Indiana University Press Transactions of The Charles S. Peirce Society
Indiana University Press Transactions of The Charles S. Peirce Society
Peirce's Realism
Author(s): Claudine Engel-Tiercelin
Source: Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, Vol. 28, No. 1 (Winter, 1992), pp. 51-
82
Published by: Indiana University Press
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40320354
Accessed: 20-04-2020 20:53 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/40320354?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Indiana University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Claudine Etyjel-Tiercelin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
52 Claudinc Engcl-Ticrcclin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity ofC.S. Peirce's Realism 53
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
54 Claudinc Engel-Tiercelin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity of C.S. Pcirce's Realism 55
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
56 Claudinc Engel-Tiercelin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness ani the Unity of C.S. Peirce's Realism 57
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
58 Claudinc Engcl-Ticrcclin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity of C.S. Peirce's Realism 59
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
60 Claudinc Engel-Tiercelin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity ofC.S. Peirce's Realism 61
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
62 Claudinc Engel-Tiercelin
and always must be so" (1.20). But it also becomes clearer why
"pragmaticism could hardly have entered a head that was not al-
ready convinced that there are real generals11 (5.503).
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and die Unity ofC.S. Peirce's Realism 63
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
64 Claudinc Engcl-Ticrcclin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity ofCS, Peirce's Realism 65
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
66 Claudinc Engcl-Ticrcclin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity of C.S. Peirce's Realism 67
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
68 Claudinc Engd-Tiercdin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness ani the Unity of C.S. Peirce's Realism 69
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
70 Claudinc Engcl-Ticrcclin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity ofC.S. Peirce's Realism 71
such difficulties?
First it might be said that to qualify Peirce's position as a form
of realism is futile, not only because the very concept of realism
is itself fuzzy, but also because Peirce develops a position which
is evidently original, and even baroque.36 But Peirce's own ethics
of terminology and the insistence with which he calls himself a
realist invite us to think more about the meaning and scope of
his position.
In fact Peirce's position has many affinities with idealism, and
he himself considers that his philosophy is a form of objective
idealism. He even sometimes says that it looks somewhat "Hege-
lian" (1.42). In that respect, one could say that he would not ac-
cept a current opposition made between realism and idealism. But
again, there arc many ways of being an idealist, and Peirce is care-
ful to distinguish his "objective idealism" from idealisms such as
are embodied in Plato, Berkeley or Hegel. "Idealism," however, is
as fuzzy as "realism," and this is why Peirce's own interpretation
of medieval philosophers is much more helpful to get a more ac-
curate picture of the meaning he attaches to realism; Peirce ap-
proves of the scholastics' insistence on the impossibility of a rela-
tion of correspondence between words and things.37 One must
not confound first and secondary intentions, the properties of
signs and the properties of things signified. By identifying being
with intelligibility and predicability Peirce means above all that
naive realism, according to which reality is totally independent of
mind, is absurd. The same can be said of the reduction of reality
to existence or hard facts. In that sense it seems to me that, al-
though Peirce does not defend any theory about semantic realism
as such, by stressing that "the real is that what signifies something
real," (my emphasis) he follows a line of argument very close to
Putnam, when he writes: "I do not think that there can be any
object totally independent of mind or of a theory," or to Dum-
mett when he says: "There can be no complete description of the
world in terms of hard facts. " 38
Although Peirce refuses to reduce reality to facts, he does not
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
72 Claudinc Engd-Tiercelin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and lije Unity of C.S. Peirce's Realism 73
One must therefore take into account the various elements of be-
ing, but also try to locate them within their respective order. In
other terms, even if realism extends to all kinds of fields, it does
not imply that it should be monolithic. The principle of unity
does not work as a principle of uniformization. This has very im-
portant consequences for Peirce's realistic position according to
the subject-matter to which it is applied. For example, although
realism should be extended to mathematics, not only should it be
distinguished from Platonism, but it should also be able to cope
with some constructivistic or intuitionistic elements that must be
taken into account, without again falling into a straightforward
nominalistic formalism. Another consequence of such a position is
not only that mathematical realism does not obey the same crite-
ria as ultimate realism or cpistemological realism, but also that
