relationships can increase
one’s fear of death, two of which concern one’s own death, while the other two concern
the death of those one loves. One can fear one’s own death because it deprives one of the
future enjoyment of relationships, or one can fear one’s own death because of the pain
and grief that it will cause others. This latter fear increases if one has young, dependent
children. However, one can also fear the death of others, both for the deprivation they
will suffer and the pain and grief that one will suffer at their death. Each of these fears
increases the more one values the current and future enjoyment of one’s relationships.
Pity and sympathy are what the paraders of children seek most of all. The accused
understand that no one in the audience would want to be deprived of their children, and
for that reason, they hope to secure acquittal by appeal to the attachments of others. The
jury, they hope, will realize that in similar circumstances, they would also seek pity.
When this wins the defendant an acquittal, it is a large number of people on the jury think
that attachment to one’s children and friends serves as sufficient motivation to avoid
58
death, perhaps even at the cost of unsavory, “womanish,” or less than fully virtuous
behavior.
emotional attachment is not a good reason to fight to stay alive. He does not consider the
loss of his friends and family to be sufficient reason to act unjustly, whether that means
begging for an acquittal against false charges that will end in his unjust death or arranging
to escape prison, both of which were common and relatively minor injustices in Athens at
the time. It is not sufficiently important to him that he continue to enjoy the pleasure of
his friends’ company, or that they continue to enjoy the pleasure of his company.
Other dialogues about the death of Socrates indicate that his friends and family
find this component of Socrates’ refusal to avoid death perplexing and frustrating. In the
Crito, for instance, Crito urges Socrates to consider escape because his continued
livelihood is important to his friends, but more importantly to his children’s care and
support (45c-e). The fact that Socrates will orphan his children especially frustrates
Crito, and he claims that Socrates’ refusal to escape for his children’s sake is “unjust”
[οὐδὲ δίκαιόν, 45c5] and cowardly. Socrates, he thinks, “betrays” [προδιδόνα, 45c9] his
children, since orphans do not fare well. Socrates, however, denies the significance of
59
truth belong to those people who easily put men to death…
Socrates’ friends, Cebes and Simmias, who in the Crito are reported to have come to
Athens with the express purpose of springing Socrates from jail, initiate a discussion of
death in the Phaedo by objecting that Socrates, in their words, “bears leaving us too
So, if the jury does not understand Socrates’ detachment, neither do his friends.
His ability to care more for justice than his continued relationships with his family,
though, is an important factor in his ability to face death fearlessly, and this results in a
difficult tension between the desire to get rid of the fear of death and a Socratic
CONCLUSION
the success of Socrates’ arguments that death is better than injustice depends. I have also
demonstrated the role that Socrates’ acceptance of both of these assumptions plays in his
defense. First, his consistent refusal to commit injustice, whether small or large, explains
why he lacks the resources necessary to protect himself from an unjust prosecution that
57
ἃς
δὲ
σὺ
λέγεις
τὰς
σκέψεις
περί
τε
ἀναλώσεως
χρημάτων
καὶ
δόξης
καὶ
παίδων
τροφῆς,
μὴ
ὡς
ἀληθῶς
ταῦτα,
ὦ
Κρίτων,
σκέμματα
ᾖ
τῶν
ῥᾳδίως
ἀποκτεινύντων
καὶ
ἀναβιωσκομένων
γ
ἄν,
εἰ
οἷοί
τ
ἦσαν,
οὐδενὶ
ξὺν
νῷ,
τούτων
τῶν
πολλῶν.
60
will lead to his death. It has also left him powerless to protect his friends and family
should they find themselves in similar circumstances. His audience, in short, must accept
that even a minor injustice is worse than gaining the means to security against unjust
Second, his audience must accept that the loss of their personal relationships at
death does not count as a significant harm, and that any attachment they form should
never override the call to act justly. They should avoid growing attached to external
goods like projects and people. In order to rid themselves of their fear of death, and
certainly to see death as a benefit, they must believe that death does not deprive them of
anything of value, especially anything of value that outweighs the harm of a minor
injustice.
One might think that it is impossible for humans to live like Socrates, even if it
would make them more just and lessen their fear of death. The desire for protection
against violence may be a good candidate for a hard-wired desire that we share with
animals because we are animals. One might make a similar case for our emotional
attachment to our young. However, unless we are to believe that Socrates is divine,
Socrates intends for his audience to believe that ignoring the desire for security and
avoiding strong attachment to others is possible for a human being sufficiently committed
58
It could be argued that the introductory conditional of this sentence is satisfied.
Socrates may in fact be divine, or rather, his ability to act as he does may be a result of
61
Even if one concedes that such attitudes can stand up to worries about descriptive
plausibility (i.e. it is the case that they are possible to attain for humans), there looms a
normative question. Is it really better for us to adopt this stance? First, one might think,
as Crito does, that protecting oneself for the sake of one’s young overrides the
prohibition against minor injustice. An even stronger argument can be offered in support
probably right that one’s personal relationships do not matter enough to justify a grave
injustice, but what about a request for pity and an attempt to avoid an unfair death that
will orphan one’s children? Second, developing attachments to personal relationships and
life projects may be worth increasing one’s fear of death. Socrates may simply be wrong
that external goods like relationships lack genuine positive value and that the desire to
lessen one’s fear of death is a good reason to convince oneself otherwise. A little fear of
So, the debate issues in an open question: security, attachment, minor injustices,
and some fear of death vs. insecurity, absence of attachment, a pure commitment to
justice, and no fear of death. I presume with some confidence that most non-
philosophers in Socrates’ audience (as well as myself and many of the people I know),
divine dispensation that is not granted to almost anyone else. First, Socrates has a
special, singular daimonion, which suggests that he is dear to the gods. Second, Plato has
Socrates argue in the Republic that only someone with a divine dispensation could be
philosophical in a non-ideal city. Socrates then identifies himself (as well as a few others
with gifts from the gods) as a philosopher in a non-ideal city (R. 6: 496a-e).
59
This, of course, is a stock objection to absolutisms of the Kantian variety.
62
will opt for a little fear of death and a little injustice in exchange for a sense of security
and emotional attachment to goods that are external to them and beyond their control.
down to admirers with a philosophical nature, who may be more willing and able to adopt
a Socratic lifestyle. In the next chapter, then, I consider whether it might be possible for
the young men who want to be like Socrates to eschew security and attachment for the
sake of justice and courage, with the added benefit of getting rid of the fear of death.
More importantly, I consider how the picture changes once philosophical wisdom and a
strong commitment to the immortality of the soul get thrown into the mix.
63
CHAPTER THREE
The Apology and the Phaedo share a mission—convincing the present audience
that they should not fear death. In the Phaedo, Socrates intends to persuade his friends
and, to some extent, himself, that a philosopher should face death confidently, even
eagerly. His young friends, quite naturally, are distressed that he will die before the day
is out, and they are confounded by his own apparent lack of distress. He sets out to
change their attitudes towards death in three steps. First, he offers a conception of the
philosopher such that fearing death is contrary to her nature and desire for wisdom.
Second, he and his two principal interlocutors run through a series of arguments for the
immortality of the soul. Third, mixed among the arguments, he provides a couple of
myths that bolster his belief that death is a benefit for the just and pious. Then he takes
the poison.∗
that I set aside many interesting facets of the dialogue. Thus, I will not address the
strengths and weaknesses of the arguments for immortality, 60 or the role of the theory of
the Forms in Plato’s epistemology and metaphysics, whether in the Phaedo or elsewhere.
∗
All citations in this chapter in which the dialogue is unspecified reference the Phaedo.
60
I find Gallop [1975], Hackforth [1955], and Bostock [1986, 1999] especially helpful
regarding the arguments for immortality in the Phaedo. Bostock and Gallop focus almost
exclusively on the arguments, devoting very little attention to dramatic elements or the
myth.
64
These matters feature in the discussion only insofar as they are instrumental to
determining why Plato thinks people fear death and how he believes they can control it.
In this chapter, I argue for two big-picture theses. First, I contend that in the
Phaedo, Plato argues that everyone, philosophers included, fears death. Philosophers fear
death far less than non-philosophers, but they are not without some recalcitrant fear of
death. This is the case for two reasons: 1) Human beings are embodied creatures, and
bodies are full of fears; 2) the philosopher’s central desire is for wisdom, which will,
Socrates contends, remain forever frustrated unless the soul is immortal. Since
immortality is something of which no one can be certain, the soul suffers anxiety about
never satisfying its central desire. Nevertheless, the philosopher fears death less than the
non-philosopher, since she reduces and controls her body’s fears and has a greater
confidence in the immortality of the soul. Keeping her fear of death in check has a
significant positive impact on her ability to live a good human life, since she lives
Second, I argue that the philosopher uses three strategies to keep her fear of death
in check. Socrates, I contend, not only offers these strategies to his friends, but he
rehearses them through the course of the Phaedo in order to calm himself before he
drinks the hemlock. The first strategy, the adoption of a strong brand of asceticism, aims
to minimize fear given the possibility that the soul is not immortal. The second strategy
depends upon some degree of confidence that the soul is immortal, and the final strategy
tames the remaining, exceptionally recalcitrant fears through myths and stories. Socrates
distances himself from his friends and family, runs through arguments for the soul’s
65
immortality, and offers two eschatological myths. The first strategy, I argue, targets fears
in the body, the second targets a fear in the soul that is specific to philosophers, and the
myths target the residual fears of both the body and the soul.
For Plato, we fear death because we are regrettably embodied. Every human has
a body, and that body ushers in a host of anxieties and attachments, great and small. The
body is the soul’s prison [φρουρᾷ, 62b4; διαδεδεμένην ἐν τῷ σώματι, 82e], and there is
no escape from the body’s needs until death (64c, 67e), since death is, by definition, the
separation of the soul from the body (64c). The body makes “adequately” knowing the
[ἀλήθειάν 65b2; 65b9-11; 66a6] and “real” [τι τῶν ὄντων, 65c2-3, 66a3]. It is always
present, so that “seeing true things is not possible because of it” [ὥστε μὴ δύνασθαι ὑπ
requires that we take time to eat (at least occasionally) and buy clothes and shoes. Its
diseases can keep us from study altogether (66c1-2). Worse, the body is full of needs and
desires, so that “as is said, truly and in reality no thinking at all ever comes to be for us
from the body” (66c2-6).61 The body’s needs and desires are the cause of war within the
61
ἐρώτων
δὲ
καὶ
ἐπιθυμιῶν
καὶ
φόβων
καὶ
εἰδώλων
παντοδαπῶν
καὶ
φλυαρίας
ἐμπίμπλησιν
ἡμᾶς
πολλῆς,
ὥστε
τὸ
λεγόμενον
ὡς
ἀληθῶς
τῷ
ὄντι
ὑπ
αὐτοῦ
οὐδὲ
φρονῆσαι
ἡμῖν
ἐγγίγνεται
οὐδέποτε
οὐδέν.
Burnet
notes
that
τὸ
λεγόμενον,
as
it
often
does,
indicates
that
this
phrase
is
proverbial
(rendered
by
Burnet
as
we
don t
even
get
a
chance
of
thinking
for
it ).
He,
however,
66
city and without (πολέμους
καὶ
στάσεις
καὶ
μάχας), since they “require” (ἀναγκαζόµεθα)
us to seek wealth for their satisfaction. The desire for wealth causes all wars (66c5-d2).62
In short, the body is full of fears and needs, and philosophers have a body.
The worst thing about the body, though, is that it keeps the philosopher from
gaining wisdom, her greatest desire. Socrates, noting the body’s constancy during life,
concludes that human life itself serves as a persistent obstacle to gaining wisdom. He
claims:
cannot
determine
to
what
proverb
Socrates
might
be
referring
[1911:
36].
Geddes
calls
this
an
iteration
of
a
cardinal
principle,
though
he
leaves
it
unclear
whose
cardinal
principle
is
under
discussion
[1885:
33].
The
whole
phrase
is
meant
to
be
emphatic,
though,
especially
with
the
conjunction
of
ὡς
ἀληθῶς
and
τῷ
ὄντι.
Even
if
it
is
proverbial,
then,
it
seems
that
this
does
not
lessen
Socrates
apparent
commitment
to
its
conclusion.
62
In the Republic, soldiers, or “guardians,” only become necessary after the first city is
abandoned for a city that includes luxury goods. When luxury goods are introduced,
Socrates claims that war is inevitable (R. 2: 373e-374a).
67
itself will be by itself apart from the body, and not before.
[66e2-67a2].63
Socrates reiterates that death brings a release from the body and the opportunity to
body, and they desire to have the soul itself by itself, then
63
καὶ
τότε,
ὡς
ἔοικεν,
ἡμῖν
ἔσται
οὗ
ἐπιθυμοῦμέν
τε
καί
φαμεν
ἐρασταὶ
εἶναι,
φρονήσεως,
ἐπειδὰν
τελευτήσωμεν,
ὡς
ὁ
λόγος
σημαίνει,
ζῶσιν
δὲ
οὔ.
εἰ
γὰρ
μὴ
οἷόν
τε
μετὰ
τοῦ
σώματος
μηδὲν
καθαρῶς
γνῶναι,
δυοῖν
θάτερον,
ἢ
οὐδαμοῦ
ἔστιν
κτήσασθαι
τὸ
εἰδέναι
ἢ
τελευτήσασιν·γὰρ
αὐτὴ
καθ
αὑτὴν
ἡ
ψυχὴ
ἔσται
χωρὶς
τοῦ
σώματος,
πρότερον
δ
οὔ.
A third option, of course, is that there is an afterlife in which wisdom remains
unattainable. One might think that Socrates can ignore this possibility for the same
reason that he ignores the possibility of a torturous afterlife at the close of the Apology—
piety rules it out. However, just as in the Apology, Socrates would be epistemically
unjustified in committing himself to details of the afterlife outside of its basic desirablity,
and the afterlife could be desirable in a number of ways that do not include gaining
wisdom. Nevertheless, if the gods are extremely beneficient, they will award
philosophers wisdom, and the afterlife remains the only place philosophers can hope to
attain it. This hope may be sufficient to make philosophers content to die and find out
what happens.
68
released from the company of that with which they have
Socrates concludes that the philosopher should look forward to the afterlife, “for he
believes this intensely—that he will discover wisdom purely no other place but there”
(68a).65
So, Socrates believes full wisdom is unattainable in this life because of the body.
Only in the afterlife will the philosopher be able to gain full wisdom, since only then will
she be completely free the body’s persistent disruptions, desires, and fears. The
philosopher, then, must believe that the soul is immortal if she is to avoid fearing that she
can never attain the thing she most desires. That alone is a significant hurdle to getting
rid of the fear of death. However, dealing with the fear of death requires more than
simply believing in the existence of an afterlife in which the philosopher gets what she
has always wanted. The philosopher must arrange her life in order to be “least” troubled
by fears (67e5-6), so that she can get as “close as possible” to wisdom while she is alive
(65e4, 67a3). She requires, then, strategies to squelch the body’s fears as much as they
can be squelched (64e1, 65a1-2, 65c8, 66a3-5 67a3-4). Obviously, the unruly body that
64
εἰ
γὰρ
διαβέβληνται
μὲν
πανταχῇ
τῷ
σώματι,
αὐτὴν
δὲ
καθ
αὑτὴν
ἐπιθυμοῦσι
τὴν
ψυχὴν
ἔχειν,
τούτου
δὲ
γιγνομένου
εἰ
φοβοῖντο
καὶ
ἀγανακτοῖεν,
οὐ
πολλὴ
ἂν
ἀλογία
εἴη,
εἰ
μὴ
ἅσμενοι
ἐκεῖσε
ἴοιεν,
οἷ
ἀφικομένοις
ἐλπίς
ἐστιν
οὗ
διὰ
βίου
ἤρων
τυχεῖν̶
ἤρων
δὲ
φρονήσεως̶ᾧ
τε
διεβέβληντο,
τούτου
ἀπηλλάχθαι
συνόντος
αὐτοῖς;
65
φρονήσεως
δὲ
ἄρα
τις
τῷ
ὄντι
ἐρῶν,
καὶ
λαβὼν
σφόδρα
τὴν
αὐτὴν
ταύτην
ἐλπίδα,
μηδαμοῦ
ἄλλοθι
ἐντεύξεσθαι
αὐτῇ
ἀξίως
λόγου
ἢ
ἐν
Ἅιδου,
ἀγανακτήσει
τε
ἀποθνῄσκων
καὶ
οὐχ
ἅσμενος
εἶσιν
αὐτόσε;
οἴεσθαί
γε
χρή,
ἐὰν
τῷ
ὄντι
γε
ᾖ,
ὦ
ἑταῖρε,
φιλόσοφος·
σφόδρα
γὰρ
αὐτῷ
ταῦτα
δόξει,
μηδαμοῦ
ἄλλοθι
καθαρῶς
ἐντεύξεσθαι
φρονήσει
ἀλλ
ἢ
ἐκεῖ.
69
Socrates describes cares nothing for theoretical arguments about the immortality of the
Socrates claims that the philosopher manages her fear better than everyone else,
or that she fears death “least” (67e5-6). How, though, does she do it? Socrates’ reply to
Simmias’ final objection to his arguments for immortality is a good place to begin, since
it not only provides evidence that the philosopher best manages, rather than eliminates,
her body’s fears and desires, but it also casts light on the multitude of strategies the
does not depend on the material body by offering a competing theory according to which
the soul is a sort of “harmony” [ἁρμονίας, 85e3] that depends upon the material form of
the thing that produces the harmony. For instance, a harmony might depend upon a lyre,
both its wood and the proper tuning of the lyre’s strings. When the body weakens as a
result of age or sickness, then the strings weaken or break, and the harmony is destroyed.
The wood eventually rots. Since the soul is the harmony, the destruction of the lyre is the
Socrates offers two replies to Simmias’ conception of the soul as a harmony. The
first is an ad hominem that relies on Simmias’ firm belief in the process of recollection.66
66
The Theory of Recollection is introduced in order to show that the soul must have had
a pre-natal existence, since we often learn what seem to be new things by being
“reminded” of things that we must have known before birth (72e-77a). Simmias assents
70
Socrates shows Simmias that he cannot believe both that the soul is a harmony and that
someone else (i.e. most of us) might be willing to ditch recollection in order to maintain
that the soul is a harmony. Thus, Socrates needs an additional argument for those not
terribly convinced by the theory. In his second argument, then, Socrates shows Simmias
that the “harmony conception” cannot account for a few common beliefs about souls. It
cannot account for disagreement within the soul, it cannot account for the idea that some
souls are more or less virtuous, and it entails that one soul can be more or less a soul,
the obvious truth that even the best souls are constantly at war with the body, vigilantly
staving off the body’s desires and fears. Absent opposition of this sort, Socrates claims,
the soul might reasonably be a harmony, but given that the soul is always fighting the
body, it cannot reasonably be a harmony. Instead, as Socrates says, the soul constantly
to the theory very early, but often does not seem to realize what his assent entails. Thus,
he is interested to discover that his earlier assent to Recollection defangs his later
objection. The other dialogue in which Recollection plays the largest role is the
discussion with the slave boy in the Meno (80d-86c), and it also makes an appearance in
the Phaedrus. For discussion of Recollection in the Phaedo, see Gallop [1975] and
Bostock [1986].
