Dialectics of Labour
Dialectics of Labour
Contents
Introduction →
1. Acknowledgements
2. Abbreviations
3. Introduction
4. PART ONE Marx’s Theory of Alienation
5. Chapter 1
6. Chapter 2
7. Chapter 3
8. PART TWO The Critique of Hegel
9. Chapter 4
10. Chapter 5
11. Chapter 6
12. Chapter 7
13. Chapter 8
14. PART THREE 1844 The Turning Point
15. Chapter 9
16. Chapter 10
17. Chapter 11
18. APPENDIX Problems of Translation
19. Bibliography
Introduction →
Introduction
← Contents | Chapter 1 →
In V.I. Lenin’s little article ‘The three sources and three component parts of Marxism’
the said sources are identified as ‘German philosophy, English political economy and
French socialism’.[1] There is widespread agreement that this is indeed the case.
[2] But what is the thread that links these disparate intellectual sources together? The
answer is that Karl Marx effected this synthesis once he grasped the importance of
human labour in the history of society. The idealist dialectic of the German philosopher
G.W.F. Hegel, presented in his Phenomenology of Spirit as the self-movement and self-
estrangement of spirit, Marx re-read in terms of human practice – centrally in terms of
the alienation of labour; English political economy (Adam Smith, David Ricardo), he
discovered, based itself on the labour theory of value; French socialism protested
against the exploitation of the labourer and counterposed to the division of labour the
principle of ‘association’.
It was in Paris in the year 1844 that the young Marx first drew these threads together
and put material labour at the centre of his research programme. In his manuscripts of
that year we can see this new synthesis taking shape. [3] They begin as a simple set of
notes on his reading of economic texts; then he breaks off to write the section (now
justly celebrated) on estranged labour; he goes on to reflect on the meaning of
communist doctrines in this light; along the way he conducts a running debate with the
shade of Hegel, especially around the central question of our time – that of alienation. It
should be noted that most works on Marx’s theory of alienation are defective because
they do not recognize that all the sections of the manuscripts are equally essential and
inform each other.
For Marx, from 1844, the problem of alienation in modern society is understood to
gravitate around the estrangement of labour. All other spheres of estrangement are to
be related to this. [4]
What we find, then, in the 1844 Manuscripts is the emergence of a new theory of
extraordinary scope and fertility.[5] As such it is one of the most exciting texts in the
history of modern philosophy. At the same time, it is one of the most difficult, partly
because of its fragmentary character; even more, because of the complexity and
originality of Marx’s new ideas. Indeed the vast scope of the project sketched out in
these manuscripts defeated Marx himself. Only a part of the programme he outlined for
himself was undertaken, namely the researching and writing of Capital – and even that
project remained incomplete at his death. The critique of Hegel, by contrast, was never
taken up; although Marx continually promised himself that he would write some sheets
on what is rational in Hegel’s dialectic.
This book sets out an interpretation of Marx’s 1844 Manuscripts. It will attempt to clarify
what is obscure and to complete thoughts Marx left incomplete. A special effort is made
to assess Marx’s relationship to Hegel, which is one of extraordinary complexity; the
influence of Hegel on Marx is enormous, yet Marx’s embrace of materialism sets him
poles apart from Hegel. Not surprisingly, the matter is a controversial one. The
evidence offered by the 1844 Manuscripts of Marx’s own understanding of his relation to
Hegel has been insufficiently studied (except by Georg Lukács in his masterly work The
Young Hegel), and never properly explicated. The question is not without its importance;
for the central role played by labour in Marx’s thought, and its character as ‘the activity
of alienation, the alienation of activity’, is much illuminated by tracing Marx’s route out
of Hegel. Above all, this book aims to bring out fully the dialectical aspects of Marx’s
thought at this important turning point. The book ends by indicating the continuing
importance of the themes of 1844 in Marx’s later work.
Although an enormous literature exists on Marx’s theory of alienation, and although
certain remarks of his about Hegel’s philosophy are frequently quoted, there has been
no thorough study of the 1844 Manuscripts themselves, and certainly no detailed
exegesis of Marx’s critique of Hegel’s dialectic therein. That is why it is worthwhile to
devote a whole book to the study of this important turning point in the birth of Marxism.
1 VI. Lenin, ‘The three sources and component parts of Marxism’ (1913), in Selected
Works, London, 1969, P. 20. This idea is not original to Lenin. Indeed, a tripartite
division of this sort was elaborated as early as 1840 by M. Hess. In Die europäische
Triarchie he said England would produce a revolutionary combination of German theory
and French practice. Engels, in an article of 1846, puts in the mouths of the so-called
‘true socialists’ the following: ‘Did we not assign to the Germans the sphere of theory,
to the French that of politics, and to the English that of civil society?’ C.W.6, 3.
2 Pierre Naville rightly points out that the matter is somewhat complex because the
sources are already ‘mixed’ (De L’Aliénation à la Jouissance, Paris, 1957, p. 11); just one
example: Marx could read political economy in Hegel through Hegel’s own
appropriation of it.
3 David McLellan in Marx Before Marxism, London, 1970, says these elements appear
in the Paris manuscripts ‘together, if not yet united’ (p. 206). I hope to show that there
is more unity than is apparent.
4 1844 Mss: C.W.3, 297; Werke Eb., 537.
5 ‘A synthesis in statu nascendi‘ says István Mészáros, Marx’s Theory of Alienation,
London, 1970, p. 15.
Introduction
In 1844 a turning point occurs in Marx’s philosophical development. For the first time
he attributes fundamental ontological [1] significance to productive activity.[2] Through
material production humanity comes to be what it is. Through the process of production
the worker realizes his potential and becomes objective to himself in his product. He
develops his productive powers and knows himself in and through his activity and its
result. It is important to observe that this is possible only because there exists raw
material with which to work. Marx says that ‘the worker can create nothing
without nature, without the sensuous external world’. [3] It is the material in which his
activity realizes itself, and, in the absence of any distortion of the relationship, this
material production is the ‘mediation‘ in which the unity of man with nature is
established.
The category of ‘mediation’ Marx takes from Hegel, and it is as central to his work as it
is to Hegel’s. It is to be contrasted with ‘immediacy’. In the present case, someone who
argues that man is nothing but a part of nature, a natural being subject to natural laws,
is taking the position that man is in immediate unity with nature. By contrast, someone
who takes a dualistic position, representing man as separate from the natural realm,
developing himself spiritually, and struggling against the power of nature latent in
himself as well as the influence of external determinants, is taking man to
be immediately opposed to nature.
Marx’s position is much more complex. On the one hand, he speaks of nature as
‘man’s inorganic body’ and says that ‘he must maintain a continuing dialogue with it if
he is not to die … for man is a part of nature’. [4] On the other hand, he says that ‘it is
in his fashioning of the objective world that man really proves himself; through such
productive activity ‘nature appears as his work and his reality . . . and he can therefore
contemplate himself in a world he himself created’; [5] this process is characterized
as ‘objectification’ (Vergegenständlichung) – another important category Marx employs.
In truth, man is neither passively dependent upon nature, nor is he able to create his
world from nothing. It is rather the case that through industry, productive activity, a
dynamic relationship between man and nature is established in which both poles are
transformed. In a discussion of this problem in the German Ideology (1846) Marx and
Engels explain that ‘the celebrated “unity of man with nature” has always existed in
industry … and so has the “struggle” of man with nature …’. [6] In summing up Marx’s
position we may therefore refer to the relationship of man and nature as mediated in that
it is not immediately given, and forever untransformed, but is one in which productive
activity, interposed as a third ‘moment’, provides a principle of development,
transformation and self-transformation. On the objective side there is the development
of productive powers, which enable society to appropriate natural materials to human
use with decreasing effort. On the subjective side, Marx elaborates the idea of the
constitution of a ‘wealth of human needs’, [7] and the development of ‘the richness of . .
. human sensibility (a musical ear, an eye for beauty of form – in short, senses capable
of human gratification, senses affirming themselves as essential powers of man)’. [8]
The mediation of productive activity (objectification) Marx views as ontologically
fundamental to the whole social and historical development of mankind (see figure 1).
Where idealist social ontologies try to purge social categories of the natural, and
biological reductionists evacuate the social mediations, the strength of Marx’s category
of ‘productive activity’ lies precisely in its double determination as the linking element
between the human and the natural, the ideal and the material, teleology and causality.
Productive activity is at the same time both a material interchange (the combination and
transformation of raw materials into goods for human consumption) and a human social
process – whereby the cunning of human practice realizes its aims within the context of
definite, historically determined and transformed, socio-economic relationships.
The perspective just outlined is admittedly very general, but it underpins Marx’s theory
of alienation as it is sketched in the well-known chapter of the 1844 Manuscripts –
‘Estranged Labour’ – to which we now turn. (For notes on the German terms for
alienation/estrangement see the Appendix, pp. 147-9.)
Estranged Labour
Marx’s 1844 Manuscripts are justly famous for conceptualizing the situation of the wage-
labourer as one of alienation. Because the worker has no property in the means of
production his labour-power is excluded from the instrument and object of production
owned by another; his labour realizes itself therefore only through the wage-contract
whereby it is alienated to the master and works in his behalf. The labourer treats his
labour as a commodity; as a consequence he has no interest in the work itself but only
in the wage; labour does not belong to itself but to private property. Marx comments
trenchantly on the situation endured by the worker: he executes plans he does not
form; he objectifies himself in his product only to have it taken from him; he produces
palaces but lives in hovels; his labour creates beauty but deforms himself; the more
intelligence is embodied in the design of the factory system the more machine-like and
stupefying the routine of work, so much so that the labourer faces machinery as a
competitor for his place; at work he does not feel at home; he feels himself only when
he is not working; his work is not voluntary therefore, but is forced labour; in it the
worker belongs not to himself but to another.[9]
Marx’s diagnosis of ‘estranged labour’ is a complex shifting one in which he continually
comes back to elaborate themes initiated earlier. Because we have before us a first
draft, the presentation is not clearly organized. However, the underlying structure of
Marx’s thought articulates the different moments of the system of estranged
relationships by mapping the alienating mediations on to the ontologically fundamental
relationships already outlined.
Marx’s frame of reference is the relationship man – activity – nature. In his production
man works upon the naturally given object of his activity and develops himself and his
powers on a corresponding basis. Marx thematizes alienation in the same dimensions.
Alienating activity estranges man from the object of production and his essential human
qualities. Although the active moment is the central one, in his exposition Marx finds it
convenient to deepen the analysis in the sequence object – activity – man. Let me
elaborate these moments (see figure 2).
1. The worker is confronted by the product of his labour ‘as an alien object exercising
power over him’ says Marx; not only does he lose the product to the capitalist, but its sale by
the latter reinforces the power of wealth over the labourer; and, likewise, nature, the basis of
production, is monopolized by the propertied class and appears as ‘an alien world inimically
opposed to him’. [10] ‘The product of labour’, says Marx, ‘is the objectification
{Vergegenständlichung} of labour’, but, given that labour is separated from its objective
conditions of realization (namely the material and the instruments of production) by their
status as private property, the objectification of labour is at the same time its alienation, and
the outcome is the estrangement of the worker from the material basis of his existence and
life activity. [11]
2. ‘The relation of labour to the act of production within the labour process’, Marx says,
‘is the relation of the worker to his own activity as alien . . .’ Marx derives this aspect from
the first by means of the argument that, if estrangement is manifest in the result of
production, this means that production itself must be alienating, ‘the activity of alienation,
the alienation of activity’. The wage-labourer has no satisfaction in his work and only
endures it for the sake of the wage, subordinating his activity to an alien power. ‘His life-
activity’, says Marx, ‘does not belong to him.’ Since, for Marx, activity is the central
determinant of human being (for as men express their life so they are), the alienation of
labour is at the same time self-estrangement. Marx concludes: ‘Here we have self-
estrangement, as previously we had the estrangement of the thing.’ [12]
3. ‘Estranged labour’, Marx says, ‘turns man’s species being . . . into a being alien to him,
into a means for his individual existence.’ [13] What does Marx mean by ‘species
being‘? [14] He explains that ‘man is a species being . . . because he looks upon himself as
a universal and therefore free being.’ [15] The most important species activity is ‘productive
life’. [16] It is worth quoting an extended passage in which this is thematized:
Let us now try to get an overview of our progress so far. At the beginning I showed that
the category of ‘productive activity’ has general ontological significance for Marx.
Already in 1844, therefore, we have the first glimpses of the science of historical
materialism, because this mediation provides the possibility of a historical dimension to
human existence in so far as men’s relationships to nature and to each other are
transformed through it.
The actual development of this activity, however, has become subsumed under a
further set of mediations; in the present economic conditions we find that productive
activity itself is mediated through the division of labour, private property, exchange,
wages, in sum a system of estrangement in which productive activity loses itself and
falls under the sway of an alien power. Istávan Mészáros has termed this ‘a set
of second-order mediations . . . i.e. a historically specific mediation of the ontologically
fundamental self-mediation of man with nature.`[27] The most important distinction
between the two orders is that initially it is presupposed that productive activity is in
immediate unity with its object, whereas with the imposition of the estranging second-
order mediations labour is immediately confronted by its object as something separate
from it. This immediate opposition is not ontologically given in the nature of things but is
the result of historically determinate mediations. (It is necessary to note that the
categories immediate/mediate do not divide elements into two different classes; rather,
the same relation may be mediated from one point of view and immediate from
another.)
For Marx, what requires historical explanation is not the unity but the separation of
these moments, through a process whereby ‘man alienates the mediating activity itself’,
and hence becomes the slave of an ‘alien mediator’. [28]
It is important to understand that the emergence of the second-order mediation does
not substitute itself for the first – it further mediates the mediation itself. This means
that it would not be correct to erect a dichotomy between them such that everything
true of one side is untrue of the other (a strategy typical of analytical thought); this, in
turn, would facilitate a faulty diagnosis of the problem of alienation in terms of an
opposition of the ideal and the real.
Let us note in particular that, if through productive activity man objectifies himself and
lives in a world he has himself made, this is no less true when he alienates himself and
fails to recognize himself in the system of estrangement brought about through
alienated objectification. It is this conceptual inflection rather than mutual exclusion of
the categories ‘objectification’ and ‘alienation’ that permits theoretical space for
grasping the objective necessity of a historical supersession, which would otherwise be
a utopian ‘demand’. Equally, the possibility of historical supersession depends on a
refusal to identify the second-order mediation with the first (easy to do because in
recorded history the rule of private property bulks large), thus building into the theory
the inevitability of alienation, whatever philosophy may endeavour to reconcile us to it.
In order to overcome estrangement, the alienating mediations must be overcome. But
this does not mean that Marx rejects all mediation, for the ‘first-order mediation’ –
productive activity as such – is an absolute ontological dimension of social life; Marx
opposes only its specific alienated form, imposed through second-order mediations
which are historically surpassable. If this distinction is not drawn, and social philosophy
collapses the two levels into one, such that private property and exchange are taken to
be as absolute as productive activity itself, then it is not possible for such a philosophy
to grasp the conditions of a positive supersession of estrangement; it must descend to
apologetics and pseudo-solutions.
So hostile was Marx to labour under capitalism, that at first he called, not for the
’emancipation’ of labour, but for its ‘abolition’. That is why, at first, he termed
man’s function not ‘labour’, but ‘self-activity’ . . . No matter how the language
changed, the point remained that labour, in a new society, would in no manner
whatever be the type of activity it is under capitalism where man’s labour is
limited to the exercise of his physical labour-power. [34]
Erich Fromm follows Dunayevskaya closely. [35] Robert Tucker sums up the matter
correctly as follows:
By ‘labour’ or ‘alienated labour’ – terms that he employs interchangeably –
Marx means productive activity performed by man in the state of alienation from
himself. He declares that all human activity up to now has been labour . . .
Consequently, man has never been fully himself in his creative activity. This
activity has never been ‘self-activity’, by which Marx means free creativity in
which a person feels thoroughly at home with himself, enjoys a sense of
voluntary self-determination to action, and experiences his energies as his
own. [36]
Mészáros detects some ambiguity:
Let us now establish the textual evidence for Marx’s early ‘negative’ definition of
‘labour’ and his anticipation of its ‘abolition’. In the first three sections of the first
manuscript it has not yet occurred to Marx to organize the material under the rubric of
estrangement. His main critical category is ‘abstraction’. Capital, landed property and
labour are separated from each other and this ‘abstraction’ is ‘fatal for the
worker’. [39] Marx shows that the evidence of the political economists themselves
proves this; but they do not recognize ‘that labour itself . . . is harmful and pernicious’ –
even though it follows from their own arguments. [40] This is partly because the
political economist does not consider the human being of the worker but merely his
function as a labourer – one who lives ‘by a one-sided abstract labour’ – hence ‘in
political economy labour occurs only in the shape of the activity of earning a
living. [41] This might leave open the possibility of some other ‘shape’ of labour, but in
the following discussion of estrangement Marx says more conclusively that ‘political
economy conceals the estrangement inherent on the nature of labour‘. [42]
In the following pages there is a summarizing passage in which ‘labour’ is equated with
‘the act of estranging practical human activity’ [43] and in which ‘the act of production’ is
said to become ‘an alien activity’ turned against the worker, within
‘the labour process’. [44]
In the second manuscript a very important passage includes the following definition:
‘Within the private property relationship there is contained latently . . . the production of
human activity as labour – that is, as an activity quite alien to itself, to man, and to
nature.’ [45] In this passage ‘labour’ is defined as productive activity transformed by the
private property system into an activity alien to itself. Were it not that this is simply
ignored by political economy, simply not understood, then ‘alienated labour’ would be a
pleonasm. In this sense of ‘labour’, human activity as such is distinguished from it as
free activity which harmoniously relates man and nature, the producer and his object.
In the third manuscript Marx says that the history of industry presents – albeit ‘in the
form of estrangement’ – an ‘open book of man’s essential powers’. ‘This was not
conceived in its connection with man’s essential being but only in the external relation
of utility’, he goes on, because ‘all human activity hitherto has been labour’, that is
‘activity estranged from itself.’ [46] Here there is a clear distinction between the positive
side of the history of production, in so far as it mobilized ‘mans essential powers’, and
the negative side, constituted by the forms of estrangement within which it has
developed. ‘Labour’ is clearly assigned to the latter as ‘activity estranged from itself’.
Later, in a fragment on the division of labour in civil society, the same negative
definition of ‘labour’ appears again; since ‘labour is only an expression of human
activity within alienation’ then the division of labour is ‘the estranged and alienated form
of human activity as an activity of the species’. [47]
A couple of years later Marx worked with Engels on another manuscript, known to us
as the German Ideology, in which even more striking formulations occur. He proposes
not only the end of the division of labour (for which ‘private property’ is an ‘identical
expression’ [48]) but also the abolition of labour. For example: ‘In all previous
revolutions the mode of activity always remained unchanged and it was only a question
of . . . a new distribution of labour . . . whilst the communist revolution is directed
against the hitherto existing mode of activity, does away with labour . . . ‘ [49] There
followed the beginnings of a further amplification: ‘the modern form of activity under the
rule of. . .’ – but this was crossed out; nevertheless it is clear that ‘labour’ is understood
as an activity which is not free and falls together with private property.
The ‘abolition of labour’ (‘Aufhebung der Arbeit‘) is spoken of on several occasions later
in this text, [50] of which the most interesting states:
Labour, the only connection which still links them with the productive forces and
with their own existence, has lost all semblance of self-activity and . . . while in
earlier periods . . . the production of material life was considered a subordinate
mode of self-activity, they now diverge to such an extent that material life
appears as the end, and what produces this material life, labour (which is now
the only possible but, as we see, negative form of self-activity) as the
means.’ [51]
All these passages show that ‘labour’ is defined as alienating activity, to be
distinguished from self-activity, free activity, human activity. In all these passages, also,
the context makes it clear that the labour defined negatively is not productive activity
itself (the manifestation of ‘essential power’) but only that carried on within the division
of labour and private property. Equally, abolition of labour does not do away with work
itself (not even manual work) but sets it in the framework of ‘free’ and ‘universal’
activity. If we want to know the immediate source of this way of talking about ‘labour’,
we need look no further than Marx’s own acknowledgement of the influence of M. Hess
on his thought. In the Preface to the 1844 Manuscripts Marx says that ‘the
only original German works of substance in this science’ include ‘the essays
by Hess published in Einundzwanzig Bogen‘. [52]
This refers the reader to some essays by Hess, in a book published abroad in 1843 to
defeat the German censorship. The first of these is a review of a book by Lorenz von
Stein on French socialism and communism, which made a big impact on radical circles
in Germany. At the time he wrote the review, Hess was already in Paris and so had
first-hand knowledge of the Fourierists and other socialist currents. In his review Hess
declares that in communism ‘the opposition of enjoyment and labour disappears’. This
is because ‘every man has an inclination to some kind of activity, even to very different
sorts of activity, and out of the multiplicity of free human inclinations and activities
arises the free, living and ever-youthful organism of free, human society, free, human
occupations that cease to be ‘work’ and become identical with ‘pleasure’.’ [53]
There is no doubt, therefore, that in his 1844 Manuscripts Marx is writing under the
immediate influence of such views.
Two of the commentators we cited earlier as failing to notice that in the 1844
Manuscripts ‘labour’ is the term construed as a ‘negative’ form of self-activity, as
alienation, are yet struck by the fact that Marx calls for the ‘abolition of labour’ in
the German Ideology; and they provide similar solutions to the problem – which will
serve to introduce our own reflections on the matter.
Marcuse (in his Reason and Revolution) makes the following comment:
These amazing formulations in Marx’s earliest writings all contain the Hegelian
term ‘Aufhebung‘, so abolition also carries the meaning that a content is
restored to its true form. Marx, however, envisioned the future mode of labour to
be so different from the prevailing one that he hesitated to use the same term
‘labour’ to designate alike the material process of capitalist and of communist
society. He uses the term ‘labour’ to mean what capitalism actually understands
by it in the last analysis, that activity which creates surplus value in commodity
production, or, which ‘produces capital’. [54]
Oizerman permits himself to express the view that in speaking of the abolition of labour
Marx adopts ‘a form of expression which is not very apt terminologically’;[55] and he
excuses it with much the same reasons as Marcuse, namely that Marx is simply
borrowing the category of the political economists and that, in any case, ‘Aufhebung‘
does not quite mean ‘abolition’. [56]
The problem is clear – in some sense the alienated form of activity seems to demand a
distinct concept which is correlative with the other moments of the bourgeois totality,
notably capital, that is a concept which is historically specific; in another sense there is
a continuity of reference when we discuss productive activity under the rule of private
property, and under socialism.
Earlier I mentioned that there is a conceptual problem underlying the sense in which
‘labour’ is used. This is because, throughout the 1844 Manuscripts, Marx continually
relates labour to private property in a very intimate way, as ‘the subjective essence of
private property’. Since private property is understood by Marx as a historically specific
system, to be superseded, it must surely follow that its essence cannot be a first-order
mediation but must be equally determined within the framework of second-order
mediations. Either Marx should have said that the essence of private property is
‘alienated labour’, reserving the term ‘labour’ for the ontologically prior level; or, if
‘labour’ as such is to be ‘the subjective essence’, then we need some other term for the
relevant first-order mediation. If we take the second alternative, then a reading of
Marx’s 1844 Manuscripts and the German Ideology readily gives us a candidate, namely
‘activity’ or, more precisely, ‘productive activity’; ‘labour’ may then be defined as
‘alienated productive activity’, or, if that is to beg the question, as ‘activity within the
relationships of private property’. The next chapter investigates these private property
relations.
Summary
Marx’s ontology comprises the complex totality man – activity – nature. In the history of
human society the mediating moment is productive activity. But imposed on this first-
order mediation is a set of second-order mediations, principally private property, estranging
man from himself, his powers, his activity and his object. Objectification is then at the
same time alienation. Within the system of second-order mediations, productive activity,
now an alienating activity, is redefined as (alienated) labour.
Marx’s project is to conceptualize the positive supersession of this system of
estrangement.
1 I use ‘ontology’ to indicate that set of fundamental categories through which the
character of the social sphere is delimited and the general framework for theory
construction established. I do not mean that a priori arguments establish the necessity
of these categories, but I think that every research programme presupposes a
commitment to some ontology. For Marx’s ontology see Georg Lukács, Ontology of
Social Being: Marx (1972), trans. D. Fernbach, London 1978; Carol C. Gould, Marx’s
Social Ontology, Cambridge, Mass., London, 1978; Scott Meikle, Essentialism in the
Thought of Karl Marx, London, 1985.
2 I deliberately choose this phrase rather than ‘labour’ because the latter is open to
some ambiguity of interpretation, as will be seen later an this chapter.
3 Werke Eb., 512; C.W.3, 273; E.W., 325.
4 Werke Eb., 516; C.W.3, 276; E.W., 328.
5 Werke Eb., 517; C.W.3, 277; E.W., 929.
6 C.W. 5, 40.
7 Werke Eb., 546; C.W.3, 306.
8 Werke Eb., 541; C.W.3, 301.
9 Werke Eb., 512-14; C.W.3, 272-4; E.W., 322-6.
10 Werke Eb., 515; C.W.3, 275.
11 Werke Eb., 511-12; C.W.3, 272; E.W., 324.
12 Werke Eb., 514-15; C.W.3, 274-5.
13 Werke Eb., 517; C.W.3, 277; E. W., 329.
14 One should not be disturbed by Marx’s borrowing the term ‘species being’
(Gattungswesen) from Feuerbach. The content is different (see Part Three below).