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
74 Claudinc Engd-Tiercdin
within this last form of realism, one must not mistake for ontolog-
ical differences the differences which concern only epistcmic activ-
ities. This attitude is particularly evident in Pcircc's subtle analysis
of perception, where, leaving out a spectator view, he shows that
the pragmatist analysis implies that we decompose perception into
various elements - the percept, the percipuum, and the perceptive
judgment - and that we consider the perceptive universe accord-
ing to experimental methodology or as an interactive unity be-
tween man and the unanalyzable factiáty of experience.41
These considerations can help us to deal with what appear pri-
ma facie as contradictions within Peirce's definition of reality; re-
ality is sometimes defined as the object of knowledge, the result
of the final opinion which the scientific community would reach,
and sometimes as what is entirely independent of our thought
(and not only of what such and such an individual can think).42
In that sense, as Haack has observed, "reality is intersubjective,
but can lack objectivity.1143 Of course, this is not only a difficulty
for Peirce's own realistic view, but for realism in general. For the
first definition implies that the meaning of "true" consists in the
criteria of its application or verification, which is, in Dummett's
sense, an H anti-realist " thesis. But by identifying truth with the
criteria of truth, Peirce is not guilty of mistaking the one for the
others, and of reducing truth to something subjective. As Haack
points out, the identification is a consequence of his "criteriolog-
ical theory of signification1* {ibid.). If scientific method is sup-
posed to lead to a consensus, it is because it is constrained by re-
ality (5.384). Peirce's declarations here in favor of scientific
realism look more often like a realistic profession of faith than as
a genuine argument for realism. He nevertheless gives us argu-
ments. These are based first on the thesis that what cannot really
be doubted cannot really be believed either, at least until experi-
ence has not brought to us contrary evidence. Another important
Peircean argument is that science is, first and foremost, in the
business of explaining things. A nominalist can reject disposition-
al realism and consider laws only as conventional regularities; but
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and ihe Unity of C.S. Peirce's Realism 75
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
76 Claudinc Engel-Tiercelin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity of C.S. Peirce's Realism 77
NOTES
All our references are to Collected Papers ofC.S. Peirce, Hartshome, Weiss
& Burks, eds., Harvard 1933-1958, 8 volumes; ex: 5.470 and The New
Elements of Mathematics, (NEM), C. Eisele ed., Mouton The Hague,
1976, 4 vols.
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
78 Claudinc Engel-Tiercdin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity of C.S. Peirce's Realism 79
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
80 Claudinc Engel-Tiercelin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vagueness and the Unity ofC.S. Peirce's Realism 81
perior relatives inside collections which are not discrete but inside contin-
ual systems. See 1.548.
32. On the illusion of simplicity in sensation, see C. Engel-
Tiercelin, "Que signifíe "voir rouge"? La sensation et la couleur selon
C.S. Peirce," Archives dc Philosophic, 1984, 409-429.
33. Peirce calls this also formal hypothesis, e.g.; "1 received
today a number of English books printed by Hindoos in Culcutta. The
manufacture is rude, yet peculiarly pleasant. Remembering other Indian
manufactures I have seen, I now get a more definite conception of the
characteristic of Indian taste. This, since it is an idea derived from the
comparison of a number of objects, is called gcncr*Hztition. Yet it is not
an extension of an idea already had, but on the contrary, an increase of
definiteness of the conception I apply to known things" (2.422nl.).
34. See Peirce's definition of vagueness in Baldwin's diction-
ary: "Vague (in logic) [. . .] Indeterminate in intention, a proposition is
vague when there are possible states of things concerning which it is in-
trinsically uncertain whether, had they been contemplated by the speaker,
he would have regarded them as excluded or allowed by the proposition.
By intrinsically uncertain, we mean not uncertain in consequence of any
ignorance of the interpreter, but because the speaker's habits of language
were indeterminate; so that one day he would regard the proposition as
excluding, another as admitting, those states of things. Yet this must be
understood to have reference to what might be deduced from a perfect
knowledge of this state of mind; for it is precisely because these ques-
tions never did, or did not frequently present themselves, that this habit
remained indeterminate" (p. 966, vol. 2, 748).
35. This covers the traditional sorites arguments (the heap,
the bald) as well as the problems in contemporary literature on "border-
line-cases," fuzzy-sets, etc. Cf. Nadin, pp. 356, and Engel-Tiercelin,
1989, p. 569.
36. This is e.g. Boler's point of view, of. cit.^ p. 8.
37. This thesis pervades medieval writings (Anselm, Abelard,
Duns Scotus, Ockham, Aquinas). See Boler, "Peirce, Ockham and Scho-
lastic Realism," The Monist 63y 1980, pp. 209-304.
38. Putnam, "Vagueness and Alternative Logic," Erkenntnis,
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
82 Claudinc Engel-Tiercelin
This content downloaded from 132.204.9.239 on Mon, 20 Apr 2020 20:53:12 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms