Immanuel Khant
Immanuel Khant
Immanuel Khant
Prepared by
Marigel Corpin
BSBA HR 1-K
Presented to
Prof. Vhon Villanueva
January 2019
TABLE OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION
Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant is a philosopher who tried to work out how human beings
could be good and kind – outside of the exhortations and blandishments
of traditional religion.
He was born in 1724 in the Baltic city of Königsberg, which at that time
was part of Prussia, and now belongs to Russia (renamed Kaliningrad).
Kant’s parents were very modest; his father was a saddle maker. Kant
never had much money – which he dealt with cheerfully by living very
modestly. It wasn’t until he was in his fifties that he became a fully
salaried professor and attained a moderate degree of prosperity.
His family were deeply religious and very strict. Later in life, Kant did not
have any conventional religious belief, but he was acutely aware of how
much religion had contributed to his parents’ ability to cope with all the
hardships of their existence – and how useful religion could be in fostering
social cohesion and community.
Kant was physically very slight, frail and anything but good looking. But
he was very sociable and some of his colleagues used to criticise him for
going to too many parties.
**
-3-
pessimist about human character and believed that we are by nature
intensely prone to corruption.
It was this awareness that led him to what would be his life’s project: the
desire to replace religious authority with the authority of reason; that is,
human intelligence. Kant pursued this grand project in a major series of
books with fearsome titles, including:
It was in this context that Kant came up with the idea for which he is
perhaps still most famous: what he called the Categorical Imperative.
This strange sounding term first appeared in a horrendously named
work, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. It states:
“Act only according to that maxim by which you can at the same time will
that it should become a universal law.”
What did Kant mean by this? This was only a very formal restatement of
an idea that had been around for a long time – something we meet with
in all the main religions: “do unto others as you would have them do unto
you”. Kant was offering a handy way of testing the morality of an action
or pattern of behaviour by imagining how it would be if it were generally
practiced and you were the victim of it.
Similarly, if you have an affair and keep it quiet from your partner you
might feel it’s OK. But the Categorical Imperative comes down against
this, because you would have to embrace the idea that it would be equally
OK for your partner to have affairs and not tell you.
The Categorical Imperative is designed to shift our perspective: to get us
to see our own behaviour in less immediately personal terms and thereby
recognise some of its limitations.
Kant went on to argue that the core idea of the Categorical Imperative
could be stated in another way: “Act so as to treat people always as ends
in themselves, never as mere means.”
Kant extended his thinking about the Categorical Imperative into the
political sphere. He believed that the central duty of government was to
ensure liberty. But he sensed that there was something wrong with the
ordinary definition of freedom. It should not be thought of
in libertarian terms: as the ability to do whatever we want. We are free
only when we act in accordance with our own best natures; we are slaves
whenever we are under the rule of our own passions or those of others.
As he put it, ‘a free will and a will under moral laws are one and the
same.’
As we’ve been seeing, Kant thought that life involved a constant struggle
between our better selves and our passions, between duty and pleasure.
-5-
Beauty – Kant especially liked roses, vines, apple trees and birds –
delights us in a very special and important way. It is a reminder of, and
goad to, our better selves. Unlike so much else in our lives, our love of
beauty is ‘disinterested’. It takes us out of narrow selfish concerns, but in
a charming, delightful way – without being stern or demanding. The
beauty of nature is a continual, quiet and insistent reminder of our
common universal being. A pretty flower is just as attractive to the tired
farmworker as to the prince; the graceful flight of a swallow is as lovely to
a child as to the most learned professor.
For Kant, the role of art is to embody the most important ethical ideas.
It’s an extension of philosophy. He held we needed to have art continually
before us so as benefit from vivid illustrations and memorable symbols of
good behaviour, and thereby keep the wayward parts of ourselves in
check.
SUMMARY
IMMANUEL KANT
Kant also argued that his ethical theory requires belief in free will, God,
and the immortality of the soul. Although we cannot have knowledge of
these things, reflection on the moral law leads to a justified belief in
them, which amounts to a kind rational faith. Thus in answer to the
question, “What may I hope?” Kant replies that we may hope that our
souls are immortal and that there really is a God who designed the world
in accordance with principles of justice.
-7-
In addition to these three focal points, Kant also made lasting
contributions to nearly all areas of philosophy. His aesthetic theory
remains influential among art critics. His theory of knowledge is required
reading for many branches of analytic philosophy. The cosmopolitanism
behind his political theory colors discourse about globalization and
international relations. And some of his scientific contributions are even
considered intellectual precursors to several ideas in contemporary
cosmology.
Kant’s books were dense, abstract and highly intellectual. But in them he
sketched a highly important project that remains crucial to this day. He
wanted to understand how the better, more reasonable parts of our
nature could be strengthened so as to reliably win out over our inbuilt
weaknesses and selfishness. As he saw it, he was engaged in the task of
developing a secular, rational version of what religions had (very
imperfectly) always attempted to do: help us to be good.
-9-