15 Werke Eb., 515; C.W.3, 275; E.W., 327.
16 Werke Eb., 516; C.W.3, 276; E.W., 328.
17 Werke Eb., 516-17; C.W.3, 276-7; E.W., 328-9.
18 Werke Eb., 517; C.W.3, 277; E.W., 329.
19 Werke Eb., 520-1; C.W.3, 280; E.W., 332.
20 Werke Eb., 517-18; C.W.3, 277-8.
21 Werke Eb., 546-7; C.W.3, 306; E.W., 359. Hegel already explained thus in bourgeois
society ‘the system of needs’ multiplies indefinitely. He observes thus the need for
greater comfort . . . is suggested to you by those who hope to make a profit from its
creation’: P.R. (Knox), p. 269.
22 Werke Eb., 547; C.W.3, 307.
23 Werke Eb., 540; C.W.3, 300. But it is wrong to speak of Marx’s ‘producer’s morality’
(Eugene Kamenka, The Ethical Foundations of Marxism London, 1962, p. 149) for he also
values here ‘human use’.
24 Werke Eb, 565-7; C.W.3, 325-6.
25 See S.S. Prawer, Karl Marx and World Literature, Oxford, 1976, pp. 76-85.
26 XLI – XLIII: New MEGA 1,2, 318-22; Werke Eb., 563-4; C.W.3, 323-4.
27 István Mészáros, Marx’s Theory of Alienation, London, 1970, p. 79.
28 ‘Comment on James Mill’ (1844): Werke Eb., 446; C.W.3, 312. Also: ‘is is not the
unity of living and active humanity with the natural inorganic conditions of their
metabolic exchange with nature, and hence their appropriation of nature, which
requires explanation or is the result of a historic process, but rather
the separation between these inorganic conditions of human existence and this active
existence, a separation which is completely posited only in the relation of wage labour
and capital.’ (Marx, Grundrisse, trans. M. Nicolaus, Harmondsworth, 1973, p. 489).
29 Werke Band 23, Das Kapital, Berlin, 1962, p. 192; C.l (Penguin), 283; C.1 (Moscow),
177.
30 C.3 (Penguin), 964; C.3 (Moscow). 804.
31 Georg Lukács: ‘In seinem oekonomischen Betrachtungen zieht Marx an der Hand
der Tatsachen des wirklichen Lebens scharf dis Grenze zwischen
Vergegenständlichung in der Arbeit an sich und Entfremdung von Subjekt und Objekt
in der kapitalistischen Form der Arbeit.’ Werke 8, 674; also The Young Hegel, trans.
Rodney Livingstone, London 1975, pp. 551-2.
32 ‘The foundations of historical materialism’ (1932), quoted from Herbert
Marcuse, From Luther to Popper, essays trans. Joris de Bres, London, 1983, p.
13; Reason and Revolution (194l), 2nd ed. London, 1954, p. 277. To cite a more recent
account: Paul Walton and Andrew Gamble, in their book From Alienation so Surplus
Value, London, 1972, put forward the view that Marx’s ‘ontological position’ is grounded
in ‘the dialectics of labour’ and they quote freely from all periods of Marx’s work to
establish this without noting any problems about the early terminology.
33 T.I. Oizerman, The Making of the Marxist Philosophy (1977), English trans., Moscow,
1981, p. 230.
34 Raya Dunayevskaya, Marxism and Freedom, New York,1958, p. 61.
35 Erich Fromm Marx’s Concept of Man (196l), New York, 1971, p. 40. Despite the fact
that this book appears under Fromm’s name, it consists mostly of Bottomore’s
translation of Marx’s 1844 Mss; Fromm’s Preface attempts to popularize Marx by
characterizing him as an ‘existentialist’ and a ‘Zen Buddhist’.
36 Robert C. Tucker, Philosophy and Myth in Karl Marx, Cambridge, 1961 p. 134.
37 Mészáros, Theory of Alienation, p. 78.
38 Article on ‘praxis’ in A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, ed. T.B. Bottomore, Oxford,
1983, p. 386.
39 Werke Eb., 471; C.W.3, 235.
40 Werke Eb., 476; C.W.3. 240; E.W., 288.
41 Werke Eb., 477; C.W.3, 241; E.W., 289.
42 Werke Eb., 513; C.W.3, 273.
43 ‘Wir haben den Akt der Entfremdung der praktischen menslichen Tätigkeit, die
Arbeit . . . ‘: Werke Eb., 515; C.W.3, 275; E.W., 327 gives a misleading translation of this
sentence.
44 Werke Eb., 515; C.W.3, 275.
45 Werke Eb., 524; C.W.3, 285; E.W., 336.
46 Werke Eb., 542-3; C.W.3, 302-3.
47 Werke Eb., 557; C.W.3, 317; E.W., 369.
48 C.W.5, 46.
49 Ibid., 52.
50 Ibid., 77, 80, 87, 88, 205.
51 Ibid., 87.
52 Werke Eb., 468; C. W. 3, 232; Marx also gives credit to W. Weitling and to Engels.
53 Quoted from David McLellan, The Young Hegelians and Karl Marx, London, 1969, pp.
148-9.
54 Marcuse, Reason and Revolution, p. 293. For ‘Aufhebung‘, see Appendix.
55 Oizerman, Making of the Marxist Philosophy, p. 392.
56 The editors of the current English edition of the Collected Works simply ignore the
problem and write in their Preface: ‘Labour will be transformed from an activity people
perform under compulsion into genuine self-activity of free people.’ C.W.5, xxii.
57 C.1 (Penguin), 126 n.4, Das Kapital, p. 50 n.4.
58 C.1 (Penguin), 138 n.16; Das Kapital, pp. 61-2, n.16.
2 – Private Property
← Chapter 1 | Chapter 3 →
Introduction
The first chapter brought out the character of estranged labour by showing how the
fundamental mediatedness of social development, articulated through the complex
man – activity – nature, becomes transformed in all its dimensions: man is specified
socially as labourer or exploiter; productive activity becomes alienated labour; and the
object is constituted within the sphere of private property as an independent power, as
capital.
This chapter will take a closer took at this set of second-order mediations. In particular,
it will discuss the way in which Marx conceives of the relation between alienated labour
and private property; the dialectic of the movement of private property; and the
contradictions that require resolution.
The Movement of Private Property
At first sight it appears that the worker’s alienation in his labour is due to the
subordination of labour to private property. His estrangement follows from the
separation between labour and private property, and the power of private property over
the immediate producer. The only certainty in the worker’s life is that his destiny
depends upon private property – on whether it has any use for the labour he offers.
The immediate precondition of alienated labour thus appears to be private property in
the means of production which excludes the worker.
Unwary readers of the section on ‘estranged labour’ in the 1844 Manuscripts – assuming
that what is being claimed is that the worker is alienated because he works under the
sway of the property owner – are then astonished when Marx suddenly turns round and
says that private property is not so much the cause as the consequence of alienation.
Here is the passage in question:
Private property is . . . the product, result, and necessary consequence,
of alienated labour, of the external relation of the worker to nature and to himself .
. . It is true that we took the concept of alienated labour . . . from political
economy as a result of the movement of private property. But it is clear from an
analysis of this concept that if private property appears as the ground, the basis
of alienated labour, it is much more its consequence, just as the gods
were originally not the cause but the effect of the confusion in men’s minds.
Later, however, this relationship becomes reciprocal. [1]
It is of the first importance to understand what Marx is saying here, and the significance
of his view of private property as the product of alienated labour. [2] A clue to the
direction of his thought is given a few tines later, when he comments: ‘In speaking
of private property one imagines that one is dealing with something external to man. In
speaking of labour one is immediately dealing with man himself.’ [3] This reminds us
that private property is a social institution. It is simply a way of organizing human
relationships in the production and distribution of material goods. Ultimately it has to be
grasped as a human creation. Otherwise one would be
illegitimately naturalizing (treating as a given basis of human existence) what is
produced and reproduced in and through human history.
None the less, as we shall see in a moment, in the case of pre-capitalist society one is
not going too far from the truth in seeing property, e.g. landed property, as a
prior condition of labour’s realization: but developed private property, held as capital, is
different. Capital, as a store of value, is internally related to value-creating labour.
In the first part of the 1844 Manuscripts Marx stays close to his sources in political
economy and shows from facts admitted by political economy itself that the more the
worker produces the less he can call his own and ‘the more he falls under the
domination of his product, of capital’. [4]
In its theory political economy says that labour is the basis of production and exchange;
Adam Smith is quite clear that the real ‘wealth of nations’ lies in the labour force and in
improvements in productivity brought about by the division of labour. The economy
appears to be founded on the movement of private property, on buying, selling,
investing, profiting; but behind these relationships lies labour and its relations and
development. Marx says that there is therefore a paradox in that ‘political economy
starts out from labour as the real soul of production, and yet gives nothing to labour
and everything to private property’! ‘Proudhon has dealt with this contradiction’, Marx
continues, ‘by deciding for labour and against private property’; but that is insufficiently
dialectical; what we are faced with is ‘the contradiction of estranged labour with
itself. [5] Today, private property is, paradigmatically, capital, which is nothing but a
store of value. What is the origin of value? What is its substance? Why – labour! Every
time the worker labours, therefore, he creates a value which, when realized on the
market by the employer, adds to his capital. The worker produces and reproduces that
which dominates him – capital.
The relation of cause and consequence is grasped here from the point of view of the
self-reproduction process of the totality rather than an external conjunction of
antecedent and consequent. Abstract alienated labour, and capital, stand in an internal
relation which structures the whole of capitalist society in such a way that its
reproduction depends on the constant reflection of these moments into each other (for
‘moment’, see Appendix). To prioritize labour is not to overlook the power of capital; but
capital’s effectivity as the proximate moment in the worker’s estrangement does not
prevent Marx from grasping it as the mediating moment in labour’s self-alienation,
established by labour itself as its own otherness. In grasping this dialectical relation of
reflection in otherness we are dealing not with the constant conjunction of otherwise
unrelated elements but with a polar relation in which, although one can follow the
movement of private property as its current principal aspect, the ultimately overriding
moment must be labour, which alienates itself in the capital to which it is subordinated.
Marx says:
The labourer produces capital and capital produces him, which means that he
produces himself; man as a labourer, as a commodity, is the product of this
entire cycle. [6]
In relating labour in its alienation to fully developed private property, that is, capitalist
property, in this way, Marx is well aware that relationships were different in previous
social formations. When he gives priority to labour over property he is not posing it as
historically antecedent but rather as ontologically more fundamental in the social totality
established by their dialectic. However, this dialectical relationship between labour and
private property is itself a historically developed result. Hence, it had not merely to be
discovered, but to be created. If one looks, as Marx does in the first manuscript, at
precapitalist formations, there is no internal economic dialectic between labour and
property as there is between labour as the substance of value and capital as ‘stored up
labour’ – as Marx defines it (following Adam Smith). [7]
In the main form of pre-capitalist property, namely landed property worked by serfs, or
yielding tithes, there is certainly an opposition between labour and property in that, in
virtue of the political ties of lordship and bondage, the exploitation of the propertyless
mass of labourers is effected. But this process of exploitation does not sustain the
property relation itself in purely economic fashion. Romanticism views this state of
affairs as the absence of alienation – for the market is very marginal to life and the land
is inalienable. But, despite the absence of the activity of huckstering in the daily round,
estrangement is still present as a permanent condition. ‘Feudal landed property is
already by its very nature’, Marx says, ‘huckstered land, which is estranged from man
and hence confronts him in the shape of a few great lords.’ Thus, the basic condition of
labour, the earth, appears as ‘an alien power over man’. Hence ‘the rule of private
property begins with property in land; that is its basis’. [8] However, it does not yet
appear as an economic power, because it is politically enforced and reproduced. From
an economic point of view feudal property is an externally enforced condition
determining one’s place in production and the possibility of gaining wealth; for example,
the serf is condemned to be an appurtenance of the land, the land itself is inalienably
linked to the system of primogeniture.
But when private property is fully developed it is free from all such restrictions and is
universally alienable. Along with the development of markets in all kinds of
commodities goes the reduction of land and labour themselves to alienable
commodities. Possession now depends no longer on political mediation, but on the
effect of the purely economic movement. It becomes inevitable, Marx says,
that the rule of the property owner should appear as the naked rule of private
property, of capital, divested of all political tincture; that the relationship
between property owner and worker should be reduced to the economic
relationship of exploiter and exploited; that the personal relationship between
the property owner and his property should come to an end, and that property
itself should become merely objective material wealth . . . [9]
It is noteworthy, moreover, that Marx commonly speaks of the power of property or of
capital rather than the domination of the property owner or the capitalist. Much more is
involved here than a rhetorical figure. This usage represents Marx’s insight into the real
conditions of social relationships in bourgeois society. This is: that the nature of the
relationship between persons follows from their relationships to things. If one asks of
two persons going into a factory why it is that one can boss the other around, the
answer cannot be given in terms of the personal qualities of the individuals concerned
but only in terms of their differing relation to capital. The one who owns (or acts on
behalf of) capital is thereby the master of the other. Marx says:
Capital is the power to command labour and its products. The capitalist possesses
this power not on account of his personal or human properties but in so far as he
is the owner of capital. His power is the purchasing power of his capital, which
nothing can withstand. [10]
Throughout his work Marx never tires of contrasting the relationships of personal
dependency in pre-capitalist society with the liberation from personal dependence
established by the bourgeois revolution; but then there comes the common
dependence on impersonal relations; through the mediation of money and capital new
social dependencies arise.
In feudalism there is the appearance of a meaningful unity between the individual and
the means of production in that land is individuated with its lord and its serfs – just this
particular estate is his and they belong to it. Hence the proverb: ‘No land without its
lord.’ [11] Developed private property, by contrast, has an abstractly universal form:
value. One can put one’s wealth ‘into anything – factories, land, works of art – without
ceasing to be ‘worth’ so much. Money dissolves all feudal fixity and we find the modern
saying ‘Money has no master’ expressing the absolute contingency of the relationship
between property and personality. In the Communist Manifesto Marx and Engels
(following Carlyle [12]) will declare that there remains ‘no other nexus between man
and man than naked self-interest, than callous “cash-payment”.’ [13] We no longer bow
the knee to princes, but now, says Marx, ‘an impersonal power rules over
everything’. [14]
What Marx traces in his treatment of pre-capitalist forms is a movement from a
situation where property is a politically enforced condition of labour (for example, one
just finds that one is obliged to work as a serf for the propertied) to that in which
property rests on the exploitation of the ‘free’ labourer in the capital relation. There is a
shift from a state of estrangement between labour and its conditions of actualization
(appearing over against it as another’s property) to the constitution of a process of
alienation sustaining the system of estrangement of labour from its object and itself.
The first relation (politically effected estrangement) is a historically prior condition of the
second complex; but in the movement of the economic totality that is now constituted
by the relations of labour and capital, labour establishes private property as its
estranged self. Marx says: ‘It is only at the culminating point of the development of
private property that this its secret re-emerges, namely, that on the one hand it is
the product of alienated labour, and on the other it is the means through which labour
alienates itself, the realization of this alienation.’ [15]
The relation of immediate exclusion between labour and its object remains in the new
dynamic, not now as a precondition, but as a mediated result, as the recurring moment
at which the worker is forced to sell his labour-power because he has no other
property. The whole system, including the reproduction of this very moment, is
sustained by labour’s continual self-alienation. [16]
Private property, originally other than labour, becomes in practice labour’s own other,
private property as alienated labour. Private property is unmasked as itself a structure of
alienation, rather than the (apparently external) cause of estrangement.
Let us now summarize the position we have reached – in so doing, perhaps,
elaborating it rather more sharply than it is explicitly articulated in the text.
It is necessary first to recognize the fact that we have now seen two senses in which
private property is less fundamental than productive activity. In the first place the
general level of discussion of these issues has led us to emphasize the importance of
conceptualizing the system of private property as a historically specific form of
organizing the material life of society. In principle it is possible to envisage material
production going on without it, and it is possible to discuss the work-process in
abstraction from it (as Marx does in the first section of the chapter on ‘the labour-
process’ in Capital). The question of the origins of the alienating second-order
mediations is something Marx does not attempt to tackle in the 1844 Manuscripts. (In
the German Ideology he links back private property to the development of the social
division of labour.) But this question is not relevant to his purposes in any case,
because what counts from the point of view of the dynamic of the supersession of the
private property system is its present articulation and contradictions. This in turn leads
us to the second striking aspect of Marx’s theory of alienation. As we have seen, even
if we take it that private property, and hence the estrangement of labour from its object,
is historically given, study of the movement of private property itself leads Marx to
conclude that in its reciprocal relationship with labour it is ultimately best understood as
the consequence rather than the cause of alienated labour. The state of estrangement
between labour and private property is developed, historically and conceptually, to a
process of active alienation of labour from itself.
At the level of first-order mediation Marx puts at the centre productive activity. At the
level of second-order mediation he puts at the centre, correspondingly, alienated
labour.
At the level of first-order mediation we are concerned with ‘human activity’ and its
‘object’, but these are now related within the second-order mediations, summarized as
the private property system, such that the first is constituted ‘as labour’, an activity
‘wholly alien to itself’, while the second is now held ‘as capital’ over against the
labourer. Their participation in the relationship of private property changes the
nature both of activity and its object. Furthermore, they now stand in a relation of mutual
opposition; but this opposition is itself a relationship, in which each defines itself
through exclusion from its other.
Marx goes on to explain that this contradiction emerges in all its purity only with the full
development of the private property system. Earlier, historically specific distinctions
existed both in forms of property-holding and in the sites of labour. Labour had ‘not yet
reached the stage of indifference to its content’; [24] but now it is merely a ‘source of
livelihood’ and as such the worker has no genuine identification with the work as it
is determinate, a specific job. Liberated from all traditional ties to. a foreordained
occupation, the ‘free worker’ of the industrial revoluton is a labour-power machine to be
slotted into any job as required, subject to the needs only of capital accumulation.
Likewise, while landed property still existed apart from industrial capital, it was still
‘afflicted with local and political prejudices’. [25] Marx gives a graphic description of the
ideological battles fought by the representatives of movable property and immovable
property (‘this distinction is not rooted in the nature of things’, he says, ‘it is
a historical distinction’ [26]); and the subsequent development ‘results in the necessary
victory of the capitalist over the landowner – that is to say, of developed over
underdeveloped, immature private property – just as in general, movement must
triumph over immobility, open selfconscious baseness over hidden unconscious
baseness, cupidity over self-indulgence, the avowedly restless, adroit self-interest
of enlightenment over the parochial wordly-wise respectable, idle and fantastic self-
interest of superstition, and money over the other forms of private property.’ [27]
At all events, the upshot of the development of the system of private property is a pure
contradiction between two poles: Labour (‘indifferent to its content’) and capital
(likewise ‘indifferent to its real content’). The two terms (opposed and united) of the
property relationship, labour and its object, the propertyless and the propertied, were
previously chained together in particularized fixed units. Now, each side has become
free to move and has attained abstractly universal form; both enter into a systematic
totality, and become posited by the private property relationship itself.
Marx notices that the real history of private property is paralleled by the development of
the theory of political economy. He says that the real process ‘repeats itself in the
scientific analysis of the subjective essence of private property, labour. Labour appears
at first only as agricultural labour, but then asserts itself as labour in general’. [28] Marx
draws two conclusions. It is only with the victory of industrial capital ‘that private
property can complete its domination over man and become, in its most general form, a
world historical power’; [29] and ‘only when labour is grasped as the essence of private
property can this economic process be analysed in its actual specificity’. [30]
This contradictory unity of labour and its other is important for Marx’s dialectical
development of the downfall of the whole private property system as it is drawn out in
this and other passages. For example, the communist movement has the historic task
of overthrowing private property assigned to it by Marx: but what is the ground of this
necessity? If it were simply a matter of a discrepancy between wealth and poverty, an
opposition between those who own property and those who have nothing, this might
lead to a ‘call for’ the rectification of this antithesis based on some criterion of social
justice applied externally to the existing situation. Marx, however, is able to root the
necessity of the communist movement in the contradiction internal to the development
of modern private property. In so doing he has to reinterpret the antithesis of property
and propertylessness as that of capital and labour, because only in the latter form does
the possibility arise of understanding the relation in a suitably dynamic fashion. It is true
that throughout the 1844 Manuscripts Marx more often speaks of private property than of
capital, but it is perfectly clear that his reading of political economy had allowed him to
grasp the central importance of the capital – labour contradiction. The following
passage puts the matter beyond all doubt:
The antithesis {Gegensatz} between propertylessness and property, so long as it is
not comprehended as the antithesis of labour and capital, still remains an
indifferent antithesis, not grasped in its active connection, in its internal relation,
not yet grasped as a contradiction {Widerspruch}. It can find expression in
this first form even without the advanced development of private property (as in
ancient Rome, Turkey, etc.). It does not yet appear as having been established by
private property itself. But labour, the subjective essence of private property as
exclusion of property, and capital, objective labour as exclusion of labour,
constitute private property as its developed state of contradiction hence a
dynamic relationship driving towards resolution {Auflösung}. [31]
Private property in ‘its developed state of contradiction’ is characterized by the
simultaneous identity and exclusion of two poles, labour and capital. Hence there can
be no harmonious synthesis – only a drive towards dissolution. This important feature
of the dialectic of second-order mediation (private property and exchange)
distinguishes it markedly from that of the first-order mediation.
What precisely is the reason for this? Each side is posited purely negatively against the
other as everything which it is not. There is no mutually supportive interpenetration of
opposites (as in the positive sense the difference between the sexes has in the need of
each for the other): there is mutual repulsion within the exploitative relationship of
private property. The mediations that give room for this relation to develop itself
(wages, profit, etc.) establish the identity of each with its other only because each
moment internalizes the contradictory unity in itself. To use the language of Capital: the
private property relation as capital appears in the distinction between constant capital
and variable capital; the private property relation as labour appears in the oppression of
living labour by dead labour. In the language of 1844 Marx defines labour as ‘the
subjective essence of private property as exclusion of property’ and capital as
‘objective labour as exclusion of labour’. No matter how highly mediated the
relationship of private property becomes, at bottom labour and capital remain as
untransformed extremes. Hence Marx’s prediction of a clash of mutual contradictions
precipitating a collapse of the system.
This takes him way beyond his sources in classical political economy (even that which
reflects the full development of modern industry in prioritizing productive labour)
because such political economy mirrors the process of objectification in alienated form.
When Smith traces wealth to labour, he traces the bourgeois form of wealth to its origin
in value-producing labour. The first-order mediations are grasped through the prism of
the estranging second-order mediation (private property).
In a very suggestive comparison, Marx, following Engels, says of Smith that he was
‘the Luther of political economy’. [34] Just as Luther attacked external religiosity in the
form of fetish-worshipping, priests, ritual, churches etc., in order to implant God all the
more firmly in the hearts of the religious, so Smith mocked the mercantilists’ illusions
about gold and other external forms of property, in order to put labour as such all the
more firmly under the category of property as the inner essence of wealth, that is, of
value. However, this political economy cannot conceptualize the matter in a critical way
because it takes property in all factors of production for granted. It therefore sees the
social synthesis achieved only through money, wages and the market.
In spite of its advance from the ‘being’ of wealth to its ‘becoming’, the standpoint of
classical political economy is thus not that of productive activity as such, but of this
activity only as it is determined within the private property system as
productive labour (‘an activity alien to itself’).
On the one hand political economy has the merit of turning the spotlight from the
merely objective form of wealth to the human subject creating it. Thus Marx says that
only ‘the political economy which acknowledged labour as its principle – Adam Smith –
and which therefore no longer looked upon private property as a
mere condition external to man . . . has to be regarded . . . as a product . . . of the
real movement of private property – as a product of modern industry . . .’. [35] On the
other hand political economy, in conceptualizing labour as the subjective essence of
wealth, at the same time absolutizes these alienating mediations. But as a result man
is brought within the orbit of private property, just as with Luther he is brought within the
orbit of religion’, Marx points out.
Under the semblance of recognizing man, the political economy whose principle
is labour rather carries to its logical conclusion the denial of man since man
himself no longer stands in an external relation of tension to the external
substance of private property, but has himself become this tense essence of
private property. [36]
The meaning of the shift from external tension to tense essence in political economy is
easily comprehended if we remember that we developed above the real dialectic of (a)
‘mutual exclusion’; (b) ‘opposition of each to itself’; and (c) ‘hostile reciprocal
opposition’.
Political economy makes labour its principle, but since this labour is itself a
determination of private property it is not productive activity organically united with its
object and recognizing itself in its product, at home with itself in its activity; it is labour
as the ‘tense essence’ of private property, it is an alienating mediator producing the
product as loss of the object, activity as hateful, not as self-fulfilment but merely a
source of livelihood.
Political economy capitulates to this reality because it does not problematize the private
property system itself. For political economy, productive activity is necessarily labour, a
determination of private property itself; hence the benefits of productive activity
naturally accrue to private property. Political economy endorses this contradiction. Its
principle (labour) is a category which refers us implicitly to productive activity itself, but
this activity is estranged from itself, in contradiction with itself. Its principle, says Marx,
is ‘the principle of this rupture’, hence a contradictory principle, the consequences of
which ramify throughout the system. [37]
By contrast, Marx grasps the situation as one of labour’s self-alienation in and through
private property. Only if labour is grasped as the overriding moment in the alienated
labour/private property complex can the conditions of a real transcendence of
estrangement be established. Grounded in the alienation of labour, the immanent
movement of private property necessarily produces ‘its own grave diggers’ (in the
famous phrase of the Communist Manifesto). But in the dialectical opposition of private
property and alienated labour the principal aspect of the contradiction then becomes
the latter; hence Marx says that the fall of wage-labour and private property –
‘identical’ [38] expressions of estrangement – takes place ‘in the political form of the
emancipation of the workers‘. [39]
Later in the year 1844 Marx supplements this analysis of the contradictions while
composing The Holy Family (a critique mounted against the Young Hegelian Bruno
Bauer). He argues as follows:
Private property as private property, as wealth, is compelled to maintain itself,
and thereby its opposite, the proletariat, in existence . . . The proletariat, on the
contrary, is compelled as proletariat to abolish itself and thereby its opposite,
private property, which determines its existence, and which makes it proletariat.