71
other times warning them, speaking with them as one to
another (94d1-6).67
Socrates tells Simmias that denying such tension would not only contradict the poets, but
must fight and monitor her body’s emotions in order to do what her soul deems best.
Which strategies are particularly good for dealing with the fear of death, though?
Speaking of the vast number of the emotions and desires of the body, Socrates
and medicine. One, some, or all of these strategies may be useful for combating the fear
of death specifically. If the philosopher recognizes she must minimize her fear of death,
then she needs to determine which strategies are most useful for controlling a fear that
mentioned at the outset, I argue that Socrates uses three strategies, though two of the
strategies depend on confidence that the soul is immortal. Some contemporary readers
are uncomfortable with or hostile to Plato’s discussion of immortality and myth, and they
think Plato should accomplish his philosophical tasks without recourse to stories about
67
ἐναντιουμένη
ὀλίγου
πάντα
διὰ
παντὸς
τοῦ
βίου
καὶ
δεσπόζουσα
πάντας
τρόπους,
τὰ
μὲν
χαλεπώτερον
κολάζουσα
καὶ
μετ
ἀλγηδόνων,
τά
τε
κατὰ
τὴν
γυμναστικὴν
καὶ
τὴν
ἰατρικήν,
τὰ
δὲ
πρᾳότερον,
καὶ
τὰ
μὲν
ἀπειλοῦσα,
τὰ
δὲ
νουθετοῦσα,
ταῖς
ἐπιθυμίαις
καὶ
ὀργαῖς
καὶ
φόβοις
ὡς
ἄλλη
οὖσα
ἄλλῳ
πράγματι
διαλεγομένη;
72
eschatology, then, we should examine and evaluate Socrates’ strategies for combating the
fear of death should the soul turn out to be mortal through and through.
For all of Socrates’ attention to the immortality of the soul in the Phaedo, he has
what seems to be a perfectly good explanation for why philosophers fear death least—
they are ascetics, and ascetics have less to lose by dying. If an individual becomes
attached to her body and the things her body desires, then death threatens to deprive her
of everything she values. This is a grave problem for the non-philosopher. As Bobonich
embodiment.
Since death, regardless of the eternal state of the soul, is the loss of the body, the
non-philosopher has reason to fear the loss of what she loves. The greater her attachment
to the body, the more she stands to lose by death and the greater her fear.
Those who disdain the body, though, among them philosophers, have little reason
to fear the loss of the body at death (67d-e). If an increase in asceticism leads to decrease
in fear, then the philosopher reduces her fear by minimizing her attachment to pleasures.
73
On this reasoning, ascetics have less fear than the power-hungry, sex-obsessed,
gluttonous tyrants. Or, for that matter, than people who want to write a book or go to
Europe next year. Thus, the philosopher should have an advantage over everyone else
So why does Socrates not merely offer his interlocutors an argument for
philosophical asceticism and consider it sufficient to make the philosophers fear death
less than everyone else? First, we should get clear about what kind of asceticism
person completely spurns and deprives herself of as many external goods as possible,
including money and fine food, personal relationships, the pursuit of individual security,
and any desire for social respect and honor. He calls this the “ascetic stance.” On the
second conception, the philosopher does not deprive herself of external goods, but affects
the appropriate philosophical attitude towards her external goods. She affords them no
that is not at odds with engaging in “the usual range of human activities.”68 This, he calls
the “evaluative stance.” Thus, a philosopher can pursue and enjoy personal relationships,
68
Woolf, 100
69
It may be worth considering the following: an unjust person can be an ascetic on either
conception. She may be attached to none of the great wealth she acquired through
injustice, and thereby be an evaluative ascetic. Likewise, she might be an unjust person
who does not pursue goods of the body at all. She may lack the resources, ability, or
even desire to pursue external goods, while remaining a vile and unhappy individual.
74
Woolf argues that Socrates must be advocating the “evaluative stance” as the
philosopher’s way of life. Woolf appeals to the historical Socrates’ own apparent choice
of the “evaluative stance” as supporting evidence. We know, for instance, that Socrates
lived an active life in the city, married and had children, fought in wars, and formed
many friendships with attractive, young men. Therefore, if Socrates serves as the model
ascetic, Plato must recommend the sort of asceticism that allows a person to marry, have
children, and, at least to some extent, get involved in the city’s business. Socrates, then,
does not mean to tell his friends that they should not pursue goods; rather, they should
not develop strong attachments to their goods, such that being deprived of friends, family,
a form of asceticism he has not pursued, and this would undermine his claim to have
or as represented in the Phaedo, is the ideal philosophical ascetic. The ideal human
ascetic, just like the fully wise philosopher, may prove non-existent. Or we might have
good reason to think Socrates has in fact failed to prepare for death as best he could, and
that his involvement in the life of the polis and his family were mistakes.
Woolf says something brief about this: “if someone never indulged in bodily pleasures
but still thought that the material world was reality, one would score no points as a
philosopher” (104). He is surely right that they would not be philosophers, but one might
nevertheless wonder whether they would be able to control their fear of death just as well
as a philosopher. With respect to the fear of death, then, the ascetic stance may not
sufficiently differentiate the philosopher from the non-philosopher.
70
Woolf, 98-100.
75
Woolf is surely right, however, that the philosophical ascetic must pursue some
goods, just as the philosopher must make some use of her deceiving bodily senses. But,
the number of acceptable external goods open to a philosopher may be much smaller than
Woolf suggests, and the strictures of Socrates’ indifference should not be overlooked.
With respect to the asceticism that mitigates the fear of death, I think we should ask three
questions, and the answers to these questions should make some room for both ascetic
stances. First, if asceticism is “preparation for death,” what particular goods must a
philosophical ascetic relinquish in order not to fear death? Perhaps some goods should be
rejected wholesale. Second, does her “evaluative” stance towards the goods she can
pursue (if any) require that she assign no significant positive value to them, so that, for
instance, a philosopher permits herself, but only so long as she remains indifferent to
their continued existence? Finally, to what extent can we expect embodied humans, even
In response to the first question, the philosopher must surely abandon any and all
goods that conflict with the pursuit of wisdom and virtue. Obvious candidates for goods
that conflict with virtue include honor and power won by political intrigue, safety that
requires injustice, and material goods won from unfair gain. One might suppose, though,
that the injustice required to acquire or to maintain many such external goods is
political circumstances, then, it might be possible to gain safety, win honor, or protect
one’s children without injustice. If there were, however, a class of goods that require
76
prohibited to the philosopher. A primary candidate for such a good, one might think, is
money.
One might nevertheless think that goods that can be acquired justly could distract
one from the intense study necessary to gain wisdom. The fact that one can pursue such
goods justly does not entail that they are not at odds with the pursuit of wisdom. For
instance, marrying and having children might fall into this class of goods on some
interpretations of philosophers like Epicurus and Plato. We should not forget that
pursuing wisdom and acting justly might require absolute deprivation and avoidance of
Thus, Woolf’s idea that a philosopher adopts the “evaluative stance” seems right,
with the caveat that she adopts it only towards justly acquired and justly maintained
goods that do not distract her from the pursuit of wisdom. Speculation about how many
goods remain available will likely depend upon political circumstances and the
conception of wisdom at stake. Regardless of whether the historical Socrates pursued all
of his external goods justly, though, and regardless of whether he would prefer upon
reflection to have deprived himself of his wife and children, he clearly adopts the
evaluative stance towards them in the Phaedo—he is not sorry to lose his children,
friends, family, or continued life. This, no doubt, makes it a good bit easier to die.
stance” to Socrates in the Phaedo, we should not lose sight of his extreme indifference to
those few external goods he possesses. His level of emotional detachment frustrates his
friends and family, and could strike readers as surprising, strange, and even unethical.
77
Getting clear on the nature and extent of Socrates’ detachment is important for
considering whether his young interlocutors will be able to adopt it, and to what extent
Socrates’ detachment from his human relationships is evident from the outset of
the prison scene. When his friends arrive in the morning, Socrates banishes his crying
wife and infant son from his presence. Though some, including Hackforth, Burnet, and
Taylor have argued that this is a gentle, caring gesture, meant to save Xanthippe from
further sorrow, it is more likely that Socrates simply finds her a nuisance.71 He later
expresses his distaste for women who cry about the death of their loved ones, shaming his
friends for their own tears, accusing them of engaging in womanly “offensiveness”
[πλημμελοῖεν, 117e1]. They should shape up, since such behavior is “the reason [he]
Socrates, though, also displays an absence of concern about leaving behind his
good friends. Remember that his initial “defense” is a response to Cebes’ quite natural
71
Hackforth, siding with Burnet, casts Socrates’ dismissal of Xanthippe as sympathetic
(33n1). Taylor [1927, 178] calls charges that Socrates’ is uncaring “absurd.” I have
trouble believing that she will cease grieving simply because she has left the prison, so I
am inclined to think Socrates is more concerned to save himself from her grieving.
72
Grief, for Plato, is the purview of women (cf. Ap. 35b, R. 3:387e; 10:605d-e; Phd. 60a-
b,), which is for him very much an insult. Women were often hired to grieve publicly for
the death of those they did not even know (see Pomeroy [1975]). However, men were
also prone to express strong grief, especially in Homeric epic and vicariously when
watching tragic theater. I address grief and the philosopher in the final chapter.
78
63a8-9, cp. Cri. 43b8-10]. In other words, they want him to display a strong enough
attachment to them that he will, at least to some degree, “resent” [ἀγανακτεῖν, 62d4,
62e6] dying. This is not to say that Socrates does not care for the welfare of his friends.73
He wants them to become philosophers, which he considers the best life. He wants them
to adopt a philosophical attitude towards his and their own deaths, which he believes will
be to their benefit. He does his best to comfort them with stories, physical affection, and
arguments. He does not, however, express any regret that he is leaving them, his
Even at the end of the dialogue, by which point Socrates must have told Crito
many, many times about his eagerness to die, Crito again asks Socrates for direction
about how to care for his children (114b). As the day ends, Socrates calls for the poison.
Crito, however, notes that some daylight remains, so that Socrates has plenty of time to
delay his death. Others, Crito says, delay taking the poison in order to “converse with
116e4-5].74 Crito still does not understand that Socrates does not prefer to spend any
additional time with friends when the gods have granted him permission to die. Socrates
declines, claiming that he would not benefit from any more time. He does not consider,
73
Woolf, 104
74
One might be tempted to translate and read this as Crito’s suggestion that Socrates
share a more “biblical” sense of intimacy with his wife or some lover, for instance,
instead of further conversation with his friends. I think that since Socrates had already
sent the women, and since I doubt (but cannot prove, obviously) that he has made a habit
of sexual relations with anyone in the prison, I think it must be Crito’s request that
Socrates delay taking the poison for the sake of those assembled.
79
however, whether Crito, his friends, his children, or his wife would benefit from that
time. In short, Socrates remains perfectly comfortable leaving his children and his
Socrates makes clear that his asceticism is a key reason that he is so calm and
collected about his impending death, and he intends to encourage his audience to
cultivate the same attitudes and detachment. Since his audience wants to be virtuous, and
the fear of death serves as an impediment to virtue, Socrates has given them good reason
to think that minimizing their fear of death through ascetic deprivation and emotional
His hard sell of asceticism, though, has two problems. First, the majority of those
listening to his conversation will likely prove unwilling or unable, whether from
incapacity or unfavorable circumstances, to choose the way of life that enables Socrates
to remain detached. Second, even if they could become philosophical ascetics, they
recognize that deprivation and indifference is a flawed strategy for convincing oneself
that death should not be feared, avoided, and “resented.” The soul, they rightly insist,
must be immortal.
There are three reasons to think that Socrates’ friends will likely fail to adopt
Socrates’ asceticism. First, they have strong personal attachments. In particular, they are
extremely attached to Socrates. In the Crito, Cebes and Simmias have, Crito says, just
arrived in Athens with the funds necessary to spring Socrates from jail, should Socrates
80
feel bad about accepting Crito’s money (45b). No doubt the friends are all still a bit
frustrated that Socrates turned down their offer. When Socrates dies, even if they are
convinced by his arguments for immortality (and I will argue that most of them are not),
their copious weeping suggests that they remain very attached to Socrates. Of course,
they must realize their attachment is not equally reciprocated. Socrates, who accepted no
offers for assistance, would also make no offers should they themselves be falsely
accused. They could also not very well expect Socrates to weep should they be forced by
others to die an unjust death. Socrates, again, is not the sort to grow attached.
Second, his friends cannot quite understand Socrates’ lack of concern for his
children or Xanthippe. This indicates that they would have trouble detaching themselves
from their future children in a similar fashion. True, Socrates expresses confidence that
his friends will take care of his children, and true, Socrates’ commitment to justice may
be the only impediment to protecting his own children and raising them with attention
and care, but his general failure to express any worries or particular concern for the future
welfare of his children consistently baffles his friends. In the Crito, Crito thinks Socrates’
responsibility to care for his children and the unsavory prospect of their fate as orphans
require Socrates’ escape. Socrates disagrees (45d). At the close of the Phaedo, Crito
asks Socrates again for any final advice or guidance on the care of his children. We are
told that he has inquired on the topic a number of times by the fact that Socrates tells him
Powerful familial and political influences provide the third reason that Socrates’
young friends will likely fail to become Socratic ascetics. They will be urged or even
81
required to pursue external goods and protection for their families and the city. The
young men’s desire to protect Socrates from an unjust death indicates a tendency to
protect those for whom they care, and their families and children may need protection in
the future. Unlike Socrates, though, their friends and families will not only accept
assistance, but also expect it. One can reasonably suspect that Simmias would not reject
Cebes’ offer to bribe the guard and escape prison, and Cebes would just as happily offer
So, most, if not all of Socrates’ interlocutors will have trouble living ascetically
(or with the appropriate “evaluative stance”). Their various attachments will increase
their fear of death and will tempt them to act unjustly. Even if, however, they lose their
attachment to each other and their families, and even if they prove as competent at ascetic
detachment as the Socrates of the Phaedo, the Socratic stance on the value of external
goods will prove insufficient for ridding them of their fear and resentment of death. For
there is one attachment they seem to share with Socrates, and this attachment has
legitimate value that even Socrates cannot not deny. Namely, they all value the life of
philosophy and the pursuit of wisdom. This shared attachment, I argue, requires the
discussion of the immortality of the soul, and without immortality, everyone involved in
75
The perversion of philosophical talent by family and political influence plays a central
role in the Republic’s treatment of true and false philosophers and proper philosophical
education. I address these concerns more fully in the Republic chapters. Another useful
point of comparison is Callicles’ indictment of Socrates’ powerlessness to protect
himself, his family, and his friends in the Gorgias.
82
The Deprivation of Philosophy objection
Socrates introduces his belief in immortality as part of his reply to Cebes’ first
objection, and unless he can provide a convincing proof of the soul’s immortality, the
objection stands. If the objection stands, though, Socrates would be unable to salvage his
claim that the philosopher should not resent death, much less his stronger claim that the
philosopher should eagerly anticipate death. The objection is simple. Like Socrates,
Cebes and Simmias believe that philosophy is the best way of life. Thus, they consider
death a deprivation because it deprives them of their of their ability to continue practicing
philosophy. Their attachment to philosophy is a good reason to resent death, and they
think Socrates is mistaken to refuse to escape an unjust death in order to, among other
permissibility of suicide.76 Socrates argues that, though the philosopher is in fact better
off dead than alive, she must wait until the gods either kill her or place her in a situation
in which they clearly condone her killing herself. Socrates believes his own death, which
is under one description self-inflicted, satisfies the latter condition. The philosopher,
then, looks forward to the gods killing her or granting her permission to die.
that the philosopher’s life is better than the lives of others, since, among other things, the
philosopher recognizes that her life is governed by beneficent gods, then why does she
76
See especially Brickhouse and Smith [1989b], Cooper [1999: 515-541] and Miles
[2001].
83
not have more reason to resent death than the non-philosophers, since she loses a life of
genuine value (62e, cp. EN 3: 9: 1117b). Even if the philosopher is materially poor and
socially ridiculed, her life itself is objectively better. Thus, the philosopher alone actually
loses by dying, since death deprives her of the best, and perhaps the only genuinely
This objection has bite. There is no point at which Plato in any dialogue denies
that some ways of life are better than others. If the philosopher’s life has positive value,
then she stands to lose something of true value by dying—her ability to continue doing
philosophy. One might think that as the value of a person’s life increases, so does the
amount of value of which death deprives her. Even if only one kind of life were to have
value, then death deprives that life of its value. If, on the other hand, no lives have any
positive value, then the philosopher and the non-philosopher both stand to benefit or at
While I have argued that this latter option is a viable interpretation of the first
disjunct of the “Two Things Argument” in the Apology, the Phaedo does not readily lend
itself to this interpretation. I argued that the Socrates of the Apology thinks that death
can be a benefit even if there is no afterlife. This is the case because life is overall full of
pain. On this picture, the philosopher might live philosophically as the best way of
dealing with a bad situation (i.e., life), but she still stands to gain by death because she
loses a great deal of pain. She might simply be distinguished by the fact that she is able
to recognize that life is all-around bad and that death is a benefit, while non-philosophers
falsely believe death is harmful. In the Phaedo, Socrates seems to concede that the
84
philosophical life does have genuine positive value; thus, he needs a further account of
why the philosopher should not resent being deprived of a valuable life.
