Essay: A Bargaining Power Theory of Default Rules
Essay: A Bargaining Power Theory of Default Rules
Essay: A Bargaining Power Theory of Default Rules
ESSAY
Omri Ben-Shahar*
This Essay explores the merits of a new criterion for default rules in
incomplete contracts: filling gaps with terms that are favorable to the party
with the greater bargaining power. It argues that some of the more common
gaps in contracts involve purely distributive issues, such as the contract
price, for which it is impossible to choose a unique, joint-maximizing, “most
efficient” term. Instead, the term that mimics the hypothetical bargain in
these settings must be sensitive to the bargaining power of the parties—the
term they would have chosen to divide the surplus in light of their relative
bargaining strengths. This Essay explores the justifications for such a bar-
gain-mimicking principle, the ways in which it could be implemented by
courts, and the subtle ways it is already in place.
INTRODUCTION
How to fill gaps in incomplete agreements is perhaps the most im-
portant question in contract law. It is important both because courts
often interpret and supplement contracts and because the default rules
set by law determine how contracts will be written. One of the greater
successes of the economic approach to contracts is the development of
systematic ways to think about gap filling.1 The most broadly accepted
principle of gap filling is that courts should “mimic the parties’ will.”2
Under this principle, only gap fillers that mimic what the parties them-
selves would have chosen are allowed to remain in place and survive opt-
out, thereby eliminating unnecessary drafting costs. Of course, the no-
tion of the parties’ will is hypothetical. Because the contract contains a
gap, we do not know what they would have consented to. Here, the eco-
nomic approach provides another powerful insight: The parties’ will is to
have the most efficient arrangement. That is, they are best served by de-
* Frank and Bernice Greenberg Professor of Law, University of Chicago Law School;
omri@uchicago.edu. I am grateful to Ian Ayres, Richard Brooks, Clay Gillette, Bob
Hillman, Ariel Porat, Peter Siegelman, Kathy Zeiler, and workshop participants at the
Universities of Amsterdam, Chicago, Cornell, Duke, Michigan, and NYU for helpful
suggestions. Financial support from the Olin Center at the University of Michigan Law
School is gratefully acknowledged.
1. See Ian Ayres, Valuing Modern Contract Scholarship, 112 Yale L.J. 881, 890–92
(2003) (summarizing contribution of economic analysis to theory of default rules).
2. Richard Craswell, Contract Law: General Theories, in 3 Encyclopedia of Law and
Economics 1, 3–4 (Boudewijn Bouckaert & Gerrit De Geest eds., 2000); see Ian Ayres,
Default Rules for Incomplete Contracts, in 1 The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics
and the Law 585, 586 (Peter Newman ed., 1998).
396
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 2 23-FEB-09 11:10
fault rules that maximize the contractual surplus.3 The idea that gap fill-
ers should maximize the contractual surplus is based on the following
well-known logic. Assuming parties are rational, they would have agreed
upon terms that maximize their joint surplus, irrespective of the distribu-
tive impact of such terms. True, such terms might be more favorable to
one side, but the parties would have corrected for any distributive effects
by appropriately adjusting the contractual price or another purely distrib-
utive term.4 But for this theory to be valid, it must assume that there is at
least one contract term that the parties use to make the appropriate dis-
tributive adjustments—usually the price term—to which the theory does
not apply. The content of the purely distributive terms is not determined
by the surplus-maximizing criterion; it is surplus neutral. Rather, the con-
tent of the purely distributive term is determined by the bargaining
power of the parties. In other words, the surplus-maximizing conception
of gap filling is, by definition, insufficient to resolve all gaps because it
does not resolve gaps in the price term or in any other contract term that
is purely distributive. Thus, there is a troubling paradox surrounding the
basic criterion of gap filling. It assumes that the parties’ joint will exists—
that there is a single term such that, if only the parties spent the time and
attention dealing with the gap, they would have jointly desired the sur-
plus-maximizing term. Yet the existence of a gap in a contract is often an
indication that a consensus could not be reached because a single jointly
preferable term does not exist.5 If the parties’ interests had coincided,
they would have been able to agree on a term. But when the issue is
distributive, the parties’ interests are in conflict, and it is this divergence
of interests that leads to the gap. Ironically, as I will show later, many of
the cases used in contracts casebooks to introduce the topic of indefinite-
ness and gap filling involve purely distributive gaps over issues such as
3. See E. Allen Farnsworth, Contracts 486 (4th ed. 2004) (noting courts may provide
terms “that an economist would describe as maximizing the expected value of the
transaction”); Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law 99 (7th ed. 2007) (“[C]ontract
law cannot readily be used to achieve goals other than efficiency, as a ruling that fails to
interpolate the efficient term will be reversed by the parties in their subsequent dealings.”);
see also Frank H. Easterbrook & Daniel R. Fischel, The Economic Structure of Corporate
Law 21–22 (1991) (stating that gap fillers must duplicate terms that optimally promote
parties’ interests); Mark P. Gergen, The Use of Open Terms in Contract, 92 Colum. L. Rev.