It is the negative side of the antithesis, its restlessness within its very self,
dissolved and self-dissolving private property . . . Indeed private property drives
itself in its economic movement towards its own dissolution, but only through a
development which does not depend on it, which is unconscious and which takes
place against the will of private property by the very nature of things, only
inasmuch as it produces the proletariat as proletariat . . . [40]
The proletarian revolution is itself necessarily only a moment of transition. The content
of the movement reveals itself as the transformation of the whole society. When the
proletariat is victorious, it by no means becomes the absolute side of society, for it is
victorious only by abolishing itself and its opposite. Then the proletariat disappears as
well as the opposite which determines it, private property. [41]
The next chapter will investigate the significance of this victory, that is to say, Marx’s
understanding of communism.
Summary
In and through the private property system labour is separated from its object. This state
of estrangement develops into a process of active alienation of labour from itself, when
private property becomes posited as capital, as the product of alienated labour. The
condition (private property as the ground of estrangement) becomes the conditioned
(private property as the result of alienated labour). The presupposition (mutual
exclusion of labour and its object) of the private property relationship
becomes posited by the dialectic of the system itself (as a contradictory unity).
Classical political economy grasps labour as the subjective essence of private property;
but since it absolutizes the system of second-order mediation (conflating it with the
first-order level) it identifies itself with the standpoint of alienating mediation (labour).
In Marx’s view, the project of superseding alienation is grounded in the contradictory
development of private property itself. It takes political form as the revolt of the
proletariat against private property; but the proletariat overcomes this its other only by
abolishing itself as proletariat at the same time.
Chapter 3 – Communism
← Chapter 2 | Chapter 4 →
Introduction
We have seen that Marx puts productive activity at the centre of his ontology. Man
produces himself in and through this mediator; he develops new powers and new
needs in the dialectic of this practice. Under the rule of private property this whole
development takes place under the guise of estrangement. So, far from gaining
confidence in himself and enjoying himself in his object and his activity, the producer
cannot identify himself in the world he has made, his labour is the activity of alienation.
It is in this light that Marx reinterprets communism. For him it is no narrowly political
and juridical adjustment of existing powers and privileges. It has fundamental
ontological significance as the gateway to the reappropriation by the community of the
human essence, the recovery of a human meaning to production, consumption and
society. This chapter is concerned with exploring Marx’s concept of communism, as it
is outlined at the beginning of the third manuscript.
Marx begins with the objective power of private property over the immediate producer.
His investigation discloses that this alien power is the product of labour itself in its
alienation. Abolition of estrangement requires the abolition of private property. But it is
important to understand that Marx does not adopt a purely negative attitude to property
and that he attributes a positive meaning to his call for the supersession of the private
property system. A mere ‘abstract negation’ of private property would mean, he says,
the negation ‘of culture and civilization, the regression to the unnatural simplicity of
the poor, crude man without needs, who has not only failed to go beyond private
property, but has not even reached it’. [1]
Marx believes that there are good reasons why the private property system was a
historically necessary stage in the development of wealth. It took the pressure of capital
to awaken the slumbering powers of humanity and promote ‘general industriousness’.
Although this means that human productive power has taken the shape of
estrangement, Marx clearly distinguishes the ontological necessity of objectification
from the historical fact that it presently constitutes a world of estrangement founded on
alienated labour. Overcoming estrangement through communism means the
reappropriation of the ‘ontological essence’ of humanity which has constituted itself
‘through developed industry, that is, through the mediation of private property’,
objectively as an external alien power. [2] This means that there is something positive in
property, disguised by its alien form as the power of capital, namely the wealth of
human self-development. Marx says: ‘The meaning of private property, freed from its
estrangement, is the existence of essential objects for man, both as objects of
enjoyment and of activity’. [3] Previous communist doctrine, he claims, had not
‘grasped the positive essence of private property’. [4] It is not a question for Marx of
annulling private property and all its works, then, but of taking possession of the
immensely powerful modern productive forces by society for the satisfaction on this
basis of rich human needs.
Stages of Communism
When Marx considers the communist movement thrown up in opposition to the rule of
the propertied classes, he distinguishes various stages in its development. The only
two he treats at any length are (a) crude egalitarian communism and (b) ‘communism
as the positive supersession of private property as human self-estrangement, and
therefore as the actual appropriation of the human essence . . . ‘. [5]
The first stage, ‘raw communism’ (‘der rohe Kommunismus‘) is based on ‘envy’ of the
propertied rather than any critical understanding of the essence of the property
relationship. Its programme involves a levelling down and an attempt to impose
equality through the negation of individual differences of any kind: [6] ‘the category
of worker is not done away with but extended to all men; the relationship of private
property persists as the relationship of the community to the world of things.’ [7] Equal
wages are to be paid out by the community as a kind of ‘abstract
capitalist’. [8] Property is therefore not so much transcended as universalized. An
expression of the ‘vileness of private property trying to set itself up as
the positive community system’ [9] is the counterposing to marriage (‘certainly a form of
exclusive private property’) of ‘the community of women, where the woman becomes a
piece of communal and common property’. [10] This leads Marx to the following
reflections: ‘The relation of man to woman reveals the extent to which need has
become human need; the extent to which, therefore, the other, as human, has become a
need, the extent to which in his individual existence he is at the same time a communal
being.’ It follows that ‘from this relationship one can therefore judge the whole level of
development of mankind’. [11] This statement of Marx’s is often cited nowadays, but it
is by no means original to him. Fourier argued strongly that ‘the progress women make
towards freedom . . . is the general principle of all social progress’. [12] In fact, Marx
was reading Fourier at the time and cites a similar passage from the latter’s work:
The change in a historical epoch can always be determined by women’s progress
towards freedom, because, here, in the relationship of woman to man, of the
weak to the strong, the victory of human nature over brutality is most evident.
The degree of emancipation of women is the natural measure of general
emancipation. [13]
Communism in its true form may be contrasted with crude equalitarianism by its
attitude to private property. The ‘abstract negation’ of private property, mentioned
above, treats it as ‘the enemy’, a malevolent power disrupting human fraternity and
setting men at odds with each other. Grasped as the contradiction of alienated labour
with itself, private property requires a determinate negation which preserves in some
form the human wealth created in its history. This ‘negation of the negation’ takes us
forwards not backwards. As Marx puts it, very generally:
Communism is the positive supersession of private property as human self-
estrangement, and hence the true appropriation of the human essence through and
for man; it is the complete restoration of man to himself . . . which takes place
within the entire wealth of previous periods of development. [14]
It is obvious, Marx points out, that communism understood in a historical light does not
amount to a revulsion from the achievements of the epoch of private property, ‘an
impoverished regression to primitive simplicity’, as he puts it, [15] but the
reappropriation of mankind’s historically developed essential powers through the
destruction of the estranged character of this reified world in which they are embodied.
In contrast to this picture of communism as a result immanent in history, crude
communist ideology seeks an empirical proof for itself in isolated examples of
cooperation torn from their historical context. As Marx observes, ‘all it succeeds in
showing is that by far the greater part of this development contradicts its assertions and
that if it (communism) did once exist then the very fact that it existed in the past refutes
its claim to essential being {Wesen}’. [16] Marx is confident that communist revolution is
the outcome of the movement of private property itself; it is ‘the riddle of history
solved’, [17] he says. However, this does not mean it has the status of an ‘Absolute’ in
his philosophy. At the end of this section he equates ‘the position’ of communism with
‘the negation of the negation’; in so far as private property – the negation of human
freedom – must itself be negated, this is a ‘real phase’, necessary to the liberation and
recovery of mankind. But this is not the whole story. Note Marx’s conclusion:
‘Communism is the necessary shape and the dynamic principle of the immediate
future, but communism itself is not as such the goal of human development – the
shape of human society.’ [18]
Complete failure to understand this dialectic is exhibited in the identification by certain
commentators of ‘communism as such’ with equalitarian communisms discussed
earlier in Marx’s chapter. [19] But those are ideological stages in the development of
communist ideas, whereas here we are speaking of a ‘real phase’. [20] By ‘communism
as such’ Marx clearly understands ‘communism as the opposite of private property’.
The communist movement develops in opposition to private property. Thus, in some
sense it is even the creation of the movement of private property. But in a higher phase
of development socialism stands on its own feet so to speak and ‘no longer needs such
mediation’. [21]
Marx illustrates the point with the example of atheism. This is a peculiar kind of
humanism because it depends for its sense on first of all positing what it denies. It
asserts the autonomy of man, only through the negation of god. First man is negated
through being reduced to a creature of god; but then the negation of the negation
reasserts the essentiality of man. This humanism is thoroughly infected by the opposite
through which it developed its position. This is very clear in the Sartrean man who says
to himself: ‘God is dead; I am abandoned; I am alone; there is no commandment; I
must take complete responsibility for my destiny.’ This kind of consciousness is that of
the man who first believed in god and then lost his faith. It is quite different from a
humanism that never knew god in the first plate and hence could never feel lost without
him!
In the same way socialism as ‘positive humanism’ stands on the ground of the
essential relations of man to himself and to nature. It does not require to be perpetually
mediated through its understanding of itself as the opposite of private property,
although this is a historically necessary stage. Marx says that ‘atheism is humanism
mediated with itself through the supersession of religion, whilst communism is
humanism mediated with itself through the supersession of private property’. He
continues: ‘only through the supersession of this mediation – which itself, however, is a
necessary premise – does positive humanism come into being’. [22]
If ‘communism as such’ is not the goal, what then is the aim of human development?
Erich Fromm has the merit of addressing this question: ‘Quite clearly the aim of
socialism is man’, he says, ‘it is to creates a form of production and an organization of
society . . . in which he can return to himself and grasp the world with his own powers,
thus becoming one with the world.’ [23] Fromm’s answer is not far off the mark, as the
following passage from Marx’s Grundrisse (1857-78) shows:
The old view, where man, in spite of his various limitations . . ., still appears as
the aim of production, seems very superior to the modern world where
production appears as the aim of man and wealth as the aim of production. In
fact, however, when the narrow bourgeois form has been cast off, what is wealth
other than the universality of needs, capacities and enjoyments, productive
forces, etc. of individuals . . .? The full development of human mastery over
natural forces, those of his own nature as well as those of socalled ‘Nature’? The
absolute working out of his creative dispositions, without any presupposition
other than previous historical development . . .? Where he does not produce
himself in any determined form, but produces his totality? Seeks not to remain
something he has become, but is in the absolute movement of becoming? [24]
Marx’s Standpoint
Let us try to identify the various levels of discussion of the problem of alienation as we
have clarified them. Then we can explain Marx’s standpoint with regard to the
possibility of overcoming alienation.
Summary
The ‘positive essence of private property’ is its embodiment of the objectification of
human productive activity. Communism is hence given the significance of a ‘positive
supersession of private property’, that is, the reappropriation of the human essence
presently estranged in it.
Hence communism is ‘the riddle of history solved’, but it is not as such ‘the goal’
because its position is that of ‘the negation of the negation‘, still determined by its
opposite.
Marx’s investigation of the private property system discloses that the estrangement of
the worker from the object and the product of his activity is the presupposition and the
result of alienated labour. Hence Marx takes the critically adopted standpoint of labour in
conceptualizing the supersession of estrangement.
Introduction
The 1844 Manuscripts is intended by Marx as a work in the field of political economy,
taking its object critically, from a socialist point of view. This is explained in the Preface;
but then, abruptly, Marx states that he considers it ‘absolutely necessary’ to include ‘a
critical discussion of Hegelian dialectic and philosophy as a whole’. [1] This seems an
odd ambition for a critical work on economics; certainly he does not explain why he
considers it necessary to undertake this here. One is left to suppose that he thought it
necessary to engage with the methodological concerns of his contemporaries, the
Young Hegelians, who thought their philosophical inheritance allowed them to criticize
anything under the sun without knowing anything about it. Marx observes pointedly that
his is ‘a wholly empirical analysis based on a conscientious critical study of political
economy’. [2] Nevertheless, Marx had very good reason to give an important place to
‘discussion of Hegelian dialectic’. We can understand why if we trace the course of his
thought in the manuscripts themselves. In fart, the unhelpful ‘Preface’ was one of the
last passages to be written; it was drafted after all the material on Hegel.
Why Hegel?
If we look at the manuscripts in their original order of composition, it becomes obvious
that initially Marx had no intention of bringing in Hegel. There is no mention of him in
the first two manuscripts. It is only in the third manuscript, in which Marx embarks on a
series of discrete reflections on the topic of communism, that ‘point six’ begins with the
remark that ‘this is perhaps the place to offer, by way of explanation and justification,
some considerations on Hegelian dialectic generally and especially its exposition in
the Phenomenology and Logic, and also, lastly, the relation [to it] of the modern critical
movement’. [3]
At first it seems there will just be a short digression, but in the remaining pages he
returns twice to the question, linking the passages with his own cross-references, so
that in the end we have a substantial set of notes. At this point he decides that he will
pull all this material together in a ‘concluding chapter’ and, as we saw, he announces
this when he goes on to write the Preface. [4]
The crucial question to investigate is this: what forced Marx to feel under an obligation
to offer ‘by way of explanation and justification’ his critical discussion of Hegelian
dialectic under the original sixth point? Not surprisingly, the problem is solved as soon
as we refer to the last paragraph of the fifth point. [5] This begins with an important
statement of Marx’s view of genesis: ‘since for socialist man the whole of so-called world
history is nothing but the creation of man through human labour, nothing but the
emergence of nature for man, so has he palpable, incontrovertible proof of
his birth through himself, of his genesis.’ [6]
Several problems of interpretation arise from this remarkable statement (even if one
neglects Marx’s belief that he therewith disposes of the religious theory of creation). It
is fairly clear that Marx is not saying that man creates himself entire out of nothing. On
the contrary, we have seen earlier that Marx stresses that human activity requires an
object, and that labour cannot create anything, not even man himself, without nature.
What Marx is summarizing here is the process whereby man, originally nothing but a
part of nature, takes himself and nature as his object. At first he is ‘at one’ with nature,
but then nature becomes ‘for‘ man, something he can work with, and transform. At first
again this must appear as a dependence on natural conditions, but in so far as these
conditions of his existence pass more and more under his own control, with the
development of his productive powers, so in his existence he depends more and more
on himself and his productive activity. He becomes his own product, so to speak.
Speaking thus, we inevitably recall Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, in which absolute
spirit grasps itself as its own product. Its being is self-mediated. In his Preface Hegel
emphasizes that spirit mediates itself with itself only through ‘the labour of the
negative’, in alienation and transcendence of alienation. [7] This refers us back to Marx
again; for the paragraph under discussion concludes (in an argument we considered
earlier) with a definition of communism as the phase of ‘negation of the negation’,
ushering in ‘socialism as socialism’, ‘real life . . . no longer mediated through the
abolition of private property, through communism’. [8] We can understand now that
Marx ‘by way of explanation and justification’ has to undertake a discussion of Hegel,
because friends and enemies of Hegel alike could not fail to notice these parallels and
interpret the text accordingly, probably with unfortunate consequences. For example,
Marx needs to show how his ‘positive supersession of private property’ differs from
Hegelian positing through negativity.
Another problem of interpretation arising from Marx’s account of human genesis is the
use of the term ‘labour’ in ‘the creation of man through human labour’. Remembering
that we earlier distinguished two possible connotations of the term in the 1844
Manuscripts, which interpretation should be adopted here? In truth, both interpretations
are possible. This could well be a case where Marx draws attention to the ultimate
consequences of the (first-order) mediatory activity constituting man for himself, and
nature for man; thus ‘labour’ would here refer to that (ontologically
fundamental) productive activity in and through which man becomes who he is.
However, this does not exclude a narrower reading of ‘labour’ as ‘alienated activity’
along the lines of the interpretation offered earlier, if it is accepted that, in history to the
present, productive activity has been identical with ‘labour’ defined in terms of the
determinations of the ruling property systems. This means that human genesis
proceeds by way of alienated activity. This is undoubtedly what Marx believed, and it
constitutes an almost exact parallel with Hegel’s view. Marx indeed gives Hegel credit
for this: ‘the great thing in Hegel’s Phenomenology‘, he says, ‘is that Hegel conceives the
self-creation of man as . . . alienation and as transcendence of this alienation, that he
thus grasps the essence of labour and comprehends objective man . . . as the result of
his own labour‘. [9] He goes on to repeat the point – this time critically noting a direct
connection between Hegel’s Phenomenology and political economy. He claims that
‘Hegel’s standpoint is that of modern political economy’. This is because he
‘grasps labour as the essence . . .’ In his work, just as in political economy, ‘labour is
man’s coming-to-be-for-himself {Fürsichwerden} within alienation or
as alienated man’, [10] (This last statement makes particularly clear the sense of
‘labour’ employed.)
Marx also give notice (in his first passage on Hegel) that he will show that Hegel’s
standpoint does not go beyond that of ‘negation of the negation’ and that this ‘is not yet
the real history of man as a previously posited subject, but simply the act of creation,
the history of the genesis, of man’. [11]
The above remarks and quotations are enough to show that a number of questions
arise about Mare’s understanding of his relationship to Hegel. The answers will help us
at the same time to judge the significance of the claims he advances in his theory of
alienation.
Summary
In evolving his theory of alienation, Marx realizes that, since the pattern whereby labour
grasps its other (private property) as its own self, estranged from itself, and negates
this negation, has obvious parallels with Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, he must
explain and justify his position in relation to Hegel’s dialectic. He finds both strengths
and weaknesses in it, as we shall see.
Introduction
In his 1844 Manuscripts, although he promises a critique of Hegel’s dialectic as a whole,
Marx pays most attention to Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit (1807) on the ground that it
is ‘the true birthplace and secret of Hegelian philosophy’. [1] Marx is most interested
here in trying to situate Hegel’s achievement in relation to his own concept of alienated
labour. Hegel’s strengths and weaknesses are evaluated in this light. Hegel’s strength
is precisely that he gives full recognition to the problem of estrangement. His weakness
is that, in spite of the wealth of social and historical material treated, he considers it
ultimately as a problem of consciousness.
After Marx, whose labours remained unknown for nearly a hundred years, it is not until
Georg Lukács that the problem of Hegel’s Phenomenology is considered, first and
foremost, as alienation and its overcoming. [2] It is hard for us now to realize how
original Lukécs was in taking up, as long ago as 1938, the question of Hegel’s concept
of ‘Entäusserung‘ (alienation), [3] albeit with he benefit of Marx’s recently discovered
manuscripts in front of him. The last chapter of his masterly work The Young Hegel is
entitled ‘Entäusserung as the central philosophical concept of the Phenomenology of
Spirit‘.
A point of terminology to bear in mind is that the translators of Hegel, and of Marx, do
not agree on the rendering of ‘Entäusserung‘ – some give ‘alienation’ and others give
‘externalization’. I prefer, and give here, ‘alienation’. Lukács notes that there is nothing
novel about the terms Entäusserung and Entfremdung in themselves. ‘They are’, he says.
‘simply German translations of the English word “alienation”. [4] The alternative to
‘alienation’, namely ‘externalization’ (the closest rendering of Entäusserung from a purely
etymological point of view), is liable to be confused with ‘objectification’. It is important
to notice this because Marx explicitly distinguishes objectification (Vergegenständlichung)
from alienation (Entäusserung). The difference, broadly, is that,
while Entäusserung carries the sense of ‘posited as objective’, it also connotes
relinquishment, such that an objectivity is set up from which the subject is
estranged. Entfremdung is quite unambiguous, and may be tendered as ‘estrangement’.
(For further philological information, and a comparison of translations, see Appendix.)
Before embarking (in the next chapter) on Marx’s critical analysis of The Phenomenology
of Spirit, let us recall here some of the salient points about its method and results.
Phenomenological Method
In his Introduction (not to be confused with the more famous Preface), Hegel argues
that traditional epistemology, worrying itself about the criterion of true knowledge, gets
caught up in insoluble contradictions. It itself is making a claim to knowledge, and
hence must either appeal to that same criterion (circularity) or to some other criterion
(regress). This problem has been called ‘the dilemma of epistemology’. [5] Hegel
considers the possibility that we could spare ourselves the trouble of engaging in the
epistemological problematic and go straight to scientific work confident that the science
itself will provide its own proof of itself; but he rejects this too, because such a claim to
positive knowledge, facing other claims to knowledge, as well as commonsensical
views, seems helpless to prevail. It asserts itself as true – but so do they. ‘One bare
assurance is worth just as much as another’, [6] Hegel comments.
But it is in just such phenomena that Hegel sees the possibility of a way forward. He
undertakes ‘an exposition of how knowledge makes its appearance’. This is what he
understands by a phenomenology. The exposition of claims to knowledge in this form
seems ‘not to be science’ yet Hegel believes that ‘the series of configurations
{Gestaltungen} which consciousness goes through along this road is, in reality, the
detailed history of the education {Bildung} of consciousness itself to the standpoint of
science’.[7] In his Preface Hegel likewise speaks of ‘the spirit that educates itself (‘der
sich bildende Geist‘). [8] ‘Education’ is too narrow a translation of Bildung if it suggests
only formal training, of course; one could even speak here of ‘the spirit that builds itself
up’. It is apposite here also to recall the popularity in Hegel’s time of the
‘Bildungsroman‘. A Bildungsroman is a novel that presents the educative effect of the
hero’s experience. [9] Thus the Phenomenology, in a similar way, may be understood as
the story of the Bildung of spirit. [10] Indeed, Royce argues that
the Bildungsroman model certainly influenced Hegel’s procedure in the Phenomenology;
he cites Goethe’s Wilhelm Meisters Lehrjahre.[11] Hyppolite says the same, but draws
attention to Hegel’s study of Rousseau’s Émile. [12] Lukács prefers the epithet: ‘an
odyssey of spirit’, but also calls attention to Goethe’s work. [13]
There are some very peculiar characteristics of this Bildungsroman of spirit. One relates
to method: Hegel’s method depends, he explains, on the dialectical point that when a
given claim to knowledge is to be rejected as untrue ‘the exposition of the untrue
consciousness in its untruth is not merely a negative procedure’, because if the result of
the argument is properly understood as a determinate negation of the original thesis, ‘a
new form has thereby immediately arisen’. [14] That is to say, to refute is not simply to
deny, but to find relevant grounds for such rejection. Every claim to knowledge has its
specific refutation, and this involves consciousness in a new set of commitments.
Making progress in this way we generate a complete series of forms of knowledge.
Validity appears here not in relation to an external measure but in accordance with
what consciousness provides ‘from within itself’ at each stage. As Hyppolite points out,
the condition of this method is the assumption that knowledge is a whole. Indeed the
whole is immanent throughout the development. ‘Negation is creative’, he argues,
‘because the posited term has been isolated and thus was itself a kind of negation.’ It
follows that its negation is in turn a step towards the restoration of the whole. According
to Hyppolite, ‘were it not for the immanence of the whole in consciousness, we should
be unable to understand how negation can truly engender a content’. [15]
Hegel’s goal is to reach ‘the point where knowledge no longer needs to go beyond
itself’. [16] Under what conditions could such an absolute resting place arrive? He
answers that, ‘in pressing forward to its true existence, consciousness will arrive at a
point at which it gets rid of its semblance of being burdened with something alien’.
Thus, at the point where consciousness grasps its own essence, this will signify ‘the
nature of absolute knowledge itself’. [17]
Hegel presents this progression as immanent in the phenomena themselves: for ‘the
necessary progression and interconnection of the forms of the unreal consciousness
will by itself bring to pass the completion of the series’. [18] Consequently, ‘we do not
need to import criteria, or to make use of our own bright ideas and thoughts during the
course of the inquiry’, he says; ‘it is precisely when we leave these aside that we
succeed in contemplating the matter in hand as it is in and for itself.’ [19] Hegel takes
this so seriously that he says: ‘all that is left for us to do is simply to look on’. [20] The
book therefore takes the form, not of Hegel’s refutations and proofs, but, as we said, of
a Bildungsroman of spirit in which it develops a more and more comprehensive
consciousness of itself and its world.
In the Phenomenology the crucial problem is that of objectivity. However, this is a
problem primarily because of the way Hegel construes the relationship of knowledge to
its object. More particularly, the problem is: how can consciousness claim to know its
object (Gegenstand) when the latter is posited as other than it? Interesting, in view of
Hegel’s Swabian origins, is the information M.J. Petry provides: that in the Swabian
dialect of Hegel’s day ‘Gegenstand‘ was also synonymous with ‘impediment, opposition,
obstacle, resistance’. [21] Any reader of the Phenomenology cannot fail to be struck by
the stress laid on the developing activity of consciousness in knowing, and the
presentation of the independence of the object as an obstacle to its free movement.
Nothing could be further from Locke’s tabula rasa. As the phenomenological dialectic
proceeds, the solution to the antinomy of subjectivity and objectivity emerges:
consciousness becomes more and more aware that it is its own activity that constitutes
the object as an object of knowledge. The very distinction between knowledge and its
object is drawn from the point of view of consciousness and is hence to be construed
as a distinction falling within consciousness itself. [22]
So, if Hegel begins with a situation in which the knowing self takes it that what stands
over against it is objectivity, he overcomes this opposition through showing that every
higher shape of consciousness posits the form of knowledge, and the object as it is
now known, as more and more adequate to each other. The upshot is Absolute
Knowing, in which knowing knows that what appears to it as its object is only itself.
