Gilles, Demarcation Problem
Gilles, Demarcation Problem
Contents
(1) Introduction
(2) The Demarcation Problem and the Vienna Circle
(3) Popper on the Demarcation Problem
(4) Falsifiability and the Duhem-Quine Thesis
(5) Alternative Medicine
1. Introduction
5
4. Falsifiability and the Duhem-Quine Thesis
Newton’s first law is a perfect example of this since it cannot be tested on its
own, as an isolated hypothesis, but only as part of a theoretical group. Let
us call Newton’s first law T. To obtain observable consequences from
Newton’s theory, we have to add to T:
6
(1) further theoretical assumptions: namely, the second and third laws of
motion and the law of gravity – call the conjunction of these T’, and
Now, from the conjunction T & T’ & A, we can indeed deduce observable
consequences regarding the motions of the planets. Call one such
consequence O. Suppose now that we observe not-O. We cannot conclude
‘not-T’, but only ‘either not-T or not-T’ or not-A’. To put the point another
way, we know that one of the assumptions used in the deduction is false, but
we do not know which one. So none of the assumptions has been falsified.
Moreover, as the Duhem-Quine thesis holds for any application of Newton’s
first law to explain observable phenomena, it follows that this law is
unfalsifiable.
Popper did attempt to deal with this difficulty. See, for example, his
1
1983, p. 187. But his attempts were not very convincing. Here, however, a
danger arises which I mentioned in the introduction. It is the danger of
throwing out the baby with the bath water. It is perfectly true that there are
some laws such as Newton’s first law which are indeed scientific but which
are not falsifiable because of the Duhem-Quine thesis. This has led some
critics of Popper to conclude that no scientific laws are falsifiable for the
same reason, and that therefore the concept of falsifiablity is useless and
irrelevant for science. Such a conclusion is too extreme in my view. In
every branch of science there is a generally acknowledged class of
observation statements, that is, of singular statements which can come to be
accepted or rejected by the scientific community on the basis of observation
and experiment. There are moreover laws and generalisations which can be
falsified by a finite set of observation statements. ‘All swans are white’ was
indeed falsified by the observation of black swans in Australia. Kepler’s
first law that planets move in ellipses with the Sun at one focus could be
falsified by a finite set of astronomical observations of a planet which did
not lie on an ellipse. In a sense this did happen historically since accurate
observations of the planets did show small deviations from an ellipse owing
to the gravitational attractions of other planets. However Kepler’s first law
continues to hold to a high degree of approximation although it could easily
be falsified by observing some curious planetary behaviour.
So falsifiablility is part of the story but not the whole story. This
suggests that we might divide scientific hypotheses into two levels. Level 1
7
hypotheses are falsifiable, while level 2 hypotheses, such as Newton’s first
law, are not falsifiable but still confirmable. Metaphysical statements,
however, would be too far removed from the empirical basis to be even
confirmable. This amounts to taking confirmability rather than falsifiability
as the demarcation criterion separating science from metaphysics.
Popper had, in effect , a 3 level model. The 3 levels being observation
statements, scientific hypotheses, and metaphysical statements. My
suggestion is to replace this by a 4 level model in which scientific
hypotheses are divided into those which are falsifiable and those which are
not falsifiable but which are still confirmable. This 4 level model is shown
in Figure 1.
Figure 1
8
observations but only as the result of the complicated process of a scientific
revolution. This is what one would expect of level 2 theories which cannot
be knocked out by a single observational blow, but only undermined by a
series of disconfirming instances. However there still exist level 1 theories
to which Popper’s concept of falsifiability and so his methodology of
conjectures and refutations can apply.
Secondly let us consider one of these level 1 hypotheses, namely
Kepler’s first law that all planets move in ellipses with the Sun at one focus.
This law can be tested by observing a sequence of positions of a planet and
checking whether these lie on an ellipse of the required type. If they do not,
the law is falsified. If they do, the law is confirmed. I propose to call this
type of confirmation: direct confirmation. Now Kepler’s first law, in an
approximate form, can be deduced from Newton’s theory together of course
with some auxiliary assumptions. This opens up a channel for some indirect
confirmation of Kepler’s first law. Newton’s theory is confirmed not only
by observations on the planets, but by observations on the tides, on the
motion of pendula, on the motion of projectiles etc. Since these
observations confirm Newton’s theory and since Kepler’s first law in an
approximate form is derivable from Newton’s theory, it follows that
Kepler’s first law is indirectly confirmed by these observations on the tides,
on pendula, etc. which, prior to the introduction of Newton’s theory might
well have seemed completely irrelevant to Kepler’s laws.
Popper himself makes what is essentially this point but using a
different terminology and with a different though related example. He writes
(1972, p. 20):
“Thus I assert that with the corroboration of Newton’s theory, and the
description of the earth as a rotating planet, the degree of corroboration of
the statement s ‘The sun rises in Rome once in every twenty-four hours’ has
greatly increased. For, on its own, s is not very well testable; but Newton’s
theory, and the theory of the rotation of the earth are well testable. And if
these are true, s will be true also.”
To put the point again, this time in Kuhnian terms that Popper would not
of course accept., a law which is derivable from the core assumptions of an
accepted paradigm gains indirect confirmation in addition to any direct
confirmation which it obtains from being tested out by observation and
experiment. Suppose, however, that a level 1 law is tested out and
confirmed by observation and experiment, but that, far from agreeing with
the core, level 2, theories of the dominant paradigm, it contradicts them.