997, 1064–72 (1992) (asserting that default rule should be a joint maximization rule); Alan
Schwartz & Robert E. Scott, Contract Theory and the Limits of Contract Law, 113 Yale L.J.
541, 554 (2003) [hereinafter Schwartz & Scott, Contract Theory] (“Parties jointly choose
the contract terms so as to maximize the surplus, which the price may then divide
unequally.”).
4. See, e.g., George L. Priest, A Theory of the Consumer Product Warranty, 90 Yale
L.J. 1297, 1313 (1981) (pointing out that disclaimers of warranty result in price
adjustments); Schwartz & Scott, Contract Theory, supra note 3, at 554 (“Bargaining power R
instead is exercised in the division of the surplus, which is determined by the price term.”).
5. See, e.g., Omri Ben-Shahar, “Agreeing to Disagree”: Filling Gaps in Deliberately
Incomplete Contracts, 2004 Wis. L. Rev. 389, 399–405 [hereinafter Ben-Shahar, Agreeing
to Disagree] (arguing that gaps in contracts are often created deliberately when parties fail
to agree on a negotiated provision).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 3 23-FEB-09 11:10
price, for which the prescription “choose the terms that maximize the
total surplus” does not provide a definite solution. For example, in
Oglebay Norton v. Armco, two large companies had a long-term relational
contract for transportation of iron ore, but ended up in a bitter legal
dispute about the price.6 Their agreement originally had a price
formula, but over time this formula failed and needed to be revised.
When the parties turned to the court to help fill the price gap, there was
no single term that reflected the “market price” which the court could
invoke.7 Indeed, if there were such a price, the parties would not have
needed the court to supply it. Of course, there was no “surplus-maximiz-
ing” price to fill the gap because price is surplus-neutral. Instead, the
court had to supply a “reasonable” gap filler that was purely distributive.
It ended up doing so by splitting the difference in a creative and unortho-
dox manner, forcing the companies’ CEOs to meet and mediate the fu-
ture price.8 And yet, the difficulty the court encountered and the ad hoc
solution it found merely emphasize the absence of a systematic and ra-
tional criterion for filling such gaps. The purpose of this Essay is to begin
developing a systematic new gap-filling criterion for these distributive
price gaps.
The proposed criterion, which I label the “bargain-mimicking” gap
filler, is consistent with the fundamental norms of mimicking the parties’
will. In cases of purely distributive terms there is no joint will. Instead,
each party’s will is to have a term at the more favorable end of a range of
reasonable terms. What courts need, then, is more information about
how parties would have resolved their a priori conflict of wills. Specifi-
cally, a court needs information that would help it mimic the bargain: the
division of surplus that the parties would have struck given their relative
bargaining powers. Since the division of bargaining power between two
parties may be uneven, the gap filler in these situations would be differ-
ent than the midrange “market” term. When one party has greater bar-
gaining power, the gap filler should tilt to favor this party, because this is
the party whose will would have more likely prevailed if an explicit bar-
gain were struck. Purely distributive gaps, therefore, would be filled with
terms more favorable to the party with greater bargaining power.
At first blush this criterion might seem unfair. As a normative crite-
rion, it is counterintuitive. Uneven bargaining power is hardly a desirable
phenomenon; why then should it be mimicked? I will defend its more
subtle appeal later in this Essay, but the core claim is perhaps less objec-
tionable than it initially seems and can be illuminated with a nonlegal
example. Take, for example, an incomplete command issued by a parent
to a child to “mow the lawn.” If imperfectly specified, it needs supple-
mentation—“only the front yard” or “both the front yard and the back
9. U.C.C. § 2-305(1)–(2) & cmt. 3 (2004) (establishing that one party may be
accorded power to set price, but must do so in good faith).