Since the activity of consciousness itself in knowing becomes more and more
prominent in the development, it is clear that self-consciousness becomes centrally
involved. Equally, if the self is to make itself an object of consciousness, it can only do
so (i.e. become known to itself as what it really is) through its own activity, its self-
realization. Thus Hegel’s discussion imperceptibly slides into terrain unknown to
epistemology. The progress of critical reflection upon the adequacy of knowledge to its
object becomes a progress in the history of Geist (spirit or mind). Spirit learns what it
truly is (and its relationship to the world of objectivity) at the same time, and in exact
proportion, as it becomes what it truly is through manifesting itself in objective form (in
morality, in bourgeois life, in the state, in religion), and in so doing it eventually ends its
estrangement from its world through identifying itself in it. The relationship of this
history to real history is an extremely difficult and controversial topic in Hegelian
scholarship; nevertheless, it is clear from the wealth of obvious allusions that Hegel
wishes us to bear this connection in mind.
Engels characterizes the Phenomenology of Spirit as ‘the embryology and paleontology
of the mind, a development of individual consciousness through its different stages, set
in the form of an abbreviated reproduction of the stages through which the
consciousness of man has passed in the course of history’. [23] In answer to those
readers who find the historical points of reference appear in a jumble, Lukács points
out that these moments occur in their correct historical sequence, but that this
sequence is traversed three times. [24] Hegel’s point of departure is the natural
consciousness existing as an individual to which objective reality presents itself as
given even where socio-historical determinations underly the developing shapes of
consciousness. The acquisition of reason makes possible the perception of society and
history as the product of activity. With this, the conscious individual enters the second
cycle and must traverse the whole path again, understood now in the shape of
explicitly social forms of experience. In the ‘absolute’ stage consciousness looks back
over the panorama of the whole history of its experience, and by recognizing,
recollecting and ordering those moments, spirit grasps the significance of the whole.
However, this knowledge too is not just an abstract truth, but is acquired in the dialectic
of a specific domain. Thus the third stage once again recapitulates the past in its
entirety but on this occasion we no longer find the actual series of moments, but a
summary of mankind’s efforts to comprehend reality. The last chapter, on absolute
knowing, contains a compressed history of modern philosophy, for example. In it Hegel
equates his own philosophy with fully developed absolute knowledge – knowledge as
science.
Alienation
Absolute knowledge comprehends that ‘objectivity’, standing over against the
‘subjectivity’ estranged from it, is brought forth only within the self-alienating movement
of spirit. Lukács is quite correct, therefore, to see Entäusserung (alienation) as the
central philosophical concept of the Phenomenology. Marx points us to the following
crucial passage from Hegel’s last chapter in which he employs this term in
summarizing his conclusions:
Surmounting the object of consciousness is not to be taken one-sidedly to mean
that the object showed itself as returning into the self . . . but rather that it is the
alienation {Entäusserung} of self-consciousness that posits thinghood {die
Dingheit} and that this alienation has not merely a negative but a positive
meaning . . . for self-consciousness . . . for in this alienation it posits itself as
object, or the object as itself. . . This positing at the same time contains the other
moment, that self-consciousness has equally sublated {aufgehoben} this
alienation and objectivity too and taken it back into itself so that it is at home
with itself in its otherness as such {in seinem Andersseyn als solchem bey sich
ist}. [25]
Of great service to Hegel in preserving, while supposedly overcoming, objectivity as a
moment in the absolute, is his dialectical category of ‘Aufhebung‘ (sublation). In
his Logic Hegel tells us that in ordinary language Aufheben means not only to abolish
but also to preserve, and that he intends to take advantage of this double meaning. In
his criticism of Hegel Marx comments that ‘Aufheben‘ plays ‘a peculiar role’ in Hegel’s
system. In it, affirmation and negation are brought together; thus, in spite of their
‘sublation’ in the course of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, property, the family, civil society,
etc. ‘continue to exist’, he points out, ‘but have become moments . . . which mutually
dissolve and engender one another, moments of movement’. [26] In the Phenomenology,
likewise, ‘Aufhebung‘ preserves alienation in the very moment of retracting it.
How does self-consciousness ‘surmount the object of consciousness’ and ‘take it back
into itself’? Very schematically, one could say that, in collecting together the various
determinations taken on by the object of consciousness as it is experienced throughout
the path traversed by spirit, the totality of these determinations is grasped by spirit as
its own self-determination. This comprehension Hegel characterizes as a recollection
(Erinnerung). Here we must return to our philological apparatus again, because the
second time this term occurs in the final paragraph of the Phenomenology Hegel rakes
the opportunity to bring out the etymological possibility of characterizing this as an Er-
Innerung, an inwardizing movement – the appropriate counter-movement to an
‘externalization’ (one of the meanings of ‘Entäusserung‘). He says: ‘die Er-Innerung hat
sie aufbewahrt . . .’ – ‘the internalization has preserved it’. [27]
Lukács thinks this passage is so important that he quotes it three times. [28] For
example: if spirit has created the real objects of the world in the process of
‘Entäusserung‘, ‘it is only logical’, he says, ‘for the reverse process of “Er-lnnerung” to be
nothing other than the sublation of the forms of objective reality so created, and their
reintegration into the subject’. [29] He points out that, consistently with this, the
standpoint of absolute knowledge does not give us any new content: ‘all the contents
available’, he says, ‘arise not from philosophy itself, but from . . . the historical process
of the self-positing of spirit . . . now . . . illuminated by the light of absolute
knowledge’. [30]
It follows from this that the estranged forms taken on by spirit when it posits itself as
objective remain as they are. The novelty consists solely in the reconciliation
philosophy affords, whereby spirit can feel at home, notwithstanding this estrangement,
because, in it, it is in its own other. Indeed, the alienation of self-consciousness is given
a positive significance above in that it posits the self as objective. Accordingly Hegel
stresses, in another crucial passage, that there is no need to be afraid of such
objectification.
‘Spirit’, he recalls, ‘has shown itself to us to be neither merely the withdrawal of self-
consciousness into its pure inwardness, nor the mere submergence of self-
consciousness into substance.’ Using the language of ‘subject’ and ‘substance’, he
explains that ‘spirit is this movement of the self which empties {entäussert} itself of itself
and sinks into its substance, and also, as subject, has gone our of that substance into
itself. He goes on: ‘that first reflection out of immediacy is the subject’s differentiation of
itself from its substance . . . the withdrawal into itself and the becoming of the pure “I” . .
.’. But – and this is the important point – ‘neither has the “I” to cling to itself in
the form of self-consciousness as against the form of substantiality and objectivity, as if it
were afraid of its alienation; the power of spirit lies rather in remaining the self-same
spirit in its alienation and, as that which is both in itself and for itself, in making its being-
for-itself no less merely a moment than its in itself . . .’. [31]
Thus, because spirit must posit itself in objective form, the objectivity consciousness
opposes to itself cannot merely be subsumed away through the inwardizing movement
of recollection; its problematical character must be resolved by comprehending it in all
the immediacy of its otherness at the same time. Therefore, one must understand the
phenomenological odyssey not merely as spirit’s struggle to negate an alien objectivity,
but also as the story of its gaining an objective existence, a story understood as such
by spirit itself only in recollection when it achieves absolute knowledge, but a story
whose meaning is understood from the outset by Hegel and ourselves who ‘look
on’ [32] this development precisely from that standpoint. In the middle part of
the Phenomenology masses of concrete historical material, including actual estranged
spheres of existence (religion, the state, bourgeois life and so forth) are brought within
this framework.
The objective shapes given in consciousness as it moves towards self-consciousness
and absolute knowing are to be understood as shapes of the existence of spirit itself
and hence its positive achievement. This explains why Hegel says that alienation has a
positive meaning for self-consciousness in so far as it posits itself as objective, and
becomes being-for-itself. It explains also why, whether one looks at
the Phenomenology or the Encyclopaedia, one finds that Objective Spirit always occupies
a higher place than Subjective Spirit. In both these systematic works the creation of a
wealth of spiritual forms, for example, the state, religion and so on, is seen as a
positive achievement of spirit as well as entangling it in estrangement. The ‘sublation’
of estrangement consists in stripping the spiritual forms of their ‘external’ character, not
abolishing them outright, that is to say, in recognizing them precisely as spirit’s own
work.
Spirit in the form of substance gives us the phase of consciousness as consciousness
of an objectivity standing over against it; consciousness turned inwards achieves
certainty of self and becomes subject; then in the final dialectic the self recognizes that
its negative attitude towards objectivity must in turn be superseded through a
recognition of the necessity of this self-alienation. In this way we have a positing through
negating. Hegel explains this movement thus: if ‘self-consciousness enriches itself
till . . . it has absorbed into itself the entire structure of the essentialities of substance’,
then ‘since this negative attitude to objectivity is just as much positive, it is a positing’. It
has both ‘produced them out of itself’, and in so doing ‘has at the same time restored
them for consciousness’. He goes on to explain that ‘in the concept that knows itself as
concept, the moments thus appear earlier than the whole in its fulfilment; the
movement of these moments is the process by which the whole comes to be’. In
consciousness, by contrast, ‘the whole, though uncomprehended, is prior to the
moments’. [33]
In his Preface Hegel explains that the exposition will show that truth is not only
‘substance’ – something ‘out there’ to appropriated by the consciousness of the subject
– but it is equally ‘subject’ – the activity that produces the true. There follows the famous
passage:
Further, the living substance is being which is in truth subject, or, which is the
same, is in truth actual only in so far as it is the movement of positing itself, or
the mediation of its becoming-other with its own self. As subject it is pure
simple negativity and thus the bifurcation of the simple; it is the doubling which
sets up opposition, and then again the negation of. . . opposition. Only this self-
restoring sameness, or this reflection in otherness within itself – not
an original or immediate unity as such – is the true. It is the process of its own
becoming, the circle that presupposes its end as its goal, having its end also for
its beginning and only by being worked out to its end, is it actual. [34]
‘Thus’, he goes on, ‘the life of God and divine cognition can be spoken of as love
playing with itself,’ But he immediately qualifies this edifying notion: if, in itself, the
divine life is one of untroubled unity with itself in itself, ‘for which otherness and
estrangement and the overcoming of estrangement are not serious matters’, this
leaves out the fact that its actualization in developed form is necessarily marked by ‘the
seriousness, the suffering, the patience and the labour of the negative’. [35]
In the last chapter he explains that spirit needs time to do this: hence ‘the movement of
carrying forward the form of its self-knowledge is the labour which it accomplishes as
actual history’. [36] The conclusion of the Phenomenology is that ‘comprehended history’
is the realm of absolute spirit, ‘the actuality, truth, and certainty of its throne, without
which it would be lifeless and alone’. [37]
If ‘the immediate existence of spirit, consciousness, contains the two moments of
knowing and the objectivity negative to knowing’, [38] in the absolute these are united
and their difference is mediated in the act of ‘pure negativity’. [39] ‘Our own act here’,
says Hegel, ‘has been simply to gather together the separate moments . . .’[40]
However, there may be more to it than this, as far as Hegel’s ‘own act’ is concerned.
For in the final chapter of the Phenomenology there is a merger between the standpoint
that ‘looks on’ and grasps the nature of the necessity in the transitions as it is known ‘to
us’ (rather than in the experience of consciousness itself at that stage) and the
standpoint of self-consciousness itself at each stage. This may well mean that Hegel’s
‘absolute’ philosophy represents an arrogant claim, not merely to the discovery of truth,
but to the instantiation of it. From Feuerbach [41] onwards critics have charged Hegel
with representing his philosophy as ‘the absolute’. A recent example is Peter Singer
who says that, in Hegel’s view, spirit comes to its final resting-place when he, Hegel,
understands the nature of reality. The momentous conclusion follows that ‘the closing
pages of the Phenomenology . . . are no mere description of the culmination of all human
history: they are that culmination’. [42]
This point, among others, will be taken up in the consideration of Marx’s critique in the
following chapters.
Summary
Hegel’s Phenomenology undertakes an exposition of how knowledge makes its
appearance, through a sequence of determinate negations. Absolute knowing knows
that what appears as its object is itself. But this requires spirit to know itself through
producing itself as alienation (Entäusserung) and then sublating this alienation, such that
‘it is at home with itself in its otherness as such’. Thus the truth of spirit is actual when
posited through the negation of the negation. This labour of the negative is at work in
the movement of history.
The great thing in Hegel’s Phenomenology and its final result – the dialectic of
negativity as the moving and producing principle – is that Hegel conceives the
self-creation of man as a process, objectification {Vergegenständlichung} as loss
of object {Entgegenständlichung}, as alienation {Entëusserung} and as sublation of
this alienation; that he therefore grasps the nature of labour and conceives
objective man as the result of his own labour. [5]
As far as the ‘producing principle’ is concerned, Marx is impressed by the dialectic of
spirit’s actualization of itself through positing itself in the form of objectivity as the
negative of itself and then negating this negation. Marx sees in this the philosophical
reflection of the material process whereby man produces himself through his own
labour. Marx amplifies his ‘humanist’ reading of Hegel as follows: ‘the real active relation
of man to himself’, he says, ‘is only possible if he really employs all his species powers –
which again is only possible through the cooperation of mankind and as a result of
history – and treats them as objects, which is at first only possible in the form of
estrangement’. [6]
Be it noted that both in Hegel and Marx ‘the producing principle’ involves the moment
of estrangement and its overcoming. Nevertheless, in Hegel, a heavy price is exacted
by the mystified form of his insight. Thus Marx immediately embarks on a multi-layered
critique of the Phenomenology even at its strongest points, namely, the ‘producing
principle’ and the acknowledgement of estrangement. His most detailed discussion is
on the closing chapter, ‘Absolute Knowledge’, which, he says, ‘contains the
concentrated essence of the Phenomenology, its relation to the dialectic, and
Hegel’s consciousness of both and their interrelations’. [7] (We shall follow Marx in this,
reserving discussion of other parts of the Phenomenology to the next chapter.)
Marx’s notes, being unrevised, are thus not organized in any way. Here we shall
distinguish four threads in his criticism and discuss them separately before relating
them. To give the reader advance notice, these are the four mistakes Marx finds in
Hegel: (a) the reduction of man to self-consciousness and activity to spiritual labour; (b)
the identification of objectivity with estrangement; (c) the claim that spirit (read ‘man’) is
‘at home in its other-being as such’; (d) the failure to go beyond ‘negation of the
negation’ to the self-sustaining positive.
Labour: Material and Spiritual
Marx praises Hegel for grasping the nature of labour, and, more particularly, for
conceiving man as the result of his own labour. As we have seen, Marx can say this
sort of thing only by reading into the labour of spirit, at work in the Phenomenology, the
work of man, that is to say, primarily material labour. We must not, therefore, take
Marx’s praise too literally. The activity of Hegel’s ‘spirit’ is, naturally, primarily ideal in
character, because it is the activity of consciousness and self-
consciousness. [8] Consequently, Marx immediately adds to the above-mentioned
praise of Hegel, for grasping the nature of labour, the qualification that he knows only
‘abstract spiritual labour’. [9] In fact, Hegel reverses the terms of the real relations
within his philosophical reflection on the problem of estrangement. Consistently with his
idealism, he identifies the human essence with self-consciousness, according to Marx,
and this has the result that, in his work, ‘all estrangement of human nature is
therefore nothing but estrangement of self-consciousness‘. Furthermore, this means that the
estrangement of self-consciousness ‘is not regarded as the expression . . .
of real estrangement’, but, instead, actual estrangement ‘is in its innermost essence –
which philosophy first brings to light – nothing more than the appearance of the
estrangement of . . . self-consciousness’. Marx finds it entirely appropriate that the
science comprehending this is thus called ‘phenomenology’. [10]
Despite the wealth of content in the Phenomenology everything is treated under the form
of consciousness or self-consciousness. This makes a big difference to the manner in
which estrangement is to be superseded. To begin with, Marx points out that a natural
being endowed with material powers works upon real objects and in its alienation
produces in this process a real world of estrangement; but, he goes on, ‘ a self-
consciousness, through its alienation, can posit only ‘thinghood’ {“die Dingheit“}, [11] an
abstraction, a mere postulate of self-consciousness. We saw that in his final chapter
Hegel declares that ‘it is the alienation of self-consciousness that posits thinghood’, but
then it ‘takes it back into itself’. It is clear ‘thinghood’ has no independent being and as
a postulate of self-consciousness is at the mercy of a retraction by the self-
consciousness that postulated it. Hence a change in attitude abolishes the
consciousness of estrangement because estrangement itself is understood only as an
attitude to the world adopted by consciousness. This ‘reconciliation’, as Hegel calls it,
leaves things as they are. As Lukács points out, this reverse movement of ‘Er-Innerung‘,
this supersession of ‘externalization’, is ‘not an internal movement of objective reality at
all, but merely something he has invented in order to bring his philosophy to a
conclusion’. [12] This means that no radical critique of the real world of estrangement
can be undertaken, much less a practical objective transformation.
Marx complains that when ‘Hegel conceives wealth, the power of the state, etc., as
entities estranged from the being of man, he conceives them only in their thought form’;
with the consequence that ‘the appropriation of man’s objectified and estranged
essential powers is therefore only an appropriation which takes place in
consciousness, in pure thought, i.e. in abstraction’. That overcoming estrangement is
achieved, for Hegel, by a change in consciousness alone is at the root of his
conservatism, Marx believes. He sums up the matter thus:
For Hegel the human essence is self-consciousness and Marx argues that, since
something comes to exist for consciousness in so far as it knows that something, its
only objective relationship is knowing. What absolute knowing realizes is that its ‘other’
is posited as such only through self-alienation, and is reappropriated through an
inwardizing movement of thought, which is forced, in so far as consciousness
must have an object, to preserve estrangement as a moment of consciousness (and, of
course, the consciousness of estrangement is all this problematic knows!). In the middle
part of the Phenomenology masses of concrete historical material, involving actual
estranged spheres of existence, are brought within this framework, and the practical
problems are provided with a pseudo-solution when philosophy reconciles itself, both
with objectivity in general and with historically created objective estrangement in
particular. Hegel appears as a radical critic of all objectivity, charging it with being
estrangement; but he ends by accepting uncritically both the genuine and reified
objectivities, in so far as their character as objective is granted the necessity of a
moment in spirit’s self-positing movement in its other as its estranged self. To the
extent that Hegel accepts the necessity for such alienating objectification he becomes
uncritical of the sphere of estrangement brought to life within spirit’s self-actualization.
In this way the positive achievement of history hidden within estrangement is equated
with that estrangement itself. Objectification and alienation are one. Marx speaks,
therefore, of ‘Hegel’s false positivism’ or ‘his merely apparent criticism’.[34]
Hegel’s greatness as a philosopher is that he is sensitive to the complexities of the
system of alienation in which we live, and, although in a mystified way, he understands
that it must be the result of the manner in which human self-objectification has been
actualized. His misfortune is that he is unable to see the possibility of a historical
reappropriation by man of his alienated powers. Instead, the historically conditioned
problem is interpreted by him as a general ontological problem of existence. Hence, to
posit the possibility of a solution the fatal option of idealism was taken up, whereby the
world of real objective estrangement was grasped only from the point of view of the
consciousness of it as other than consciousness, that is objectivity, and thus a solution
could be posited at that level in so far as reason could penetrate objectivity.
Historically, Hegel cannot see beyond the horizon of capitalism. What happens,
therefore, is that real alienation is conceptualized in such a thinned-out manner that
this ‘Entäusserung‘ can be overcome in the recollection of its origins. He is too realistic
to opt for utopianism in his social theory. But, in the words of Lukács, ‘the idealist
dialectic transforms the entire history of man into a great philosophical utopia; into the
philosophical dream that “alienation” can be overcome in the subject, that substance
can be transformed into subject’. [35]
Hegel’s tragedy is that, though objectification and alienation are conceptually distinct,
and are distinguished brilliantly by Marx, Hegel cannot grasp this possibility, for it
depends upon a historical potential beyond the limits of his bourgeois standpoint. Thus
he collapses them together so that the necessity of spirit’s odyssey of self-
objectification becomes at the same time its self-estrangement, and scientific criticism
is powerless to do more than point to the content hidden behind the forms of
estrangement and pass off this insight as their sublation. But as Marx mercilessly
demonstrates, this still leaves real objective estrangement intact.
In presenting the activity of spirit as pure negativity Hegel abstracts from all determinate
content. Real alienation is subsumed in the logical category of ‘the negative’ and its
supersession is naturally another logical operation, ‘the negation of the negation’. Marx
complains that ‘the inexhaustible, vital, sensuous, concrete activity of self-
objectification is therefore reduced to its mere abstraction, absolute negativity, an
abstraction which is then given permanent form as such and conceived as . . . activity
itself’. [39]
Furthermore, the incorporation of the problematic of estrangement within the
conceptual framework of absolute negativity means that Hegel’s critical apparatus is
unable to identify the specific historical origins of alienation, or the concrete historical
conditions of its supersession. In effect, he endorses the moment of estrangement as
an ontological necessity, instead of grasping it as brought about through specific
material processes in the history of mankind’s emergence, and as subject to radical
abolition, through a revolution which is the outcome of changed historical conditions.
So, while Marx allows that ‘in grasping the positive significance of the negation which
has reference to itself’ [40] Hegel grasps self-alienation as self-objectification, at the
same time, ‘since this negation of the negation is itself still trapped in estrangement,
what this amounts to is a fibre to move beyond the final stage, the stage of self-
reference in alienation’. [41] Spirit knows itself in its negation, but posits itself only in
the negation of the negation. Thus, this negation of the negation does not give rise, in a
practical transformation of the entire structure of labour, to the ‘self-sustaining positive’.
As we have seen, for Marx communism is the positive supersession of private property
as human self-estrangement. We have seen also that he characterizes communist
revolution (because of its character as the negation of the negation, as the
reappropriation of the human essence through the negation of private property) ‘as
being not yet the true, self-originating position but rather a position originating from
private property’. [42] He concludes that ‘only when we have superseded this mediation
– which, however, is a necessary precondition – will positive humanism, positively
originating in itself, come into being’. [43]
This is the crucial difference between Hegel and Marx: Hegel stays within the circle of
circles of his absolute, while Marx wants to open out a new historical perspective
subsequent to the supersession of alienation. Marx sums up the relation of Hegel’s
philosophy to real history in two propositions: (a) ‘Hegel has merely discovered
the abstract, logical, speculative expression of the movement of history’; (b) ‘This
movement of history is not yet the real history of man . . . it is simply the process of his
creation, the history of his emergence‘. [44]
The first point is that the abstract expression of the process of man’s creation of
himself, through labour and its alienation, is given in Hegel under the concept of
‘absolute negativity’, an abstract speculative version of activity which is empty of
content and can be supplied with any content accordingly. The other point is that in the
cycle of negation, and the negation of the negation, Hegel states as an absolute what
is in real history relative only to the process of emergence which culminates in
communist revolution; but ‘communism as such is not the goal of human development’.
The point here is that, though Hegel’s treatment of positing through double negation is
abstract, this abstraction is taken from real history, namely the genesis of objective
powers of production in the shape of estrangement from the immediate producer, and
the potential to reappropriate this estranged essence. But in Hegel, precisely because
of his ambivalent attitude to objectivity in the dialectic of spirit, the abstract treatment is
subject to the further limitation that self-recognition in estrangement is preserved as a
moment within the absolute. A radical transcendence, a positive supersession, of
estranged objectivity cannot be thought.
Conclusion
For an idealist to take offence at objective reality and to deny its independence would
not in itself have any interest. What strikes Marx as very interesting, and serves as the
point of departure for both his praise and his criticism of Hegel, is that Hegel’s definition
of alienation has a positive connotation just in so far as it posits objectivity. Hegel
clearly distinguishes his position from that of subjective idealism in so far as the
moment of objectivity is granted its necessity; consciousness must be conscious
of something. At the same time, the identification of objectivity with estrangement poses
a problem. Again, unlike Stoicism for example, Hegel’s philosophy does not attempt a
solution through a retreat into the inner life and a denial of the effectivity of objective
reality in the subject’s freedom of thought. Rather, Hegel insists that estrangement can
be overcome precisely when self-consciousness appropriates objectivity and finds itself
at home in this its other. This is achieved when spirit understands that the object is
nothing but its own self-alienation.
Marx’s objections to Hegel’s idealist construction he sums up for himself at the
beginning of a notebook started in November 1844 (the 1844 Manuscripts themselves
are dated April to August). He makes the following four points. First: Hegel puts ‘self-
consciousness instead of man’; second: ‘the differences of things are unimportant,
because substance is conceived as self-distinction’, although it is granted that Hegel
makes distinctions that ‘grasp the vital point’; third: ‘abolition of estrangement is identified
with abolition of objectivity‘; fourth: supersession of ‘the object as object of
consciousness is identified with real abolition’ of alienation. [45]
These points are connected in the following way: given that Hegel expounds the
phenomenology of knowing subjectivity, all human relations are brought within this
framework; distinctions between man and the objects of his activity are hence rendered
as self-distinctions produced in the negating action of consciousness; objectivity equals
estrangement for such a subjectivity until the estrangement is overcome in the final
revolution of spirit’s progressive self-realization as a self-identical totality; this is
confused with real objective abolition because of the treatment of objects as objects of
consciousness simply.
It might be objected that to say nothing is really changed when absolute knowledge
recollects and recognizes the determinations of substance as spirit’s self-determination
fails to notice that this itself counts as a change given the framework of Hegel’s
speculative problematic. A new shape of consciousness is born.
