Immanuel Kant: "Kant" Redirects Here. For Other Uses, See
Immanuel Kant: "Kant" Redirects Here. For Other Uses, See
Immanuel Kant: "Kant" Redirects Here. For Other Uses, See
Notable Abstract–concrete
ideas distinction[12]
Aesthetic–teleological
judgments
Analytic–synthetic
distinction
Categorical and
hypothetical imperative
Categories
Cosmotheology
Critical philosophy
Copernican revolution in
philosophy
Disinterested delight
Empirical realism
Kant's antinomies
Kant's pitchfork
Kingdom of Ends
Mathematical vs. dynamical
sublimity[13]
Nebular hypothesis
Noogony and noology
Noumenon vs. thing-in-itself
Ontotheology
Primacy of practical
reason[14]
Public reason
Rechtsstaat
Sapere aude
Transcendental schema
Theoretical vs. practical
philosophy
Transcendental idealism
Transcendental theology
Understanding–reason
distinction
Influences[show]
Influenced[show]
Signature
Part of a series on
Immanuel Kant
Major works
Critique of Pure Reason
Critique of Practical Reason
Critique of Judgment
The Metaphysics of Morals
Opus Postumum
Kantianism
Kantian ethics
Transcendental idealism
Critical philosophy
Sapere aude
Thing-in-itself
Schema
A priori and a posteriori
Analytic–synthetic distinction
Noumenon
Categories
Categorical imperative
Hypothetical imperative
"Kingdom of Ends"
Political philosophy
People
George Berkeley
René Descartes
J. G. Fichte
F. H. Jacobi
G. W. F. Hegel
David Hume
Arthur Schopenhauer
Baruch Spinoza
African Spir
Johannes Tetens
Related topics
Schopenhauer's criticism
German idealism
Neo-Kantianism
Related Categories
► Immanuel Kant
v
t
e
Immanuel Kant (UK: /kænt/,[17][18] US: /kɑːnt/;[19][20] German: [ɪˈmaːnu̯eːl ˈkant, -nu̯ɛl -];[21][22]
22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was an influential German philosopher[23] in the Age of
Enlightenment. In his doctrine of transcendental idealism, he argued that space, time, and causation are
mere sensibilities; "things-in-themselves" exist, but their nature is unknowable.[24][25] In his view, the
mind shapes and structures experience, with all human experience sharing certain structural features. In
one of his major works, the Critique of Pure Reason (1781; second edition 1787),[26] he drew a parallel
to the Copernican revolution in his proposition that worldly objects can be intuited a priori ('beforehand'),
and that intuition is therefore independent from objective reality.[b]
Kant believed that reason is also the source of morality, and that aesthetics arise from a faculty of
disinterested judgment. Kant's views continue to have a major influence on contemporary philosophy,
especially the fields of epistemology, ethics, political theory, and post-modern aesthetics. He attempted to
explain the relationship between reason and human experience and to move beyond the failures of
traditional philosophy and metaphysics. He wanted to put an end to what he saw as an era of futile and
speculative theories of human experience, while resisting the skepticism of thinkers such as David Hume.
He regarded himself as showing the way past the impasse between rationalists and empiricists,[28] and is
widely held to have synthesized both traditions in his thought.[29]
Kant was an exponent of the idea that perpetual peace could be secured through universal democracy and
international cooperation. He believed that this would be the eventual outcome of universal history,
although it is not rationally planned.[30] The nature of Kant's religious ideas continues to be the subject
of philosophical dispute, with viewpoints ranging from the impression that he was an initial advocate of
atheism who at some point developed an ontological argument for God, to more critical treatments
epitomized by Schopenhauer, who criticized the imperative form of Kantian ethics as "theological
morals" and the "Mosaic Decalogue in disguise",[31] and Nietzsche, who claimed that Kant had
"theologian blood"[32] and was merely a sophisticated apologist for traditional Christian faith.[c]
Kant published other important works on ethics, religion, law, aesthetics, astronomy, and history. These
include the Universal Natural History (1755), the Critique of Practical Reason (1788), the Metaphysics
of Morals (1797), the Critique of Judgment (1790), which looks at aesthetics and teleology, and Religion
within the Bounds of Bare Reason (1793).
Contents