10. See, e.g., D.R. Curtis, Co. v. Mathews, 653 P.2d 1188, 1189, 1191 (Idaho Ct. App.
1982) (using original price set by middleman in damages calculation, even though final
price was not set by contract).
11. For example, the doctrine of duress is often justified as redressing the disparity of
bargaining power. See, e.g., John P. Dawson, Economic Duress—An Essay in Perspective,
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 5 23-FEB-09 11:10
as examples, default rules that try to upset the potential bargaining out-
come are undesirable because they are a futile effort—the parties can
always opt out of them, and strong parties likely will. Moreover, the anal-
ysis in Part II illustrates that the traditional justifications for default
rules—saved transactions costs, facilitating entry into desirable forms of
relationship, and inducing optimal reliance—also apply to the bargain-
mimicking conception of gap filling.
Part III of this Essay identifies the existence of bargain-mimicking
gap fillers in current contract law. It demonstrates how this idea was im-
plemented in leading cases, although without courts always recognizing
that their decisions relied on—or at least conformed to—a bargain-mim-
icking principle. In illustrating that courts already do this, I suggest that
it is not institutionally impossible to base a legal rule on a criterion as
elusive as relative bargaining power. This Part also highlights situations
in which the bargain-mimicking idea was rejected, thereby recognizing
that in certain situations the bargain-mimicking idea conflicts with other,
deep-rooted principles of contract law. Finally, Part IV extends the analy-
sis by introducing a problem posed by excessive terms, which go beyond
the threshold of permissible contracting. When such excessive terms are
struck down and need to be replaced, courts are faced with a problem of
gap filling. The original, excessive, term is no longer valid; what should
be put in its place? Here, it is generally clear that one party holds greater
bargaining power, which it employed to dictate the excessive term.12 A
bargain-mimicking term would maintain maximal loyalty to the bargain
struck between the parties by filling the gap with the maximally tolerable
term that remains one-sided and favorable to the party who dictated the
original one-sided term, but which is moderated sufficiently so that it is
tolerable. Instead of substituting the offensive term with the most bal-
anced “majoritarian” term, the court would reduce it only enough to fit
within the range that is considered legitimate. In so doing, the court
would mimic the hypothetical bargain that parties negotiating over a
truncated domain would reach.
I. BARGAIN-MIMICKING TERMS
A. No Joint Will
There is a troubling paradox surrounding one of the most basic ten-
ets of contract law that gaps in contracts should be filled with terms that
mimic the will of the parties—terms that most parties would have jointly
45 Mich. L. Rev. 253, 282–88 (1947) (discussing work of duress doctrine in context of
economic bargaining power). Likewise, weak bargaining power can support a claim of
unconscionability. See, e.g., Shell Oil Co. v. Marinello, 307 A.2d 598, 601 (N.J. 1973)
(declaring that courts may find void a “grossly unfair contractual provision[ ]” when “there
is grossly disproportionate bargaining power”).
12. Many cases of intervention in unconscionable contracts explicitly recognize the
presence of superior bargaining power. See Farnsworth, supra note 3, at 301–02. R
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 6 23-FEB-09 11:10
chosen. On the one hand, this conception of gap filling makes basic
sense: It minimizes the need of the parties to contract around the default
rule, and it spells out performance provisions that maximize the parties’
joint well-being. But on the other hand, the mimic-the-parties’-will prin-
ciple assumes that the parties’ joint will exists. It assumes that there is a
single term such that, if only the parties spent the time and attention
dealing with the gap, they would have jointly supported the drafting of
this term. Yet the existence of a gap in a contract is often an indication
that a consensus could not be reached—that a single jointly preferable
term does not exist. The claim from which the analysis in this paper be-
gins is that there are situations in which more than one term satisfies the
standard conception of the joint will of the parties to a contract. Absent a
more powerful prescription, then, the will-mimicking principle would be
indeterminate and too amorphous to fill the gap.
Put differently, contract design involves two tasks: creating the pie
and dividing it, with many terms affecting both aspects. Principles of sur-
plus maximization are synonymous with the creation of the pie. Once
the maximal pie is created, through a combination of express terms and
surplus-enhancing gap fillers, it has to be divided. But the term that ac-
complishes this aspect has no bearing on the size of the pie. If one of the
distributive terms is missing from the agreement, the surplus-maximizing
conception of gap filling would, by definition, be indeterminate in sup-
plementing it. So what do we do if the gap involves one of these distribu-
tive aspects?