The answer to this would be that, although earlier stages of self-development of spirit
are associated by Hegel with objective historical transformations, the development after
the culmination of this in the stage of ‘self-estranged spirit’ leaves the ground of
objective social relationships and moves in increasingly interiorized shapes of spirit: art,
revealed religion and philosophy. In this way philosophy reconciles itself with the forms
of social objectivity (the economy, the state) previously experienced as alienated. Marx
can legitimately complain that the underlying objective relationships remain
untransformed and preserve their effectivity in everyday experience. After all, the mass
of people cannot become Hegelian dialecticians! In any case, it is not that his
philosophy abolishes estrangement – it merely abstracts from it.
Appendix
For this third object I am thus an other actuality than it, that is, its object. To
assume a being which is not the object of another is thus to suppose
that no objective being exists. [53]
This is said by Rose to be a place where Marx’s thought does not rely on abstract
dichotomies, but ‘captures what Hegel means by actuality or spirit’. [54] The curious
thing about this is that Marx’s intention in the passage at issue is to criticize Hegel’s
absolute spirit. It forms part of a discussion of Hegel’s statement that it is the alienation
of self-consciousness which posits thinghood. At the same time, leaving aside Marx’s
intention, it could be argued that when he says that a being with no object would exist
‘solitary and alone’ (‘einsam und allein‘) [55] this reminds us immediately of the end of
the Phenomenology where comprehended history is the actuality of absolute spirit
without which it would be ‘lifeless and alone’ (‘das leblose Einsam‘ in Hegel’s curious
phrase). [56]
None the less, Marx’s point is that where the absolute is concerned, the relation to the
object is grasped by Hegel ultimately as not a really objective relation. Likewise, in
his Logic, Hegel defines being determinate as being for another; but again, in parallel
with the Phenomenology, the absolute idea absorbs all available content, it
‘contemplates its contents as its own self’. [57]
In truth, Marx’s argument at this point does bear traces of the presence of Fichte.
Thinghood (Dingheit) is said by Marx to be something posited by the Hegelian self-
consciousness. ‘And what is posited, instead of confirming itself, is but the confirmation
of the act of positing which for a moment fixes its energy as the product, and gives it
the semblance – but only for a moment – of an independent, real substance.’ Marx goes
on to argue against this that man ‘creates or posits objects’ because he is himself
objectively posited. ‘In the act of positing, therefore, this objective being does not fall
from his state of “pure activity” into a creating of the object; on the contrary,
his objective product only confirms his objective activity.’ [58] (This is equally so in
alienating objectification of course.)
Hegel, however, does not talk of ‘pure activity’ on the relevant pages, but this
phrase is very reminiscent of Fichte. [59] In Fichte’s Science of Knowledge (1794), it is
argued that ‘the pure activity of the self’ is presupposed by ‘objective activity’; it is a
‘condition of any activity that posits an object’ even though ‘pure activity originally
relates to no object at all’. [60] (Earlier, where ‘the act of positing’ is shown to entail ‘the
activity of alienation’, there is also a nice definition of the object created: ‘the activity of
alienation’, he says, ‘must have a passivity opposed to it; and such there is, indeed, in
that a portion of absolute totality is alienated; is posited as not posited.’ [61])
A related point brought forward by Rose is the role of alienation in
Hegel’s Phenomenology. She argues that the Phenomenology is not ‘the experience of
consciousness recapturing its alienated existence’ and that the experience of alienation
is restricted to a historically specific period, namely pre-bourgeois society. [62] As we
earlier said, there are two German terms used by Hegel that translate as ‘alienation’,
namely ‘Entäusserung‘ and ‘Entfremdung‘. There is no doubt at all that the former plays
the role attributed to it by Marx at the level of the upshot of the whole Phenomenology.
This may be confirmed by examining the last chapter. [63] Rose’s reference to a
historically specific period (i.e. the period covered in ‘Der sich Entfremdete Geist‘),
suggests that she may wish to restrict the reference to the term ‘Entfremdung‘, However,
Hegel’s Preface employs this expression in several places: for example, the experience
of consciousness is said to be a movement ‘in which the immediate, the
unexperienced, i.e. the abstract, whether it be of sensuous being, or only thought of as
simple becomes alienated {entfremdet} from itself and then returns to itself from this
alienation {Entfremdung} . . .’ [64]
1 The Holy Family: C.W.4, 192. As is well known, this theme recurs in Marx’s Afterward
to the 2nd edition of Capital.
2 Ibid; C.W.4. 139.
3 Werke Eb., 580; C.W.3, 339; E.W., 392.
4 Werke Eb., 573; C.W.3, 332; E.W., 385.
5 Werke Eb., 574; C.W.3, 332-3; E.W. 385-6.
6 Ibid.
7 Ibid.
8 The role of material labour as such in Hegel’s Phenomenology is discussed in chapter
7.
9 Whether this is fair to Hegel is discussed in the following chapters.
10 Werke Eb., 575-6; C.W.3, 334; E.W., 387.
11 Werke Eb., 577; C.W.3, 305; E.W., 389.
12 The Young Hegel, trans. Rodney Livingstone, London, 1975, p. 516.
13 Werke Eb., 573; C.W.3, 332; E.W., 384-5. For a brief discussion of Hegel’s later work,
see chapter 8.
14 Werke Eb., 553; C.W.3, 313; E.W., 365.
15 Werke 8, 673-4; Young Hegel, p. 551. Livingstone’s translation gives ‘alienation and
objectification in general’. This appears to be a mistake. For ‘objectification’ see the
discussion below. Note that although Lukács’ chapter heading refers to ‘Entäusserung’,
this point is made with reference to ‘Entfremdung’. For a Hegelian response to Lukács
see Errol Harris’s 1978 discussion ‘Marxist interpretations of Hegel’s Phenomenology of
Spirit‘, in Method and Speculation in Hegel’s Phenomenology ed. M. Westphal, Atlantic
Highlands, NJ, and Brighton, 1982.
16 Werke Eb., 580; C.W.3, 339; E.W., 392.
17 Werke Eb., 575; C.W.3, 333-4; E.W., 386-7.
18 Werke Eb., 580; C.W.3, 338; E.W., 391.
19 Werke Eb., 577-8; C.W.3, 336-7; E.W., 389-90.
20 See also the Appendix to this chapter.
21 Werke Eb., 572; C.W.3, 331; E.W., 384.
22 Young Hegel, pp. 551-2.
23 Werke 8, 671; Young Hegel, p. 549. Livingstone gives ‘alienation is sharply
distinguished from objective reality … ‘, allowing the impression that alienation might be
unreal.
24 For a defence of Hegel’s equation of objectification and alienation see Hyppolite’s
review of Lukács’ The Young Hegel in Jean Hyppolite, Studies on Marx and Hegel, trans. J.
O’Neill, New York, 1955, pp. 87 ff. For a counter-attack on Hyppolite, see István
Mészáros, Marx’s Theory of Alienation, London, 1970. pp. 244-5.
25 Besides The Young Hegel compare Lukács’ 1967 Preface to Volume 2 of his
collected works, pp. 24-6, reprinted in the English translation of History and Class-
Consciousness (1923), trans. Rodney Livingstone, London, 1971, pp. xxii-xxiv.
Livingstone translates both ‘Entfremdung‘ and ‘Entäusserung‘ here as ‘alienation’ – in
truth, Lukács seems to equate them.
26 Werke Eb., 573; C.W.3, 332; E.W., 385.
27 Joachim Ritter, in Hegel und die französische Revolution, Köln and Opladen, 1957,
says that Hegel’s treatment of the dichotomy of objectivity and subjectivity (the central
problem of Hegelian philosophy) is now treated, under the influence of Marx, as a
problem of estrangement. He adds (p. 61): ‘what is important . . . is that one does not
lose sight of the positive meaning of the dichotomy presupposed in estrangement’
(Hegel and the French Revolution, trans. RD. Winfield, Cambridge. Mass., 1982, p. 118).
Dupré says that in 1844 Marx, for the first time, realized on re-reading Hegel that
alienation is ‘highly positive’: it is ‘the forward march of self creation’ (The Philosophical
Foundations of Marxism, New York, 1966, p. 122). Nathan Rotenstreich says ‘Hegel set
a positive value on alienation … ‘ (Basic Principles of Marx’s Philosophy, Indianapolis,
1965, p. 156). Rotenstreich’s chapter ‘Concept of alienation and its metamorphoses’ is
interesting on the changing senses of ‘alienation’ in the history of thought.
Unfortunately, there is a slip on p.158 arising from a misreading of a critical gloss by
Marx on Hegel as Marx’s own view. Rotenstreich says: ‘Having asserted that to abolish
alienation is ipso facto to abolish the status of the object qua object, Marx said, in a
marginal comment, that this follows from Feuerbach’s line of reasoning. What
Feuerbach sought to abolish was obviously not . . . objectivity (Gegenständlichkeit) but
the fictitious status of pseudo-objects. Purporting to be based on Feuerbach’s
premises, Marx’s conclusion – at least with regard to the existence of products of
labour – is that the status of object qua object itself is to be abolished, since latent in its
very existence is not the enrichment but the distortion of the creative subject.’ The
reference is not clear but it is probably the following passage: ‘Abolition
of estrangement is identified with abolition of objectivity (an aspect evolved by
Feuerbach in particular)’ (.C.W.4, 665). This occurs under the head ‘Hegel’s
Construction of the Phenomenology.’. It is meant as a criticism of Hegel, first made by
Feuerbach, and endorsed by Marx. The present discussion shows how absurd it would
be to say that Marx wants to abolish the object ‘qua object’. (It would be equally absurd
in Feuerbach’s case). Marx wants to abolish the object qua alienated. Rotenstreich
rightly goes on to a discussion of Capital‘s characterization of the commodity form of
the produce of labour as a fetish; but this refers to its status, not as a natural object, but
as a value (which ‘has a purely social reality’ and ‘contains not an atom of matter’). It is
interesting that in his 1844 notes on James Mill Marx says that ‘value is
an alienated designation of [the product] itself, different from its immediate existence,
external to its specific nature, a merely relative mode of existence of this’ (C.W.3, 219).
28 Werke Eb., 583-4; C.W.3, 341-2; E.W., 395.
29 Werke Eb., 581; C.W.3, 339; E.W., 393.
30 For example: Jean-Paul Sartre, The Problem of Method (1960), London, 1963, p. 13;
Mészáros, Theory of Alienation, p. 84.
31 ‘The foundation of historical materialism’ (1932), in Herbert Marcuse, From Luther to
Popper, essays trans. Joris de Bres, London, 1983, pp. 13, 45.
32 ‘Vergegenständlichung’ is absent from J. Gauvin’s Wortindex zu Hegels Phänomenologie
des Geistes, Bonn, 1977. (P. Slater drew my attention to this point.) It is tear that J.B.
Baillie’s translation (Phenomenology of Mind, London, 1949) uses the term, once (p. 86)
in the Preface (but he is excessively free in his translation at that point) and again (p.
790) at the beginning of the last chapter (but this is a mistake for ‘objectivity’
– Gegenständlichkeit).
33 Werke Eb., 572; C.W.3, 331; E.W., 384.
34 Werke Eb., 581; C.W.3, 339; E.W., 393.
35 Werke 8, 415-16; Young Hegel, p. 333.
36 Werke Eb., 574; C.W.3, 333; E.W., 386.
37 Werke Eb., 513; C.W.3, 273; E.W., 325.
38 Werke Eb., 584; C.W.3, 342; E.W., 396.
39 Ibid.
40 Werke Eb., 583; C.W.3, 342; E.W., 395.
41 Werke Eb., 586; C.W.3, 344; E.W., 398.
42 Werke Eb., 553; C.W.3, 313; E.W., 365.
43 Werke Eb., 583; C.W.3, 341-2; E.W., 395.
44 Werke Eb., 570; C.W.3, 329; E.W., 382.
45 C.W.4, 665.
46 e.g. J. Maguire, Marx’s Paris Writings: an Analysis, Dublin, 1972, thinks Marx’s
account of Hegel less than fair.
47 Rose G., Hegel Contra Sociology, London, 1981, p. 150.
48 Ibid., p. 214.
49 The Holy Family: C.W.4, 139.
50 Richard Norman, Hegel’s Phenomenology, Brighton, 1976, pp. 112-15. Hegel’s
admission is quoted in J.N. Findlay’s Foreword to Hegel’s Logic, trans. W. Wallace, 3rd
ed., 1975, p. vii.
51 Rosen M., Hegel’s Dialectic and its Criticism, Cambridge. 1982. p. 81.
52 Werke Eb., 584; C.W.3, 342.
53 Werke Eb., 578; C.W.3, 337; E.W., 390.
54 Rose, Hegel Contra Sociology, p. 215.
55 Werke Eb., 571; C.W.3, 337.
56G.W.9, 765.
57 Hegel’s Logic, para. 237. See Henri Lefebvre, Dialectical Materialism (1939), London,
1968, pp. 48-58.
58Werke Eb., 577; C.W.3, 336.
59 For a vigorous, assertion of Hegel’s difference from Fichte, and the claim that he is
not ‘idealist’ but ‘realist’, see Alexandre Kojève, Introduction to the Reading of
Hegel (1947), ed. A. Bloom, trans. J.H. Nicols, New York, 1969, pp. 150-4.
60 J.G. Fichte, Science of Knowledge (1794), trans. P. Heath and J. Lachs, Cambridge,
1982, pp. 231-2.
61 Ibid., p. 154.
62 Rose, Hegel Contra Sociology, pp. 152, 219.
63 For example: Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford, 1977, paras. 788,
803-8.
64 Ibid., para. 36.
Introduction
The fact that
Marx hangs his criticism of Hegel largely on a passage from the last
chapter of the Phenomenology warrants the inference that the main influence
of the work on him is its dialectic in general. However, there is no
doubt that Marx could not have been so interested in it if he had only
acquainted himself with the rather abstract formulations in the
conclusion and the Preface. Clearly the way Hegel works through historical
material in the concrete to flesh out the dialectic of consciousness and
self-consciousness must have impressed Marx.
Accordingly, this chapter is
devoted to a discussion of some of the materials concerned. In
relation to this, there is first a myth to be refuted. [1]
Clearly Marx
would agree with two points here: that human work has a universal
character, and that bourgeois individualism needs to be transcended. Less clear
is why Hegel’s discussion is objectionable. Recall the following
passage from Marx’s critique:
The rich, living, sensuous, concrete activity
of self-objectification is therefore reduced to its mere abstraction, absolute
negativity – an abstraction which is again fixed as such and
considered as an independent activity – as sheer activity. Because this
so-called negativity is nothing but the abstract, empty form of that
real living act, its content can in consequence be merely a formal content
produced by abstraction from all content. [39]
This seems very
pertinent to the idea of absolute negativity Hegel evolves at the beginning
of this discussion. Instead of the universality of activity being
celebrated in the wealth of its content, the content vanishes in the purity
of absolute negativity. But did not Hegel himself find wanting such
abstract universality? Yes and no. The concept of ‘absolute negativity’
represents a real gain in the constitution of spirit, as is clear from its
retention in the overview given in Hegel’s ‘Preface’. The problem at
this stage of the phenomenological dialectic is that it is constituted
in
opposition to the real life of the individual subject. There is an
‘antithesis of doing and being’. The solution arrived at is to make the universal itself the
real individual, which makes itself identical with
the entire content. The emphasis here, as in the rest of the story,
prioritizes logical forms over real content. [40]
The third section mentioned by Marx, ‘the struggle of noble and base consciousness’,
is part of
an important stage of spirit’s development, namely, ‘self-estranged
spirit’ (‘Der sich entfremdete Geist‘). The historical allusions become
particularly clear here; the material draws on the world of eighteenth
century France up to, and including, the revolution. We are not therefore
dealing with absolute spirit and the total process of its recovery of
itself from alienation, but with a finite stage of its development. It
deals with the individual and his alienation from society. We are at a
richer, more concrete, level of development of consciousness than in the
previous stages considered, in that the self knows the substance of
social life as its spiritual essence, but society also faces the
individual as an ‘alien reality . . . in which it does not recognize itself’.
The individual and its world are estranged from each other. Even though
the individual knows that it belongs in that world and must find its
place there, to begin with it finds social institutions face it simply as
objectively given realities to which it must conform. It achieves
something within its world only in alienating itself from itself, in
leaving behind its natural self and moulding itself to these objective
requirements. This process of mediating the extremes (nature and society) is
‘Bildung‘ – perhaps here to be translated as ‘acculturation’. Hegel
says: ‘it is therefore through culture [Bildung] that the individual
acquires standing and actuality’. In observing this development, says Hegel,
we will see ‘the estrangement estrange itself and, through this,
return into its concept’. [41]
This second alienation needs explaining.
The idea is symptomatic of Hegel’s dialectic in general. Given a totality
within which two moments stand in an antagonistic opposition, this can
exist only through a mediating movement. If the estranged elements are
not transformed and brought into harmony, the mediating movement
itself must appear as an alienation. The original estrangement is sublated
in a second alienation. Earlier we discussed the case of labour: given
the estrangement of labour-power from its object, any reunification
under the aegis of wage-labour is alienating in itself and reproduces the
whole system of estrangement. Here, in Hegel, the self alienates itself
from its original nature in cultivating social skills and acquiring
power in society. In this way the original subject-object split is
overcome, but within estrangement.
Rousseau’s critique of his times rested in
just such a diagnosis, namely that natural and civilized man were at
odds. Even in his positive prescription we find a second alienation
solution. Lacking the political virtues of the ever pre-given unity of the
Greek polis, and thus beginning with ‘natural’ individuals, unity is to
be established politically in ‘the general will’ through ‘the total
alienation of each associate … to the whole community’. Moreover,
Rousseau stresses the fact that this involves taking away man’s ‘natural
resources’ and providing ‘new ones alien to him, and incapable of being
made use of without the help of other men’. [42]
Returning now to Hegel,
the social order is presented as structured in terms of state power
and wealth. It is in considering the possible attitudes of
self-consciousness to these that the ‘noble’, and ‘base’, consciousness appear. The
consciousness that takes a positive attitude towards each sphere is
called noble. It respects public authority and is grateful for its
enjoyment of wealth. The consciousness that adopts a negative relation to them
is base. It regards sovereign power as a fetter and it obeys only with
a secret malice, always on the point of revolt. It loves wealth but,
conscious of its temporary and contingent enjoyment, suspects it at the
same time. There are fairly obvious allusions in Hegel’s discussion to
the class struggles between the nobility and the third estate.
In a way
similar to the master-servant dialectic, Hegel then develops each side
into its other. The noble consciousness comes to see in the state and
wealth the power of an alien reality on which it depends. The base
consciousness learns to affirm itself even in its negative relation to
them.
Summary
As
far as the separate sections of the Phenomenology are concerned, Marx
does not mention, and does not draw upon, the dialectic of ‘lordship and
bondage’. Of the three sections he mentions as evidence for ‘critical
elements’ in Hegel’s work, the most influential is ‘the struggle of
noble and base consciousness’. Here Hegel treats of the estrangement of
the individual from social institutions such as state power and wealth.
As always, Marx finds in Hegel that the idealist exposition of such
elements of criticism results in their presentation still in estranged
form.
Introduction
The extraordinary complexity of Marx’s verdict on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit is
evident if we take three statements from the same (crucial) page.
1. Hegel grasps the nature of labour and conceives man as the result of his own labour.
2. Hegel’s standpoint is that of political economy, namely labour (= alienation) as the
essence of man.
3. Hegel knows only abstract mental labour.
It seems almost impossible at first sight to make these consistent. It seems equally
impossible to take even one of them at face value. If (3) is true, how can (1) and (2) be
true? But how can (3) be fair when we know about the labour of the servant and the
‘honest consciousness’? As for political economy, Hegel never mentions it in
the Phenomenology! (Somewhat bewildered, the editors of Marx’s works cite in a
footnote [1] two other works of Hegel – one of them unknown to Marx! I deal with both
below.)
The exhaustive exposition of Marx’s arguments so far has provided the necessary
basis for endorsing all three points, properly interpreted. This interpretation requires
discussion of the method at work in Marx’s criticism of Hegel. The main difficulty in
understanding Marx’s critique is that he does not compare like with like. His own
interest is in material production, and more especially the material labour of the wage-
worker with its inherent alienation. But what he compares with his own discoveries
is not what Hegel says about such labour, but Hegel’s alternative ‘producing principle’,
the negating action of consciousness and self-consciousness. That this must give rise
to problems becomes obvious when we recall that for Marx the contradictions of
consciousness are to be subsumed under the practical ones, whereas for Hegel
material labour is merely one sphere in which spirit is at work.
The procedure adopted by Marx is to evaluate Hegel by reading spiritual activity as
material. This is how he can praise Hegel for grasping man as his own product, and
equally how he can blame Hegel for confusing productive activity with alienating
activity. Hence, in Hegel, alienating activity is taken as the essence, just as the
standpoint of political economy is that of (wage-)labour. As we noted earlier, Hegel’s
crucial misidentification is not the simple-minded castigation of objectification as
alienating, but the more subtle endorsement of alienation because it is taken to be the
only possible form of objectification. In fine, the parallelism is not one of content but of
a homology of conceptual structure in the speculative philosophy of Hegel and the
ideological presuppositions of political economy. This means that Marx can criticize
both on the same grounds.
Once we grasp the character of Marx’s procedure in his Hegel critique, two things
follow: first, that what he says about Hegel’s equation of objectification and alienation
has nothing to do with anything Hegel says about material labour; second, that his
failure to deal with what Hegel says about material labour, and more especially his
claim that Hegel knows only abstract mental labour, might amount to an injustice to
Hegel. Certainly, if anyone were to claim that Hegel thought material labour necessarily
alienating, or even that he knew nothing of material labour at all, Hegelians could come
flying with contrary quotations from nearly all his works. We have already mentioned
the positive role labour is given in the master-servant dialectic and in the work
occupying the ‘honest consciousness’. Even in the chapter on ‘self-estranged spirit’,
individual labour is seen as socially constitutive in so far as each ‘in working for
himself . . . is at the same time working for all and all are working for him’. [2] Indeed it
would be closer to the truth to say that Hegel has a claim precedent to that of Marx to
be the first to found social theory on material labour. It even has an important place in
his Science of Logic. It appears in its greatest prominence in the Jena lectures of the
early 1800s and then gradually diminishes in its significance in Hegel’s thought. Yet as
late as 1821 Hegel speaks almost casually, in the Philosophy of Right, of ‘the moment of
liberation intrinsic to work’, as if this were obvious. [3]
Nevertheless, Marx is ultimately in the right, because the interest Hegel takes in labour
is to show that it exhibits in actuality moments of consciousness, determinations of the
will, or even categories of logic. In spite of the fact that he has more acute things to say
about labour than any other pre-Marxist philosopher, Hegel is, after all, an idealist.
Instead of objective relations of production, the ultimate reality is absolute spirit in
communion with itself. For Hegel, material labour has an important role in the sphere of
objective spirit but this is in turn incorporated within absolute spirit. If we are to
compare Marx with Hegel in terms of content then it is instructive to compare what
Marx says about wage-labour with what Hegel says. This is the objective of the present
chapter. Here the Phenomenology is not of much help. The treatment of ‘wealth’ in the
‘self-estranged spirit’ section does not specify the relations of production involved; and
if it did they would hardly be those of modern industry, given the historical background
to it.
In truth, the young Hegel was a radical critic of modern industrial production. This is
especially so in his writings from the Jena period (1801-6). In a manuscript known
as Hegel’s First Philosophy of Spirit (1803-4) Hegel points out that the subjugation of
nature in modem industry increases the individual’s dependence on outside forces
because the division of labour ties the individual to a particular task (he cites Smith’s
account of a pin factory); that the labour becomes deadening mechanical work; and
that ‘the coherence of the singular kind of labour with the whole infinite mass of needs
is quite unsurveyable . . . so that some far-off operation often suddenly cuts off the
labour of a whole class of men . . . and makes it superfluous and useless’. Hegel adds
that ‘need and labour’, elevated into the universality of money, create a ‘monstrous
system’ of mutual dependence in society, ‘a self-propelling life of the dead, ebbing and
flowing blindly’, which ‘requires . . . taming like a wild beast’. [4]
Such striking passages were unknown to Marx because they remained unpublished for
many years (a curious parallel to Marx’s own 1844 Manuscripts!)
The fact that property is realized and actualized only in use floats before the
minds of those who look on property as derelict and ownerless if it is not being
put to any use, and who excuse its unlawful occupancy on the ground that it has
not been used by its owner. But the owner’s will, in accordance with which the
thing is his, is the primary substantive basis of property; use is a further
modification of property, secondary to that universal basis, and is only its
manifestation and particular mode. [8]
In the relation of use the will is still debased by its involvement with the particularity of
the things and their use-value. Hence the will must be asserted absolutely and not in
connection with the particularity of its objects. This is realized in alienation. In the
dialectic of the will’s relation to the thing as property, the moment of alienation, rather
than posing any problem for Hegel, is seen as the most complete actualization of
ownership. It is in distinguishing myself as an owner rigorously from any particular
content to this proprietorship that I become a real proprietor! Possession and use are
limited, finite relations of the will to property in which its movement runs aground; but
through treating things merely as exchangeable objects, in the endless cycle of
acquisition and alienation, the will is reflected into its own self, without getting bogged
down in the natural features of the alienated objects; in this way the dialectic
progresses to contract where the will is dealing with its own other. ‘This relation of will
to will is the true and proper ground in which freedom is existent.’ [9]
Raymond Plant points our that this is a particular case of a general pattern in Hegel’s
thought. [10] An advance in self-consciousness (in this case the institution of private
property) requires the descent into particularity (in this case the things held as
property); yet institutions allowing this differentiation develop their own pattern of
integration of the particulars within an ideal totality. The form in which it is achieved in
this case is that, when the autonomous persons holding various objects as private
property align their wills through contractual arrangements, this means that ‘one
identical will can persist within the absolute difference between independent property
owners’ [11] Thereby universal freedom is made possible. In sum: the overriding
moment in the ‘mastery of things exhibited by free-will’ is that which is most removed
from their useful material character, namely the process of their alienation; this pushes
forward the actualization of the will to the form of contract whereby it achieves
recognition in another person. Only as a proprietor among proprietors am I free!