Socrates grants that Cebes’ argument is a good one, and he claims that he would
in fact be upset to leave a life of servitude to the gods through philosophy, if he did not
expect an afterlife:
would come first to other wise and good gods, then also to
men who have died [who are] better than those here, wise
hope that something exists for people who have died and,
just and as it has been said long ago, that it is much better
It is only natural that Cebes and Simmias should insist on a proof of the
immortality of the soul; Socrates has just admitted that his “good hope” for an afterlife is
the reason he does not resent dying. Before they even get around to challenging him on
77
ἐγὼ
γάρ,
ἔφη,
ὦ
Σιμμία
τε
καὶ
Κέβης,
εἰ
μὲν
μὴ
ᾤμην
ἥξειν
πρῶτον
μὲν
παρὰ
θεοὺς
ἄλλους
σοφούς
τε
καὶ
ἀγαθούς,
ἔπειτα
καὶ
παρ
ἀνθρώπους
τετελευτηκότας
ἀμείνους
τῶν
ἐνθάδε,
ἠδίκουν
ἂν
οὐκ
ἀγανακτῶν
τῷ
θανάτῳ·
νῦν
δὲ
εὖ
ἴστε
ὅτι
παρ
ἄνδρας
τε
ἐλπίζω
ἀφίξεσθαι
ἀγαθούς̶καὶ
τοῦτο
μὲν
οὐκ
ἂν
πάνυ
διισχυρισαίμην̶ὅτι
μέντοι
παρὰ
θεοὺς
δεσπότας
πάνυ
ἀγαθοὺς
ἥξειν,
εὖ
ἴστε
ὅτι
εἴπερ
τι
ἄλλο
τῶν
τοιούτων
διισχυρισαίμην
ἂν
καὶ
τοῦτο.
ὥστε
διὰ
ταῦτα
οὐχ
ὁμοίως
ἀγανακτῶ,
ἀλλ
εὔελπίς
εἰμι
εἶναί
τι
τοῖς
τετελευτηκόσι
καί,
ὥσπερ
γε
καὶ
πάλαι
λέγεται,
πολὺ
ἄμεινον
τοῖς
ἀγαθοῖς
ἢ
τοῖς
κακοῖς.
85
the point, Socrates has mentioned the afterlife six times.78 He repeatedly claims that the
dying.
With each objection, his interlocutors insist that unless the soul is immortal, the
philosopher should fear and resent death. Cebes even threatens Socrates with the epithet
of fool at the close of his Weaver Objection (85e-86e). Though Cebes grants the
possibility that the same soul travels cyclically through life and death, birth and re-birth,
he denies that Socrates has offered a proof against the possibility that any given soul
might eventually wear itself out and go out of commission. Given the possibility that this
body (88b3-8). 79
78
Phd. 63b5-c7; 63e8-64a3; 67b7-c3; 67e10-68a3; 68a9-b2; 69d.
79
εἰ
δὲ
τοῦτο
οὕτως
ἔχει,
οὐδενὶ
προσήκει
θάνατον
θαρροῦντι
μὴ
οὐκ
ἀνοήτως
θαρρεῖν,
ὃς
ἂν
μὴ
ἔχῃ
ἀποδεῖξαι
ὅτι
ἔστι
ψυχὴ
παντάπασιν
ἀθάνατόν
τε
καὶ
ἀνώλεθρον·
εἰ
δὲ
μή,
ἀνάγκην
εἶναι
ἀεὶ
τὸν
μέλλοντα
ἀποθανεῖσθαι
δεδιέναι
ὑπὲρ
τῆς
αὑτοῦ
ψυχῆς
μὴ
ἐν
τῇ
νῦν
τοῦ
σώματος
διαζεύξει
παντάπασιν
ἀπόληται.
86
Before addressing Cebes’ objection, Socrates restates it. Cebes, he notes, calls the
philosopher who cannot prove that the soul is immortal “simple-minded and a fool”
believe that death is not a harm. It is tempting to believe that Socrates, however, does not
need the soul to be immortal. Perhaps Socrates only uses immortality for educative,
protreptic purposes. In other words, one might believe he uses it to calm novice
philosophers, but that nothing about his own attitudes towards death depends on a belief
suggests that Socrates agrees with his interlocutors that the soul must be immortal for his
attitude towards death not to be foolish. In his initial “defense,” he grants that if he did
80
ἔστι
δὲ
δὴ
τὸ
κεφάλαιον
ὧν
ζητεῖς·
ἀξιοῖς
ἐπιδειχθῆναι
ἡμῶν
τὴν
ψυχὴν
ἀνώλεθρόν
τε
καὶ
ἀθάνατον
οὖσαν,
εἰ
φιλόσοφος
ἀνὴρ
μέλλων
ἀποθανεῖσθαι,
θαρρῶν
τε
καὶ
ἡγούμενος
ἀποθανὼν
ἐκεῖ
εὖ
πράξειν
διαφερόντως
ἢ
εἰ
ἐν
ἄλλῳ
βίῳ
βιοὺς
ἐτελεύτα,
μὴ
ἀνόητόν
τε
καὶ
ἠλίθιον
θάρρος
θαρρήσει.
81
διαφέρειν
δὲ
δὴ
φῂς
οὐδὲν
εἴτε
ἅπαξ
εἰς
σῶμα
ἔρχεται
εἴτε
πολλάκις,
πρός
γε
τὸ
ἕκαστον
ἡμῶν
φοβεῖσθαι·
προσήκει
γὰρ
φοβεῖσθαι,
εἰ
μὴ
ἀνόητος
εἴη,
τῷ
μὴ
εἰδότι
μηδὲ
ἔχοντι
λόγον
διδόναι
ὡς
ἀθάνατόν
ἐστι.
87
not believe in the immortality of the soul, “it would be wrong not to resent death”
everyone involved fears that Socrates’ arguments have been undone, Socrates, who has
consistently admonished his friends for their grief, admits that the death of the argument
would be a sufficient reason for everyone to grieve. If the argument dies, and his
confidence about death proves false and foolish, Socrates vows to cut his own hair as a
sign of grief (89b, cp. Od. 4: 208-9). He reiterates his agreement—he is a fool if the soul
is not immortal—at 91b, in a passage that I consider in the final section the chapter.
One might wonder, then, whether Cebes and Simmias conclude the dialogue
believing that Socrates has died a fool. For they are not, I argue, convinced that the soul
Socrates’ conclusion.
Simmias has two worries. The first lies in the nature of the question at hand, and
the second is a more general concern about the philosophical enterprise altogether.
Simmias expresses an extreme pessimism about the possibility of proving the soul’s
knowledge about questions like the nature of the soul is “impossible or most difficult in
85c3-4; cp. 88c6-7]. Even though the odds are stacked against finding the answer,
though, Simmias thinks the question is sufficiently important that one should nevertheless
88
endeavor to advance and refute arguments about immortality. The extreme likelihood of
failure should not be a deterrent, and one should not give up. He says,
Simmias, then, thinks one should seek out the best arguments, though those
arguments will generally fail to prove anything conclusively. It seems that the best of
Socrates’ reply to his objection does not fully assuage these worries, as Simmias
holds to his skepticism and remains troubled. When Cebes offers Simmias a chance to
82
δεῖν
γὰρ
περὶ
αὐτὰ
ἕν
γέ
τι
τούτων
διαπράξασθαι,
ἢ
μαθεῖν
ὅπῃ
ἔχει
ἢ
εὑρεῖν
ἤ,
εἰ
ταῦτα
ἀδύνατον,
τὸν
γοῦν
βέλτιστον
τῶν
ἀνθρωπίνων
λόγων
λαβόντα
καὶ
δυσεξελεγκτότατον,
ἐπὶ
τούτου
ὀχούμενον
ὥσπερ
ἐπὶ
σχεδίας
κινδυνεύοντα
διαπλεῦσαι
τὸν
βίον,
εἰ
μή
τις
δύναιτο
ἀσφαλέστερον
καὶ
ἀκινδυνότερον
ἐπὶ
βεβαιοτέρου
ὀχήματος,
λόγου
θείου
τινός,
διαπορευθῆναι.
There is a manuscript debate that affects whether the divine doctrine is a disjunct or an
appositive. Thus, the divine doctrine is the sturdier vehicle, or the vehicle could be
another argument instead. If it is appositive, and Socrates claims it is the safest thing he
can offer, one might argue that Socrates considers the Forms a “divine doctrine.”
89
But I myself do not have further grounds for doubt after
The difficulty, then, lies not only in the epistemic hurdles that arise from the question
itself, but also in the tendency of humans to offer and believe weak or even false
arguments.
What of Cebes, though? Simmias has already warned Socrates that Cebes resists
accepting arguments more than anyone else he knows (77a). During the course of
Socrates’ final argument, Cebes twice suggests that he remains unconvinced, and perhaps
even evidences some frustration. Simmias, remember, abandons his conception of the
premise—the Doctrine of the Forms. Cebes, though, does not express Simmias’
eagerness to accept the fundamental premise of the argument. He does not openly deny
the existence of the Forms, but when Socrates makes it clear that the argument depends
on his acceptance of their existence, Cebes responds: “Take it that I grant you this, and
83
Ἀλλὰ
μήν,
ἦ
δ
ὃς
ὁ
Σιμμίας,
οὐδ
αὐτὸς
ἔχω
ἔτι
ὅπῃ
ἀπιστῶ
ἔκ
γε
τῶν
λεγομένων·
ὑπὸ
μέντοι
τοῦ
μεγέθους
περὶ
ὧν
οἱ
λόγοι
εἰσίν,
καὶ
τὴν
ἀνθρωπίνην
ἀσθένειαν
ἀτιμάζων,
ἀναγκάζομαι
ἀπιστίαν
ἔτι
ἔχειν
παρ
ἐμαυτῷ
περὶ
τῶν
εἰρημένων.
90
hasten to your conclusion” (100c1).84 Granted, the group is under time constraints, and
Socrates and Cebes with an objection, Socrates responds briefly, then asks Cebes whether
the objection “troubles” him. Cebes replies that the objection has not troubled him, but
then adds that “I do not say, though, that many things do not trouble me” (103c5-6).85
The whole group’s behavior at the death of Socrates, though, provides the
strongest evidence that everyone remains unconvinced. Crito asks Socrates how he
wants to be buried, and Socrates recognizes that Crito would not ask such a question if he
understood that Socrates’ soul was not part of his body. Socrates responds to Crito and to
attempts to persuade Crito that death is followed by an afterlife in which philosophers can
expect to fare well has failed. “I seem to myself,” he says, “to be saying all these things
84
ὡς
διδόντος
σοι
οὐκ
ἂν
φθάνοις
περαίνων
Following
Burnet
[1911:
110].
One
might
think
that
this
is
a
pro
forma
response
of
the
sort
that
Socrates
gets
all
the
time.
The
request
for
the
premise
and
the
response
certainly
make
clear
that
the
argument
turns
completely
on
Cebes
admitting
the
premise
and
that
Socrates
thinks
it
must
be
given
to
him.
Since
Socrates
himself
has
only
faith
in
the
existence
and
causal
power
of
the
Forms,
he
surely
cannot
expect
Cebes
to
take
it
as
more
than
a
central
posit.
A
more
pro
forma
exchange
would
have
gone
more
like
this:
Don t
we
say
that
there
is
a
form
of
the
Beautiful
and
the
Equal,
with
a
response
of,
Certainly!
85
οὔτι
λέγω
ὡς
οὐ
πολλά
με
ταράττει.
91
to him in vain, in my attempts to comfort you all and myself at the same time (115d5-
6).”86
Once Socrates leaves to bathe before taking the poison, the group gives further
indication that they remain unconvinced by gathering together and, Phaedo says,
“questioning what had been said, and then talking about the great misfortune that had
befallen us. We all felt as if we had lost a father and would be orphaned for the rest of
our lives” (116a-b).87 Their copious weeping as Socrates dies, which is checked only by
the shame Socrates brings down upon them by calling them women, most clearly
indicates that, regardless of whether they are convinced, their emotions do not conform to
Simmias, then, doubts his current agreement with the conclusion, and Cebes never
fully assents to the crucial premise in which Socrates expresses faith and upon which the
last argument depends. The rest of the company grieves excessively, even if they claim
to be persuaded. Does this mean that they must believe Socrates to be a fool? No, for
two reasons. First, though they are not convinced, they also cannot prove he is wrong.
At worst, they are at a standstill or an impasse. Simmias may even suspect that he has
just encountered the “most irrefutable of human theories,” or the “safest raft.” He may
think that Socrates’ Forms serve as a divine doctrine that is even better than an irrefutable
theory (85c-d). Even though Simmias and Cebes are far short of certain, then, they lack
86
ταῦτά
μοι
δοκῶ
αὐτῷ
ἄλλως
λέγειν,
παραμυθούμενος
ἅμα
μὲν
ὑμᾶς,
ἅμα
δ
ἐμαυτόν.
87
διαλεγόμενοι
περὶ
τῶν
εἰρημένων
καὶ
ἀνασκοποῦντες,
τοτὲ
δ
αὖ
περὶ
τῆς
συμφορᾶς
διεξιόντες
ὅση
ἡμῖν
γεγονυῖα
εἴη,
ἀτεχνῶς
ἡγούμενοι
ὥσπερ
πατρὸς
στερηθέντες
διάξειν
ὀρφανοὶ
τὸν
ἔπειτα
βίον.
92
grounds for rejecting the starting posits of the arguments. Second, though they are not
convinced, they want to be convinced. They want to believe the soul is immortal, not
simply because they do not want their friend to be a fool, but also because they
themselves do not want to fear death. Thus, they agree to continue working through the
arguments, presumably with some hope of determining that Socrates is right, or, for those
who already think he is right, with the hope of conforming their emotions to their
judgment.
At some points in the dialogue, though, Socrates does not seem particularly
concerned with whether they are convinced that the soul is immortal. In a somewhat
bizarre passage before he begins his final replies, he claims that his true purpose is to
hold to his own belief that the soul is immortal. Securing his interlocutors’ agreement
This short passage raises two questions. First, one might wonder quite simply
whether Socrates persuades himself. Second, one might also wonder whether would
Socrates would be “eager” to believe that the soul is immortal regardless of whether he is
able to establish that it is immortal. In other words, does he recognize prudential benefits
to believing something that he admits could be false? I set aside this question of the
88
οὐ
γὰρ
ὅπως
τοῖς
παροῦσιν
ἃ
ἐγὼ
λέγω
δόξει
ἀληθῆ
εἶναι
προθυμήσομαι,
εἰ
μὴ
εἴη
πάρεργον,
ἀλλ
ὅπως
αὐτῷ
ἐμοὶ
ὅτι
μάλιστα
δόξει
οὕτως
ἔχειν.
93
To what extent, then, is Socrates himself convinced that the soul is immortal? He
may not insist on Cebes and Simmias’ whole-hearted affirmation because he has his own
limited doubts. In fact, he repeatedly hedges his bets. Apart from the Phaedo’s recurrent
theme that wisdom is unattainable in this life, there are other clues that Socrates’
confidence is tempered.
reexamine the starting premises. If he continues to puzzle them through, Socrates says,
he will “follow the argument as far it is possible for a human to follow it, and if the
conclusion is clear, [he] will look no further” (107b7-8). 89 A claim that there is only so
far a person can follow the argument squares with Socrates’ constant claim that there are
significant limits on one’s ability to gain knowledge while embodied. It also shows that
he recognizes that the starting premises upon which his argument depends are premises in
which one can only believe, but which one cannot prove.
One of these hypotheses, obviously, is the existence of the Forms, and Socrates
recognizes that his belief in the Forms is not amenable to proof. It is, rather, the “safest”
perhaps foolishly” holds fast.90 At the close of the Cyclical Argument, Socrates tells
Simmias that if the Forms do not exist, “then this argument is in vain” [ἄλλως ἂν ὁ λόγος
οὗτος εἰρημένος εἴη, 76e4-5]. Since both the Cyclical Argument and the final argument
89
ἀκολουθήσετε
τῷ
λόγῳ,
καθ
ὅσον
δυνατὸν
μάλιστ
ἀνθρώπῳ
ἐπακολουθῆσαι
90
ἁπλῶς
καὶ
ἀτέχνως
καὶ
ἴσως
εὐήθως
ἔχω
παρ
ἐμαυτῷ
[cp. ἔχειν
παρ
ἐμαυτῷ
,
107a]
94
for immortality depend upon his posit that Forms exist and are causes, he admits that his
arguments depend upon a firm belief that is no better than “very safe.” He may, he
Second, if Socrates, unlike Simmias, has reached the very limit to which the
argument can take him, that distance is not sufficient to give him more than “hope.” His
epistemic confidence about the immortality of the soul has not appreciated since he first
claimed to have “good hope” that his death will usher in a new afterlife. The discussion,
then, has in no way thwarted his hope, but it also has not increased it. He has managed to
hold his epistemic confidence steady, but his starting premises are no more established
cannot offer a proof for them. His confidence allows for the possibility that he is wrong,
and he cannot fully convince himself or others that he is not dying a fool.
However, the most complex indication that Socrates has some residual worries is
that he twice discusses the importance of charming or incanting away one’s fear of death
[ἐπᾴδειν αὐτῷ, 77e9; 114d7]. These two discussions of charms, I argue, have less to do
with Socrates’ arguments for immortality, though, than with Socrates’ third and final
In the previous sections, I have argued that Socrates employs two strategies to
control the fear that arises at the prospect of death. First, he believes living ascetically
95
lessens one’s fear of death, makes it easier to live virtuously, and enables one to practice
philosophy “in the right way” (69d). However, he also grants that a philosopher must
have reason to believe that the soul is immortal if she is not to resent losing her valuable
philosophical life. Socrates, I contend, clearly believes he has the best arguments he can
make for immortality, even if they depend on fundamental premises that cannot be
proven. So, if Socrates has reasonable confidence that the soul is immortal, and he lives
as ascetically as possible, are these two strategies sufficient to make him die with the
Perhaps. The text leaves the question slightly open, I think, but in what follows, I
offer some reason to think that Socrates needs one more strategy—the telling of myths. 91
Though some may resist my argument that Socrates needs the myths to calm his own
fear, I insist that Cebes, Simmias, and Socrates’ other young friends must have the myths.
The myths, I argue, are meant to tame the recalcitrant fears that asceticism and the
prospect of immortality are unable to control. Since no one can ever be fully ascetic, and
no one can be certain that the soul is immortal, there remains a bit of residual fear, both
of the soul and of the body. The myths, I argue, contribute a final weapon to the arsenal
with which the philosopher wages war against her fear of death. Since I argue that
91
The exhaustive text about Plato’s myth of late has been Brisson [1998]. The much
older canonical text is Stewart [1905]. For a short and excellent summary of Plato’s
distinction (or lack thereof) between muthos and logos, I recommend Edmonds [2004:
161-171]. Edmonds argues that the final myth in the Phaedo illustrates the journey to
discover the Forms in a three-stage process. Also of interest is Betegh [2009], who, like
Edmonds, defends an account of the narrative arc of Platonic myth; Betegh, though,
focuses on Socrates’ comments about Aesop at the beginning of the Phaedo (61a-d). A
collection of articles about Plato’s myth has just been released, edited by Partenie [2009].