The fundamental reason to doubt whether there is a single joint will
that could be mimicked when the gap involves a distributive issue is that
the parties have opposite interests in resolving this issue. In these set-
tings, it is impossible to articulate solely on the basis of economic effi-
ciency what term the parties would have chosen. The process of reaching
agreement over distributive elements is resolved by bargaining, and is
thus determined by ad hoc factors that affect the parties’ bargaining
power.13 Filling distributive gaps, then, is not an exercise in surplus max-
imization or in figuring out the optimal transaction design, but in guess-
ing how the surplus would have been divided.
Consider, for example, a sales contract that does not specify payment
terms. There are many ways to supplement this gap, but it can hardly be
said that the different modalities for payment affect the size of the pie. In
many cases, whether payment is made before, during, or after delivery, is
merely a matter of the time value of money, and it would affect the well-
being of the parties in a zero-sum fashion. There is no more or no less
efficient arrangement; the only effect is distributive. As a result, there is
no joint will to mimic. Earlier payment is usually preferable to the seller
13. See, e.g., Martin J. Osborne & Ariel Rubinstein, Bargaining and Markets 50–55
(1990) (showing that strategic bargaining power depends on bargaining procedure;
parties’ relative costs of delay and relative patience; outside options; and more).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 7 23-FEB-09 11:10
to the same extent that it is detrimental to the buyer. The seller, there-
fore, has one will, while the buyer has another.
How, you might wonder, could parties enter a binding contract with-
out specifying the surplus division and leaving the price term out? Is this
scenario realistic? Not only is this scenario possible, but some of the most
prominent cases on contractual indefiniteness involve gaps in the price
term, the one term that by definition has a purely distributive effect. For
example, one of the leading cases, Joseph Martin, Jr., Delicatessen, Inc. v.
Schumacher, involved a lease of commercial property with an option to
renew under an indefinite price, the contract stating that the renewal
price needed “to be agreed upon.”14 Another classic case, Sun Printing &
Publishing Ass’n v. Remington Paper & Power Co., involved a sales contract
that contained an indefinite price formula.15 Furthermore, sales law
casebooks typically devote a chapter to the case law of commercial con-
tracts with missing price terms—a scenario that is fully anticipated by sec-
tion 2-305 of the Uniform Commercial Code and other international
sales law provisions.16
Courts and commentators may disagree whether such distributive
gaps render contracts too indefinite to be enforced.17 The missing price,
it is sometimes argued, is a conclusive indication that the parties have not
yet intended to be bound, since they left the most essential term for fur-
ther assent.18 And yet, modern contract law tends to conclude that a
14. 417 N.E.2d 541, 542 (N.Y. 1981). In that case, the court refused to fill the gap and
held that the contract was too indefinite to be enforced. Id. at 543–44. But the growing
trend is to enforce such contracts. See, e.g., Daniel E. Feld, Annotation, Validity and
Enforceability of Provision for Renewal of Lease at Rental to Be Fixed by Subsequent
Agreement of the Parties, 58 A.L.R.3d 500, 503–06 (1974) (surveying case law on lease
renewals subject to price agreement).
15. 139 N.E. 470, 470 (N.Y. 1923) (examining role of mutual assent in interpreting
open terms and agreements to agree). See generally Sw. Eng’g Co. v. Martin Tractor Co.,
473 P.2d 18 (Kan. 1970) (addressing gap filling where payment and credit terms—
elements that are purely distributive—are not fully specified); Mantell v. Int’l Plastic
Harmonica Corp., 55 A.2d 250 (N.J. 1947) (addressing gap filling in contract in which
price was deliberately left out and yet court was more than ready to supply it).
16. U.C.C. § 2-305 (2004) (“The parties if they so intend may conclude a contract for
sale even if the price is not settled.”); see also United Nations Convention on Contracts for
the International Sale of Goods (CISG) art. 55, Apr. 11, 1980, S. Treaty Doc. No. 98-9
(1986), 1489 U.N.T.S. 59, 69 (implying price where contract was validly concluded but
without a price); Int’l Inst. for the Unification of Private Law, UNIDROIT Principles of
International Commercial Contracts art. 5.1.7 (2004) [hereinafter UNIDROIT Principles]
(same); Bruce W. Frier & James J. White, The Modern Law of Contracts 256–89 (2005)
(discussing interpretation of contract terms); Richard E. Speidel & Linda J. Rusch,
Commercial Transactions: Sales, Leases and Licenses 174–203 (2d ed. 2001) (discussing
effect of open contract terms).
