Löwith-Taubes - Evil in History
Löwith-Taubes - Evil in History
Löwith-Taubes - Evil in History
Eschatology
Willem Styfhals
Journal of the History of Ideas, Volume 76, Number 2, April 2015, pp. 191-213
(Article)
Access provided by Universitat Pompeu Fabra (30 Jan 2019 14:34 GMT)
Evil in History: Karl Löwith and
Jacob Taubes on Modern Eschatology
Willem Styfhals
This article has benefitted greatly from the advice of André Cloots, Jerry Z. Muller, Mark
Lilla, Nicolas de Warren, Stéphane Symons, and the readers for the Journal of the History
of Ideas.
1
Karl Löwith, Meaning in History: The Theological Implications of the Philosophy of
History (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1949), 2, 60.
2
Jacob Taubes, Abendländische Eschatologie (Berlin: Matthes und Seitz, 1947). I refer to
the English translation: Jacob Taubes, Occidental Eschatology, trans. David Ratmoko
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009).
3
Carl Schmitt, Der Nomos der Erde im Völkerrecht des Jus Publikum Europaeum
(Cologne: Greven, 1950); Eric Voegelin, The New Science of Politics: An Introduction
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952); Norman Cohn, The Pursuit of the Millen-
Copyright by Journal of the History of Ideas, Volume 76, Number 2 (April 2015)
191
PAGE 191
................. 18716$ $CH2 03-30-15 06:16:52 PS
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF IDEAS ✦ APRIL 2015
nium: Revolutionary Millenarians and Mystical Anarchists of the Middle Ages (London:
Pimlico, 1957).
4
Hans Blumenberg, The Legitimacy of the Modern Age, trans. Robert Wallace (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1983), 37–52.
5
See Robert M. Wallace, ‘‘Progress, Secularization, and Modernity: The Löwith-
Blumenberg Debate,’’ New German Critique 22 (1981): 64; Martin Jay, ‘‘Review of The
Legitimacy of the Modern Age,’’ History and Theory 24 (1985): 192; Laurence Dickey,
‘‘Blumenberg and Secularization: Self-Assertion and the Problem of Self-Realizing Teleol-
ogy in History,’’ New German Critique 41 (1987): 152.
192
6
Löwith, Meaning in History, 248 n.19 and 255–56 n.4.
7
Karl Löwith, Von Hegel zu Nietzsche. Der revolutionaire Bruch im Denken des neun-
zehnten Jahrhunderts (Zürich: Europa Verlag AG, 1941), part I, chap. I and V; Karl
Löwith, ‘‘Nietzsche’s Doctrine of Eternal Recurrence,’’ Journal of the History of Ideas 6
(1945): 3, 274.
8
Jacob Taubes, To Carl Schmitt: Letters and Reflections, trans. Keith Tribe (New York:
Columbia University Press, 2013), 2.
9
Jacob Taubes, The Political Theology of Paul, trans. Dana Hollander (Stanford: Stan-
ford University Press, 2004).
10
Giorgio Agamben, The Time that Remains: A Commentary on the Letter to the
Romans, trans. Patricia Dailey (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005). For Taubes
and Agamben see Nitzan Lebovic, ‘‘The Jerusalem School: The Theopolitical Hour,’’
New German Critique 35 (2008): 97–120; Mark Lilla, ‘‘A New, Political Saint-Paul,’’
The New York Review of Books 55 (2008): 16. For Taubes and interwar political theol-
ogy see Benjamin Lazier, ‘‘On the Origins of Political Theology: Judaism and Heresy
between the World Wars,’’ New German Critique 35 (2008): 143–64; Marin Terpstra,
193
‘‘God’s Love for his Enemies: Jacob Taubes’ Conversation with Carl Schmitt on Paul,’’
International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 70 (2009): 185–206.
11
Löwith, Meaning in History, 1–7; Taubes, Occidental Eschatology, 3–9.
12
Jan Assmann, Of God and Gods: Egypt, Israel and the Rise of Monotheism (Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press, 2008), 122.
194
13
Löwith, Meaning in History, 197.
195
14
Ibid., 160–73.
15
Ibid., 195.
16
For the (a)political role of incarnation also see Marcel Gauchet, The Disenchantment
of the World: A Political History of Religion, trans. Oscar Burge (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1999), 76–86; Mark Lilla, The Stillborn God: Religion, Politics and the
Modern West (New York: Vintage Books, 2008), 31–39.
17
Löwith, Meaning in History, 195.