I have no doubt that it contains interesting work that I have not yet examined.
96
Socrates’ audience will likely fail to be ascetics and have greater doubt about immortality
than Socrates, the myths will far more integral to their psychology than to Socrates’. I
contend, but do not insist, that the myths play a role, though a much less integral role, in
interpretation of the myths as “charms.” The content and role of the ‘charms,” however,
is a bit contentious, and there is actually very little discussion of them in the literature,
despite the growing literature on the myths themselves. I structure my discussion around
two questions. First, are the ‘charms’ the myths, the arguments for immortality, or both?
Socrates first mentions charms after he combines the Cyclical Argument (69e-
72d) and the Argument from Recollection (72e-77d) in order to conclude that the each
soul must have existed before it was born, must exist after it dies, and must never cease to
exist. Cebes, however, who Simmias claims is “most difficult of humans with respect to
77a8-9], has further worries about the soul’s existence after death. Before Socrates replies
by launching into a discussion of the nature of the soul, though, he jokes that they seem
to have a “childish fear” [δεδιέναι τὸ τῶν παίδων] that the wind would scatter and carry
away their soul. If one had a soul of that sort, it would be especially dangerous to die in a
high wind. Acknowledging Socrates’ joke at his expense, Cebes laughs, and replies:
97
some child who fears such things. Try to persuade him not
Cebes offers Socrates two candidate fears in this passage, the adult Cebes’ fear, and the
fear of the child in Cebes, who fears death as if it were a “bogey”. Before returning to
the arguments for immortality, which Socrates directs at the adult in Cebes, he offers a bit
of advice for dealing with Cebes’ inner child: “You should sing a charm over him each
77e9-10].” Cebes responds that Socrates is the best charmer alive, and he worries that his
frightened child will become unruly once Socrates is not around to play charmer.
Socrates, however, encourages Cebes to search for a surrogate, perhaps even among his
peers.93 After Cebes promises to seek out a new Socrates, everyone returns to
conversation at a level at which the child cannot participate. They resume the “argument
92
Καὶ
ὁ
Κέβης
ἐπιγελάσας,
Ὡς
δεδιότων,
ἔφη,
ὦ
Σώκρατες,
πειρῶ
ἀναπείθειν·
μᾶλλον
δὲ
μὴ
ὡς
ἡμῶν
δεδιότων,
ἀλλ
ἴσως
ἔνι
τις
καὶ
ἐν
ἡμῖν
παῖς
ὅστις
τὰ
τοιαῦτα
φοβεῖται.
τοῦτον
οὖν
πειρῶ
μεταπείθειν
μὴ
δεδιέναι
τὸν
θάνατον
ὥσπερ
τὰ
μορμολύκεια.
For
another
instance
of
persuasion
through
myth,
see
R.
3:
414d.
The
NeoPlatonists
make
good
use
of
this
passage
and
the
idea
of
child
in
us.
However,
I
need
to
be
convinced
that
the
NeoPlatonists
were
much
more
privileged
interpreters
than
the
rest
of
us
in
order
to
treat
their
word
with
greater
than
average
authority.
93
White [1989] notes that it is bit strange that Socrates would encourage them to pay to
do philosophy, especially since Socrates in other dialogues refuses to take money for his
services and suggests that those who do charge money are swindlers. I cannot help but
wonder whether this is subtle advertising for the school of one of their philosophical
peers who was not present that day.
98
The second mention of charms follows the closing myth, and it complicates the
100d7; cp. Men. 86b-c] that his myth is correct in detail, but he thinks it right in spirit. He
embraces his account of the afterlife, then, saying that “the soul appears to be immortal,
and one should incant these things to oneself, which is why I am just now prolonging the
myth” (114d6-8).94 Socrates again claims that the “charm” should be repeated over and
Socrates, then, all or part of the discussion has been part of an incantation for himself.
Socrates who needs to tell himself stories before he dies—twice, even, in one afternoon.
Those tempted to resist a myth reliant Socrates, though, have a few options.
First, one might claim that the “charms” are only the arguments for immortality,
so that what Socrates encourages is the repetition of arguments without the involvement
of myths. Socrates does not need myths; arguments suffice. This seems to be
94
ἐπείπερ
ἀθάνατόν
γε
ἡ
ψυχὴ
φαίνεται
οὖσα,
τοῦτο
καὶ
πρέπειν
μοι
δοκεῖ
καὶ
ἄξιον
κινδυνεῦσαι
οἰομένῳ
οὕτως
ἔχειν̶καλὸς
γὰρ
ὁ
κίνδυνος̶καὶ
χρὴ
τὰ
τοιαῦτα
ὥσπερ
ἐπᾴδειν
ἑαυτῷ,
διὸ
δὴ
ἔγωγε
καὶ
πάλαι
μηκύνω
τὸν
μῦθον.
99
his courage and serenity he has plainly shown himself
(79n1).
I have already offered number of reasons to think that Socrates cannot be “devoid” of
fear unless he is divine. Given that he has a body, any case for his divinity would
encounter at least one hurdle. In addition, since I have argued that he cannot prove that
the soul is immortal, he recognizes that he cannot be fully justified in fearlessness. For
these reasons, I argue that Socrates needs the charms. However, if the charms are not
myths, but arguments, I doubt anyone would seriously object to the idea that Socrates
needs arguments to quell his fear of death to whatever extent that it can be quelled.
“good arguments” instead of, for instance, “beautiful words.” I do not intend to delve
into the role of the “charms” in the Charmides. However, it should be noted that
Hackforth refers to only this one additional dialogue, and perusing the role of charms in
dialogues outside the Phaedo offers a wealth of evidence that charms are often songs and
stories that contain truths.95 I think concluding that the charms are arguments by appeal
95
In addition to the Charmides passage, “charms” show up in a few other dialogues. In
the Laws, everyone is required to sing daily in choruses, and they sing charms they
learned as children to the city’s children (Lg. 2: 664b). Perhaps most interestingly, the
Athenian claims that the charms must be constantly varied so that no one gets bored with
them (Lg. 2: 665c), which could explain why Socrates tends to tell myths with the same
upshot but different details. At 666c6, the Athenian claims that charms make old men
young in order to make them less irritable. Later, he notes that the Guardians of the Laws
will select only the charms that evoke the right emotions in order to charm the young
people (Lg.7: 812c). In the Republic, in a passage that I discuss in my fifth chapter,
100
only to the Charmides does not account for the wide variety of other instances of
“charms” that suggest they can sometimes be something other than arguments.
Within the Phaedo itself, the conception of charms as arguments has its own
problems. First, Socrates recommends giving the charm or incantation to oneself as one
would to a child. Charming a child by arguments, though, provides the child with a
immediately upon the close of the final myth. Socrates explains the prolongation of his
discussion about whether death is a harm or benefit is launched after Socrates claims that
it is appropriate for someone about to die, like himself, not only to “examine”
[διασκοπεῖν, 61e1] what is said about death, but also to “tell stories” [μυθολογεῖν, 61e2]
about it.96
White’s conception of the charm as both the arguments and the myths, then,
seems not only less restricting, but makes room for some account of the myth’s presence
and squares with the wealth of evidence from dialogues other than the Charmides that the
charms are songs and stories that contain accepted truths. However, if myths that contain
Socrates tells Glaucon that they should “incant” their “argument” against tragedy
whenever tempted by its allure (R. 10: 607e-608b). In the Theaetetus, when Socrates
compares himself to a midwife, he claims that midwives control the birthing process by
using drugs and “singing incantations” (Tht. 149d).
96
cf. Protagoras’ choice of a tale over an argument in the prelude to the Great Speech.
He notes that tales are better for the young and more entertaining, while suggesting that
the lesson of both will be the same (Ptr. 320c).
101
truths are a crucial part of the recommended charms, and those myths are directed at an
inner child, then we are left with a Socrates that tells his own inner child a story to abate
I have no problem with the notion that Plato thinks everyone, Socrates included,
has an inner child that needs to hear stories. Those who prefer a Socrates who does not
need myths, though, have another available refuge. Even if one grants that myths are part
of the charm, one might deny that Socrates is telling the myth for his own benefit.
Rather, he is “prolonging the myth” for the benefit of Cebes and Simmias, who remain
unconvinced by the arguments and need a charm to motivate them to continue working
through the arguments. Or, if he does not provide it for Cebes and Simmias, then Socrates
might provide the myth for the remaining young men in the audience, for they are clearly
less philosophically sophisticated than the chief interlocutors. Thus, when Socrates says
that one ought to repeat these charms to oneself, he does not consider himself one of the
people who ought to do so. When he claims it is appropriate for him to mythologize, he
believes he should tell stories to others. In short, Socrates does not use but makes myths.
myth-maker and someone who needs myths. Even the cobbler wears shoes. There
remains one persistent, very principled reason to think that Socrates needs myths, though.
The constant nuisance of the human body stands in the way of interpretations that isolate
Socrates from strategies employed by the soul to keep the body in check. If the myths are
designed to tame and control fears in the body, either fears that cannot be tamed by
102
asceticism at all, or fears that cannot be tamed by asceticism alone, then Socrates must
The basic fact that myths are stories rather than theoretical arguments weighs in
favor of thinking they are intended to quell the fears of the body. The body, like a child,
does not have the capacity to handle theoretical arguments. Textual evidence,
interpretation. Recall Socrates’ argument that the soul cannot be a harmony because it
constantly struggles against the body’s desires and fears; if the soul were a harmony, such
struggle would be unnecessary. Socrates employs a stock example for illustrating this
conflict between the soul and the emotions—Odysseus’ labor to repress his desire to
slaughter Penelope’s maids on their way to sleep with the suitors. Odysseus “rebukes” his
heart and saves his slaughter for later, using one of the many possible strategies for
controlling the body’s “desires, passions and fears.” Other strategies include “punishing
them rather harshly and with pains, by both exercise and medicine, sometimes more
gently, sometimes promising them and other times warning them, speaking with them as
one to another.” The myths, one might reasonably think, fall into the class of “promises
and warnings.” They are part of the consolation (παραμυθούμενος) that Socrates offers
One might also think, though, that the myths target the residual fears of the soul.
I have argued that Socrates and his interlocutors are not and cannot be fully convinced
that the soul is immortal. They may have a nagging suspicion that its belief is foolish. In
addition, they cannot be confident that, even if the soul proves immortal, that they will
103
get the wisdom they desire. Perhaps humans are fated never to achieve wisdom, even
after they have died. By what means does Socrates recommend that these residual fears
be controlled? If the arguments for immortality prove insufficient, then one might
speculate that a useful option is to tell it a story in which it gets what it wants.
I have argued that the charms include myths and that the myths target residual
fears of the body and soul that asceticism and argument alone cannot assuage. Socrates is
as ascetic as possible, believes confidently if not certainly in the soul’s immortality, and
has created a myth intended to calm himself and his friends. He needs and employs three
We are left, though, with a question I tabled earlier, and I left it until the end
because I cannot answer it. Namely, one must wonder whether Socrates thinks it matters
whether the soul is actually immortal. If believing that the soul is immortal has
that cannot be proven and telling oneself stories about it? Can these advantages outweigh
the prospect of folly? Again, I cannot answer this question, but I conclude with a passage
that suggests that Plato entertains the idea that life is better when one believes the soul is
immortal, even if the soul is altogether mortal. These advantages are not postmortem
104
Socrates twice grants that he could very well be a fool. Remember that he
acknowledges that his belief in the Forms could be wrong. He more fully entertains the
possibility of his folly, though, during the interlude before he addresses the friends’ final
objections. Here, he considers the positive effects of having lived and died as a fool.
Believing in immortality, he suggests, even if falsely, has made it possible for him to face
there is nothing for the one who has died, at least for this
So, if Socrates remains persuaded that the soul is immortal, and it is, he believes
something true and beneficial. If he remains convinced that the soul is immortal, and it is
not, then he at least manages to die nobly without distress, which he believes benefits
everyone involved. Remaining convinced until he dies is a win-win, or, as Burnet puts it,
97
λογίζομαι
γάρ,
ὦ
φίλε
ἑταῖρε̶θέασαι
ὡς
πλεονεκτικῶς̶εἰ
μὲν
τυγχάνει
ἀληθῆ
ὄντα
ἃ
λέγω,
καλῶς
δὴ
ἔχει
τὸ
πεισθῆναι·
εἰ
δὲ
μηδέν
ἐστι
τελευτήσαντι,
ἀλλ
οὖν
τοῦτόν
γε
τὸν
χρόνον
αὐτὸν
τὸν
πρὸ
τοῦ
θανάτου
ἧττον
τοῖς
παροῦσιν
ἀηδὴς
ἔσομαι
ὀδυρόμενος,
ἡ
δὲ
ἄνοιά
μοι
αὕτη
οὐ
συνδιατελεῖ̶κακὸν
γὰρ
ἂν
ἦν̶ἀλλ
ὀλίγον
ὕστερον
ἀπολεῖται.
105
Socrates, then, thinks there are a few advantages to living and dying a fool. These
prudential advantages may turn out to be a final tipping point in Socrates’ attempts to
convince his interlocutors to take the immortality of the soul seriously. In Simmias’
words, believing in immortality may be the best way to get through life, born upon it “as
106
CHAPTER FOUR
Kallipolis, the ideal city of Plato’s Republic, has three social classes: the
philosophers, the auxiliaries, and the multifarious third class. This chapter concerns the
auxiliaries, or the second class, whose special task is to serve as warriors and protectors
of the city. Of the four civic virtues, the auxiliaries represent the virtue of courage
(4:429a-d), and courage requires that they stand firm in the face of death. ∗ Their craft
because they are quite likely to die on the job, often violently and young. However,
auxiliaries are non-philosophers, so to whatever extent they possess virtue, it will always
be volatile, since they lack wisdom and internally regulated, stable characters.98 Even
∗
All citations in chapters four and five in which the dialogue is unspecified are to the
Republic.
98
I operate in this chapter under the assumption that the auxiliaries do not possess true, or
psychic, courage, since non-philosophers cannot possess any true, or complete virtue.
True courage requires two things, neither of which non-philosophers possess. First, it
requires wisdom achieved through knowledge of the Forms, and only philosophers
possess wisdom. Second, it requires what Irwin [1995] calls “counterfactual reliability,”
or moral consistency across a wide-range of circumstances (see esp. 230-234). Instead,
the non-philosophers possess “political courage” (πολιτικήν, 430c3) because they hold
firm to “true belief” about what is fearful. Irwin argues that only wisdom and true virtue
ensures “counterfactual reliability,” so the auxiliaries will lose their “political courage” if
the city crumbles. Kamtekar [1998] makes an interesting case for the possibility that the
first generation of soldiers would remain courageous during the first devolution of the
ideal city into an oligarchy. Again, though, Kamtekar concedes that auxiliaries never
possess true courage. Commentators greatly disagree about whether complete virtue
107
after they, like all members of the upper two classes, have been trained and educated,
In this chapter, then, I argue that the mechanisms by which auxiliaries both
acquire and sustain the appropriate attitudes towards death are largely social in nature, or
features of the political organization that are external to them and generally beyond their
control. I contend that the most important mechanism for controlling their fear of death,
somewhat surprisingly, is the prohibition against possessing private external goods like
children and property. I devote the greater portion of the chapter to a defense of this
claim.
I divide the argument into two sections. In the first section, I address the
straightforward role that religious belief and immortality of the soul play in controlling
the auxiliaries’ fear of death. Piety is not a listed as cardinal virtue of the city or the soul
in Kallipolis, but Plato thinks that the right beliefs about the gods are a necessary
“advantageous” (380c) beliefs about the possibility of an afterlife will prove insufficient
admits of degrees and whether political virtue can make one incompletely happy I do not
weigh in on these questions.
99
McPherran [2006] claims that the “key obstacle to understanding the place of piety in
the Republic is Plato’s decision in Book IV no longer to count piety as a cardinal virtue”
(90). He argues that the absence of piety is not a problem at all, since it is the same thing
as justice, but “aspectually differentiated” with relation to the gods, and justice has
certainly not disappeared from the Republic (91). That may be true, but I cannot find
much textual support for his claim.
108
In the second section, then, I revisit a theme from the second chapter—the link
between security, external goods, and the fear of death. I argue that commentators have
overlooked the important role that the strange material circumstances of the auxiliaries
play in controlling their fear of death and desire to grieve. In particular, auxiliaries (as
well as rulers) are prohibited from having private wives and children and are absolutely
prohibited from even touching money (3: 417a). The only private external good
auxiliaries receive is immortal honor, and they receive it solely on the basis of their
willingness to risk death. I argue that outside of these circumstances and without these
incentives, the auxiliaries’ fear of death skyrockets, and their desire and capacity to act
In the first chapter, I argued that the success of Socrates’ arguments about the fear
of death in the Apology depend on some background assumptions about piety and the
gods. Those same assumptions must also be at work in Socrates’ representation of the
afterlife in the Phaedo, since Socrates never considers the possibility of an afterlife that
would be anything short of highly desirable for a philosopher. The central component of
this Socratic (and Platonic)100 conception of piety is that the gods are perfectly good.
unpredictable source of anxiety for humans. Consider Euthyphro, who snares himself in
100
See, for instance, in Book X of the Laws and the Theatetus (176c); also the Timaeus,
in which the world is designed providentially by a divine craftsman, and Phd. 97b-98b.
109
a contradiction. He thinks, on the one hand, that the gods are supremely good (Eu. 6a).
On the other hand, he believes a number of traditional stories about the gods in which
they judge arbitrarily or commit what would be unjust and illegal acts if perpetrated by a
human being (Eu. 6b-c). Even if the gods do act fairly and justly in some or most
whether the gods will on this particular occasion choose to act beneficently and fairly.
The prospect of an afterlife ruled by unpredictable, unjust gods does not inspire
confidence. The gods might judge the dead arbitrarily or incorrectly (cf. Grg. 523a-
524a). They might favor the rich and unjust, or they might simply make everyone
miserable indiscriminately. The afterlife could be dark, dank, and no fun, as it seems to
be in Homer. Clearly, the prospect of an unfair and miserable afterlife contributes to the
fear of death. Worse, fear and worry motivate a person to pursue all available avenues
for avoiding death, even if doing so requires acting cowardly and unjustly.
Given that he wants courageous soldiers, then, it should be unsurprising that Plato
makes Socratic piety the belief of the realm in Kallipolis and that any undesirable
representation of the afterlife is strictly prohibited. Education about the nature of the
gods is, in fact, the first priority in the childhood training of the future auxiliaries and
guardians. Socrates and Glaucon agree that all representations of the gods must adhere to
two key rules that follow from the gods’ perfect goodness: gods cannot cause harm (2:
379b), and they cannot make themselves worse by altering their nature and form (2:
380d).