17. See Feld, supra note 14, at 503–06 (surveying different approaches taken by R
courts); see also sources cited in Ben-Shahar, Agreeing to Disagree, supra note 5, at 395–96 R
nn.15–19 (citing sources that describe some reasons why case outcomes differ).
18. See, e.g., Walker v. Keith, 382 S.W.2d 198, 203–04 (Ky. 1964) (finding that missing
price indicates lack of mutual assent); U.C.C. § 2-305 cmt. 2 (“Under some circumstances
the postponement of agreement on price will mean that no deal has really been
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 8 23-FEB-09 11:10
ces.21 Or, they may expect that, if needed, a third party can arbitrate or
split their difference.22 In all these cases, if the price resolution mecha-
nism subsequently fails, courts are presented with the reality that disput-
ing parties entered a binding contract but left out a crucial distributive
term.
21. This is the typical situation in lease agreements with a tenant option to renew
upon its expiration.
22. See U.C.C. § 2-305(1)(c) & cmt. 4 (recognizing situation in which third party’s
judgment as to price is used to fill gap).
23. Craswell, supra note 2, at 3–4. R
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 10 23-FEB-09 11:10
greater the seller’s bargaining power, the higher the interest rate that the
gap filler would supply. And conversely, the greater the buyer’s bargain-
ing power, the more lenient the credit terms.
Another example of a gap filler that would tilt in favor of one party
arises in auto manufacturing contracts. Sellers, known as “tier-1” suppli-
ers, compete through a bidding process to produce auto parts to be as-
sembled into a car model manufactured by an automaker.24 Because
there are only a few automakers but many suppliers, the buyer in this
setting has much of the bargaining power. And indeed, once the sup-
plier is selected and the price is set, the buyer dictates all the remaining
terms of the contract, including price adjustments over time.25 The stan-
dard form contracts utilized in the auto industry, however, are short and
contain many gaps.26 For example, they often leave the price under
which “service parts” will be sold unspecified.27 Service parts, which are
sold to dealers and car owners in the retail market for a substantial pre-
mium, are a significant source of profits, but how should this surplus be
divided between the automaker and the parts supplier in the absence of a
specific agreement? There is no “market” term to refer to because there
is no competitive market. There is only a single seller who sets different
prices for different buyers. A midrange, split-the-profit price is one way
to fill the gap. Of course, it would not reflect the parties’ relative bargain-
ing powers. Nor would it come close to mimicking the express deal they
would have reached—that is, the deal the buyer would have dictated, and
that some automakers do in fact dictate.28 The bargain-mimicking gap
filler, by contrast, would supply a price that accords the greater share of
the premium to the buyer.
The content of a bargain-mimicking gap filler is fact dependent and
specifically tailored to the contracting parties. The same contract, with
the same gap, can be filled with a pro-seller term in one case and a pro-
buyer term in another, depending on the parties’ relative bargaining
power in each case. For example, a lease with an option to renew under a
24. See Omri Ben-Shahar & James J. White, Boilerplate and Economic Power in Auto
Manufacturing Contracts, 104 Mich. L. Rev. 953, 961–63 (2006) (describing contracting
process in auto manufacturing).
25. Id. at 963–64.
26. For example, General Motors, who in 2004 entered into close to one million
procurement transactions for a total volume of $80 billion, used for all these contracts a
short, thirty-one paragraph, standard form. Id. at 957.
27. Id. at 961; see, e.g., Toyota Motors Mfg. N. Am., Inc., Terms and Conditions § 4.2
(Oct. 1, 1998) (leaving price for service parts to be determined later). Due to the
confidential nature of this contract, the Columbia Law Review does not have a copy of it on
file.
28. For example, Nissan’s contract forces suppliers to commit to selling the service
parts for fifteen years at the price negotiated during the production phase, which is
typically the lowest possible price and the one that accords the entire surplus from the
service parts market to the buyer. Nissan N. Am., Inc., Master Purchase Agreement art. 19
(2003), available at http://www.butzel.com/AutoIndustry/080907tcNissan_AI.pdf (on file
with the Columbia Law Review).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 11 23-FEB-09 11:10
appropriate a term more favorable than the midrange default rule. The
agreement that results from midrange gap filling is distinctly different
from that which she would have expressly negotiated. The more gaps she
leaves, the greater the wedge between the hypothetical agreement and
the legally supplemented contract. It is this discontinuity—the diver-
gence between the hypothetically negotiated deal and the legally-implied
deal—that the proposed conception of gap filling resolves. The closer
the gap fillers are to the hypothetical bargain, the smaller the divergence.