18
Gershom Scholem, ‘‘Toward an Understanding of the Messianic Idea in Judaism,’’ in
The Messianic Idea in Judaism and Other Essays on Jewish Spirituality (New York:
Schocken Books, 1971), 1.
196
19
See Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica: Volume I—Part I (New York: Cosimo,
2007), art. 49.
20
Aurelius Augustine, On the Free Choice of Will, On Grace and free Choice, and other
Writings, ed. Peter King (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010).
21
Löwith, Meaning in History, 3.
197
hope for a better, and hence significantly different future has to be imagin-
able. Since this projected future presupposes an ontological subversion in
the course of time as the linear transition from evil to good, history has to
allow for structural change. Meaning in history is thus indissolubly con-
nected to the possibility of historical change proper.
Consequently, the interconnected problems of evil, hope, and salvation
are for Löwith absent in a non-eschatological conception of time—he has
the Greek-Nietzschean eternal recurrence in mind.22 Observing that ‘‘no
similar hope and despair can be found in any classical writer,’’ Löwith
maintains that the classical cosmologies, and Greek philosophy combined
an ontological optimism with a cyclic conception of time.23 Not unlike his
teacher Martin Heidegger, Löwith obviously had a very monolithic and
idealized conception of ‘‘the Greeks.’’ In his perspective, the optimism of
Greek cosmologies guaranteed that the ancient experiences of evil could
not have had ontological bearing. These cosmological presuppositions are
also reflected in the ancient experience of time. Because cosmological evil is
absent, the hope for a better and different future did not exist, or was con-
sidered to be a form of Hubris.24 Since Löwith, not unlike Nietzsche, char-
acterizes the Greek experience of time as a continuous repetition of the
same cycle, the past, present, and future are even structurally indistinguish-
able in Greek thought: ‘‘According to the Greek view of life and the world,
everything moves in recurrences, like the eternal recurrence of sunrise and
sunset, of summer and winter, of generation and corruption.’’25As such,
significant events in the political or cultural history could never be con-
ceived as real evolutions. For Löwith, structural historical changes, let
alone progress, are philosophically inconceivable in ancient thought: ‘‘To
the Greek thinkers a philosophy of history would have been a contradiction
in terms.’’ Philosophical knowledge can only be about the unchangeable:
‘‘The immutable, as visible in the fixed order of the heavenly bodies,
had a higher interest and value to them than any progressive and radical
change.’’26
According to Löwith, the problem of evil that gave history its eschato-
logical meaning is thus absent in antiquity. Apparently, the eschatological
22
Karl Löwith, Nietzsche’s Philosophy of the Eternal Recurrence of the Same, trans.
Harvey Lomax (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1997).
23
Löwith, Meaning in History, 61.
24
Julian Potter, ‘‘Meaning in Eternity: Karl Löwith’s Critique of Hope and Hubris,’’ The-
sis Eleven 110 (2012): 27–45.
25
Löwith, Meaning in History, 4.
26
Ibid.
198
search for meaning in history only arises if humanity can no longer conceive
the world as a harmonious cosmos. When the experience of evil is so funda-
mental, historical change first becomes conceivable, and eventually even
necessary. For Löwith, the relation between linear time and the problem of
evil, however, is also valid in the opposite sense. The meaning of history is
not just an answer to the problem of evil, but the experience of evil itself is
only conceivable within the eschatological perspective of the ultimate
meaning of history: ‘‘it is only within a pre-established horizon of ultimate
meaning, that actual history seems to be meaningless. This horizon has been
established by history, for it is Hebrew and Christian thinking that brought
this colossal question into existence.’’27 Without the touchstone of a future
that gives meaning to history as a whole, the present state of affairs cannot
be experienced as evil or meaningless. Singular historical events in their
own right do not have any meaning at all—as such, they are neither good
nor bad.
In the Christian tradition, the eschatological interpretation of history
is initially present without an explicit emphasis on the problem of evil. As
the dynamics of evil remain latent or at least ambiguous in (medieval)
Christianity, the linearity of eschatological time seems to be more primor-
dial than the problem of evil. This is why, in Scholasticism, the optimism
of Greek cosmology could still be reconciled with Christian eschatology.
Nonetheless, the historical structure of Christianity will eventually allow
the problem of evil to resurface. Once a better future is thinkable, inevita-
bly, the depravity of the present world becomes conceivable. Such conse-
quences of Christian eschatology will only be manifested after the rise of
modernity and modern eschatology.
