Notes From The Lectures of FR Nemy S. Que, SJ: Ph104: Foundations of Moral Value
Notes From The Lectures of FR Nemy S. Que, SJ: Ph104: Foundations of Moral Value
Notes From The Lectures of FR Nemy S. Que, SJ: Ph104: Foundations of Moral Value
To be able to do this, he will have to show that theoretical or scientific knowledge has limitations that prevent it
from reaching all of reality. In other words, scientific knowledge leaves room for and does not undermine
morality.
Kant’s aim is then to rehabilitate morality. But to do this, he first had to analyze knowledge, to explain how we
come to know the world and what counts as such knowledge. Only then would he be in a position to show the limits
of knowledge.
Limits of
knowledge
HOPE
Limits of Morality
Our presentation of Kant’s thinking on morality will be guided by the following three questions:
1. What can we know? [Kant had to analyze knowledge first.]
2. What ought I to do?
3. What may I hope for?
What can I know?
Kant’s main contention … is that man as reason, as unity of consciousness, as the “I think,” is not so much
he who is subjected to some object as he who constitutes the subjective condition which makes possible the
object of experience. Thus, the Kantian subject is one that “legislates,” sets the rules and boundaries for the
emergence of the object. This, in general, is what is meant by Kant’s “transcendental” method.
(Sullivan, 1989:55)
I am subjected / controlled / conformed to a tree (Aristotelian and Thomistic).
“I” constitutes: I give measure but not so much a measure as a sense manifold. Prior to this sense manifold
meeting me, there is no tree (Kantian).
Unity of consciousness
not subjected to some object …
… constitutes the subjective conditions that make possible the object of experience } Key terms to
understanding
The human being contributes something. The thing out there contributes something. The relation gives a tree.
Transcendental Deductive Method
This is Kant’s attempt
To ask what the conditions of possibility of experience and knowledge are Kant goes back to the
conditions that make possible a tree.
To uncover the limit-boundaries of what we could possibly know
Space and time is the way we constitute experience. According to Kant, space and time are not out there but in here
(within). Space usually is conceived of as a container. For Kant, space is where we order objects. For example, we
cannot think of a piece of chalk without space but we can think of a space without a piece of chalk.
Space and time will be the conditions of possibility. Without space and time, it is not possible to experience a table
or anything else. Space and time are a priori (before experience) Forms. They cannot be part of experience because
they are what make possible experience. Space and time are a priori Forms because they make possible the
conditions for experience. The unity of consciousness is the subject. The subject “provides” space and time.
a priori
The function of reason is to produce a good will this is where duty comes in.
In the New Orleans (Hurricane Katrina), it is okay to steal according to Aristotle and the Natural Law because of
survival. Not so for Kant. You cannot consider survival as a duty and then everything else falls in place because
stealing, no matter how useful, is contrary to duty (cf. pg 157, paragraph 2).
Different examples of Kant: last paragraph of pg 156 to pg 157
It is possible and more difficult to determine when duty and direct inclination point toward the same direction.
Pg 158, paragraph 2
For Kant, loving your parents (whom you love) is an inclination, not a duty. However, loving your parents who
make you (truly) miserable is a duty. That is why the Scriptures command us to love our enemies (duty) and not
[just] our friends (inclination).
To do your duty is never to sacrifice. We should be happy doing our duty. To sacrifice is not to do a duty.
Inclination and obligation can coincide. Who knows you are doing things from duty? Yourself.
Pg 158
Kant wants to distinguish between two different ways of acting. The first we might call “outward agreement with
duty.” Here the action does do what duty requires. But the motive behind the action was not duty itself, but some
other inclinations.
The second way of acting is acting from duty. Here the action does not only require what duty requires, but the
motive behind the action is duty as well. What Kant wants to argue, here, is that it is only this second way of
acting – only acting from duty – that has true moral worth.
It is that duty which can become a universal law.
First Proposition: That act has moral content which is performed not in conformity with duty from the motive
of duty.
Second Proposition: An action done from duty has its moral worth, not in the purpose to be attained by it, but in
the maxim in accordance with which it is decided upon; it depends therefore, not on the
realization of the object of the action, but solely on the principle of volition in accordance
with which, irrespective of all objects of the faculty of desire, the action has been performed.
Pure ethics good will reason
Duty maxim (subjective principle – my reason for doing something)
Principle of the will (principle of volition)
Objective principle (universal and necessary)
2
Another word for maxim is rule.
3
Cf. Aristotle
That is why the expression “Everyone has her price” denigrates a person so viciously. What the second formula
stipulates is that we may not regard or treat others or allow ourselves to be treated only as instrumentally valuable,
merely as means to satisfy someone’s desires, merely as a source of pleasure. We may never renounce our right to
respect, and we ought never to act so as to reduce ourselves or others to the status of mere things. Persons demand
respect just by being persons, and that means not acting on a rule that treats any person merely as a thing.
(Sullivan, 69)
Pg 166 (last paragraph) to the top of pg 167
Kant is making a distinction here between things/objects and human beings. The value of objects come from outside,
not from within, i.e. comes from my inclinations. Existentialist philosophers will point out that this is correct, e.g. a
piece of chalk will not protest against its use. Only a human being can protest against being used as a thing.
To be subject means to be free, to be rational … (all of which are not found in things). By the very nature of human
beings as subject, they are already ends in themselves this for Kant means not to be treated as an object or a
means but always as ends in themselves.
We cannot avoid treating other humans as means but Kant reminds us that we are also to treat humans as ends (they
can react to our reactions).
autonomous law
Each one does come up with the universal law and therefore Law of Autonomy.
In general, as long as you understand the Categorical Imperative as fencing in what we can or are allowed to do (i.e.
within space and time), [that is the basic/minimum view of what it entails].
Once it is done by reason, what is rational for one is rational for all even if I was the only one making the statement.
(Kant was probably very appreciative of mathematics; cf. 1+1=2 is not just for me but for everyone).
The Categorical Imperative is the criteria of universability4 and reversibility5 of reason.
4
When I say “universal,” then whatever applies to others should also apply to me and vice versa.
5
That is, reverted back to me.