The other problem arises for Hegel’s apologetics. There is a contradiction implicit in his
view of personal powers as, on the one hand, inward property of a free being, and, on
the other hand, potentially alienable property held mediatedly as a ‘thing’. If this second
relation is realized in the alienation of labour, the will exists in contradiction with itself;
for, in Hegel’s general theory, the moment of alienation establishes the will as will
through its reflection from the thing back into itself; in the contractual relation with
another will, symmetrically mediated in the thing, it becomes identical with its other and
both equally achieve objective recognition; but, since the thing here itself embodies the
will, as we have seen, the alienating mediation presupposes
an asymmetrical relationship at the same time, in which one will bends to the other,
being thus ‘refracted’ rather than reflected, so to speak, in this alienation. [23] This is
nothing less than self-estrangement.
It is to be noted that this contradiction between the symmetry of the wage-contract
effected between autonomous, juridically equal, persons, and the asymmetry of the
employee’s relationship during the working day to his ‘hands’ (to employ the striking
vernacular of capital), finds its way into Hegel from reality. This reality disguises the
relations of personal dominance inherent in wage-slavery by reifying the personal
powers of the labourer so that they become a ‘factor of production’ like any other, to be
sold or hired on the market.
Conclusion
We have shown that Hegel thinks private property is necessary for human freedom and
that he manages to justify wage-slavery at the same time. What is it about his method
that allows this? The procedure is in fact stunningly simple. Instead of making the
historical judgement that in this society freedom means freedom of property, he makes
the philosophical judgement that the concept of freedom actualizes itself in the private
property system. Hegel says of his method that in philosophical science ‘the concept
develops out of itself, and in a purely immanent process engenders its determinations.
It does not advance ‘by the application of the universal to extraneous material . . .
culled from elsewhere’. [24] Not withstanding this assertion, Hegel does in fact ‘apply
universals’ to extraneous material, namely the existing property system.
What Hegel does in his philosophy is to find methodological resources that allow him to
pass off the facts about wage-labour as rational, as the actualization of freedom. With
regard to private property itself, its various determinations are organized in a hierarchy
that makes freedom appear less real in concrete work with, and use of, one’s property,
but more fully actualized in relations that abstract from the determinate content
involved. He does not attend to the evil consequences of the commodification of
labour. Whilst acknowledging that personal powers are not ‘external by nature’, Hegel
manages to assimilate them to property in external things (and hence properly
alienable within the limit specified and criticized above) through abstracting from the
specific difference involved in order to pass off the alienation of labour as free activity.
Summary
ln the 1844 Manuscripts Marx compares his theory of alienated labour with Hegel’s
negating action of spirit. Hence, as far as content is concerned, it might be said that he
does not compare like with like. In fact Hegel has a lot to say about material labour. It is
in the Philosophy of Right that his fullest account of wage-labour is found. He is uncritical
of it, reconciling it with property, and both with freedom.
1 C.W.3, 604-5.
2 Phenomenology of Spirit trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford, 1977, para. 494.
3 P.R., para. 194. On the background see Manfred Riedel, Between Tradition and
Revolution (1969), Cambridge, 1984, ch. 1.
4 Jenaer Systementwürfe I (1803-4): Gesammelte Werke Band 6, Hamburg, 1975, pp.
329-4; System of Ethical Life and First Philosophy of Spirit, trans. H.S. Harris, Albany, NY,
1979, pp. 248-9. For the background to Hegel’s thinking at this time see Bernard
Cullen, Hegel’s Social and Political Thought, Dublin, 1979, pp. 70-2.
5 Some of the argument below is condensed from my paper ‘Personality and the
dialectic of labour and property – Locke, Hegel, Marx’ in Radical Philosophy Reader, ed.
R. Edgley and R. Osborne, London, 1985.
6 P.R., para. 194.
7 ‘Person and property’ (1961), in Hegel and the French Revolution, trans. R.D. Winfield,
Cambridge, Mass., 1982, p. 135.
8 P.R., para. 59.
9 Ibid., para. 71.
10 Raymond Plant, Hegel: an Introduction, 2nd ed., Oxford, 1983, p. 155.
11 P.R., para. 74.
12 Ibid., para. 43.
13 Ibid., para. 57.
14 Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind, trans. W. Wallace, Oxford, 1971, para. 482.
15 P.R., para. 57.
16 C.1 (Penguin), 303, n.18.
17 P.R., para. 66.
18 Ibid., para. 57 & Addition.
19 Ibid., para. 43.
20 ‘Hegels eigenhändigen Randbemerkungen’ in Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts,
ed. J. Hoffmeister, Hamburg, 1955, p. 330.
21 P.R., para. 67. Ernest Mandel says that for Hegel material labour is alienating
‘because labour is, by its nature, the externalizing (Veräusserung) of a human capacity,
which means that man loses something that previously belonged to him’: The Formation
of the Economic Thought of Karl Marx, London, 1971, p. 155. Mandel seems to have in
mind this paragraph of the Philosophy of Right, which deals with
the Veräusserung (=alienation in the sense of sale) of human powers. If so, this is a
misrepresentation of it. It is clear that Hegel does not say labour ‘by its nature‘ as
‘externalizing’ is alienating; rather, he says complex social mediations achieve alienation
through setting labour in an (artificial) external relation to the person.
22 ‘If the whole and entire use of a thing were mine, while the abstract ownership was
supposed to be someone else’s, then the thing as mine would be penetrated through
and through by my will and at the same time there would remain in the thing something
impenetrable by me, namely the will, the empty will, of another’ (P.R., para, 62).
23 For Marx private property in general is an alien mediator estranging man from man.
What is shown here is that even if one accepts Hegel’s defence of private property it
implies that capitalist property relations are contradictory. It is utterly absurd, however,
to speak of ‘Hegel’s devastating critique of capitalist private property’ and to equate him
with Marx, as does David MacGregor, The Communist Ideal in Hegel and Marx, London,
1984, 189 et passim. Hegel’s intentions are manifestly apologetic. Even when he
recognizes that material to meet wants is barred to the needy because it consists of
external objects held as private property by others, and hence ‘its recalcitrance is
absolute’ (P.R., para. 195), he seems to assume at this point that the problem is
overcome through universal exchange. Later, when he concedes that modern society
in fact creates ‘a rabble of paupers’ (P.R. para. 244), he speculates on a solution
through imperialism (P.R., para. 246).
24 P.R., para. 31.
Introduction
The turning point in Marx’s intellectual development comes in 1844 with his discovery
of labour, an event documented in his manuscripts composed in Paris that year under
the impetus of his first encounter with political economy. In this chapter the process of
Marx’s intellectual formation is investigated with the aim of illuminating the importance
of this transition, and, in particular, the way in which he appropriates, and yet rejects,
Hegel, as we have already seen, and appropriates, and finally yet rejects, Hegel’s most
determined critic, Ludwig Feuerbach, as we shall see below.
A great deal of energy can be expended in assessing the relative influence of thinkers
such as Rousseau, Hegel, Feuerbach and the ‘Young Hegelians’ on the formation of
Marx’s thought. For example, Lukács declares roundly that, methodologically, ‘Marx
took over directly from Hegel’ rather than from the ‘Young Hegelians’, who had affinities
with Fichteanism. [1] Michael Löwy replies that ‘the philosophy of practice’ of Fichte,
Cieszowski and Hess, ‘is also a foundation stone for Marxism, a necessary step in the
evolution of the young Marx’. [2]
Certainly, Marx is quite properly identified at the time of his move to Paris as a member
of the so-called ‘Young Hegelian’ movement. None the less his relationship to it was
always nuanced. He was never a wholehearted disciple of any of its leading figures,
except, for a few months, Feuerbach. We cannot now accept as good Marxian coin the
aphorism: ‘There is no other road to truth and freedom but through the brook of fire
{Feuer-bach}’. It comes from an anonymous article of 1842. attributed to Marx by
Riazanov, but now thought not to be his work. [3] None the less, it expresses very well
Marx’s attitude to Feuerbach in 1844. At the same time, he was always ‘his own man’
when participating in the movement, even when heaping praise on Feuerbach.
This chapter will show that Marx, in his 1844 Manuscripts, advances decisively beyond
the standpoint of Feuerbach. Marx’s own genius first shows through in 1844 with his
category of labour, founded on the ontologically constitutive nature of productive
activity for social being. We have seen that in complex ways he relates this discovery
to Hegel’s speculative version of activity. It could be argued that Marx’s discovery of
the importance of material production is not unexpected in the context of the Young
Hegelians’ anthropological reading of Hegel. Indeed, as early as the 1830s the first of
them, D.F. Strauss, delivers himself of such vague formulations as that, in the course
of human history, humanity ‘ever more completely subjugates nature, both within and
around man, until it lies before him as the inert matter on which he exercises his active
power’. [4] The idea of production as a ‘species activity’ is further developed by
Feuerbach and by Hess. However, in the works of the ‘Young Hegelians’ such views
have no fundamental significance. They lie alongside remarks about other human
functions. Only with Marx does the social and historical theory of man as his own
product emerge – and here the important source is Hegel himself!
The strange thing, none the less, is that the manuscripts are penned explicitly under
the sign of Feuerbach. [5] The Preface declares that ‘it is only
with Feuerbach that positive, humanistic and naturalistic criticism begins’; his writings
‘contain a real theoretical revolution’. [6] If for no other reason, this solidarity with
Feuerbach makes it necessary to avoid reading too much ‘Marxism’ into the early
Marx. We know that as late as 1847 he was still engaged in the process of ‘self-
clarification’ and the effort to ‘settle accounts’ with the Young Hegelian heritage. Only
then, in the context of polemics against Feuerbach, does the first outline of the
materialist conception of history as a sequence of modes of production take definite
shape. Given the self-affiliation of Marx to Feuerbach in 1844 it is necessary to clear up
the question of the role played by Feuerbach in Marx’s evolution in general, and his
influence on the 1844 Manuscripts in particular.
Young Hegelianism
Hegel died in 1831 and within a few years his followers polarized: there were
conservatives, or ‘Old Hegelians’, and radicals, or ‘Young Hegelians’. [7] This
divergence is foreshadowed in internal tensions in Hegel’s own philosophy. In spite of
the rationalist and historical elements in Hegel’s thought, he did not give philosophy a
radical role in social affairs, at least in his well-known mature works; it seemed that the
role of philosophy was to reconcile thought to the present. The Young Hegelians
claimed that there was, nevertheless, an esoteric radical Hegel in the exoteric
conservative who compromised with the Prussian monarchy. Certainly the younger
Hegel welcomed the French Revolution and its Napoleonic extension to Germany. He
gave philosophy the task of herald of the new order, indeed, even its promulgator.
Soon after the publication of his Phenomenology of Spirit Hegel wrote to a friend: ‘Daily I
become more convinced that theoretical work accomplishes more in the world than
practical; once the realm of ideas is revolutionized, reality cannot hold out.’ [8] Whether
Hegel himself continued to believe this or not, the Young Hegelians certainly held such
a view wholeheartedly.
We need look no further than Friedrich Engels, in the period before he joined forces
with Marx, to find a typical exponent of Young Hegelianism. Although already a
declared ‘communist’ in the early 1840s (having been converted by Hess), he held that
communism followed directly from ‘German Philosophy’, that is, from the ‘left’
interpretation of Hegel. Engels makes this claim in a fascinating article he wrote in
1843 for the Owenite periodical New Moral World. Here he explains to his English
readers that Hegel ‘neglected to free himself from the prejudices of his age’, notably
the attachment to monarchy and religion, but that the Young Hegelians had freed the
principles of his thought, little by little, from these conservative encrustations.
Eventually, indeed, Hegelianism became in effect atheism, a charge Engels declared
himself the first to have allowed just. [9] The reference here is to a pamphlet he had
published anonymously in Germany the previous year. This was a counterattack on
Schelling’s Berlin lectures directed against Hegelianism. [10]Here Engels develops at
greater length the theory of Hegel’s ‘prejudices’. He says that Hegel’s conclusions
would have been different if he had proceeded from ‘pure thought’; but, instead,
‘positive’ elements crept in because he was ‘a product of his time’. ‘The principles’,
says Engels, ‘are throughout independent and free-minded, the conclusions – no one
denies it – sometimes cautious, even illiberal’. [11]All that is necessary for a left wing to
take form, then, is to keep to the principles and reject the conclusions. Here Engels
expresses the outlook of Young Hegelianism perfectly.
But what would be the right conclusions to draw? Engels has no doubt whatever that
‘the necessary consequence of New Hegelian philosophy’ is communism. He informs
the English socialists that ‘philosophical communism may be considered for ever
established in Germany’. Striking a note he will return to at the end of his life, he
declares that ‘our party’ must prove to the Germans that they must either reject their
philosophical tradition as useless, or ‘they must adopt communism’. [12]
Let us turn now to the knotty problem of Marx’s very different encounter with
Hegelianism. Althusser says that the Hegel Marx met was ‘the Hegel of the neo-Hegelian
movement, a Hegel already summoned to provide German intellectuals of the 1840s
with the means to think their own history and their own hopes; a Hegel already made to
contradict himself, invoked against himself, in despite of himself’. [13] There is some
truth in this; but Marx had his own distinctive position based on his own acute reading
of Hegel. Well before Engels repeats the above commonplaces of Young Hegelianism
with respect to ‘principles’ and ‘prejudices’, Marx was writing in his doctoral dissertation
that it was silly for Hegel’s followers to explain some feature of his system by his
accommodation to existing reality; [14] even if a philosopher is consciously making
some sort of accommodation, ‘what he is not conscious of is the possibility that this
apparent accommodation has its deepest roots in an inadequacy . . . of his principle
itself’. [15]
Thus the searchlight must be turned on the principle itself to see how it makes possible
the expression of conservative prejudices. This is precisely the task Marx undertakes in
1844 when he shows how Hegel’s conceptualization of the problematic of alienation
leads to a reconciliation of ‘reason’ with ‘unreason’ and an accommodation with
religion, the state etc. This false position, Marx concludes, is founded in ‘the falsehood
of his principle’. [16] The Young Hegelian attempt to preserve the ‘principle’ from
‘accommodations’ on Hegel’s part is therefore untenable. However, we are running
ahead of our story.
Let us return to the beginning. We know that when Marx first came into contact with
Hegel’s philosophy at the University of Berlin its ‘craggy melody’ repelled him. For a
time he was imbued with ‘the idealism of Kant and Fichte’ and wrote effusive poetry in
this vein. [17] He later dismissed this poetry as marked by ‘complete opposition
between what is and what ought to be’. [18] A slightly later poem is of peculiar interest
in exhibiting his first reaction to Hegel. In a book of verse sent to his father in the spring
of 1837 we find the Hegel Epigramme, which are full of irony at Hegel’s expense. The
most piquant is the third:
Kant and Fichte soar to heavens blue
Seeking for some distant land;
I but seek to grasp profound and true
That which in the street I find. [19]
This epigram is completely misunderstood when it is thought that ‘I’ refers to Marx
himself. [20] The ‘I’ is Hegel – just as it is in the previous epigram beginning ‘words I
teach all mixed up in a devilish muddle’ – but it is Hegel forced to speak against himself
by Marx. Given this, it is not the case that Marx here endorses the standpoint of Hegel
against that of Kant (much less opts for materialism). [21] According to Marx’s own
account, in a letter to his father, it is later in 1837 that he ‘arrived at the point of seeking
the idea in reality itself’ and found himself delivered into ‘the arms of the enemy’,
namely Hegel. [22] As was noted in the remarks on his dissertation, Marx very soon
begins to depart from Hegel, but the project of ‘seeking the idea in reality itself’
remains.
In departing from Hegel Marx was enormously encouraged by the work of Feuerbach.
In 1843 and 1844 he works with the slogan ‘real humanism’, following Feuerbach’s
basic principle. Feuerbach wrote: ‘the new principle makes man, together with nature, as
the basis of man, the sole, universal and highest object of philosophy.’ [23] At this time
Marx is an enthusiastic partisan of Feuerbach and continually tries to interest him in
new publishing projects.
The received version of events is that Marx was an Hegelian, then he was converted
by Feuerbach to materialism and then he struck out on his own ‘to change the world’.
The true story is more complicated.
The authority of Engels has to be recognized of course, so let us begin with the
account in his book Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy (1888).
He speaks of Feuerbach in dramatic terms: ‘with one blow’ Feuerbach’s Essence of
Christianity (1841) ‘broke the spell’ of idealism; Hegel’s system was ‘exploded and cast
aside’; ‘the liberating effect of this book’ aroused ‘general enthusiasm’; ‘we all became
at once Feuerbachians’ [24]
Engels’ memory plays him false here. At first Feuerbach’s book was generally taken to
be an application of Hegelian principles rather than a refutation. Engels himself is
testimony to this. In his anti-Schelling pamphlet of 1842, in passing he defends Hegel
also against Feuerbach and opines that ‘Feuerbach’s critique of Christianity is a
necessary complement to the speculative teaching on religion founded by
Hegel’. [25] Engels also forgets to mention that as far as the critique of Hegel is
concerned Feuerbach’s major blows were delivered in the 1843 texts, Preliminary
Theses towards the Reform of Philosophy and Principles of the Philosophy of the Future.
As for Marx, Engels goes on, ‘how enthusiastically Marx greeted the new conception
and how much – in spite of all critical reservations – he was influenced by it, one may
read in The Holy Family‘. [26] But this is a work written three years after Essence of
Christianity appeared. In fact, Marx was somewhat slow to respond to the book; there is
little sign of its influence in his 1842-3 newspaper articles. In truth, the first major
impact on Marx’s thinking of Feuerbach is documented in his study of Hegel, written in
Kreuznach in the spring and summer of 1843. The method applied is taken straight
from Feuerbach’s newly published Preliminary Theses.
It is true that at the outset Marx expresses some reservations about this work. In a
letter to Ruge of March 1843 he says that Feuerbach’s aphorisms refer ‘too much to
nature and too little to politics’; he explains that philosophy needs an alliance with
politics to come true. [27]
It is a great mistake to treat this opinion as Marx’s final judgement on Feuerbach, and
to collate it with the critique offered in the theses On Feuerbach of 1845. For example,
N. Rotenstreich connects the appeal to politics here with the first of the theses, in which
Marx appeals to practice against Feuerbach’s contemplative materialism; [28] but the
practice meant there is not politics, it is a material production. At the earlier date of
1843 Marx is concluding his period as a journalist whose radicalism is clearly idealist in
tendency. In taking up in his articles such questions as the law on the ‘theft’ of wood
from forests, and the distress of the Mosel peasants, he becomes aware of the
inadequacy of his knowledge. Under the impact of this practical experience in coming
to terms with material interests, and of Feuerbach’s ‘theoretical revolution’, Marx rook
advantage of the closure of his newspaper to undertake a materialist critique of
Hegel. [29] This is inspired methodologically by Feuerbach’s charge that Hegel inverts
the real relations and that, therefore, the road to truth lies in a reinversion. Feuerbach
has in mind, very largely, central philosophical questions about man, God and nature.
Marx undertakes to remedy the one-sidedness of Feuerbach’s critique by applying the
latter’s method to Hegel’s political philosophy. In this study he shows how Hegel inverts
the real relations of ‘civil society’ and ‘the state’. But, in spite of his turn to ‘civil society’
as the ‘real basis’, there is as yet no properly materialist ontology grounded in
production. Hence the turn from politics to economics, even to nature, in the 1844
Manuscripts represents an advance over the position held at the time of the letter to
Ruge of March 1843.
Given that in the 1843 study on Hegel there is no stress on productive activity,
obviously Hegel cannot be praised for grasping man as his own product. The verdict on
Hegel at this stage is simply that his idealism mystifies real relations. Although Marx’s
critique opens up a new field of inquiry, and although he goes beyond the critique of
Hegelian ideology to a critique of real relations, the whole enterprise is Feuerbachian
through and through. For example, one of the most striking, and oft-quoted,
pronouncements is that ‘knowledge is not gained by applying “the logical concept”
everywhere, but in grasping the logic proper to the peculiar character of the object
concerned’. [30] This is well within the scope of Feuerbach’s Criticism. [31] Feuerbach
writes (in his Philosophy of the Future, 1843):
Only those determinations are productive of real knowledge which determine the
object by the object itself, by its own individual determinations; but not those that
are general, as for example the logico-metaphysical determinations that, being
applicable to all objects without distinction, determine no object. [32]
More than in the 1843 notebook study, Marx’s articles On the Jewish Question, published
in 1844, go beyond the critique of ideological inversions to criticize the real
estrangement of the modern state from civil society. Marx calls for a recuperation of the
sociality disrupted in the split between the atomized members of civil society and the
abstract community of citizenship well described by Rousseau. Human emancipation
will be achieved, Marx concludes, ‘only when the real, individual man re-absorbs in
himself the abstract citizen . . . only when man has recognized and organized his “force
propres” as social forces, and consequently no longer separates social power from
himself in the shape of political power’. [33]
It is at this date, that is early in 1844, that Marx for the first time nominates the
proletariat as the revolutionary force in Germany, in a remarkable essay which exhibits
the connection of theory and practice in the highest degree of tension.
However radical philosophical critique becomes, it remains the case, he says, ‘that
revolutions need a passive element, a material basis’. The theoretical revolution brought
about within post-Hegelian philosophy cannot complete itself within the domain of
theory. ‘It is not enough that thought should strive for realization; reality must itself
strive towards thought.’ [34] Where then is the material agent of revolution? Marx
answers that it must be a class which is forced to revolt under the compulsion of
‘material necessity’, whose revolt has a universal character ‘because of its universal
suffering’; it must be a class ‘which is the total loss of humanity and which can
therefore redeem itself only through the total redemption of humanity’. There is indeed
such a class without any stake in the existing order and thrown into opposition to it –
‘the proletariat’. [35]
So the proletariat is nominated as the material agent of revolutionary change. But let us
look carefully at how its struggle is related by Marx to ‘theoretical needs’. ‘Clearly’, he
says, ‘the weapon of criticism cannot replace the criticism of weapons, and material
force must be overthrown by material force; but theory also becomes a material force
once it has gripped the masses.’ [36] He finishes the essay with a whole series of such
propositions: ‘just as philosophy finds its material weapons in the proletariat, so the
proletariat finds its spiritual weapons in philosophy’; ‘the head‘ of the struggle is
‘philosophy, its heart, the proletariat‘; ‘philosophy cannot realize itself without . . . the
proletariat’ and the proletariat cannot liberate itself from its chains without ‘the
realization of philosophy’. These are the ‘inner conditions’ of revolution. [37]
It is clear from a reading of this text that Marx has broken with his erstwhile
philosophical background in so far as he realizes that criticism cannot change reality.
But it is equally clear that he is simply adding in a mechanical way the practical needs
of the proletariat to this theoretical criticism. It is a marriage of convenience, not a real
union. Furthermore, in the above formulations it is still theory which is the overriding
moment; it ‘grips the masses’; theory is not evolved from the practical standpoint of the
proletariat. Hence it retains an abstract and moralizing character. He speaks of the
‘categorical imperative’ to redeem humanity. [38]
The proletariat is assigned its revolutionary role because of its neediness and
oppression; it is thus qualified to be the bearer of universal emancipation. This intuitive
imputation is buttressed dialectically by a very bare and abstract play of the categories
of universality and particularity. It is too glib. It has justly been characterized as Marx’s
‘Hegelian choreography’. [39] The antithesis of property and propertylessness is not yet
interpreted as that of labour and capital. Furthermore, the revolutionary perspective
remains an utterly vague call for ‘human emancipation’.
In the Preface to the 1844 Manuscripts Marx says that he abandoned his plan to do a
critique of Hegel’s political philosophy because ‘the intermingling of criticism directed
only against speculation with criticism of the various matters themselves proved utterly
unsuitable’. [40] From this original critique of Hegel to the subtitle of Capital – ‘Critique
of Political Economy’ – ‘criticism’, is one of Marx’s favourite words. But what does it
mean? Early on, in his doctoral dissertation, a purely idealist definition appears: critique
‘measures the individual existence by the essence, the particular reality by the
Idea’. [41] This is the guiding spirit of his articles for the Rheinische Zeitung. But in the
1843 Hegel study a more interesting definition emerges: ‘truly philosophical
criticism . . . not only shows up contradictions as existing, it explains them, it
comprehends their genesis, their necessity’. [42]
In fact there is a hint of this idea already in the Rheinische Zeitung when Marx is forced
to touch on communism for the first time. In 1842 his newspaper was attacked by
another for ‘communism’; in his reply Marx ‘does not admit that communist ideas in
their present form possess even theoretical reality‘, although he also says that ‘the
sharp-witted work of Proudhon’ (What is Property?), and others, can be criticized only
after proper study. [43] Such a study must take on board the objective fact that ‘the
estate that today owns nothing demands to share in the wealth of the middle classes’.
This is ‘obvious to everyone in Manchester, Paris, and Lyons’. [44] We see that already
Marx is shifting the focus of attention from the ideological level to the real social forces
in motion. [45] A year later, nevertheless, Marx still writes that communism is ‘a
dogmatic abstraction’. The interesting thing, however, is that this complaint is spelled
out as an objection to its partial, one-sided realization of ‘the humanistic principle’, and,
more explicitly, it is said to be ‘still infected with its antithesis – the private
system’. [46] It seems that until his studies in political economy convinced him of the
dynamic potential of the struggle against capital he was inclined to regard communism
as a mere reflex response to inequality, its mere contrary, ungrounded in an adequate
theoretical understanding of the inner relationships of private property.