In sum, the fundamental intertwining of evil and history is pivotal for
Löwith: there can be no history without evil, no evil without history. This
discovery shows that the comparison between the modern philosophies of
history and Christian eschatology assumes an interpretation of the role of
evil in modernity. Because the problem of evil is the driving force of escha-
tology, this problem will also play a crucial role in the genesis of modern
progress. Without a pessimistic attitude to the present world or to human-
ity, the need for future salvation and progress would expire. For Löwith,
‘‘the starting point of the modern religions of progress is an eschatological
anticipation of the future salvation and consequently a vision of the present
state of mankind as one of depravity.’’28 To the extent that Löwith’s Mean-
ing in History is primarily concerned with the problem of secularization, he
27
Ibid.
28
Ibid., 61.
199
obviously does not present the question of evil as the key problem for mod-
ern thought. However, in order to grasp the full scope of Löwith’s argu-
ment, it is crucial to understand how he considers evil to be constitutive for
eschatology, both in its pre-modern and in its modern guise. In Evil in Mod-
ern Thought, Susan Neiman also favors such a reading of Löwith’s thought.
Observing ‘‘the absence of explicit discussion of the problem of evil’’ in
twentieth-century philosophy, she finds that the ‘‘post-war German history
of philosophy, by contrast, offered rich and significant work related to
many aspects of the problem.’’29 She even refers explicitly to Löwith, as
well as to Jacob Taubes, for that matter.30 This emphasis on the role of evil
in Löwith’s work keeps us from reducing his comparison between modern
progress and eschatology to the mere formal resemblance between their
respective orientations towards the future. By defining progress as secular-
ized eschatology, Löwith rather discovers a substantial continuity of onto-
logical problems between modernity and pre-modernity. As such, both the
eschatological problem of evil and the possibility of salvation remain fun-
damental for modern thought.
Nonetheless, Löwith argues that modern thought rejects the Christian
interpretation of salvation, and tries to solve the problem of evil by new—
now secular—means. The modern overcoming of evil is not a spiritual sal-
vation of the individual believer; rather, it becomes a historical and
controllable progress towards an immanently perfect world. Modernity
thus formulates a radically original answer to a problem that is fundamen-
tally entwined with the Judeo-Christian tradition. On this account, Löwith
radically criticizes modernity and modern progress. He argues that the
modern secularization of Christian eschatology corrupts the transcendent
and individual meaning of Christian salvation. The modern notion of prog-
ress is therefore an illegitimate heir of Christian theology: progress is escha-
tology’s bastard. The modern philosophers of history, such as Voltaire,
Condorcet, Hegel or Marx, borrow the theological framework of the his-
tory of salvation, but apply it to the immanent course of profane history.31
These modern thinkers attribute meaning and direction to history by trans-
forming the spiritual faith in the transcendent fulfillment of history into
the rational belief in a historical progress towards a perfect world. This
immanent, and hence politico-historical eschatology is inconceivable in
29
Susan Neiman, Evil in Modern Thought (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002),
288–90.
30
Ibid., 334 n. 19.
31
For Hegel and Marx also see: Löwith, Von Hegel zu Nietzsche, part I, chap. I, III,
and V.
200
32
See the later German translation of Meaning in History: Karl Löwith, Weltgeschichte
und Heilsgeschehen: Die theologischen Voraussetzungen der Geschichtphilosophie (Stutt-
gart: W. Kohlhammer, 1953).
33
See Jeffrey A. Barash, ‘‘The Sense of History: On the Political Implications of Karl
Löwith’s Concept of Secularization,’’ History and Theory 37 (1998): 69–82.
34
Karl Löwith, Heidegger and European Nihilism, ed. Richard Wolin and trans. Gary
Steiner (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995).
35
Richard Wolin, Heidegger’s Children: Hannah Arendt, Karl Löwith, Hans Jonas, and
Herbert Marcuse (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001), 78.
201
36
Ibid., 97.
37
Löwith, Meaning in History, 201–2.
38
Blumenberg, The Legitimacy, 32. Also see: Amos Funkenstein, Heilsplan und natür-
liche Entwicklung: Formen der Gegenwartsbestimmung im Geschichtsdenken des hohen
Mittelalters (Munich: Nymphenburg, 1965).
39
Löwith, Meaning in History, 60–61 (my emphasis).