110
Thus, the gods must not lie, and they must not alter their appearance in order to be
deceptive (2: 379a-382a). They do not fight amongst themselves or laugh at one
another’s expense (3: 389a). In addition, the gods do not accept bribes (3:390d-e), grieve
(3: 388b-d), or engage in wild sexual exploits (3: 390b-c).101 Absolutely no one in the
city can tell or hear a story that violates these requirements, since it would be both
Any portrayal of the afterlife in the ideal city that features gods must also
represent it as just and fair. After Socrates opens Book III with the claim that no one
“becomes courageous if he has the fear of death in him,”102 the nature of the afterlife is
the first matter of record, since soldiers must be told the stories that make them fear death
“least” (3: 386a). Socrates asks Glaucon whether anyone “who believes Hades’ domain
exists and is terrible will be fearless in the face of death and choose death in battles above
defeat and slavery” (3:388b4-6).103 Glaucon quite reasonably agrees that they will not,
so the two run through a laundry list of unacceptable portrayals of the afterlife in popular
literature.
101
Plato thinks that the belief that the gods can be bribed is perhaps the greatest source of
impiety. In the Laws, private sacrifices are outlawed for fear that people will use them in
an attempt to bribe the gods (Lg. 10: 910a-c). Adeimantus worries that there is little
reason to be just if the gods can be appeased with gifts (R. 2: 365e; cp. Lg. 10:888c).
There is some debate about whether Socrates’ opening discussion with Cephalus in the
Republic suggests that Cephalus has been offering a private sacrifice in order to
propitiate the gods in recompense for a life of injustice.
102
γενέσθαι
ἀνδρεῖον
ἔχοντα
ἐν
αὑτῷ
τοῦτο
τὸ
δεῖμα
103
τἀν
Ἅιδου
ἡγούμενον
εἶναί
τε
καὶ
δεινὰ
εἶναι
οἴει
τινὰ
θανάτου
ἀδεῆ
ἔσεσθαι
καὶ
ἐν
ταῖς
μάχαις
αἱρήσεσθαι
πρὸ
ἥττης
τε
καὶ
δουλείας
θάνατον;
111
The first and most famous text to be censored is Achilles’ exchange with
Odysseus in Hades. Before Odysseus can finally return to Ithaca, the gods force him to
visit Hades, and with much despair, he carries out the errand. In the course of his visit,
he talks with many sorrowful heroes from Troy about their postmortem existence and
answers their questions about the current state of the living (particularly the condition of
their sons and fathers). Achilles, the greatest hero of Troy, who chose a preordained,
glorious death over a long, but inglorious life, offers the darkest rumination on death.
Odysseus congratulates Achilles on the fact that everyone in Hades reveres him, treating
him as if he ruled the dead. He replies, though, that he would rather “slave on earth for
another man—some dirt-poor tenant farmer who scrapes to keep alive—than rule down
here all the breathless dead.”104 Not a ringing endorsement of death from the hero who
most represents the courageous death. The subsequent texts censored by Glaucon and
Socrates are almost all from Homer, though common terms for features of the afterlife
must also be dropped from the language—for instance, “Cocytus” and “Styx” (387b).105
At first, it seems that Socrates leaves open the option that the poets could simply
write that the afterlife does not exist at all. Perhaps he rules out stories which claim that
104
Od. 11: 556-558 (trans. Fagles). Cp. Ecclesiastes 9: 4, “Indeed, for any among the
living there is still hope: a live dog is better off than a dead lion.” (NAB).
105
Oddly, Socrates uses both Styx and Cocytus in his description of the afterlife in the
myth at the close of the Phaedo (113c). One gets the impression that none of Socrates’
eschatological myths (in the Gorgias, Phaedo, or Republic) would be permitted in the
ideal city. Perhaps the key to determining why Plato permits Socrates to be inconsistent
is to be found in Socrates’ throwaway remark at the close of the censorship of stories
about the afterlife. He says that scary stories may be good “for other purposes” (R.
3:387c). There are a number of interesting things to say about this comment, but this is
not the place.
112
it both “exists and is terrible,” so they writers could simply claim it does not exist.
Socrates, though, not only prohibits negative representations, but he requires positive
386b10). Plato clearly thinks that soldiers need the promise of a beneficial afterlife in
There are doubtless people for whom the prospect of a good afterlife is sufficient
to rid them of any fear of death, and this confidence may make some soldiers rush
headlong into danger and certain death. However, this strategy is insufficient to rid most
people of their fear of death, either because they find themselves unable to believe there
is an afterlife at all, or because they recognize the very basic fact that there are many
other reasons to fear death. People fear death not only because they believe they will
gain nothing by dying, but more often because they know they will lose things of value.
The auxiliaries are ascetics, though not of their own choosing. However, I argue
that this enforced asceticism is a key component of their ability to be courageous and
control their fear of death. There are three interesting elements of the auxiliaries’
material culture, the second a great deal more bizarre than the others, and I address the
role that each plays in controlling the fear of death. First, auxiliaries are prohibited from
short, they are prohibited from pursuing any external goods that are scarce and
competitive. Second, they do not have any private familial relationships—their wives
113
and their children are shared. Third, the only private external good they are promised is
honor and immortal fame if they die doing their job correctly.
Given that the auxiliaries receive the best education Socrates and Glaucon can
imagine, which is designed especially to motivate them to care for and protect their
fellow citizens, it comes as a bit of a surprise when Socrates closes out their education
with the claim that the possession of money will cause them to ruin the city. Their
education, it seems, is insufficient to stave off the effect of money on an imperfect soul.
So strong is the effect of money that soldiers, neither the ones who rule nor their
Socrates claims that if the strong but insufficiently virtuous soldiers possessed
wealth and rich estates, they would have the means with which they would inevitably
oppress and kill those weaker than them. Money would make them
they will lead their whole lives fearing enemies at home far
Private wealth brings the fear of violence and death too close to home. It makes even the
114
In Book V, Socrates repeats that the possession of private property by would
destroy the city. If an auxiliary were to foolishly decide he cannot be happy without
private possessions, Socrates claims, “he will hasten by means of his power to make all
the things in the city his own” bringing destruction not only to the city, but to himself as
In Book VIII, the first result of the devolution of the ideal city is the reintroduction of
private property and households, and the guardians and auxiliaries forthwith “enslave and
hold as house servants those who previously were being guarded by them as free friends
Freedom from faction and fear of violence at the hands of one’s neighbor depends
on those who possess weapons not possessing wealth. Why? I think Plato simply
believes that money lets loose the appetitive beast in human nature. For Plato, the
appetitive part of the soul wants money above all, and it wants as much money as it can
get (580e-581a). Thus, in order to “overreach” what it needs, the appetitve part will drive
individuals to compete with others in order to seize what they have. Other people,
though, are also out to “overreach.” As I argued in the second chapter, the problem with
goods like money and power is that they are always scarce and competitive. Injustice and
violence naturally arise from competitions of this sort because one will inevitably cross
paths with someone more committed to winning and getting more than to winning fairly.
Thus, one must be willing to commit injustice or stay out of the way of the person who is
107
τοὺς
δὲ
πρὶν
φυλαττομένους
ὑπ αὐτῶν
ὡς
ἐλευθέρους
φίλους
τε
καὶ
τροφέας,
δουλωσάμενοι
τότε
περιοίκους
τε
καὶ
οἰκέτας
ἔχοντες
115
willing to commit it. Once one possesses goods, one must be willing to protect what one
has from those who want it, so both parties must be prepared for violence. Anyone who
refuses to engage in the competition, and who avoids external goods in order to abstain
from injustice, leaves themselves especially defenseless against anyone who finds them a
nuisance or obstruction. In short, once the auxiliaries are permitted to give the appetitive
part what it most wants, and the objects of desire are scarce and competitive, Plato thinks
the natural result is insecurity, faction, and fear of violence. This theory, of course, was
also at work in the Phaedo, in which Socrates claimed that the pursuit of money to gratify
the body is the cause of all wars and faction (Phd. 66c).
The quest for security against violence is in itself an attempt to control a very
basic form of the fear of death. Insofar as the prohibition against touching money
ensures everyone’s mutual security, the complete absence of money helps control the fear
of death of everyone involved. Money and competition breed insecurity, and insecurity
Socrates claims that the community of wives and children is the “cause of the
not until the opening of Book V that his interlocutors interrupt him and require that he
justify such a seemingly absurd claim. They actually challenge two related claims: that
116
women can be warriors and guardians, and that the guardians’ family should be
communal.
The auxiliaries famously lack any children of their own. The rulers of Kallipolis
devise a systematic program to keep all children communal, so that no child knows the
identity of her biological parents, and no parent knows the identity of her biological child.
Mates are chosen by a “rigged” lottery, so that the best matches are assured, and
everyone who is not assigned a mate or is assigned a less than desirable mate considers
their fate a matter of luck (5: 460a). As children are born, the infants are taken
immediately from their mothers and mixed together by the nurses (5: 460c). Thus, the
child-bearing members of the auxiliary class treat all of the children of a certain age as
their children, and all the children, in turn, recognize many parents (5:457d; 5:461d).
In some sense, children and women are like money, and Socrates tends to refer to
women and children as “possessions” (5: 451c; 10: 603e).108 Mates, under certain
circumstances, can be scarce. One might think, then, that Plato makes children and wives
communal property in order to rid the city of the cutthroat competition that leads to
insecurity. One passage suggests he has this in mind. When Socrates sums up the
advantages of the communal possession of women and children, he claims that it makes
108
Okin [1977, 349-350] explores this in her excellent article on community of wives and
children in the Republic. Okin is a bit more optimistic about Plato’s thoughts on
equality of women than Annas [1999], and Annas is far more optimistic than others
because she thinks Plato takes the passage seriously. Strauss [1964] and Bloom [1968]
think the whole idea is an attempt to one-up Aristophanes’ Ecclesiazusae. Burnyeat
[1999], agrees that it is a reference to the Ecclesiazusae and that it is supposed to be
absurd; however, he argues that the absurdity is in the service of making people take the
idea seriously.
117
the guardians “free from faction, insofar as human beings divide into factions over the
However, there are three important differences between money and children in the
Republic. First, there is the simple point that auxiliaries are permitted to have children,
while they are prohibited from touching money or having any power. Second, children
are natural products, and most animals are motivated to procreate, while money is
artificial and not common in the animal kingdom. People tend not to horde children, as
they would money, and they tend not to steal other people’s children (issues with slavery
excepted). Third, and perhaps most importantly, children are dependent on their parents,
parents feel responsibility for the care of their children, and children can die or be
orphaned.
In other dialogues, Plato claims that most people have a natural, animal-like
desire to have “their own” children (Smp. 208b5; cp. R. 1: 330c). In the Symposium, for
instance, Socrates recounts the speech of Diotima, who tells him that all people desire to
be immortal, and most people pursue immortality through children. Unlike immortality
of the soul, this “immortality by proxy” is achieved by producing something that persists
after one’s death. So, when all goes right, parents have healthy children who survive
their parents. Since children represent their immortality, people have a strong personal
investment in the care and protection of their children, and they tend to be partial to their
109
ὅθεν
δὴ
ὑπάρχει
τούτοις
ἀστασιάστοις
εἶναι,
ὅσα
γε
διὰ
χρημάτων
ἢ
παίδων
καὶ
συγγενῶν
κτῆσιν
ἄνθρωποι
στασιάζουσιν;
118
own “offspring” [ἀποβλάστημα,
208b5].110 In the Laws, the first law of Magnesia
requires that citizens have children, since human beings are “provided by nature” with a
desire to not “lie nameless in the grave.” People most readily participate in immortality
by having children, and the Athenian lawgiver argues that “no one should deny himself
In the Republic, though, Plato clearly believes there is some reason auxiliaries
should be forced to challenge this natural desire to have “their own” child by
collectivizing children. I suggest that Plato does it for two reasons, both of which
contribute to each soldier’s ability to fight fearlessly and face an early death.
First, collective children make it easier to provide for the security and protection
of one’s children and parents, especially if one should die early. I argued in Chapter Two
that worry about the care and upkeep of one’s family is one of the great motivations to
commit injustice and avoid an early death. In the Apology, Socrates expresses disdain
for people who parade their soon-to-be orphaned children before the court, appealing to
the somewhat reasonable pity aroused by the fate of orphans (Ap. 34c-35b). Even though
Socrates seems impervious to such concerns, the continued care and protection of one’s
children seems a reasonable worry for the average member of an Athenian jury. Crito, in
the dialogue bearing his name, argues that Socrates is in fact “wrong” to refuse to escape
prison and his death sentence in order to take care of his family (Cri. 45d), and in the
Phaedo, Crito continues to inquire about Socrates’ children (Phd. 115b). This
110
This is a very rare word; Plato only uses it here, and he is among a very small class of
writers who use it at all. It seems positively biological.
111
trans. Saunders, Cooper [1997] volume.
119
indifference to the fate of one’s children is not possible for most people, and Plato surely
Elderly parents also need care and protection. Soldiers who risk dying early in
battle may worry about their parents as well as their children, and this is yet another
reason to avoid death. Homer’s heroes are full of this sort of anxiety and grief. For
instance, in the Odyssey, Achilles laments that his early death has left his father without
the respect or protection that a son normally provides (Od. 2: 562-73). Likewise,
Odysseus comes home to find his father, Laertes, neglected and grief-stricken (Od.
1:119-125; 24:274-284) and his son, Telemachus, in danger of his life. In the Iliad,
Hector knows that he will die, and must come to the grips with leaving his father, wife,
and son unprotected. In Plato’s Hippias Major, Hippias defines “the fine” as burying
one’s parents and being buried by one’s children (Hp. Ma. 290d-293c).
though, is that the death of a soldier or child renders no child an orphan and no parent
childless. Given that both children and parents alike are liable to die in battle or even
from sickness, having many children makes it more likely that each surviving parent or
Plato shows a great deal of concern about the fate of orphans and childless parents
in other dialogues, especially the Menexenus and the Laws. At the close of the
Menexenus, in which Socrates offers an imaginary eulogy of Athens and its fallen
soldiers, he assuages the grief of both the fathers and the sons of fallen soldiers. He
encourages the fathers not to grieve excessively, since their sons have died valiantly (Mx.
120
247e). He also promises the warriors that the city will care for their orphans and bereft
parents as they themselves would have. Those leaving behind orphans should know that
“the city itself raises their children, eager that their orphanhood be as unknown to them as
possible” (Mx. 249a3-4).112 With respect to both the bereft fathers and orphans, Socrates
claims: “for those having died she stands as son and heir, for their sons as a father, for
their parents as a guardian; giving complete assistance to all for all time” (Mx. 249b7-
c3).113
Likewise, in the ideal city of the Laws, where children are not collective, the
highest elders take care that the orphans of fallen soldiers do not fall to a bad lot and,
whenever possible, hide the very fact that they are orphans. The elders police the
treatment of orphans, “believing orphans to be a great and sacred trust” (Lg. 11:927c2-
3).114 Though the education of orphans does not usually differ from that of other
children, the Athenian lawgiver notes that with respect to “public esteem and the amount
of attention the children receive, orphanhood is usually much less desirable” (11: 927e-
928a).115 Therefore, the elders must ensure that those who adopt orphans give the “child
112
τοὺς
δὲ
παῖδας
συνεκτρέφει
αὐτή,
προθυμουμένη
ὅτι
μάλιστ
ἄδηλον
αὐτοῖς
τὴν
ὀρφανίαν
γενέσθαι
113
ἀτεχνῶς
τῶν
μὲν
τελευτησάντων
ἐν
κληρονόμου
καὶ
ὑέος
μοίρᾳ
καθεστηκυῖα,
τῶν
δὲ
ὑέων
ἐν
πατρός,
γονέων
δὲ
τῶν
τούτων
ἐν
ἐπιτρόπου,
πᾶσαν
πάντων
παρὰ
πάντα
τὸν
χρόνον
ἐπιμέλειαν
ποιουμένη.
114
παρακαταθήκην
εἶναι
μεγίστην
ἡγούμενοι
καὶ
ἱερωτάτην
115
trans. Saunders.
121
who has had the misfortune of bereavement no less affection than his own children, and
be just as zealously concerned for his ward’s property as he is for his own” (11: 928a).116
What better way to ensure such affection and protection than to make many
people the parents of many children? The philosopher-rulers of Kallipolis need not
concern themselves to police the treatment of orphans and bereft parents, since there are,
in some sense, no such persons. Thus, the fear that one will leave one’s children without
The fear that one’s death will impact the continued care of one’s family and that
they will be pained by grief, though, concerns the way that one’s death will harm others.
Some people are a bit more worried about harm to themselves. First, they might fear that
death will end their ability to enjoy their personal relationships and, second, that the death
of others will cause them grief. In the first case, a person fears not continuing the
completion of a project or seeing her children reach adulthood; in the second case, she
worries that her child will die. The community of wives and children, I argue, helps with
does not want to lose it. Since people tend to grow very attached to children, the death of
a beloved child may be the best candidate for the highest grief. Plato, at least, seems to
think this is the case. Though I discuss Plato’s treatment of grief in the Republic at
length in the next chapter, what matters for the moment is that Plato thinks one should be
as self-sufficient as possible, avoid emotional attachment to things and people, and grieve
116
μὴ
χεῖρον
ἀγαπάτω
τῶν
αὑτοῦ
τέκνων
τὸν
τῆς
ὀρφανικῆς
μετειληφότα
τύχης
122
their loss and death as little as possible (3:387d1-e1; cp. Mx. 247e6-248a7). I contend
that Plato also designs the community of wives and children to lessen the auxiliaries’ fear
of the death of their children and their grief when a child dies.
In the opening discussion of the Republic, Socrates asks Cephalus, the wealthy
merchant in whose house the whole of the Republic takes place, whether he made his
own money. Socrates explains his untoward curiosity by invoking a distinction between
two types, or degress of value—if one makes “one’s own” money, children or art, one
cares about it far more than if one considers it of only instrumental use, not having made
it oneself (3: 330b-d). Socrates claims that people who make “their own product”
and art, he seems to suggest, should have only instrumental value. This indicates that
Plato may think one can lessen people’s emotional attachments by keeping them from
Amongst the auxiliaries, there are no private children, so no private losses. The
grief is shared, and no one parent is singularly attached to any particular child. This
communal, generalized sharing of joy and grief is in fact what Socrates claims to be the
“greatest good for the city,” and this unity is evidenced when “to the greatest extent
117
Cephalus then argues that the best use of the money is to fight the fear of death (3:
330-d-331c). This claim raises all sort of interpretive questions that I would like to
answer but cannot in this dissertation. For instance, how close does Socrates mean to
draw the connection between art, children, and money? Should we think that Cephalus’
response suggests that all three could or should be used to combat the fear of death? Is
this related to Diotima’s discussion of varieties of “immortality by proxy” through art,
fame, and children?