In the years 1843 and 1844 Marx’s ideas are changing rapidly and the stages of
development are hard to map on the texts because these stages frequently overlap
each other in the same work. However, it is clear that three ‘pure’ stages may be
disentangled from the material. First there is the criticism of private property in the light
of its lack of accord with the idea of humanity, private property seen as an alien
mediator; such a criticism reveals a discrepancy of real existence and supposed
essence. Second there is the transference of the contradiction to reality itself, a self-
criticism of society in so far as it produces the propertyless proletariat as ‘the
dissolution of society’, forced into revolt by ‘material necessity’. Finally, when the
antithesis of property and propertylessness is grasped as the antithesis of labour and
capital, the proletariat is seen as reappropriating its estranged powers in the positive
supersession of private property.
Prior to 1844 Marx’s effort to unify theory and practice remains an abstract programme
because he has not yet identified productive activity as the socially constitutive axis on
which all else turns. Now the way opens for an investigation of the material foundations
of society and history.
Once Marx grasps labour as the central category of historical dialectic, communism
takes its place as the necessary moment of transition to ‘the positive supersession of
private property’. Such a communism ‘is the riddle of history solved and it knows itself
to be this solution’. [47] Thus grounded, communism, he says later, is not an ideal to
which reality has to accommodate itself: ‘we call communism the real movement which
abolishes the present state of things’. [48]
The absolute idea which ‘resolves to let the moment . . . of its other-being,
the immediate idea, as its reflection, issue freely from itself as nature‘, this whole
idea, which conducts itself in such a strange and baroque fashion, and which has
given the Hegelians such terrible headaches, is purely and
simply . . abstraction which, taught by experience and enlightened as to its own
truth, resolves . . . to relinquish itself and . . . in place of its self-absorption, to
let nature, which it concealed within itself as a mere abstraction, as a thing of
thought, issue freely from itself that is to say . . . it resolves on intuition . . .
The mystical feeling which drives the philosopher from abstract thinking to
intuition is boredom, the longing for a content. [62]
This follows the same line as Feuerbach’s criticism. Marx follows Feuerbach too in
saying that ‘the abstract thinker who decides on intuition, intuits nature abstractly’;
hence ‘the whole of nature only repeats to him in a sensuous external form the
abstractions of logic’; and it follows that ‘nature as nature . . . distinct from these
abstractions . . . has no meaning, or has only the sense of an externality to be
superseded . . .’. [63] This is seen when Hegel says that ‘since . . . the idea is present
as the negative of itself, or is external to itself, nature is not merely external in relation to
this idea . . . but externality constitutes its specificity, as nature’. [64] Nature is an
external world of objects externally related to its own truth. It is absolute externality
because the internality to which that externality is related can only be reconstituted
through the medium of thought.
In the final part of Hegel’s Encyclopaedia, ‘Spirit’, there is a ‘return out of nature’. Spirit is
defined as the unity of subject and object. ‘This identity is absolute negativity – for
whereas in nature the concept has its objectivity in a completely external manner, this
its alienation has been sublated.’ [65] When Hegel characterizes nature as ‘externality’
this sounds innocent enough; but, as Marx explains, externality here should not be
understood as a sensuously accessible world exposing itself to the light of day; rather,
he says, ‘it is to be taken in the sense of alienation, a flaw, a weakness . . .’. For Hegel
it is not a question of natural objectivity of which man is a part and in and through which
his existence is naturally mediated; it is a question of spirit positing the realm of nature
as immediately other, hence being moved to idealize this actuality, since, as inherent
externality, nature lacks ideality itself and must submit to its incorporation as a moment
in spirit’s actualization. As Marx puts it: ‘For the abstract thinker nature must therefore
supersede itself, since it is already posited by him as a
potentially superseded being.’ [66]
The difficulty in interpreting Marx’s position arises when we see that, although he does
not explicitly say so, he takes up a fundamentally different position from that of
Feuerbach with respect to materialism; and this in turn allows Marx a deeper
appreciation of Hegel’s merit. The issue turns on the centrality of material labour in
Marx’s social ontology. For Feuerbach, whatever the qualifications he introduces, the
main drift of his positive doctrine is the assertion of an immediate unity between man
and nature. He seems to identify mediation as such with the distance thought introduces
between man and the object and to reject it accordingly. For Marx, by contrast, the
unity of man with the rest of nature is not immediate, but established by labour, and
hence changes and develops with new forms of labour. The unity of man with nature is
always mediated in industry and incorporates within itself equally a struggle to bring into
human use the recalcitrant forces of nature. This gives rise to a historical dimension,
which depends on changes in the mode of production. This dimension is lacking in
Feuerbach. Marx finds it in Hegel, but it is raised to the level of purely philosophical
reflection which has lost touch with the real basis of history in material labour. None the
less, Hegel’s philosophy contains the idea of activity, and, moreover, an activity that
develops through a stage of alienation and estrangement.
Feuerbach sees Hegel’s negation of the negation only as a contradiction of philosophy
with itself: to this he counterposes the positivity of sensuous immediacy. He does not
grasp the objective basis of Hegel’s thematization of alienating objectification.
However, Marx looks deeper into the historical content of Hegel’s work, and its real
achievement. He appears to follow Feuerbach in his critique of Hegel’s dialectic, and
he endorses Feuerbach’s naturalism; but this is by no means all, because he transfers
the problems of philosophy to the ground of historical practice and of revolutionary
transition. For Marx it is necessary to take the speculative problematic seriously as a
symptom of the real historical agenda. Feuerbach sees in Hegel’s problematic of
alienation only the self-delusion of a philosophy estranged from the real world, in that it
refuses to abandon itself to sensuousness. For Marx, Hegel’s speculative problematic
is an attempt to pose, and hence to solve, within philosophy, a real historical problem,
which Marx sees in terms of the necessity to supersede the rule of private property.
Hegel’s speculative solution is inadequate because the problem is not so much a
theoretical as a practical one.
But Feuerbach’s standpoint too cannot link up with practice. He interprets the problem
of estrangement as the view of nature as the ‘otherness’ of the idea, and the logical as
opposed to the human. This is interpreted again as exclusively a problem of the
consciousness of theologians and philosophers. To this speculative illusion Feuerbach
counterposes the immediate truths of naturalism and humanism, and he sets out to
reform consciousness to this effect. This makes him an idealist in practical philosophy,
as he himself naïvely confesses. [67] For Marx ‘positive humanism’ is a result of real
historical development, a necessary sequence in the self-production of the ontological
essence of man, whereas for Feuerbach it is seen in ethical terms; Feuerbach posits
the ‘communal essence’ of man as a fixed abstraction based simply on the capacity for
universal mutual recognition on the part of individuals. At best this allows for an equally
abstract criticism of the perversities of theology and philosophy. In Marx the communal
essence is established through production in society. Its estrangement is expressed in
the development of the division of labour and the money system. Money is the
mediation that both ties and separates individuals; it is the ‘estranged and alienating
species-essence of man’; [68] a person’s bond with society lies literally ‘in his
pocket’. [69] However, this critique is not an ethical-anthropological one, for it is
grounded in an ontology which allows for the development of alienation and its
supersession to be grasped as historical necessities. Thus Marx can assert ‘both
that human life needed private property for its realization and that it now needs the
abolition of private property’. [70]
In effect, Feuerbach falls below the level of historical concreteness already attained by
Hegel. One is inclined to agree with Lukács’ verdict that Hegel poses the problem of
estrangement as a problem of the structure of social being, and in the development of
the stages of spirit the reality of the historical periods breaks through their conceptual
expressions in the aprioristic framework. [71] But, although Feuerbach uses
a methodological dialectic in evolving and situating his thought in the history of
philosophy, [72] his positive doctrine in effect rejects objective dialectic
altogether. [73] Lukács is therefore right to set Hegel above Feuerbach, because in the
materialist alignment of Marx with Feuerbach we miss Hegel’s great insight into the
dialectical movement of history. [74]
Certainly Marx had good reason to feel much sympathy with Feuerbach’s Hegel
critique. He credits Feuerbach with having drawn attention to Hegel’s conflation of
objectivity with estrangement. [75] Much of what Marx says about the objective
character of man and his world is drawn from Feuerbach. It is possible to overlook this
and take as great discoveries of Marx himself things he copied wholesale from
Feuerbach. As an example of the identity and difference of Marx and Feuerbach let us
look at the last section of the 1844 Manuscripts to be written – a fragment on money. It
begins with the premise that ‘man’s feelings {Empfindungen}, passions {Leidenschaften},
etc., are not merely anthropological phenomena in the narrower sense, but
truly ontological affirmations of being (of nature) and . . . are only really affirmed
because their object exists for them as a sensual object’. [76] This is straight out of
Feuerbach, who says that ‘man’s feelings have no empirical or anthropological
significance in the sense of the old transcendental philosophy, they have rather, an
ontological and metaphysical significance . . .’. Significantly, however, Feuerbach’s
chosen example is that ‘love is the true ontological demonstration of the existence of
objects apart from our head . . .’. [77] Marx, by contrast, chooses a different path: ‘only
through developed industry does the ontological essence of human passion come into
being’. [78]
The passage is a good illustration of how Marx goes beyond Feuerbach in the attack
on idealism. The recurrence in Marx’s text of words such as ‘feeling’, ‘passion’,
‘ontology’, etc., which come from Feuerbach, obscures the fact that Marx’s ontology is
very different. In Feuerbach’s naturalism the emphasis is on feeling, whereas in Marx it
is on productive activity. ‘Feeling’ (Empfindung) denotes a relatively low form of
experience in which no distinction is drawn between subject and object; hence
Feuerbach uses it to denote an indifferent immediacy, not a dialectically mediated
unity. It is true that Feuerbach is capable of incorporating productive activity in the
essence of man. He says in the Essence of Christianity that ‘the idea of activity, of
making, of creation, is in itself a divine idea’ because ‘in activity man feels himself free,
unlimited, happy’; and ‘the most blissful activity is that which is productive’. Hence, he
concludes, ‘this attribute of the species productive activity – is assigned to
God’. [79] Nevertheless, this is not with Feuerbach, as it is with Marx,
a synthesizing category.
For Feuerbach the paradigm case of an objective relation is love, as we have just seen.
No such thing appears in Marx’s 1844 Manuscripts. Yet Erich Fromm [80] gets excited
when he reads this from Marx’s pen in The Holy Family: ‘love . . . first really teaches
man to believe in the objective world outside himself’. [81] Although Fromm’s reading of
Marx is Feuerbachian through and through, he does not recognize the provenance of
this remark in such statements as that quoted above. What happened was that Edgar
Bauer, under the pretext of a book review, attacked the idea of a love object, thus
covertly attacking Feuerbach. Then Marx, in his critique of the Bauer circle, reasserted
the Feuerbachian view in a highly contextualized manner, within this debate. Therefore,
although it is interesting that Marx expresses his solidarity with Feuerbach even on this
point, it is not this that Marx finds important about Feuerbach. Certainly no great
ontological significance should be attached to this isolated statement when Marx over
and over again stresses production as the central mediator. For example ‘species
being’ in the 1844 Manuscripts has quite a different content from what it has in
Feuerbach. It is not constituted in consciousness but in social production.
Feuerbach’s critique of religion is often given as an important source of Marx’s theory
of alienation. Undoubtedly Marx was impressed by it; but it is important to notice how
much more thoroughgoing is Marx’s own theory. For Feuerbach, religion consists in
‘the objectification of the essence of man’. [82] This means that ‘the personality of God
is the alienated, objectified, personality of man’. [83] Feuerbach finds ‘the secret of
religion’ is that man ‘objectifies {Vergegenständlichkeit} his being, and then again makes
himself the object of this objectified being, transformed into a subject, a person’. [84] He
amplifies this in an interesting note where ‘religious self-objectification’ is distinguished
from ‘that occurring in reflection and speculation’; for ‘the latter is arbitrary, the former
necessary – as necessary as art and language’. [85] The reference in this note to
‘speculation’ is explained by Feuerbach’s claim that Hegel’s philosophy is itself
alienating! It ‘estranges man from his own being and his own activity’. [86] This remark
is indicative. Feuerbach’s critique in truth is limited to a critique of ideology – worthless
ideology in the case of theology and philosophy, man’s lived relation to himself in the
case of religion as a necessary medium of species self-awareness.
Marx, by contrast, stresses that man ‘duplicates himself not only… in consciousness,
but actively, and actually, and therefore he sees himself in the world he has created’
(see p. 9). Likewise, alienation is objective.
In this light, one must enter qualifications about Marx’s – genuine – enthusiasm for
Feuerbach at this stage of his development. When he says Feuerbach’s great
achievement is to have counterposed to the negation of the negation the self-
subsistent positive, he has in mind primarily the way in which Hegel uses the negation
of the negation to affirm the absolute as spirit. Secondarily, Marx has in mind the way
in which the idealist negation of the negation fails to move beyond the stage of self-
reference in estrangement to a positive supersession. These two aspects of the matter
are connected, of course.
On the first point, however, Feuerbach rejects objective dialectics along with idealism;
while, on the second point, Marx diverges at least as far from Feuerbach as he does
from Hegel, because for Feuerbach ‘positive humanism’ is merely a philosophical
perspective produced by inverting religion and philosophy so that speculative thought is
brought down to earth, while for Marx it is historically produced through the
supersession of real objective estrangement. Marx is primarily interested in
the historical dialectic, and he wants to root communist revolution immanently in it;
hence he tries to recuperate Hegel’s dialectic of negativity within a materialist
conception of history. Feuerbach rejects Hegel’s negation of the negation altogether
because he is primarily interested in nature, which idealist dialectic reduces to the
status of an ‘externality’ to be sublated. Here Marx is bound to go some of the way with
Feuerbach. However, although the 1844 Manuscripts contain some undigested lumps of
Feuerbach’s naturalism, it is already clear that Marx advances beyond Feuerbach’s
endorsement of the immediate unity of man and nature to pose labour as their
mediation. This provides him with the ontological basis for his historical dialectic. It
follows that, with Marx, alienation is read as objective alienation. The new interpretation
of the world and its religious reflex provided by Feuerbach is inadequate from this point
of view: the point is to change the world. [87]
At this stage Marx does not see it as his task to point out Feuerbach’s limitations with
regard to the comprehension of historical dialectic. Indeed, at this stage he still
entertains the hope of securing Feuerbach’s collaboration. He writes to him in August
1844 to persuade him that on his own humanist principles he too should become a
socialist. Marx points out that, whether he knows it or not, Feuerbach has provided ‘a
philosophical basis for socialism’ and that ‘the communists’ have understood this.
The unity of man with man, which is based on the real differences between men,
the concept of the human species brought down from the heaven of abstraction to
the real earth, what is this but the concept of society? [93]
Strangely enough, Feuerbach responds to this injunction. While at first reluctant to
state publicly that he is a communist, [94] his reply (1845) to Stirner’s criticism of his
work ends in ringing tones with the declaration that, in as much as he ‘places the
essence of man in community alone’, he is ‘Kommunist‘. [95]
Rather ungratefully, Marx later writes (in the German Ideology) that Feuerbach ‘is
deceiving himself when he declares himself a communist’ because his conception of
‘communist’ is merely a category that registers an ahistorical fact about men’s need for
society whereas ‘in the real world’ a communist is a follower of a revolutionary party
bent on overthrowing the existing order: [96] ‘rather ungratefully’ because Marx’s
original letter makes such an equation between communism and ‘the concept of
society’. As for party affiliation: it is touching to learn that, when he was almost
forgotten, Feuerbach joined the Social Democratic Party, two years before his
death. [97]
However, this is to run ahead of the story. Returning to the question of Feuerbach and
Hegel, we have seen that the 1844 Manuscripts hail Feuerbach as ‘the true conqueror of
the old philosophy’. The only hint of a doubt in Marx’s mind is revealed by a passage at
the end of the Preface. He says that ‘Feuerbach’s discoveries about the nature of
philosophy still, for their proof at least, call for a critical discussion of philosophical
dialectic’. [98] Even then Marx had second thoughts and hastily crossed it through.
In The Holy Family (1845) he still talks of Feuerbach’s ‘masterly criticism’ of
Hegel, [99] and says that ‘Feuerbach was the first to describe philosophy as
speculative and mystical empiricism and to prove it’. [100] But in the German
Ideology (1846) Mans concludes that, after all, Feuerbach does not provide a criticism
of Hegel’s dialectics. [101] Before the German Ideology we have the well-known
theses On Feuerbach. For the first time Marx comprehensively, and consciously, breaks
with Feuerbach.
It must be remarked that this break occurs after the appearance of Max Stirner’s
scorching critique Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum. Although dated 1845, this came out
late in 1844 and, judging by his correspondence, Marx must have read it at
once. [102] All the Young Hegelians felt constrained to reply to Stirner. Feuerbach’s
reply was mentioned above. M. Hess (using material in a letter of Marx’s) replied
immediately in his Die Letzten Philosophen. Marx and Engels set to work late in 1845 on
the German Ideology, by far the largest section of which is a page by page attack on
Stirner’s work. In this connection it should be noted that Engel’s reminiscences, quoted
earlier, are misleading. He lists the Young Hegelians in the order Strauss, Bauer,
Stirner, Feuerbach. The uninitiated might think that Feuerbach’s main works replied to
Stirner. In fact, it was Stirner who came last with a book, and that included a violent
attack on Feuerbach. At all events, Marx and Engels, in 1845, began to include
Feuerbach with the other young Hegelians as part of their past, now superseded.
From our point of view, the most important of the theses On Feuerbach is the first,
because in it ‘materialism’ (Feuerbach’s explicitly included) is charged with neglect of
the practical relation to objectivity; by contrast ‘the active side was set forth abstractly
by idealism’. [103] This shows how far Marx’s materialism, in its concentration on
practice, goes beyond the passivity of sensuous intuition presented by Feuerbach and
so many others as the nub of materialism. In thus distancing himself from ‘the old
materialism’ Marx even acknowledges once again merit in idealism (Hegel), despite the
fact that it transposes real activity into the dialectic of abstractions.
It is in the German Ideology that Marx and Engels develop the method of historical
materialism at length for the first time. However, these positive views are embedded in
a critique of the Young Hegelians, including Feuerbach. According to this account,
‘their polemics against Hegel and against one another are confined to this – each takes
one side of the Hegelian system and turns this against the whole system as well as
against the aspects chosen by the others’. [104] A rather nice example of this occurs in
Feuerbach’s first Hegel-critique, where he inverts Hegel’s ordering of space and time,
preferring ‘the liberality of space’ to ‘the monarchical tendency of time’; but where both
are still recognizably Hegel’s categories. [105]
The main point, of course, is the emphasis placed by Marx and Engels on the
importance of the mode of production. Feuerbach says in his Essence of Christianity that
man is distinguished from animals by religion and by consciousness. [106] Obviously
with this in mind, Marx and Engels say:
men can be distinguished from animals by consciousness, by religion, or
anything else you like. They themselves begin to distinguish themselves from
animals as soon as they begin to produce their means of subsistence . . . This
mode of production is a definite mode of life on their part . . . What they are,
therefore, coincides with their production. [107]
They take Feuerbach severely to task for his abstract contemplative materialism; they
point our that the cherry tree outside his window is an object of sensuous certainty for
Feuerbach only as a result of world trade; nature just as ‘given’ exists only on a few
coral islands; the progression of industry has thoroughly transformed the objective
world.
The final verdict of Marx on Feuerbach is given much later on. In an obituary (of
January 1865) on Proudhon, Marx remarks in passing that ‘compared with Hegel,
Feuerbach is exceedingly poor’. So why all the fuss? Because ‘he was epoch-
making after Hegel, since he laid stress on certain points disagreeable to Christian
consciousness while important for the progress of criticism, and which Hegel had left in
mystic semi-obscurity’. [108]
‘Compared with Hegel, Feuerbach is exceedingly poor’: this is interesting not only for
Marx’s opinion of Feuerbach but for a revaluation of Hegel. How does it come about
that ‘the conqueror of Hegel’ now bears no comparison with him? What happens with
Marx is that as Feuerbach’s star wanes, Hegel’s rises. Not at first: not in The Holy
Family for example. Although this was composed – mostly by Marx – immediately after
the 1844 Manuscripts, there is little trace in it of the advances made there. In particular,
there is no mention of any ‘great thing’ in Hegel; Feuerbach is the hero. Hegel is
treated scornfully throughout, under such headings as ‘Mystery of Speculative
Construction’. Indeed, for the next ten years Marx’s references to Hegel and his
dialectic are almost uniformly negative: the German Ideology dismisses Hegel’s
speculative history; the Poverty of Philosophy (1847) makes fun of Hegel’s ‘strings of
thoughts’ in the methodology section; the dialectic of negation of the negation is
attacked without reference to any virtue in it.
It is only when Marx seriously tries to get his economics into shape that there is a
second return to Hegel. The first was the 1844 return to the Phenomenology; this time it
is to the Logic. We have a letter (January 1858) in which Marx reports that he had been
made a present of Hegel’s Logic and found it of great service ‘in the method’. [109] This
influence was noted by several reviewers of Capital(1867), mostly with disapproval. In a
letter of 1868 Marx remarks of the fashion to treat Hegel’s dialectics as a dead dog that
‘Feuerbach has much on his conscience in this respect’. [110] So the man who was
first applauded for overthrowing Hegel’s dialectic should now apologize! Again in 1870
Marx mentions how put out Lange and others are by his resurrection of Hegel – after
they had long buried him! [111] When the second edition of Capital appeared in 1873,
Marx made a special point of asserting his affiliation to Hegel on the question of
dialectic – unfortunately in words too cryptic to construe easily.
Summary
What this survey shows is that there is no unilinear development from Hegel through
Feuerbach to a ‘mature’ Marxism. Moreover, in contrast to much recent talk of a ‘break’
in Marx’s work, and the contraposition of a ‘young’ and ‘old’ Marx, Marx himself showed
no inclination to reject any of his work, however early. In 1851, well after his adoption of
a communist outlook, he was happy to see republished his early journalism. [112] In
1867 he re-read The Holy Family and reported to Engels that he ‘was pleasantly
surprised to find that we do not need to be ashamed of this work, although the cult of
Feuerbach produces a very humorous effect upon one now’. [113]
At the same time, it is obvious that there are important developments in Marx’s thought.
We can mark out the following stages:
1. 1840-3
Young Hegelianism leading to radical democratic works.
2. 1843-4
Feuerbachian works, especially his notes on Hegel’s Philosophy of Right applying the
method of inversion of Hegel. A turn towards a practical thrust in the Introduction.
3. 1844
The turning point. Birth of Marxism in that labour is centralized, and political economy is
seen as a key science. Feuerbach is not yet rejected. The first return to Hegel in that there is
praise for the ‘producing principle’ of the Phenomenology.
4. 1844-57
Transitional works. Anti-speculative settling with philosophy, both Hegel’s, in The Holy
Family (still under the sign of Feuerbach) and Feuerbach’s also, in the Theses and German
Ideology. Growing concreteness of outlook, e.g. class struggle in the Manifesto.
5. 1857 on
Mature work on political economy and politics; the second return to Hegel, this time to
the Logic. [114]
Introduction
So far, we have concentrated largely on exegesis and clarification of Marx’s ideas and
their relationship to his philosophical antecedents. The remainder of this book gives
some indication of their validity and their limitations.
Given that we claim Marx’s theory of alienated labour has not been properly
understood, it follows that most previous objections raised against it are
irrelevant. [1] This chapter considers the most interesting charge, namely that Marx
does not really break with Hegel’s problematic as far as alienation is concerned. I reject
this; but acknowledge also that there are important limitations in the ontology of
the 1844 Manuscripts. I believe this is overcome in the subsequent development of
Marx’s thought, and that the ambivalence in his later writings on the question of the
abolition of labour flows from his appreciation of the difficulties inherent in such a
perspective.
The next chapter will go on to discuss briefly the contribution to Marx’s Capital of the
ontology inaugurated in the 1844 Manuscripts.
In the dynamic contradiction of labour and private property the negation of the negation
does not effect a closure then – an end of history – because this specific dialectic is
inscribed, as the estrangement of social being, within the wider intermediations of man
and nature. Hence the negation of the negation brought about through communist
revolution opens out the possibility of a real human history no longer carried on under
the mark of estrangement.
It is important here, therefore, not to oversimplify the dialectical movement of alienation
and its supersession. When Marx speaks of ‘the emergence of nature for man’ this
relation of difference – man for himself and nature for man – is a genuine advance
beyond that state in which man is sunk in the natural, unable to perceive his own
specificity as an acting subject and to grasp nature as an object of purposeful activity.
At the same time this difference must maintain its necessary unity; for man depends on
nature for his material reproduction. Two consequences follow; first, that, if in the
estranging system of secondary mediations subject and object are opposed, they are
none the less united, even though in a contradictory dynamic; second, that abolition of
estrangement does not abolish this difference and restore relations of natural
immediacy, but rather produces a unity in diversity, mediated through social labour,
and freed from the contradictions of the estranging system of private property. The
history of alienation does not go from identity to difference back to identity; rather, it
goes from identity to contradictory unity in difference, on to non-antagonistic unity in
difference.
After the end of alienation there must remain a dialectical process of interaction, even
of opposition, as successive obstacles thrown up by nature are encountered. Negative
ecological feedback cannot be supposed only a problem of capitalist anarchy, for
example. The nature that is ‘for man’ is always a continually surprising interlocutor.