202
In 1949, Hans Jonas, the most important Gnosticism scholar at the time,
received an invitation from Jacob Taubes to discuss the latter’s recently
published book Occidental Eschatology. In this book, Taubes referred
repeatedly to Jonas’s monumental two-volume work on ancient Gnosti-
cism, Gnosis und Spätantiker Geist (Gnosticism and the Spirit of Late
Antiquity).40 Not unlike Jonas, Taubes’s eschatological analysis of the his-
tory of Western thought recognizes Gnostic features in modern philosophy.
Jonas, however, neither knew Taubes, nor the book in question, and asked
his colleague Karl Löwith whether he was familiar with Taubes’s work:
Before the meeting I asked Karl Löwith, ‘‘Do you happen to know
a Jacob Taubes?’’ ‘‘Of course I know him,’’ he replied. ‘‘Well could
you tell me something about him? He’s sent me a letter. I’ve never
heard of him, but he refers to a book he’s written and asks to meet
me. Do you know the book?’’ ‘‘Oh, yes,’’ he said, ‘‘I know the
book.’’ ‘‘Well, is it any good?’’ At that he said, laughing, ‘‘Oh, it’s
a very good book. And that’s no accident—half of it’s by you and
the other half’s by me.’’41
Löwith and Jonas suggest that Taubes’s analysis, though interesting, is not
a very original contribution. One has to admit that Taubes, indeed, relies
heavily on Jonas’s conception of Gnosticism and on Löwith’s interpretation
of eschatology and modernity. Nonetheless, precisely because of Taubes’s
idiosyncratic combination of these two perspectives—Gnosticism and
eschatology—his position can be very revealing, especially with regard to
the role of evil in modern eschatology. Unlike Christian eschatology, which
40
Hans Jonas, Gnosis und spätantiker Geist. Die mythologische Gnosis (Göttingen: Van-
denhoeck und Ruprecht, 1934–35).
41
Hans Jonas, Memoirs, trans. Krishna Winston (Lebanon, N.H.: Brandeis University
Press, 2008), 168.
203
42
For Taubes’s notion of Gnosticism see Carsten Colpe, ‘‘Das eschatologische Wieder-
lager der Politik: Zu Jacob Taubes’ Gnosisbild,’’ in Abendländische Eschatologie. Ad
Jacob Taubes, ed. Richard Faber (Würzberg: Königshausen und Neumann, 2001),
105–29.
43
Taubes, Occidental Eschatology, 10.
44
Ibid., 35.
204
God and the world are not distant but estranged and divided, and
therefore hold each other in mutual tension. Just as there is noth-
ing of God in the cosmos, so God is the nothing of the world. In
the world God is the one who is ‘‘unknown,’’ ‘‘hidden,’’ ‘‘without
a name,’’ and ‘‘other.’’48
In Gnosticism, says Taubes, this radical separation between God and world
will result in an extremely pessimistic ontology that reverses Greek cos-
mology:
45
Gershom Scholem, Major Trends in Jewish Mysticism (New York: Schocken Books,
1946), 7.
46
Benjamin Lazier, God Interrupted: Heresy and the European Imagination between the
World Wars (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008).
47
See Blumenberg, The Legitimacy of the Modern Age, part II.
48
Taubes, Occidental Eschatology, 39.
205
Being characterized by the most radical dualism between God and the
world, Gnosticism claims that material reality is created by an inferior,
fallen or even downright evil principle. In addition, the Gnostics believe in
a transcendent salvation from this evil through the knowledge of this sad
cosmological truth. Gnosis is the mystical knowledge of the immanent
world’s depravity and the transcendent deity’s unaffected goodness.
In light of this, Gnosticism casts the historical basis of Apocalypticism
in an ontological mold. The historical separation between the present world
and the future kingdom of God becomes an ontological antithesis between
transcendence and immanence, between good and evil. Taubes argues that
Gnosticism gives a theoretical and speculative framework to the apocalyp-
tic myths and narratives about human alienation and the end of time: ‘‘In
their narration of the history of the world the apocalyptic myths introduce
self-estrangement as a dramatic leitmotif, and it is on this very theme that
the more theoretical, ontological speculations of Gnosis are founded. The
boundaries between Apocalypticism and Gnosis are, of course, fluid.’’50
The ontological perspective of Gnosticism, however, does not abolish
the historical and eschatological features of Apocalypticism. On the con-
trary, according to Taubes’s interpretation of Gnosticism, the ontological
evil of Gnostic cosmology is only conceivable as historical evil. Just like
Löwith, Taubes argues that the problem of evil is fundamentally inter-
twined with historicity and with the linear direction of time—no evil with-
out history, no history without evil. The latter’s reading of Gnosticism
shows that the immanent world is depraved because it is finite. In Taubes’s
perspective, this finitude can only be conceived historically. The world is
finite to the extent that its existence is essentially temporary, that is to say,
to the extent that its history has a beginning and an end. When we refer to
the end of the world, we always mean the end of time. Moreover, because
of its essential temporality, the world—both temporary and temporal—is
49
Ibid., 28.