123
possible, all the citizens alike rejoice and grieve at the same births and deaths” (5:
462b).118 Since many young soldiers will die young, and children in antiquity tend to get
sick and die, a collective response may turn out to be less grevious for everyone. In
addition, one might think parents would benefit from having a generalized attachment in
the first place, since general attachments might occasion less grief.
However, the communal family may do little to tame the fear of death occasioned
by the prospect of the end of one’s own conscious enjoyment of life, pleasures,
relationships, projects, etc. Plato may seem to have very little to offer on this front,
which would be a shame, since this may be the fear most troubling to many people. The
auxiliaries value human, external goods, and as such, death will deprive them of the
things they value. They value far fewer goods than they would outside the city, but they
still have attachments to their children and each other. Though the afterlife might take up
the slack here for many people, since it promises the ability to continue conscious
awareness in some other place, the “immortality of the soul” remains uncertain, and death
still ends current pleasures. In the next section, I argue that one remaining consolation
for the auxiliaries is that death compensates them with what they want most—immortal
honor. They are “honor-lovers,” and a noble death brings them the highest human honor
118
Οὐκοῦν
ἡ
μὲν
ἡδονῆς
τε
καὶ
λύπης
κοινωνία
συνδεῖ,
ὅταν
ὅτι
μάλιστα
πάντες
οἱ
πολῖται
τῶν
αὐτῶν
γιγνομένων
τε
καὶ
ἀπολλυμένων
παραπλησίως
χαίρωσι
καὶ
λυπῶνται
I follow Shorey in what I think is a very straightforward translation of the participals
γιγνομένων
τε
καὶ
ἀπολλυμένων.
Reeve
[2004]
renders
them
as
successes
and
failures,
Waterfield
[1998] as
gains
and
losses,
and
Griffith
[2000]
as
“any particular gain or
loss.”
Bloom
[1968]
goes
with
the
very
literal
‘coming into being and perishing” that
seems to lean more towards Shorey and myself.
124
to which they can aspire. I conclude, however, that even immortal honor can only do so
much.
Immortal Honor
Auxiliaries want very much to be honored by the city, since the most powerful
part of their soul is the spirited, or honor-loving part. Given that they are educated in the
ideal city, they only want to be honored for the right things rather than for anything at all,
unlike indiscriminate “honor-lovers” (5: 475a-b, 6: 485b). They want the highest honor
from the city to which they can aspire. Thus, they want to be remembered and honored
forever. Hero status and immortal honor are persistent themes in Greek epic poetry and
myth, and the instances and variations are too numerous to recount.119 However, it often
Most commentators with interest in the question of fame look to the Symposium.
Though Diotima notes that the easiest way to gain immortality is to have children,
children live only so long—fame lives much longer. She claims that the desire for fame
lies behind all acts of valor, whether Alcestis’ decision to die in place of her husband or
Achilles’ revenge of Patroclus. Both Alcestis and Achilles die “believing the memory of
208d4-5]. Immortal status and fame plays a significant in other dialogues, as well. In
the Menexenus, Socrates closes his imaginary eulogy to the fallen soldiers with the
119
See Vernant [1991, 50-74] for an excellent examination of Homeric conceptions of the
glorious death and immortal fame.
125
reminder that “the dead themselves the city never fails to honor” (249b). In the Laws, in
addition to having children, the first law of Magnesia mentions fame as the other way to
Immortal honor for soldiers is all over the Republic. With respect to the
auxiliaries,120 Socrates claims that their honor will span the course of their lives and long
as well; and they get prizes from their city while they live,
e2).121
Socrates claims that brave soldiers who die in battle become members of the “golden
class, [τοῦ χρυσοῦ γένους, 5:468e5-6],122 and in the manner dictated by the oracle, they
120
I address the immortal honor assigned to the philosophers-rulers in the next chapter.
121
νίκην
τε
γὰρ
νικῶσι
συμπάσης
τῆς
πόλεως
σωτηρίαν,
τροφῇ
τε
καὶ
τοῖς
ἄλλοις
πᾶσιν
ὅσων
βίος
δεῖται
αὐτοί
τε
καὶ
παῖδες
ἀναδοῦνται,
καὶ
γέρα
δέχονται
παρὰ
τῆς
αὑτῶν
πόλεως
ζῶντές
τε
καὶ
τελευτήσαντες
ταφῆς
ἀξίας
μετέχουσιν.
122
Plato alludes to Hesiod’s history of the Five Ages in Works & Days a few times in the
Republic. According to Hesiod, there was once a golden race of men, who were far
superior to any subsequent generation. The next generation was Silver, then came the
Bronze, and finally the Iron generation. After members of the golden generation died,
they began to wander the earth ensuring justice. In addition to this reference to the
golden generation, Plato clearly alludes to the division in races when he creates the Myth
of Metals to justify the class system of the city. For more on the role of Hesiod in Plato,
see O’Connor [2007: 78-87].
126
are buried “how the daemonic and god-like should be buried.” [πῶς
χρὴ
τοὺς
δαιμονίους
τε καὶ θείους τιθέναι, 5:469a3-4]. Once buried, Socrates notes, “for the rest of time we
will care for and worship at their tombs, as at those of daemons” (5:469a7-b1).123 This
reward falls not only to those who die in battle, but also to those who fight valiantly
possessions and attachments, as well as freedom to travel and do as they please (4: 419-
compensates them, at least in part, for these deprivations. In light of all of these rewards,
he asks Adeimantus whether the soldiers could possibly envy the life “of cobblers or any
other craftsmen or of farmers,” who possess their own houses and children (5:466b1-
2).124 The auxiliaries, then, are promised one final reward as a prize for their willingness
123
Καὶ
τὸν
λοιπὸν
δὴ
χρόνον
ὡς
δαιμόνων,
οὕτω
θεραπεύσομέν
τε
καὶ
προσκυνήσομεν
αὐτῶν
τὰς
θήκας;
124
Some writers, Aristotle for instance, have claimed that Plato does not make clear that
the craftsmen have different material conditions than the upper classes (Pol. 2.5:
1264aff.]. It is true that Plato tells us very little about the third class, which contains
craftsmen and merchants (and possibly servants), though some authors have used various
methods to speculate. I find some of these avenues interesting. For instance, Reeve
[1988: 176] has argued that the First City, or City of Pigs, represents the craftsmen “made
as happy as it is possible for them to be.” Rachel Barney [2001: 217] also considers this
possibility. Even without speculating about the First City, though, I think Plato tells us a
few important things. For instance, the craftsmen have private property and private
houses. When Socrates explains the conditions under which the soldiers will be housed,
he explicitly differentiates them from housing “for money-makers” [στρατιωτικάς
γε,
ἀλλ
οὐ
χρηματιστικάς, 415e9]. At the close of Book III, Socrates claims that at the
moment soldiers have “private land, houses, and currency, they will be householders and
farmers instead of guardians” (3: 417a6-7; also 421c ff). Given that the craftsmen do not
127
to die—they are celebrated as heroes by their city. Given the auxiliaries’ love of honor,
such a promise is clearly a consolation. Immortal honor will likely prove insufficient to
eliminate the auxiliaries’ fear of being deprived of their conscious pleasures, but Socrates
never claimed that the soldiers eliminate their fear. These strategies taken together,
CONCLUSION
In this chapter, I have argued that the matter of central importance for the
auxiliary psychology is controlling the fear of death. Plato recognizes that this is a
difficult task, not only because the fear of death is complex and takes many forms and
objects, but also because of the particular nature, desires, and limitations of the auxiliary
relationships; 3) the prospect of immortal hero status. All of these strategies, however,
depend on cultural luck and political features out of the control of the auxiliaries
themselves. Since the ability to act courageously depends on the city, the auxiliaries’ fear
of death will increase the moment that the city begins to devolve. In the next chapter, I
consider whether the internal regulation of emotions that the philosopher-rulers achieve is
sufficient to eliminate their fear of death and whether they also rely on features of the
political enviroment to achieve and sustain the appropriate attitudes towards death.
share houses, land, or money, it is unlikely, though not impossible, that they share wives
and children.
128
CHAPTER FIVE
In this chapter, I argue that the philosopher, even in the ideal city, cannot
eliminate her fear of death and her desire to grieve. In the Republic, then, Plato thinks
that the most virtuous humans imaginable must control their attitudes towards death by
vigilantly employing a set of strategies. I argue that these strategies are almost
indistinguishable from those employed by non-philosophers and that the philosophers are
The argument proceeds in three stages. In the first section, I consider the extent
to which the philosophers-rulers, like the auxiliaries, depend on “cultural luck.” Outside
of the ideal city, their nature would almost certainly be perverted, and they would not
attain virtue and the emotions appropriate to virtue. Thus, even though they have a
philosophical nature, they cannot avoid fearing death outside of the ideal city.125
In the subsequent two sections, I consider the philosopher in the ideal city. First, I
argue that philosopher-rulers control rather than eliminate their desire to grieve the death
125
Before anyone gets worked up, I concede at this early stage that Socrates and other
divinely gifted individuals manage to become philosophers of a sort in a non-ideal city
(6: 496a-e). However, I remind the reader, first, that they are rare and divine. Second, the
majority of them are only philosophers because they are not physically able to be
politically involved, which means they would not be suitable as philosopher-rulers.
Third, as I argue below, they must work very hard to fight the unfortunate effects of their
poor education, especially with respect to fear and grief. Most importantly, one should
not lose sight of the fact that they cannot possess wisdom and knowledge of the Forms,
while the philosopher-rulers can. Socrates never receives the right education, as should
be clear from the outline of philosophical education in Book VII.
129
of others. Much of my argument depends on an interpretation of Plato’s conception of
“lawless desires,” which I contend are natural to all humans and must be controlled rather
“lawless desires” at the opening of Book IX. The second is the illustrative image of the
tripartite soul as three beings: a small man, a lion, and a many-headed beast (9: 588b-
590c). I use these two passages to set up my discussion of the third passage, in which
Plato suggests that desire to grieve the death of people to whom one is emotionally
attached is a “lawless desire.” Thus, I argue that it is natural and must be controlled.
Some will object to my conception of a natural and lawless desire, though, since
there are at least two other ways that a desire might be natural to humans. Natural desires
may be present in everyone but eliminable for a select few; or they may be natural to
humans but only under non-ideal political and educational circumstances. With
significant “cultural luck,” they may never arise.127 While I note that one piece of textual
evidence leaves open the possibility that a few of the most “savage” of the lawless desires
can be eliminated by a few people, I argue that the images and argument Socrates offers
about the desire to grieve make it clear that it always arises and must be constantly
controlled.
126
These should not be mistaken for natural and necessary desires like the desire for food
and drink, which also cannot be eliminated. Since Plato’s “lawless desires” include the
desire to sleep with one’s mother and murder, it would be a difficult case to make that
such desires are necessary. I know the argumentative nature of philosophers, so I want to
emphasize that that case would be “difficult.”
127
These two additional conceptions of “lawless desires” are borrowed from Deslauriers
[2001], further discussed below.
130
In the final section, I consider whether the philosophers need strategies to control
the fear of their own fear death in addition to their desire to grieve the death of others. I
argue that they, like the auxiliaries, control their fear of death by hoping to be immortal,
and they desire immortal honor from the city in which they rule.
Since my argument significantly narrows the gap between philosophers and non-
philosophers, I conclude by considering the important way that philosophers are superior.
Though some readers may consider my account of the philosopher’s emotions unhappily
deflationary, I suggest that a philosopher who cannot eliminate her fear and grief presents
All things considered, the philosophers of Kallipolis have a lot in common with
the citizens they rule. Before they receive the mathematical, practical, and dialectical
education that makes them philosophers and rulers, they do not possess any singular
education. They are products of the same religious education, and they are culled from a
warrior class that has received the physical education that makes them highly qualified to
fight and die on the battlefield. Like everyone in the city, then, they are educated to
believe that the gods are good, do not deceive, and do not cause evil;128 like the soldiers
128
This is not the place for a protracted defense of this claim, but I think that all citizens,
even the third class, must receive the religious education, though not the physical
education suitable for war. Commentators on both sides of the debate have text to
support their position. Given that there is so little text on the third class, Plato’s apparent
vacillation is annoying. I side in spirit, if not in detail with Vlastos [1973, 137-8] and
Cornford [1941] over Hourani [1949] and Reeve [1999, 186-91 and n. 7 and 8].
131
they rule, they are excellent warriors. They do not possess any private property, and they
Socrates makes it clear that the philosopher-rulers, like the auxiliaries, rely of
“cultural luck.”130 Without the city, their nature would almost certainly be warped. Their
virtue, then, depends on a crucial external good—an education in the right political
environment.
Socrates expresses this dependence most forcefully in his defense of the claim
that the ideal city can only come into existence when philosophers rule (5: 473c-d).
Glaucon warns Socrates that most people will think him a fool. One cannot quite fault
the citizenry, Adeimantus suggests, for thinking the suggestion ridiculous. Their basic
powers of observation make it clear that philosophers would make poor rulers—
philosophers are at worst hacks, and at best useless to the city (5: 487b-d). Socrates,
129
The sages of some ancient schools intentionally avoid having children. The
Epicureans prefer not to have children, though they will raise the children of others if
necessary and might even have children themselves in dire circumstances (see Brown
[2009]). Democritus, the famous atomist, was exceptionally blunt: “I observe in the
acquisition of children many great risks and many griefs, whereas a harvest is rare, and
even when it exists, it is thin and poor.” (DK 68 B276, trans. Freeman [1983]). He
thought that if one insists on raising a child, one should take one’s pick from the children
of a friend in order to make sure one gets a child one likes (B277). The Stoic sage
indifferently prefers to have children. The philosopher of Kallipolis, though, must have
children, if only for the simple reason that she spends a long time as a soldier and because
she is, unsavory though it sounds, an ideal specimen for the city’s eugenic program.
Philosophers will also never know the identity of their children, since they are too young
during their prime years to be among the philosopher-rulers that fix the lottery.
130
I borrow this term from Lear [1992]. For a defense of the position that becoming a
virtuous philosopher does not depend on political circumstance, see Annas [1999: 72-95].
She is fighting a difficult battle on that front.
132
then, needs some justification for the sorry state of philosophy such that the philosophers
Socrates responds by shifting the blame for the sorry state of philosophy to the
current state of political affairs. The city prohibits the youth with natural philosophical
talent from pursuing philosophy as it should be pursued. Thus, almost everyone who
pursues philosophy lacks the necessary talent, and for this reason they do it poorly, with
results that range from embarrassing to vicious. These guys are the hacks. On the other
hand, those few people who practice philosophy “in a way that is worthy” do so only by
divine dispensation or because some physical deformity keeps their nature from being
perverted by political activity (5: 496a). These guys are people like Socrates, who seem
Worse, the non-ideal city not only keeps those with a philosophical nature from
becoming philosophers, it corrupts and ruins them. For, though only the philosophical
nature has the potential to save the city, only the philosophical nature has the potential for
“great injustices and pure wickedness” (5: 492e). The philosophical skill set can be
employed either for good or ill, and the non-ideal city ensures that it will be the latter.
The quick story about the perversion of philosophic talent in Classical Athens
goes like this: sophists teach talented youths to pander to the needs and desires of the
majority in order to gain power. Relatives, recognizing that they can use a youth’s
natural talents to their own devices, encourage him to study with the sophists. The
relatives and sophists flatter him until he believes himself capable of great acts of
statesmanship. However, since he lacks knowledge about the city’s affairs and wisdom
133
about what is true and good, he fails, often with spectacularly bad results.131 And, of
Those with a philosophical nature, then, have little or no hope of a good life
outside the ideal city, just as the auxiliaries would be fearful, insecure, and unjust in a
dangerous political climate. The fact that both the philosophers and non-philosophers
depend on the city to fulfill their nature, though, does not entail that when their nature is
fulfilled, the philosophers fear death to the same extent as the auxiliaries or control it by
the same means. Though the non-philosophers will never be able to eliminate their fear
because they value human goods and require assurances of immortal fame and hope for
an afterlife, the philosophers may afford no significant value to human honors or desire
an afterlife. I consider the philosopher’s desire for honor and immortality in the final
section. In the next section, I argue that the philosophers cannot avoid becoming
emotionally attached to other people whose death they fear and grieve; the desire to
LAWLESS DESIRES
Socrates claims at the beginning of Book IX that the tyrant’s waking life
resembles everyone else’s disturbed sleep. He illustrates the psychological state of the
seems to me, some that are hostile to law and that probably
131
This narrative arc of the corruption of the youth runs through the Platonic corpus,
most notably in the Gorgias, Alcibiades I, and Protagoras.
134
exist in everyone; but when checked by the laws and the
Socrates claims that we know that we have these desires because at night, while the
ἄρχον], the “beastly and wild part” runs rampant [θηριῶδές τε καὶ ἄγριον, 9: 571c4-5].
The desires of “beastly part” run the gamut, from the desire to sleep with one’s mother or
kill someone to eating whatever one wants. None of these actionswould be permitted by
a healthy ruling part, and all these desires are successfully suppressed by the temperate
The individual “who has a healthy and moderate relationship with himself
desires “least” [ἥκιστα, 572a8], due to a set of nighttime rituals. Before sleeping, she eats
just the right amount of food, rehearses a few arguments, and soothes the spirited part’s
anger and aggression (571d-572b). Socrates abruptly ends his discussion with a take-
home message: “surely some terrible, savage, and lawless form of desires is in every
132
τῶν
μὴ
ἀναγκαίων
ἡδονῶν
τε
καὶ
ἐπιθυμιῶν
δοκοῦσί
τινές
μοι
εἶναι
παράνομοι,
αἳ
κινδυνεύουσι
μὲν
ἐγγίγνεσθαι
παντί,
κολαζόμεναι
δὲ
ὑπό
τε
τῶν
νόμων
καὶ
τῶν
βελτιόνων
ἐπιθυμιῶν
μετὰ
λόγου
ἐνίων
μὲν
ἀνθρώπων
ἢ
παντάπασιν
ἀπαλλάττεσθαι
ἢ
ὀλίγαι
λείπεσθαι
καὶ
ἀσθενεῖς,
τῶν
δὲ
ἰσχυρότεραι
καὶ
πλείους.