The first alternative we have already seen, namely, the acknowledgement of the
permanence of the realm of necessity, the distinction from this of the realm of freedom,
and hence the view that labour remains man’s curse. All one can hope for is the
possible abolition of labour through total automation (a tendency anticipated by Marx in
his Grundrisse). [32] The second alternative is to return unblushingly to the original
perspective. This we find in one of Marx’s last works, the critique of the Gotha
programme, in which his vision of ‘a higher phase of communist society’ includes,
besides the abolition of the division of labour, the remarkable claim that labour
becomes ‘life’s prime want’! [33] This seems to return us to Fourier. For Fourier,
productive labour is a natural and spontaneous need; given a suitable social structure it
becomes identical with self-enjoyment.
The third solution would refuse such an identity, but refuse also the unmediated
opposition of self-activity and material production. it would be an attempt to try for a
dialectical interpretation of freedom and necessity. [34] This idea can be found in Marx,
when he goes for a middle way between Smith and Fourier, in his Grundrisse. Marx
argues that because Smith has in mind only capitalist forms of employment he
counterposes labour to freedom and happiness. In trying to envisage an alternative
conception Marx first argues that an individual in his normal state of health needs to
work; he then argues that this does not mean that such work is to be ‘mere fun, mere
amusement, as Fourier with grissette-like naïvety conceives it’; for ‘really free working,
e.g. composing,’ is a serious business requiring ‘intense exertion’. The key thing that
brings it within the realm of freedom is when the aims that impose this discipline are not
imposed from without but are posited by the individual himself. In such a context,
overcoming obstacles ‘is in itself a liberating activity’ [35] (a very Hegelian idea).
‘Real economy’, Marx declares, ‘consists of the saving of labour time’. This of course
depends on ‘the development of the productive forces.’ However, the free time won is
in truth ‘time for the full development of the individual, which in turn reacts back upon
the productive power of labour as itself the greatest productive power’. [36] Given this,
we cannot accept an abstract antithesis between ‘direct labour time and free time’. This
is an illusion grounded in ‘the perspective of bourgeois economy’. Marx underlines
Fourier’s contribution in shifting the attention of socialists from questions of distribution
to that of the mode of production; but he reasserts that ‘labour cannot become play, as
Fourier would like’. [37] Yet, because free time allows for ‘higher activity’ we get a
different kind of subject entering production, an educated worker. In work Marx sees
three aspects: the ‘discipline’ involved in the process of becoming human; the creative
use of acquired knowledge and power; and even ‘in so far as labour requires practical
use of the hands and free bodily movement, as in agriculture, at the same time
exercise’. [38]
The solution suggested in such passages to the supposed antithesis between free
activity and materially determined production presupposes the whole ontology
inaugurated (if not completed) in the 1844 Manuscripts. Once the socially constituted
unity in difference of man with nature is thought through, such an abstract antithesis
must be rejected; even if, from the perspective of the existing estranged relationships, it
seems all too plausible. Free activity (like alienated activity in fact) is constituted
socially. Society in turn is constituted on the basis of material production. There is
therefore a relationship between free activity and material production which it is the
task of historical materialism to elucidate. As we have seen, this relationship is not
simply quantitative, where free time depends on the shortening of the working day,
although this is certainly important and rests on the potential of the productive forces
available. It is also a matter of a growing mediatedness of the two sides such that the
material practice through which man actualizes himself is a unified process which,
though conditioned by existing wants and productive powers, also realizes both in
itself, and in its grounding of other practices, human creativity and liberation. This
process is open-ended in that new goals, new obstacles, and new powers, spring from
it.
Freedom is not something given, it is won and re-won in the dialectic of history.
Summary
Marx’s theory of alienation is not simply a materialist transformation of Hegel. None the
less, the unity of man and nature is insufficiently problematized in 1844. Hence, the
abolition of private property is identified with the abolition of ‘labour’ and the transition
to free activity. Later, Marx recognizes that productive activity, even in socialism, is a
labour caught up in the dialectic of freedom and necessity.
Appendix
Problems of Interpretation
In order to show the sheer difficulty of reading the text of 1844 (towards the overcoming
of which these labours are directed), let us take as a case study a single passage and
see how four different commentators respond to it. This passage is of peculiar
importance because it is from the beginning of the section on ‘estranged labour’ in the
first manuscript, that is to say, the place where Marx first introduces the idea of
alienation. Marx writes:
Labour produces not only commodities: it produces itself and the worker as
a commodity . . . This fact simply means that the object that labour produces, its
product, confronts it as something alien, as a power independent of the producer.
The product of labour is labour embodied and made material in an object; it is
the objectification of labour. The realization of labour is its objectification.
Under these economic conditions this realization of labour appears as loss of
reality for the workers, objectification as loss of, and bondage to, the object,
appropriation as estrangement, as alienation . ‘ . So much does the appropriation
of the object appear as estrangement that the more objects the worker produces
the less he can possess and the more he boils under the sway of his product,
capital. All these consequences flow from a situation characterized by this: that
the worker is related to the product of his labour as to an alien object. [39]
Ignorant writers, not worthy of particular notice, take ‘objectification’ here to carry a
negative load, to be nothing but a synonym for alienation. They do this without knowing
any Hegel. Yet even a sophisticated scholar like Pierre Naville tends to the same
mistaken identification when he says that what we have here is a philosophical account
borrowed from Hegel of the equation of objectification and alienation. He qualifies this
merely by granting that Marx is anxious to give the idea ‘a practical basis’. [40]
Lukács, by contrast, says of exactly the same passage that, while Hegel is not
mentioned by name, ‘even a cursory glance’ reveals that these remarks amount to ‘a
fundamental critique of Hegel’s philosophy’. This is because estrangement is sharply
distinguished here from objectification in the act of labour. [41]
Erich Fromm equates the passage with one from Capital.[42] This arouses the ire of
Ernest Mandel, who objects that ‘Fromm does not notice that in the former what is
being discussed is labour and the products of labour in general, whereas the latter
begins with these very words: “Within the capitalist system . . .”.’ [43] Mandel avers that
the passage in question does not seek the origin of alienated labour ‘in a specific form
of human society, but in human nature itself’. [44]
Mandel’s reading is clearly wrong. The references to commodities and capital are clear
enough. Furthermore, Marx cannot believe that alienated labour is rooted in human
nature itself because the sequence of oppositions between objectification and loss of
the object, etc. shows he is aware that specific economic conditions are responsible
when appropriation appears as alienation. One reason why Mandel is led astray is that,
as was explained in chapter 1, Marx uses ‘labour’ in his early writings in the same
sense as does political economy, namely as productive activity formed by the present
economic conditions, not as the more general notion Mandel takes it to be. Unlike
political economy, Marx does not take such labour to be inherent in human nature.
Hence he can look forward to the practical abolition of alienation.
Introduction
It was in 1844 that Marx first embarked on ‘the critique of political economy’; it was a
task he never really completed. The only substantial result of his labours that he
himself saw published was the first volume of Capital in 1867. A question arises
immediately. If it took Marx 23 years’ work before he could present the core of his
findings in published form, of what value are the unpublished studies of 1844? The
controversy about the ‘young’ and ‘mature’ Marx is well known. It is beyond the scope
of this work to trace the development of Marx’s thought throughout his entire opus,
although some brief indications have been given earlier; the attempt here is solely to
clarify the ideas of 1844. None the less, it is necessary to say something, however
brief, in order to indicate the continuing importance of this turning point.
The form of value, for example, as Marx points out in his well-known letter to
Kugelmann, must in some way enshrine, albeit in mystified form, the process of
objectification and material reproduction. [7] It is not necessary to know this in order to
adhere to a labour theory of value. This was possible for Smith and Ricardo. But
it is necessary if the value-form of the product of labour is to become an object of
criticism instead of being illegitimately naturalized, as it was in classical political
economy which identified the two levels of mediation. At the same time, the labour
theory of value cannot be articulated sufficiently on the basis of the ontological
premises alone. To articulate correctly the forms of appearance of the content is no
easy task. Marx had to expend enormous effort in working out the dialectic of the
value-form itself, in solving the secret of surplus value and in disentangling the essence
of the capital relation from its mystifying forms of appearance (interest, profit etc.). But
it is only when the capital relation is conceived as a specific social form of material
reproduction that the essential relation can be distinguished from the fetishized forms.
Although the failure of bourgeois economics may be explained politically, its intellectual
limitations come down to its conflation of different levels of mediation, and its
methodological individualism, that is to say, its failure to grasp the nature of social
being: its weakness is in its ontology. Conversely, Marx’s Capital is inconceivable
without its ontological underpinning, and that was first opened up in the 1844
Manuscripts.
We may say that anyone who fails to see the relevance of the 1844
Manuscripts to Capital has simply not understood Capital itself. Some corroboration of
this is that Althusser’s theoretical anti-humanism is driven into a bizarre idealism of the
structure, which treats particular individuals merely as bearers of its relations, in the
same way as Hegel’s ‘concept’ (quelle horreur!). In this way, far from providing a
critique of reification, theoretical anti-humanism capitulates to it. But, to borrow Marx
and Engels’ words, structure ‘fights no fight’; ‘it is real living man who fights’. [8] In
proletarian revolution the workers precisely refuse to be bearers of the commodity
labour-power any longer.
In comprehending such transformations the importance of an ontological framework
against which to measure the shifting historical forms is clear. Otherwise critique would
be reduced to contesting the validity of the existing order from the standpoint of a
historically contingent utopian aspiration. By contrast, Marx’s critique acquires a
rootedness in material reality whereby it can ground the historical necessity of existing
forms, while yet grasping their limits and the conditions of their supersession.
Problems of Translation
← Chapter 11 | Bibliography →
Hegel’s Phenomenology
A.V. Hegel’s Phenomenology of
Miller: Spirit, Oxford, 1977.
Entfremdung = alienation.
Entäusserung =
externalization. Miller warns
that he ‘departs from a rigid
consistency in rendering . . .’.
This is so: he has
‘externalization’
for Entäusserung in para. 804,
but in para. 805 he has
‘alienation’, while in para. 806
he switches back.
Hegel’s Phenomenology of
Mind, London, revised 2nd ed.
1949.
Entfremdung = estrangement.
Entäusserung = various, he
often resorts to a bracketed
alternative, e.g. ‘relinquishes
(externalizes)’. (He also gives
as an alternative to ‘unhappy
consciousness’ the phrase
‘alienated soul’, which does
J.B. not appear in the German (p.
Baillie: 251).)
Aufheben
Hegel tells us in his Science of Logic that ‘aufheben‘ is one of the most important notions
in philosophy. He says that it is not a question of reducing something to nothingness
but of disposing of it as a result of mediation. He points out that in ordinary
language aufheben means both ‘to abolish’ and ‘to preserve’ and that he intends to take
advantage of this double meaning. [9]
According to W.T. Harris ‘reduce to a moment’ is the ‘exact signification’
of aufheben (although he uses ‘cancel’ himself). [10] In some ways this would be a good
translation were it not for the implication of elevation in the term. I use ‘supersede’
when the stress is more on abolition, and when the stress is on preservation I use the
slightly ‘technical’ term ‘sublate’, which was the choice of the Logic’s early translator J.
H. Stirling (The Secret of Hegel). The dictionary definition of ‘sublate’ is ‘to resolve in a
higher unity’.
Der Mensch
Although this refers to human beings in general it is standardly translated as ‘man’. But
German also has ‘der Mann‘ where the male of the species is meant. Unfortunately,
because English uses ‘human’ as an adjective it is not available as a noun. I have
therefore followed standard practice in using ‘man’ as a generic both in the quotations
and my own commentary. However, it should be noted that Marx’s German is not as
sexist as English translations make it appear. Where Marx discusses the relationship of
man to woman each term is employed in its separate sense. Thus: ‘The relation
of Mannes to woman is the most natural relation of Menschen to Menschen.’ [11]
Setzen (posit)
‘To posit’ is to put in place, set up, or establish. In an intellectual context it refers to the
assertion or proof of some truth. However, Hegel and Marx use it in wider contexts,
wherever something is brought into a specific place or relation. Thus the antithesis of
property and propertylessness is ‘posited by private property itself’ when there is a real
causal relationship between them – that one has property just because the other has
not. [12]
1
Werke 8, 658; The Young Hegel, trans. Rodney Livingstone, London, 1975,
p. 538.
2
C.W.3, 299.
3
C.W.3, 272.
4 C.W.3, 332-3.
5
‘On the Jewish Question II’, E.W., 241.
6
Werke Eb., 572; C.W.3, 331.
7
Schacht, Alienation, London, 1971, p. 72 n.7.
8
Karl Marx, Early Writings, trans. T.B. Bottomore, London, 1963, p. xix.
9
Wissenschaft der Logik, Hamburg, 1955, pp. 93-5; Hegel’s Science of
Logic, trans. A.V. Miller, London, 1969. pp. 106-8.
10
In Hegel Selections, ed. J. Loewenberg, New York, 1929, esp. p. 102n.
11
Werke Eb., 536; C.W.3, 296.
12
Werke Eb., 534; C.W.3, 294.
Bibliography
← Appendix | Contents →
This bibliography assembles full details of works to
which reference is made in the text and notes into five sections. The first
covers editions and translations of Marx’s 1844 Manuscripts; the
second gives other volumes of Marx and Engels’ works cited here; the third
gives the Hegel texts; the fourth lists other primary sources; the fifth
contains the secondary literature referred to. A date in brackets is
that of original publication; then follow details of the edition or
translation.
3 G.W.F. Hegel
On Christianity: Early Theological Writings, trans.
T.M. Knox with introduction by R. Kroner, Harper, New York, 1961.
Jenaer
Systementwürfe I, Gesammelte Werke Band 6, Meiner, Hamburg,
1975.
System of Ethical Life and First Philosophy of Spirit, trans. H.S. Harris
and T.M. Knox, S.U.N.Y. Press, Albany, MY, 1979.
Phänomenologie des
Geistes, Gesammelte Werke Band 9, Meiner, Hamburg, 1980.
Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 1977.
Phenomenology of Mind, trans. J.B. Baillie. Allen & Unwin, London,
1949.
Wortindex zu Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes, J. Gauvin, Bonn,
1977.
Hegel: Texts and Commentary, trans. and ed. W. Kaufmann, Anchor,
Garden City, NY, 1966.
Briefe von und an Hegel Band 1, ed. J. Hoffmeister,
Meiner, Hamburg, 1952.
Wissenschaft der Logik, Meiner, Hamburg,
1975.
Hegel’s Science of Logic, trans. A.V. Miller, Allen & Unwin, London,
1969.
The Berlin Phenomenology, ed. and trans. M.J. Petry, Reidel,
Dordrecht, 1981.
Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im
Grundrisse, ed, F. Nicolin and O. Pöggeler, Meiner, Hamburg. 1975.
Hegel’s
Logic (being Part I of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences)
trans. W. Wallace, 3rd ed., Oxford University Press, Oxford,
1975.
Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature, ed. and trans. M.J. Petry, 3 vols, Allen &
Unwin, London, 1970.
Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind (being Part Ill of the
Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences) trans. W. Wallace,
together with Zusätze, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford University Press, Oxford,
1971.
Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts (mit Hegels eigenhändigen
Randbemerkungen), ed. J. Hoffmeister, Meiner, Hamburg, 1955.
Hegel’s
Philosophy of Right, trans. T.M. Knox, Oxford University Press. Oxford,
1965.
Hegel Selections, ed. J. Loewenberg, Scribners, New York.
1929.
Hegel-Lexikon, H. Glockner, 2nd revised ed., 2 vols, Frommann,
Stuttgart, 1957.
4 Other Sources
T. Carlyle, Past and Present, London, 1843.
L. Feuerbach, Das Wesen des Christenthums (1841), Gesammelte Werke Band 5, ed.
Werner Schuffenhauer, Berlin, 1984.
L. Feuerbach, The Essence of
Christianity, trans. Marian Evans, New York, 1957.
L. Feuerbach, The Fiery
Brook – selected writings of Ludwig Feuerbach, trans. Z. Hanfi, Garden
City, NY, 1972.
L. Feuerbach, Kleinere Schriften II (1839-46),
Gesammelte Werke Band 9, ed. W. Schuffenhauer, Berlin, 1982.
L. Feuerbach,
Sämtliche Werke Zweiter Band, new ed. W. Bolin and F. Jodl, Stuttgart-Bad
Canstatt, 1959.
J.G. Fichte, Science of Knowledge (1794), trans. P.
Heath and J. Lachs, Cambridge, 1982.
Charles Fourier, Oeuvres
Complètes, Paris, 1966-68.
J.-J. Rousseau, The Social Contract and Discourses,
trans. G.D.H. Cole, revised ed., London, 1973.
Adam Smith, The Wealth
of Nations (1776), ed. E. Cannan (from 5th ed. 1789), Chicago,
1976.
L.S. Steplevich (ed.), The Young Hegelians: an Anthology, Cambridge,
1983.
5 Secondary Literature
Adams, H.P., Karl Marx in his Earlier Writings
(1940), London, 1965.
Althusser, Louis, For Marx (1965), trans. Ben
Brewster, London, 1969.
Politics and History (1970), London,
1972.
Arthur, C.J., ‘Hegel’s master/slave dialectic and a myth of Marxology’ New
Left Review (1983), 142.
Avineri, Shlomo, The Social and Political
Thought of Karl Marx, Cambridge, 1968.Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State, Cambridge,
1972.
Axelos, Kostas, Alienation, Praxis and Techné in the Thought of Karl
Marx (1961), trans, R. Bruzina, Austin, Texas, and London, 1976.
Berki, R.N., Insight and Vision: the problem of Communism in Marx’s
Thought, London, 1983.
Bottomore, Tom, (ed.), A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, Oxford, 1983.
Callinicos, Alex, Marxism and Philosophy, Oxford, 1983.
Cullen, Bernard, Hegel’s Social and Political Thought: an Introduction,
Dublin, 1979.
Della Volpe, Galvano, Rousseau and Marx (1964), London, 1978.
Desan, Wilfred, The Marxism of Jean-Paul Sartre (1965), New York, 1966.
Descombes, Vincent, Modern French Philosophy (1979), Cambridge, 1982.
Dunayevskaya, Raya, Marxism and Freedom, New York, 1958.
Philosophy and Revolution, New York, 1973.
Dupré, Louis, The Philosophical Foundations of Marxism, New York, 1966.
Edgley, Roy, and Osborne, Richard (eds.), Radical Philosophy Reader,
London, 1985.
Elder, Crawford, Appropriating Hegel, Aberdeen, 1981.
Findlay, J.N., Hegel: a Re-Examination, London, 1958.
Fromm, Erich, Marx’s Concept of Marx (1961), New York, 1971.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg, Hegel’s Dialectic, New Haven, Conn., and London,
1976.
Geras, Norman, Marx and Human Nature: Refutation of a Legend, London,
1983.
Gould, Carol C., Marx’s Social Ontology, Cambridge, Mass., and London,
1978.
Hunt, Ian, and Swan, Roy, ‘A comparison of Marxist and Hegelian
dialectical form’, Radical Philosophy (1982) No. 30.
Hyppolite, Jean, Genesis and Structure, of Hegel’s ‘Phenomenology of
Spirit’ (1946), trans. S. Cherniak and J. Heckman, Evanston, 1974.Studies on Marx and
Hegel (1955), trans. J. O’Neill, New York. 1969.
Israel, Joachim, The Language of Dialectic and the Dialectics of
Language, Brighton, 1979.
Kamenka, Eugene, The Ethical Foundations of Marxism, London. 1962.
Kaufmann, Walter, Hegel: a Reinterpretation, Garden City, NY, 1965.
Kojève, Alexandre, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel (1947), ed. A.
Bloom, trans. J.H. Nichols, New York, 1969.
Kosík, Karel, Dialectics of the Concrete (l961), Dordrecht, 1976.
Lefebvre, Henri, Dialectical Materialism, (1939), London, 1968.
Actualité de Fourier, colloque d’Arc-et-Senans sous la direction de
Henri Lefebvre, Paris, 1975.
Lenin, V.I., Selected Works, London, 1969.
Lobkowicz, Nicholas, (ed.), Marx and the Western World, Notre Dame,
Indiana, 1967.
Löwith, Karl, From Hegel to Nietzsche (1941), London, 1965.
Löwy, Michael, Georg Lukács – From Romanticism to Bolshevism (1975),
London, 1979.
Lukács, Georg,
History and Class Consciousness (1923), trans. Rodney
Livingstone, London, 1971.
Political Writings 1919-1929, trans. M. McColgan, London, 1972.
Der Junge Hegel (1948), Werke Band 8, Neuwied and Berlin, 3 Auflage,
1967.
The Young Hegel (1948). trans. Rodney Livingstone, London, 1975.
The Meaning of Contemporary Realism (1958), London, 1963.
Werke Band 2 (with new Preface), Neuwied and Berlin, 1968.
Ontology of Social Being: Marx (1972), trans. D. Fernbach, London,
1978.
Macgregor, David, The Communist Ideal in Hegel and Marx, London, 1984.
MacInryre, Alasdair (ed.), Hegel, Garden City, NY, 1972.
McLellan, David, The Young Hegelians and Karl Marx, London, 1969.
Marx
Before Marxism, London, 1970.
Maguire, J., Marx’s Paris Writings: an
Analysis, Dublin, 1972.
Mandel, Ernest, The Formation of the Economic
Thought of Karl Marx (1967), London, 1971.
Marcuse, Herbert, Reason
and Revolution (1941), 2nd ed., London, 1954.
From Luther to Popper, essays trans. Joris de Bres, London,
1983.
Meikle, Scott, Essentialism in the Thought of Karl Marx, London, 1985.
Mepham, John, and Ruben, D.H. (eds.), Issues in Marxist Philosophy, vol.
1, Brighton, 1979.
Mészáros, lstván, Marx’s Theory of Alienation,
London, 1970.
Naville, Pierre, De L’Aliénation à la Jouissance, Paris,
1957.
Nicolaus, Martin, ‘Hegelian choreography and the capitalist
dialectic’. Studies on the Left, 7 (1967), No. I.
Norman, Richard, Hegel’s
Phenomenology, Brighton, 1976.
Oizerman, T.I., The Making of the Marxist
Philosophy (1977), English trans., Moscow, 1981.
Ollman, Berrell,
Alienation, Cambridge, 1971.
Pelczynski, Z.A. (ed.), Hegel’s Political
Philosophy, Cambridge, 1971.
The State and Civil Society: Studies in Hegel’s Political Philosophy,
Cambridge, 1984.
Plant, Raymond, Hegel: an Introduction. 2nd ed.
Oxford, 1983.
Poster, Mark, Existentialist Marxism in Post-War France,
Princeton, NJ, 1975.
Prawer, S.S., Karl Marx and World Literature, Oxford,
1976.
Riedel, Manfred, Between Tradition and Revolution (1969),
Cambridge, 1984.
Ritter, Joachim, Hegel und die französische Revolution
(1956), Köln and Opladen, 1957.
Hegel and the French Revolution: Essays an
the Philosophy of Right (1956-69), trans. R. D. Winfield, Cambridge,
Mass., 1982.
Rose, Gillian, Hegel Contra Sociology, London, 1981.
Rose,
Margaret A., Reading the Young Marx and Engels, London, 1978.
Rosen,
Michael, Hegel’s Dialectic and its Criticism, Cambridge. 1982.
Rosen,
Stanley, G.W.F. Hegel – an introduction to the science of wisdom, New
Haven, Conn., and London, 1974.
Rotenstreich, Nathan, Basic Principles
of Marx’s Philosophy, Indianapolis. 1965.
Royce, Josiah, Lectures on
Modern Idealism, New Haven, Conn., 1919.
Rubel, Maximillien, Marx Life
and Works (1965), London, 1980.
Ruben, Peter, Dialektik und Arbeit der
Philosophie, Köln, 1978.
Sartre, Jean-Paul, Being and Nothingness
(1943), trans, Hazel Barnes, London, 1958.
The Problem of Method (1960), trans. Hazel Barnes, London,
1963.
Savran, Gülnur, ‘Rousseau, Hegel, and the Critique of Civil Society’, DPhil.
thesis, University of Sussex, 1983.
Schacht, Richard, Alienation,
London, 1971.
Schmidt, Alfred, The Concept of Nature in Marx (1962),
London, 1971.
History and Structure (1971), Cambridge. Mass., and London,
1981.
Sève, Lucien, Man in Marxist Theory (1974), trans. John McGreal,
London, 1978.
Singer, Peter, Hegel, Oxford, 1983.
Solomon, R.C., In
the Spirit of Hegel, Oxford and New York, 1983.
Soper, Kate, On Human
Needs, Brighton, 1981.
von Stein, Lorenz, The History of the Social
Movement in France 1789-1850 (1851), introduced and trans. Kaethe
Mengelberg, Totowa, NJ, 1964.
Taylor, Charles, Hegel, Cambridge. 1975.
Hegel and Modern Society, Cambridge, 1979.
Toews, John Edward,
Hegelianism: Path to Dialectical Humanism. 1805-1841, Cambridge,
1980.
Tucker, Robert C., Philosophy and Myth in Karl Marx, Cambridge, 1961.
Wahl,
Jean, Le Malheur de La Conscience (1929), Paris, 1951.
Walton, Paul,
and Gamble, Andrew, From Alienation to Surplus Value, London,
1972.
Wartofsky, Marx, Feuerbach, Cambridge, 1977.
Westphal, M. (ed.), Method
and Speculation in Hegel’s Phenomenology, Atlantic Highlands. NJ, and
Brighton, 1982.
White, Alan, Absolute Knowledge: Hegel and the Problem
of Metaphysics, Athens, Ohio, and London, 1983.
Wood, Allen, W., Karl
Marx, London, 1981.
Zelený, Jindrich, The Logic of Marx (1968). Oxford,
1980.