50
Ibid., 36.
206
the antithesis of God’s eternity. In this respect, Taubes argues that time is
by definition the absence of the divine. Therefore, world history, being the
total absence of God and its divine goodness, is radically evil: ‘‘History is
identical with the aeon of sin, which is embedded between creation and
redemption.’’51 Finally, the end of time is only conceivable as salvation. The
end of history is indeed the transition from temporality to eternity, that is,
from godlessness to God, and from evil to good. In this respect, the end of
time is the redemptive end of sin.
For Taubes, this pessimistic cosmology of Gnosticism and Apocalyptic-
ism as well as their historical structure returns in what he calls the ‘‘apoca-
lyptic waves of the modern age.’’52 The discovery of the genealogical
connection between modernity and eschatology is thus also the discovery
of the epochal role of evil in modern thought and German idealism: ‘‘It is
vitally important for the history of German idealism that the eschatology
of early Christianity, even if clandestine and apocryphal, continue [. . .]
alongside the Enlightenment, so that knowledge of the radical nature of evil
is preserved.’’53 Modernity breaks with traditional Christianity, and revives
the Gnostic and apocalyptic spirit of early Christianity. In this regard,
Gnostic modernity radically rejects medieval Scholasticism’s static and
ahistorical rationality. In the same vein, however, Taubes’s interpretation
of modernity is also highly critical of rationalism and enlightenment. Refer-
ring to the earthquake of Lisbon, he claims that modern man is confronted
with experiences of evil and irrationality ‘‘which the system of reason is
unable to fathom.’’54 Thus rejecting enlightenment as well as Scholasticism,
Taubes maintains that modern man can neither interpret the world as a
good and rationally ordered universe, nor as a reflection of a transcendent
reality. In other words, the modern world is cut off from transcendence,
and becomes a de-divinized, meaningless, and possibly evil facticity that is
not created for the sake of the human being. In this nihilistic worldview,
Taubes recognizes, not unlike Hans Jonas, the modern return of Gnosti-
cism.55
Because of this disappearance of transcendence, however, the modern
world does not only lose its goodness and rationality, but the traditional
Christian hope for a transcendent salvation also becomes insignificant. For
this reason, says Taubes, modernity reintroduces history:
51
Ibid.
52
Ibid., 85.
53
Ibid., 130.
54
Ibid., 86.
55
Hans Jonas, ‘‘Gnosticism and Modern Nihilism,’’ Social Research 19 (1952): 430–52.
207
56
Taubes, Occidental Eschatology, 137.
57
Joshua R. Gold, ‘‘Jacob Taubes: Apocalypse From Below,’’ Telos 134 (2006): 142.
208
58
Jacob Taubes, ‘‘Notes on Surrealism,’’ in From Cult to Culture: Fragments Towards a
Critique of Historical Reason, ed. Charlotte Elisheva Fonrobert and Amir Engel (Stan-
ford: Stanford University Press, 2010), 98–123.
59
Taubes, Occidental Eschatology, 86.
60
Jacob Taubes, ‘‘The Price of Messianism,’’ in From Cult to Culture, 9.
209
the problem of evil was so central. Unlike Hannah Arendt’s more concep-
tual analyses, Taubes’s and Löwith’s historical outlook kept them from
confronting the evils of the Holocaust head on.61 Nonetheless, these events
must have been in the back of their minds when they tried to make sense of
the history of Western thought. Although neither thinker developed an
explicit interpretation of totalitarianism, their respective positions can be
thought through in such a way that they do allow for an implied evaluation
of it. Relying heavily on Taubes and Löwith, Eric Voegelin, for example,
explicitly connected totalitarianism to the secularization of eschatology and
to Gnosticism.62
Strikingly, however, neither Taubes’s nor Löwith’s philosophical
framework allows for any real consolation, or even hope to overcome the
evils of the Second World War. For Löwith, hope is no longer an option
today. On the contrary, it was the modern eschatological structure of hope
itself that had made the horrible events of the Second World War possible in
the first place. In this regard, totalitarianism appears as the ultimate human
attempt to create a historical eschaton as the immanent overcoming of evil.