Then the direct confirmation of the law is reduced by the indirect
disconfirmation arising out of its disagreement with the dominant paradigm.
9
This point will be important in our discussion of alternative medicine in the
next section.
5. Alternative Medicine
11
that these hard-headed science lovers would have dismissed alternative
medicine as mumbo-jumbo.
Popper, however, had a different attitude. He held that metaphysics
can be not only meaningful but even useful for science. Indeed a
metaphysical theory might suggest a scientific conjecture. Popper’s views
could lead to a much more sympathetic appraisal of scientific medicine.
For example the theory of qi, while not scientific, might still be regarded as
meaningful and as suggestive of conjectures regarding what kinds of
acupuncture treatment might prove effective. However, a Popperian would
need to make an important proviso in any such defence of CAM. Any
conjecture to the effect that a particular type of treatment might be effective
would have to be severely tested to see whether it was corroborated or
refuted. Now randomised control trials (or RCTs) are usually considered the
best way of testing whether a treatment works. Thus a Popperian would
probably require the testing of alternative therapies using RCTs.
In fact in the last decade or so there has been a movement called
Evidence Based Medicine or EBM. EBM arranges evidence in a hierarchy
with RCTs at the top. Kirstin Borgerson in her 2005 article: ‘Evidence-
Based Alternative Medicine?’ considers how CAM should react to EBM.
She argues that there are 3 options (p. 504):
There are other objections to RCTs. For example one study shows (quoted
by Borgerson on p. 506, Ftnte 1) that “a large percentage (roughly estimated
around 80%) of medical treatments currently offered in hospitals and clinics
across North America have never been tested by an RCT.” Thus higher
standards, it is claimed, are unfairly being imposed on CAM treatments.
There is also the point that RCTs are expensive to carry out. Pharmaceutical
companies have the money to finance such trials, but many CAM enthusiasts
are not so rich.
What then about Borgerson’s other two options. The second accepts
the EBM hierarchy of evidence, but claims that CAM has to use only forms
of evidence lower down the hierarchy. However, this suggests that CAM
must always be inferior. Borgerson suggests that it is probably a better
strategy for CAM to adopt option 3, i.e. to challenge EBM’s evidence
hierarchy. This line is taken by Barry in her 2006 article. She claims that
CAM should be supported by the kind of evidence used by anthropologists.
Her idea is that to test for example homeopathy a researcher should join the
homeopathy community in the way that anthropological researchers join
primitive tribes. Like such anthropologists, homeopathic observers should
report what they find. Barry’s findings sound favourable to homeopathy.
She says (p. 2654):
“Users of homeopathy did not see a need for scientific testing and were
happy with their judgement of whether the treatment was working for them.”
And again:
13
“Evidence for them was the evidence of their own eyes and embodied
experiences.”
The problem with this approach is that users can easily be deceived as to
whether a treatment they receive is effective. Suppose they take the
treatment and after a period of time, they feel a lot better. They may be
convinced that the treatment is very good. However, the body has natural
recuperative powers and the improvement may have been entirely owing to
these. Indeed the treatment might even have slowed the natural healing
process which would perhaps have occurred more quickly without any
treatment.
“ … the critical attitude would imply that the medical establishment should
be open-minded to alternatives and investigate them eagerly.
And if some inspiration can be found in CAM, all the better.”
Actually this has happened to some extent. There have been some
studies of possible mechanisms of acupuncture in terms not of qi theory but
of modern neuroscience. Kaptchuk has this to say (p. 379):
So on this account the subtle pain caused by the needles raises the level of
endorphins and enkephalins which in turn overcomes the original pain.
Doctors who take this approach may use acupuncture to relieve pain without
paying much attention to the traditional acupuncture points based on the
supposed meridians and flow of qi.
One of the curious things about evidence based medicine is that it
pays little or not attention to such basic-science evidence – that is to what we
have called indirect confirmation from level 2 theories. Indeed Borgerson
says (p. 504):
This is surely absurd and contrary to the assessments of most doctors. For
example, Kaptchuk says (p. 379):
16
out, and the same may be true of many of the 80% of treatments which have
been adopted in North American hospitals without RCTs.
Why does EBM make this remarkable mistake about the nature of
evidence? It is tempting to detect the influence of the pharmaceutical
companies here. There are many drugs whose effectiveness is confirmed by
RCTs but which have no indirect confirmation from level 2 scientific
theories. Most anti-depressants fall into this category. It is in the interest of
the pharmaceutical companies to say that there is very strong evidence in
favour of using such drugs, whereas it would probably be fairer to say that
the evidence in favour of using such drugs is rather weak. Indeed there have
been many problems with such drugs. If the mechanism of a drug is not
understood in terms of basic science, it may well be producing short term
benefits at the expense of longer term damage and deterioration.
17
Notes
[2] For some preliminary suggestions, see Gillies, 1993, pp. 214-221, but
these stand in need of further development.
[3] As well as the published paper 2002, I have benefited by reading some
of Parusnikova’s unpublished works on this subject and from several
discussions with her about CAM.
18
References
19
Popper, K.R. (1972) Objective Knowledge. An Evolutionary Approach.
Oxford.
20