135
person, even in those of us who seem to be ever so measured” (9: 572b4-6).133
These “lawless desires” resurface later in Book IX, when Socrates illustrates the
inner life of a virtuous person. He asks Glaucon to fashion, as would a sculptor, three
beings that reside within the body of a man. The first being is a “colorful, many-headed
“tame”[ἡµέρων], and others are “savage” [θηρίων, 9: 588c7-9]. The second being is a
lion, and the third is a small human being. While the unjust person allows the small
person to be enslaved by the many-headed beast and the lion, the just person, with the aid
of the lion, controls the “many-headed beast—like a gardener, nourishing and cultivating
the tame heads, and hindering the growth of the savage ones” (9: 589b2-4).134
Rachel Barney [2001], in her essay “Platonism, Moral Nostalgia, and the City of
Pigs,” argues that Plato believes the “lawless desires” are natural to all humans and
ineliminable.135 The image of the gardener, she claims, indicates that the many-headed
beast is in everyone, and even the just person must constantly tend the garden of the
133
δεινόν
τι
καὶ
ἄγριον
καὶ
ἄνομον
ἐπιθυμιῶν
εἶδος
ἑκάστῳ
ἔνεστι,
καὶ
πάνυ
δοκοῦσιν
ἡμῶν
ἐνίοις
μετρίοις
εἶναι·
134
ὥσπερ
γεωργός,
τὰ
μὲν
ἥμερα
τρέφων
καὶ
τιθασεύων,
τὰ
δὲ
ἄγρια
ἀποκωλύων
φύεσθαι
135
Barney uses this conception of “lawless desires” to support her argument that the First
City, or City of Pigs, is impossible, since it rests on a conception of human nature that
does not take account of the savage desires. Since its citizens will of necessity have these
desires, and since they do not have the philosophical apparatus with which they can
control them, the First City could not possibly sustain itself.
136
appetites and lawless desires. Barney seems to think of the “lawless desires” as hearty
and wily weeds that the rational part must vigilantly fight. She grants that hard work and
a great education may make it possible to rid oneself of some of these desires, but she
rightly notes that the image makes clear that education is insufficient to keep the weeds
from growing in the first place. They arise naturally and are suppressed or starved with
effort. However, she contends that even starvation and “riddance’” can never be “more
Barney thinks that Plato considers the desire for wealth and gain to be the most
powerful “lawless desire.” In what follows, I argue that Plato recognizes another
desire to respond to death as something “terrible” and to grieve the death of others.
The problem with tragedy, Socrates claims, is that it “nurtures and waters” [10:
606d4] the part of the soul that desires “by nature to lament and grieve” [10: 606a4-5],137
while it weakens the part that is “best by nature” [φύσει βέλτιστον, 606a7], which follows
“law and reason” [λόγος καὶ νόμος, 10: 604a10; ὁ νόμος, 10: 604b6-7, 604b9; cf. 9:
587a, 587c].
136
Barney, 219
137
τοῦ
δακρῦσαί
τε
καὶ
ἀποδύρασθαι
ἱκανῶς
καὶ
ἀποπλησθῆναι,
φύσει
ὂν
τοιοῦτον
οἷον
τούτων
ἐπιθυμεῖν
137
Though Socrates earlier divided the soul in Book IV, in Book X he uses the desire
to grieve in order to again demonstrate that the soul must have parts. Socrates invokes a
“decent man” [ἐπιεικὴς]138 who suffers a misfortune like the death of a child. He and
Glaucon agree that under such circumstances, the “decent man” will find it “impossible”
[ἀδύνατον, 10:603e8] to avoid grieving at least a little bit. However, he will also desire
not to grieve. Since a soul cannot have two contrary desires about the same thing at the
same time in the same part of itself, his competing desires to grieve and to not grieve
entail that he has two parts (10: 604b3-4; cp. 4: 436b). One part follows “law and
As the temperate person does before sleep, the decent man employs a set of
events from good ones, that grieving does not change matters, that human things are not
important, and that grieving impedes sound reasoning and recovery (10: 604b-c).
Regardless of whether we think these strategies are helpful, Plato clearly thinks they are
138
“Decent” is by no means a term of art in Greek, though it is rare in Plato, and he uses
it almost exclusively to describe the proper attitudes towards death and misfortune. [cf.
ἐπιεικεῖ
1:331b1,
1:
387d5,
8:
554c12
ἐπιεικεῖς
1:
347c6,
3:
398e4,
3:
409a8,
6:489b5,8:
568a5,
10:
605c7].
139
There are some puzzles that arise when one compares the division of the soul in Book
X with the division of the soul in Book IV. For instance, one might wonder whether
Socrates here divides the soul into two rather than three parts, and even whether this
divison of the soul occasioned by grief is the same as the one offered earlier in Book X
with respect to the confusions of perception. See Annas for a statement of the problems
[1981, 339-340], and Lorenz [2006, 59-73] for a defense of the claim that all three
instances of soul division are consistent.
138
necessary. The bereaved father must fight back the lawless desire to grieve in order to
grieve “least.”
Socrates suggests repressing the desire to grieve requires focus and energy—it is
“held down by force,” [τὸ βίᾳ κατεχόμενον, 10:606a3] and tragic poetry makes those not
properly educated “relax the guard over the mourning part” [ἀνίησιν τὴν φυλακὴν τοῦ
θρηνώδους τούτου, 606a8-b1]. One must “battle with the pain and hold out against it”
One preemptive way to fight the desire is to completely avoid situations that
encourage and “nourish” it, even if avoiding them requires a struggle. Socrates tells
Glaucon that “even the best of us” [βέλτιστοι ἡμῶν, 605c10] enjoys tragic theater, which
has the ring of Socrates’ claim in Book IX that lawless desires are found in “even those
of us who seem to be ever so measured” (9: 572b). Nevertheless, he and Glaucon, unlike
others, understand that attending tragedies weakens one’s resolve to fight grief when one
suffers a real misfortune (10: 606b5-7). Thus, Socrates says that they must never attend
They should respond as though they found themselves unable to avoid loving someone
they should not love—avoid the person altogether (10: 607e). In a return of the Phaedo’s
“incantation,” when they encounter tragic poetry, they should respond by “incanting this
argument we’re making to ourselves as a charm, taking care against falling back into this
140
ἐπᾴδοντες
ἡμῖν
αὐτοῖς
τοῦτον
τὸν
λόγον,
ὃν
λέγομεν,
καὶ
ταύτην
τὴν
ἐπῳδήν,
εὐλαβούμενοι
πάλιν
ἐμπεσεῖν
εἰς
τὸν
παιδικόν
τε
καὶ
τὸν
τῶν
πολλῶν
ἔρωτα.
139
Thus, Plato, I argue, thinks that the desire to grieve is a standard human desire
that is housed in the lower part or parts of the soul that oppose “reason and law,” and he
thinks controlling the desire requires a set of strategies, including rational arguments,
incantations, and situational avoidance. This evidence suggests, at the very least, that the
desire to grieve is common, powerful, and irrational. It does not, however, justify the
OBJECTION
Marguerite Deslauriers [2001] protests that “lawless desires” are not ineliminable.
She might allow me the claim that the desire to grieve is natural and lawless, powerful
and common. However, she would contest the idea that it arises of necessity in everyone.
The desire to grieve may arise naturally in humans, but that only under non-ideal political
circumstances. A person might hold, for instance, that people have a natural desire to
murder when educated incorrectly, but the ideal citizens of Kallipolis would never have a
desire to murder. If the desire to grieve were natural and lawless in this way, then the
problem with Socrates, Glaucon, and the “decent man” is that they were educated in the
wrong city. In the right city, they would not fight a desire to grieve because they would
never suffer from it. However, even if the desire to grieve does arise naturally in
This
is
another
instance
of
a
charm
that
seems
to
indicate
that
charms
are
sometimes
the
somewhat
rote
repetition
of
arguments.
Here,
the
charm
seems
to
be
an
argument
that
staves
off
desires.
Again,
though,
the
Laws
passages
[Lg. 2: 664b,
2: 665c, 2:666c6,
7:812c]
suggest
that
charms
are
popular
songs,
and
the
fact
that
they
are
mostly
directed
at
children
indicates
that
they
must
be
in
a
number
of
instances
something
other
than
theoretical
arguments.
140
everyone, irrespective of political circumstances, Deslauriers might further object that it
could still be eliminable. She would object to the claim that, in Barney’s words, any
“riddance” of lawless desires is only a “holding action.”141 There may be evidence that a
select few people can eliminate some, if not all of their lawless desires. If a few select
people can eliminate them, then surely these select people must be philosophers. I think
each of these alternate conceptions of lawless desires can garner a little textual support,
but I contend that there is more evidence that lawless desirescannot be eliminated, and I
argue that Plato has good independent reasons to reject the alternate conceptions, at least
One of the difficulties of the Republic is that Socrates seems to move back and
forth between the attitudes and pleasures of people educated in the ideal city and people
educated outside of it. He does this, for instance, in the passage about grief in Book X.
When Socrates argues that he and Glaucon must struggle with themselves to stay away
from tragedy, he blames their intense desire for watching it on their upbringing under
non-ideal political circumstances. Since they were exposed to the wrong literature in
their youth, their desire came into existence and is ineliminable (10: 607e-608b). Their
141
Deslauriers would contest this claim because she did contest it in her comments on
Barney’s paper at the Boston Area Colloquium, where Barney’s paper was delivered
(229).
141
One would think, then, that this desire to grieve would never arise in the ideal
city, since children would never watch tragedies and would be taught to disapprove of
such displays. Thus, no one would grapple with the desire to grieve. Contemporary
Athenians, Socrates included, must control by avoidance and extreme effort, but
There are reasons to worry about this possibility. First, remember that tragedy
does not create the grieving part—it “feeds” it. Socrates employs gardening verbs when
he talks about the desire to grieve, as he did when he discussed the proper control of the
many-headed beast. He claims that poetry “nurtures and waters” the desires of the
αὐχμεῖν, 606d4-5]. There is something already there, then, to nourish or starve. Second,
the problem with those who have not been adequately educated by their city is that they
“relax their guard over the mournful part” when they hear tragedy [ἀνίησιν τὴν φυλακὴν
τοῦ θρηνώδους, 606a8-b1]. The point of difference, then, might be that those who have
been educated properly will never “relax their guard.” They do not need the charm, but
A third reason to reject the possibility that the desire to grieve never arises in the
ideal city is that it suggests that the philosopher has a unified soul from childhood. If the
philosopher never has these sorts of desires contrary to reason, she seems no longer to
have a human soul with competing impulses and multiple parts that need to be ruled,
“persuaded,” and harmonized. Harmonizing a divided soul has been the aim of much of
the discussion of the Republic, and, more germane, a central feature of the passage about
142
grieving in Book X. Since a soul without tension is a soul without parts, the philosopher
who has never experienced a desire to grieve is a philosopher without a partite soul or a
many-headed beast to conquer. She either no longer has a human soul, or her soul is
divine and, more bizarrely, has been for the course of her life. So even the philosopher
must at some point possess the desire to grieve the loss of attachments.
The fourth and final reason to reject the claim that the desire may never arise
under ideal circumstances turns on the identity of the mysterious “decent man.” For the
decent man of Book X, who finds it impossible not to grieve at all, is the same “decent
man” of Book III, who grieves “least” (3: 387d-e). The decent man, then, is likely a
creature of the ideal city or, at the very least, he is an exceptional person outside the ideal
city who serves a model for the education of the guardian class in the ideal city. In both
passages he grieves because he has lost a friend, a child, or some other “prized
possession” (10: 603e). Since he is less attached to his children than many other people,
he grieves less than other people. He does, however, grieve. The desire, then, arises
Even if the philosopher must at some point possess the desire to grieve, this does
not entail that she cannot eliminate it. She may be better than the “decent man,” who is
educated in the ideal city but unable to eliminate his desire, and who must control it using
a set of strategies. The fact that Socrates and Glaucon cannot eliminate their existing
desire may depend on their early education in a non-ideal city in addition to the fact that
143
they are not philosophers (or, at least, full philosophers).142 However, the theoretical
education that the philosophers receive in the ideal city may eliminate their existing
desire.
Plato at one point leaves open the option that some of the more “savage” of the
“lawless” desires may be “gotten rid of” by a select few people. When Socrates
introduces the desires to murder others and sleep with one’s mother, he notes that they
hedges his already hedged claim by speculating that “in some human beings they are
entirely gotten rid of or only a few weak ones remain” (9: 571b4-c1).143 The claim that in
some people they are “entirely gotten rid of” does suggest something stronger than
himself suffers from these lawless desires, when he says that lawless desires are “in
measured” (9: 572b4-6). Nevertheless, Socrates has often admitted that he is not the ideal
philosopher, not only because he loves tragedy. So it might make sense that some ideal
philosophers (better even than Socrates) could eliminate the most savage desires and skip
What, though, of the more garden-variety lawless desires, like the desire for
money and grieving? Again, I argue that the idea that the philosopher’s constant
vigilance over the harmony of the parts of her soul indicates that the philosopher rules
142
Cp. Lorenz [2006, 64-65]
143
ἐνίων
μὲν
ἀνθρώπων
ἢ
παντάπασιν
ἀπαλλάττεσθαι
ἢ
ὀλίγαι
λείπεσθαι
144
these desires rather than eliminates them. At the end of Book IX, for instance, Socrates
indicates that the person who wants to have a balanced soul must be constantly on guard
against upsetting the harmony, which means that if she grows inattentive, her lawless
desires and the “many-headed beast” will grow unruly (9: 591e). If the desires were fully
eliminated, then there would be no reason to be on guard against upsetting the balance.
Thus, the philosopher is not so much the person who eliminates these “lawless desires,”
but the person whose can always evaluate how to best keep them from getting in her way,
weed them and leave them unwatered. With grief, then, she masterfully employs the
strategies that Socrates suggests in Book X whenever she encounters tragedy, and avoids
external conditions that tempt her to “relax her guard.” The many-headed beast may be
Most of this chapter has been about grief, though, which concerns reactions to the
death of others to whom one is emotionally attached. It may seem that the philosopher’s
fear of her own death has dropped out of the picture. Perhaps she requires strategies to
control her lawless desire to grieve, but her fear of death is simply eliminated rather than
Recall that the decent man of Book III, in addition to grieving less than everyone,
fears death least, since “he doesn’t think that death is a terrible thing for someone decent
to suffer” (387d). Again, though, we cannot conclude much on the basis of the “decent
man,” since the philosopher may be better than him. In the previous chapter, I argued
145
that the auxiliaries require a number of mechanisms to control their fear of death, and
absent ideal circumstanes, their strategies will fail. In the next section, I argue that the
philosophers rely on a number of these mechanisms. I argue, then, that they must also
control rather than eliminate their fear of death, even though their strategies consistently
work inside and outside the city. I contend that like the auxiliaries, the philosophers hope
their soul is immortal, and if afforded the opportunity to receive immortal honor from the
city, they welcome the prospect. However, I consider a final objection—why does the
In the previous chapter, I noted that Plato thinks a key reason that soldiers tend
toward cowardice is their fear of the afterlife. Thus, soldiers must believe that they will
gain a beneficial afterlife in exchange for their courageous death. One gets the sense that
Plato thinks the belief in a beneficial afterlife is merely a useful fiction employed by the
lawmaker as an instrument for creating a soldier willing to die for the city and for
keeping everyone else in line for fear the gods will smite them. Some people think that
Plato has this instrumental view of religion as “opium for the masses,” and they maintain
that, at the very least, Plato himself could not have controlled his fear of death with a
belief in the afterlife.144 The philosopher should not need useful fictions. However, I
144
This view is most commonly attributed to the writings of Straussians, though I have
heard it suggested by many people who do not fancy themselves Straussians. Straussian
methodology turns on the idea that Plato communicates at many levels. This, in itself, is
not necessarily a problem. Generally, though, they consider Plato to be a highly ironic
deceiver. With respect to religion, then, they think that Plato includes religious bits in
146
think the text shows that the philosopher-ruler does hope for an afterlife and uses this
One passage seems to provide some support for the other position, since it
suggests that the philosopher’s ability to control her fear of death has nothing to do with
Socrates separates the philosophers from the other guardians and auxiliaries, he identifies
a few features of the philosophical nature. Philosophers love learning and their love of
learning and wisdom minimize their bodily desires (6: 485d). They are not “lovers of
money.” In addition, they will not “believe that death is something terrible” (6: 486b).
Though this is the same belief ascribed to the “decent man” in Book III (3: 387d), here
Socrates ofers a new reason that a person with a philosophical nature will not think death
all time and being, do you think it possible that human life seem anything
great?
Impossible, he said.
Then will a man of this sort believe that death is something terrible?
dialogues in order keep philosophy out of trouble with the non-philosophical, ignorant
religious masses (Strauss [1952]). Plato actually disdains the beliefs of the masses, and
this is hidden, but accessible to the truly philosophical who pay close attention to the
argument (for this view in the Phaedo, see Ahrensdorf [1995]). For a response to
Ahrensdorf, see Roochnik [1997]. For a critique of Straussian methodology wholesale,
see Burnyeat [1985].
147
Least of all.145 (6: 486a8-b2)
The philosopher, then, does not fear death because she understands the value of human
life in the grand scheme of things. Since this perspective is attributed only to an
Thus, one might argue that the philosopher does not fear death because she alone
is ascetic and assigns no value to goods of this life. The non-philosophers attach their
hopes to external goods like children and honor, they fail to affect the right disdain for
human affairs, and they fear the loss of the things they value at death. The philosophers,
on the other hand, do not care about life, so they lack reason to fear death. This brand of
If my argument about grief succeeds, then we already have reason to think that
the philosopher affords some value to the life of those for whom she cares, so she must
think some human things are valuable. However, independent of my argument, other
evidence suggests that the philosopher thinks a number of human activities and honors
are valuable.
First, learning and doing philosophy is itself immensely valuable, so at least one
human activity has genuine value. Second, I argue that Plato thinks that philosophers
145
Ἧι
οὖν
ὑπάρχει
διανοίᾳ
μεγαλοπρέπεια
καὶ
θεωρία
παντὸς
μὲν
χρόνου,
πάσης
δὲ
οὐσίας,
οἷόν
τε
οἴει
τούτῳ
μέγα
τι
δοκεῖν
εἶναι
τὸν
ἀνθρώπινον
βίον;
Ἀδύνατον,
ἦ
δ
ὅς.