For Löwith, this is the most explosive and dangerous feature of modern
Hubris, as it paradoxically generates new and even greater forms of evil:
‘‘There are in history not only ‘flowers of evil’ but also evils which are the
fruit of too much good will and of a mistaken Christianity that confounds
the fundamental distinction between redemptive events and profane hap-
penings, between Heilsgeschehen and Weltgeschichte.’’63 Because the fund-
amentalist faith—‘‘too much good will’’—in a ‘‘final solution’’ for the
problem of evil has proven to be fraught with dangers, Löwith proposes to
abandon the eschatological principle of hope altogether. In view of its mod-
ern and totalitarian excesses, every form of eschatology has now become
suspect. He thereby rejects any simple return to Christianity or, for that
matter, to Judaism as a solution for the modern crisis. In contrast to many
of his Jewish contemporaries, including Gershom Scholem, Ernst Bloch, or
Taubes himself, Löwith wonders ‘‘whether the future is really the proper
horizon of a truly human existence.’’64 The Judeo-Christian perspective of
future-oriented hope has been perverted to such an extent that it has
61
Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1951);
Hannah Arendt, Eichmann In Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York:
Viking Press, 1964).
62
Voegelin, The New Science of Politics, 110–27. For the reference to Taubes and Löwith:
ibid., 111 n. 8.
63
Löwith, Meaning in History, 203.
64
Ibid., 204.
210
Two short years after the end of the most horrible destruction the
Jewish people had ever known, Taubes offered no comforting
words. Against the passive hope of those confronting the end of
the world, Taubes emphasized in 1947 the need for an immediate
decision[. . . .] Taubes had in mind a Schmittian operation from
within the destructive situation: it involved using and abusing
destruction as a tool, acknowledging its inevitability.66
In this respect, the evil of the Holocaust would be the ultimate confirmation
of the Gnostic-apocalyptic worldview for Taubes. Paradigmatically, it is in
the most intense moments of violent oppression and radical evil that the
end of time is nearest. In this regard, the Holocaust itself appears as the
apocalyptic catastrophe par excellence.67 The force of the apocalypse is for
Taubes always primarily destructive, nihilistic, and negative. Moreover, it
is only from within this negation itself that an absent God, who is in every
respect opposite to the world, can manifest himself. God’s fundamental
absence is thus the condition of possibility of the apocalyptic redemption.
Some postwar Jewish theologians, many of whom Taubes knew personally,
have indeed argued that God was fundamentally absent from the world
during the Second World War.68 In this sense, Taubes’s Gnostic conception
of God’s absence in many respects prefigures Holocaust theology’s central
notion of Hester Panim.
65
‘‘Jacob Taubes,’’ in Denken, das an der Zeit ist, ed. Florian Roetzer (Franfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp, 1987), 317.
66
Lebovic, ‘‘The Jerusalem School,’’ 106.
67
See Martin Treml, ‘‘Nachwort,’’ in Jacob Taubes, Abendländische Eschatologie
(Munich: Matthes und Seitz, 2007), 287.
68
Martin Buber, The Eclipse of God: Studies in the Relation between Religion and Philos-
ophy (New York: Humanity Books, 1952).
211
69
Peter Gordon, ‘‘Jacob Taubes, Karl Löwith, and the Interpretation of Jewish History,’’
in German-Jewish Thought between Religion and Politics, ed. Christian Wiese and Mar-
tina Urban (Boston: De Gruyter, 2012), 351.
70
Jürgen Moltmann, The Coming of God: Christian Eschatology, trans. Margaret Kohl
(London: SCM Press, 1996), 41–44; Mark Jaeger, ‘‘Jacob Taubes und Karl Löwith: Apo-
logie und Kritik des Heilsgeschichtlichen Denkens,’’ in Abendländische Eschatologie. Ad
Jacob Taubes, ed. Richard Faber (Würzberg: Königshausen und Neumann, 2001), 485–
508.
71
Odo Marquard, Schwierigkeiten mit der Geschichtsphilosophie: Aufsätze (Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp, 1973), 15.
212
University of Leuven.
72
See Jerry Z. Muller, ‘‘Reisender in Ideeen: Jacob Taubes zwischen New York, Jerusa-
lem, Berlin und Paris,’’ in ‘‘Ich staune, dass Sei in dieser Luft atmen können’’: Deutsch-
jüdische Intellektuelle in Deutschland nach 1945, ed. Monika Boll and Raphael Gross
(Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag, 2013), 48.
213