Οὐκοῦν
καὶ
θάνατον
οὐ
δεινόν
τι
ἡγήσεται
ὁ
τοιοῦτος;
Ἥκιστά
γε.
148
pursue some human honors and consider them genuinely valuable because such honors
That the philosophers receive the highest honor is clear; that they desire it may at
first seem contentious. Before Socrates introduces the idea that philosophers must rule
the ideal city, he grants the greatest share of “immortality by proxy” to the “true
guardians.” Having weeded out and turned into auxiliaries the youths who cannot hold
fast to their true beliefs when tempted or after suffering misfortune, he claims that those
who can preserve their beliefs should be rulers (3: 412b-414a). Socrates claims that the
both while living and having died, and must be allotted the
414a1-4).146
Socrates refers back to this passage when he begins the discussion of the importance of a
wisdom for the city’s rulers and the philosophical education necessary to achieve it. He
reminds Glaucon of the standard by which they had earlier sorted the rulers from the
ruled and of their agreement that the one chosen to rule “must be given gifts and prizes
146
ἄρχοντα
τῆς
πόλεως
καὶ
φύλακα,
καὶ
τιμὰς
δοτέον
καὶ
ζῶντι
καὶ
τελευτήσαντι,
τάφων
τε
καὶ
τῶν
ἄλλων
μνημείων
μέγιστα
γέρα
λαγχάνοντα·
τὸν
δὲ
μὴ
τοιοῦτον
ἀποκριτέον.
147
ἐν
πόνοις
μήτ
ἐν
φόβοις
μήτ
ἐν
ἄλλῃ
μηδεμιᾷ
μεταβολῇ
φαίνεσθαι
ἐκβάλλοντας,
ἢ
τὸν
ἀδυνατοῦντα
ἀποκριτέον,
τὸν
δὲ
πανταχοῦ
ἀκήρατον
ἐκβαίνοντα
ὥσπερ
χρυσὸν
ἐν
149
Socrates, though, recognizes that the introduction of the philosophers has further
narrowed the field of candidates for ruling. Some of those earlier dubbed rulers will need
to be rejected because they are not suitable for academic rigor. Now it is the philosopher-
rulers who receive the greatest honors at death, both from the city and from the gods in
the afterlife.
The philosopher-ruler’s political honor twice coincides with her fate in the
afterlife. After her lengthy education, both practical and theoretical, she finally becomes
a ruler at the age of fifty (7: 540a). During the course of her service to the city, her
freedom to contemplate the truth is severely limited by practical necessity. Time spent
ruling takes away from time spent studying. However, once the philosopher-rulers have
passed on their craft to a new generation, they are finally permitted to engage in
and, when they have died, crown the life they have lived
πυρὶ
βασανιζόμενον,
στατέον
ἄρχοντα
καὶ
γέρα
δοτέον
καὶ
ζῶντι
καὶ
τελευτήσαντι
καὶ
ἆθλα.
148
πολιτικῶν
δὲ
καὶ
στρατειῶν
ἐκτὸς
γίγνηται,
τότε
ἤδη
ἀφέτους
νέμεσθαι
καὶ
μηδὲν
ἄλλο
πράττειν,
ὅτι
μὴ
πάρεργον,
τοὺς
μέλλοντας
εὐδαιμόνως
βιώσεσθαι
καὶ
τελευτήσαντας
τῷ
βίῳ
τῷ
βεβιωμένῳ
τὴν
ἐκεῖ
μοῖραν
ἐπιστήσειν
πρέπουσαν.
150
Later, Socrates claims that the “city makes public memorials and sacrifices to them as to
daemons, if the Pythia is in accord; if not, as to happy and divine men” (7: 540b7-c2),149
and when they die, they “go away to live on the Isles of the Blessed” (7:540b6-7). 150
Again, though, the fact that the philosophers receive the greatest honor, both in
this world and in the afterlife, does not entail that they actively seek or care about honor,
nor does it entail that they desire an afterlife. Set aside the afterlife for the moment,
though, and consider the human honors. In some instances, the philosopher’s honor
depends on not actively seeking or desiring it. Since the best rulers do not want to rule,
and philosophers do not want to rule, they certainly cannot pursue rule for the sake of
honor (1: 347a-d; 7: 521a-b).151 In addition, the philosopher will never pursue any honor
that leads to disorder in her soul, so many human honors are ruled out by necessity—
149
μνημεῖα
δ
αὐτοῖς
καὶ
θυσίας
τὴν
πόλιν
δημοσίᾳ
ποιεῖν,
ἐὰν
καὶ
ἡ
Πυθία
συναναιρῇ,
ὡς
δαίμοσιν,
εἰ
δὲ
μή,
ὡς
εὐδαίμοσί
τε
καὶ
θείοις.
150
εἰς
μακάρων
νήσους
ἀπιόντας
οἰκεῖν
151
The fact that the philosophers would choose to do something they do not want to do—
namely, rule—causes a puzzle that has issued in a sizable literature. The problem is that
if the philosopher realizes that the city will benefit from her rule, and that it is the right
thing to do, then she should want to do what is right. However, in this instance, she
cannot want what is right, since the best rulers are the rulers who do not want to rule.
Either the philosopher always has a fully harmonious soul and wants to rule, or she does
not always have a harmonious soul and does not want to rule. For various solutions to
this puzzle, see especially Kraut [1991], Irwin [1995], and Brown [2000]. Kraut and
Irwin both think that the philosopher willl desire to express her inner harmony by ruling.
Brown thinks that any explanation of this sort does not account for the fact that the
philosophers must be compelled to rule. He argues that the philosophers must be
following a legal order to rule, and they follow it because their inner hamony makes them
the sort of people who follow just laws.
151
Other honors, though, certainly do not lead to disorder in the soul, so one might
reasonably think that an array of honors remains open to the philosopher in the ideal city.
In fact, some honors should be pursued. At the most basic level, those engaged in a
philosophical education desire the successive honors they receive from the city when they
move on to the next stage of their education (7: 537b9, 537d4, 540e1). Socrates closes
out Book IX with the claim that in the ideal city, the supreme political honor will not
disturb the order and balance of the philosopher’s soul. Thus, in the ideal city, the
philosopher will “readily share in and taste” the honor of the citizens of the ideal city
that will win her immortal recognition, but only in the city in which philosophers rule.
Socrates clearly does not mean to suggest, then, that philosophers do not fear death
because they think nothing in life is valuable, such that death deprives them of nothing at
all.
One might object, though, that Socrates does not deny that the person with
“magnificent understanding” will afford human life “some value,” or even that immortal
honors might be worth pursuing when it does not compromise one’s virtuous character.
Rather, his point is that human life has little value when compared with all time. The
value of one individual life is negligible in the great expanse of time. The philosopher,
then, fears death less that other people because she recognizes that her life lacks
importance in the grand scheme of things. Honors may be nice, and life may be pleasant,
but overall, one individual life is a drop in the bucket of the organized cosmos.
152
It would be interesting to explore this option and interesting to determine whether
this stance offers any consolation (rather than despair) to your average person who fears
death. That is a matter for another time, though, since that is not what Socrates means
when he discusses the philosopher’s understanding of time. I argue that Plato thinks the
philosopher who has an understanding of being and time does not fear death because she
understands that souls are immortal and exist continuously and forever. Just like the non-
philosophers, the philosopher does not fear death because she looks forward to an
The chief evidence to support this claim is the prelude to the proof of the
immortality of the soul. Before Socrates recounts the final myth, or Myth of Er, he
returns the the “prizes, and gifts, and wages” (613e), which had been stripped away from
the just person in order to prove to Adeimantus and Glaucon that justice is intrinsically
good, independent of rewards. The returned human rewards, including the best
marriages, a good reputation, and the highest offices, are negligible, however, by
comparison to the greatest rewards (614a), which depend on the immortality of the soul.
153
“I don’t think so, “ he said. “But what do you mean by
this?”
The Republic’s argument for the immortality of the soul commences. As in the passage
at 486a, the philosopher cannot be “serious” about life when thinking about all time, but
only because one individual human life is simply a short time, a small drop in the bucket
of that particular soul’s immortality.153 So, the “magnificent understanding” does not
fear death because the soul is immortal, and if the afterlife resembles the Myth of Er, then
One might, of course, object that the argument for immortality and the myth are
offered in a particular context to individuals who are not philosophers, and that they
152
Τί
δ
ἄν,
ἦν
δ
ἐγώ,
ἔν
γε
ὀλίγῳ
χρόνῳ
μέγα
γένοιτο;
πᾶς
γὰρ
οὗτός
γε
ὁ
ἐκ
παιδὸς
μέχρι
πρεσβύτου
χρόνος
πρὸς
πάντα
ὀλίγος
πού
τις
ἂν
εἴη.
Οὐδὲν
μὲν
οὖν,
ἔφη.
Τί
οὖν;
οἴει
ἀθανάτῳ
πράγματι
ὑπὲρ
τοσούτου
δεῖν
χρόνου
ἐσπουδακέναι,
ἀλλ
οὐχ
ὑπὲρ
τοῦ
παντός;
Οἶμαι
ἔγωγ ,
ἔφη·
ἀλλὰ
τί
τοῦτο
λέγεις;
Οὐκ
ᾔσθησαι,
ἦν
δ
ἐγώ,
ὅτι
ἀθάνατος
ἡμῶν
ἡ
ψυχὴ
καὶ
οὐδέποτε
ἀπόλλυται;
153
As in the Phaedo chapter, I am not interested in evaluating the strength of the
arguments for immortality. The argument in the Republic has been criticized and even
ridiculed, though it has been defended by Brown [1997]. He argues that the argument is
formally valid, which means, of course, that anyone interested in derailing the argument
must demonstrate that one of the premises is false. Brown argues that the premises
themselves are not as indefensible as some have argued, and that those who deny any of
the premises risk jettisoning commitments that are at the heart of the Platonic ethical
project. Since many people who consider the argument a failure are not willing to
abandon these tenets of Plato’s ethical project, he argues they have reason to take the
argument seriously.
154
alone need to believe in the myth. Since Glaucon, Adeimantus, and Socrates have not
been educated in the ideal city, they benefit from instrumental religious beliefs that are
similar to those of the auxiliaries. The fact that Socrates discusses his own attitude
towards death with his standard “good hope” (6: 496d-e) indicates that he, too, expects an
afterlife just as he did in the Phaedo. Again, though, he is not the ideal philosopher.
My argument, then, requires that I lean heavily on the connection between these
two passages, the first concerning a philosopher in the city and the second, possibly
though not certainly, concerning a philosopher outside the ideal city. Nevertheless, I
think the connection can bear some heavy weight. If Plato were to believe that the
afterlife is a useful fiction, he seems to think it is useful for just about everyone, even for
those with a more perfect understanding of “time and being” (6: 486a8).
philosopher’s emotions. She controls her attitudes towards death in roughly the same
way as the auxiliary: she depends on the city to fulfill her nature; she must fight the
desire to grieve, since she grows attached to others; she values immortal honor, and
desires an afterlife.
There is one significant difference between the two classes that I am happy to
sustain the tenuous stability of their soul, while the auxiliaries will never be self-
regulating. So, the philosophers use the same strategies as the auxiliaries, but the
philosphers are “counterfactually reliable” across situations. Attaining the right attitudes
155
A final worry might trouble some readers. If adult philosophers in the ideal city
become fully virtuous, their virtue persists after regime change, and they exercise
masterful control over their desires and emotions, why does this expert control not pass
for elimination? After all, philosophers can stave off any pernicious effect that these
In some sense, I grant that it appears for all intents and purposes as elimination,
since her emotions are so disempowered that they cannot alter the course of the ideal
philosopher or upset the balance of her soul. Nevertheless, I contend that anything over
which one must constantly rule is not eliminated. For instance, if the philosopher lost
control over her rational part, perhaps through senility, madness, or some other
diminishment of her rational capacities, these desires would pop right back up. A
contingency of this sort, I suggest, indicates that the philosopher’s perfectly executed
CONCLUSION
The inherently irrational, “lawless” nature of human attitudes towards death is the
thread running through both of my chapters on the Republic. These desires and attitudes
arise and persist because of the creatures we are, and philosophers are human just like
non-philosophers. They fight off the same urges that spring up from the fertile soil of
their irrational soul. It should be unsurprising that they are better gardeners, and that
156
Plato, though, never seems to think that attachment and grief are healthy. They are
always weeds, and they always threaten virtue, and if the philosopher had her way, Plato
thinks she should eliminate them permanently. Whether this is the best conception of the
not, I think, merely a matter of taste. Plato comes down solidly against powerful
attachments because they cause psychological pain, increase fear, increase grief, and
tempt one to commit injustice. All things considered, those are pretty good reasons to
avoid attachments and fight the irrational part of the soul. On the other hand, the benefit
of becoming attached to other people and seeking out some protection from injustice may
be worth a mildly unbalanced soul and the willingness to commit a few injustices. This
157
WORKS CITED
Adam, J., ed. (1902). The Republic of Plato. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
---------(1999). "Plato's Republic and Feminism" in Plato 2, ed. Fine, G. Oxford: Oxford
Annas, J. (1999). Platonic Ethics, Old and New. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Co.
Barnes, J., ed. (1984). The Complete Works of Aristotle. 2 vols. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Barney, R. (2001). “Platonism, Moral Nostalgia, and the ‘City of Pigs,’” in Proceedings
423.
Benatar, D. (2006). Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence.
Benson, H., ed. (2000). Socratic Wisdom: The Model of Knowledge in Plato’s Early
158
Dialogues. New York: Oxford University Press.
Betegh, G. (2009). “Tale, theology and teleology in the Phaedo,” in Plato’s Myths. ed. by
Bett, R. (1999). "Immortality and the Nature of the Soul in the Phaedrus" in Plato 2, ed.
Bloom, A. (1968). trans. The Republic of Plato. New York: Basic Books.
Bobonich, C. (2002). Plato's Utopia Recast: His Later Ethics and Politics. Oxford:
---------(1999). "The Soul and Immortality in Plato's Phaedo" in Plato 2, ed. Fine, G.
Brickhouse, T. C. and N. D. Smith (1989). "A Matter of Life and Death in Socratic
Brisson, L. (1998). Plato the Myth Maker. trans. G. Naddaf. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
159
Philosophy 20, 1-17.
---------(2004). “Minding the Gap in Plato’s Republic,” Philosophical Studies. 117: 275-
302.
Burnet, J., ed. (1900-1907). Platonis Opera. 5 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Press.
----------(1999). “Utopia and Fantasy: The Practicability of Plato’s Ideally Just City,” in
Cicero (2001). On Moral Ends. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy. Annas, J.
Cooper, J. (1999). Reason and Emotion: Essays on moral Psychology and Ethical Theory.
Cornford, F. M. (1941). The Republic of Plato. New York: Oxford University Press.
160
Dodds, E. R. (1971). "Plato and the Irrational Soul" in Plato II: A Collection of Critical
Essays, ed. Vlastos, G. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press: 206-229
Duke, E. A., Hicken, W. F., Nicoll, W. S. M., Robinson, D. B., and Strachan, J. C. G.
Dyer, L. (1893). Apology of Socrates and Crito. Boston: Ginn & Company.
Edmonds, R. G. (2004). Myths of the Underworld Journey: Plato, Aristophanes, and the
Ehnmark, Erland. 1946. “Socrates and the Immortality of the Soul,” Eranos 44: 105-122.
Enright, D. J., ed. (2002). The Oxford Book of Death. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fine, G., ed. (1999). Plato 2. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Gill, C. (1985). “Plato and the Education of Character,” Archiv für Geschichte der
Gooch, P. W. (1974). “The Relation between Wisdom and Virtue in Phaedo 69a6-c3,”
161
Grote, G. (1888). Plato and the Other Companions of Sokrates. London: John Murray.
Guthrie, W. K. C. (1971). "Plato's Views on the Nature of the Soul" in Plato II: A
Collection of Crtical Essays, ed. Vlastos, G., 230-243. Notre Dame: University of
Lamberton, R. (1993). Works and Days and Theogony, Hesiod. trans. Lombardo, S.
Hourani, G. F. (1949). “The Education of the Third Class in Plato’s Republic.” Classical
Irwin, T. (1992). "Socrates the Epicurean?" in Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates, ed.
Kraut, R., ed. (1992). The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
---------(1991). “Return to the Cave: Republic 519-521,” Proceedings of the Boston Area
Colloquium. 7: 43-62.
162
---------(1992). "The Defense of Justice in Plato's Republic" in The Cambridge
Press.
Lear, J. (1992). “Inside and Outside the Republic,” Phronesis 37: 184-215.
University Press.
---------(2006). “The Gods and Piety in Plato’s Republic” in The Blackwell Guide to
Plato’s Republic. ed. by. Santas, G. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing: 84-103.
Miles, M. (2001). “Plato on Suicide (Phaedo 60c-63c),” Phoenix. 55, 3/4: 244-58.
Plato, ed. Kraut, R.. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press: 227-247.
Moss, J. (2007). “What is Imitative Poetry and Why is it Bad?” in The Cambridge
---------(2001). The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and
163
Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Okin, S. M. (1976-1977). “Philosopher Queens and Private Wives: Plato on Women and
Pearson, L. (1962). Popular Ethics in Ancient Greece. Palo Alto: Stanford University
Press.
Penner, T. (1992). "Socrates and the Early Dialogues" in The Cambridge Companion to
Plato (1991). The Symposium. Allen, R. E. New Haven: Yale University Press.
164
---------(1996). Of Art and Wisdom. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Rudebusch, G. (1999). Socrates, Pleasure, and Value. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Shorey, Paul (1956). trans. Plato: The Republic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Strauss, L. (1952). Persecution and the Art of Writing. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
Strycker, Emile de, and Simon R. Slings (1994). Plato’s Apology of Socrates: a Literary
Taylor, A. E. (1927). Plato: The Man and His Work. London: Methuen and Co.
University Press.
of Crtical Essays, ed. Vlastos, G., Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press:
244-258.
Vlastos, G. (1991). Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca: Cornell University
Press.
---------(1999). "Socratic Piety" in Plato 2, ed. Fine, G. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
165
---------(1999). "The Individual as an Object of Love in Plato" in Plato 2, ed. Fine, G.,.
Warren, J. (2004). Facing Death: Epicurus and his Critics. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Weiss, R. (1987). “The Right Exchange: Phaedo 69a6-c3,” Ancient Philosophy 7: 57-66.
---------(1989). “The Hedonic Calculus in the Protagoras and the Phaedo,” Journal of the
Co.
University Presses.
Williams, B. (1999). "The Analogy of the City and Soul in Plato's Republic" in Plato 2,
166