In many distributive contexts, the bargain-mimicking criterion would
prescribe terms that are significantly different from the midrange, rea-
sonable terms that would be prescribed by the majoritarian criterion.
Specifically, the majoritarian criterion recognizes that different parties
could have reached different reasonable terms and that there is a distri-
bution of bargained-for terms. Accordingly, it fills contract gaps with a
term that measures a “center” of this distribution.32 Unlike the
majoritarian criterion, the bargain-mimicking criterion relies on specific
information that reflects the division of bargaining power, and conse-
quently the deal, that these particular parties would have come to.
Still, it would be a mistake to conclude from this discussion that the
bargain-mimicking gap fillers would always diverge from the majoritarian,
midrange gap fillers. The two gap-filling criteria may prescribe the same
content of gap filler in situations where the bargaining positions of the
parties are relatively equal. In these situations, information about the
specific parties’ bargaining does not change the inference about the hy-
pothetical bargain. For example, if the parties are price-takers, dealing in
matters for which there is a thick market and neither is uniquely posi-
tioned within this market, it is likely that the term they would have agreed
upon is the same term that most parties in the market adopt.33 Similarly,
if bargaining power is determined by outside options, and if there is a
thick market of alternative partners for each party, the terms of that bar-
gain will necessarily be influenced by the terms in that market.34 In these
situations, the bargain-mimicking principle would prescribe a term that
reflects the market term. But unlike the majoritarian principle, it would
do so not because this term best reflects some statistical regularity regard-
ing the market, but rather because it is the best guess as to each party’s
relative purchasing power. Put differently, majoritarian gap fillers that
refer to “reasonable market prices” will be consistent with the bargain-
35. See James Gordley, Foundations of Private Law 363 (2006) (“[T]he market price
preserves (so far as possible) each party’s share of purchasing power.”).
36. 55 A.2d 250, 254 (N.J. 1947).
37. Id. at 254–55.
38. Id. at 256.
39. See, e.g., Osborne & Rubinstein, supra note 13, at 29–65 (analyzing factors that R
affect bargaining outcome).
40. Robert Pindyck & Daniel Rubinfeld, Microeconomics 357–58 (6th ed. 2005).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 14 23-FEB-09 11:10
41. See, e.g., Carboni v. Arrospide, 2 Cal. Rptr. 2d 845, 850 (Ct. App. 1991) (“[T]here
was an inequality of bargaining power which effectively robbed [promisor] of any
meaningful choice.”); see also UNIDROIT Principles, supra note 16, art. 3.10(1) (listing R
“lack of bargaining skill” as factor relevant to determination of unconscionability).
42. See, e.g., Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 176 cmt. f (1979) (discussing
improper threats in bargaining process).
43. Id. § 206 cmt. a.
44. See, e.g., Circuit City Stores, Inc. v. Adams, 279 F.3d 889, 893 (9th Cir. 2002)
(reasoning that employer “possesse[d] considerably more bargaining power than . . . its
employees” such that employees had to “take the contract or leave it”).
45. See generally Omri Ben-Shahar & Lisa Bernstein, The Secrecy Interest in Contract
Law, 109 Yale L.J. 1885 (2000) (discussing interest of contracting parties in concealing
information for strategic purposes).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 15 23-FEB-09 11:10
inability to agree.46 Or, they may result from the stronger party’s strate-
gic calculation to leave an issue open, recognizing that on this specific
issue the weaker party would not acquiesce to a one-sided term or would
be alerted to some hidden unfavorable aspect of the deal. If the stronger
party suppressed a specific issue and deliberately left a gap, it could actu-
ally be an indication of the limits of her bargaining power. In other
words, it could be a reflection of the fact that in an explicit agreement
she could not extract the one-sided term she coveted. Here, the bargain-
mimicking term would not necessarily favor the stronger party, and grant-
ing her a favorable gap filler would encourage her to leave gaps in all
areas in which she cannot bargain for an advantage. Instead of mimick-
ing the bargain, then, this regime could distort it.
Thus, the craft of filling gaps with bargain-mimicking terms is more
nuanced than merely identifying the party with the greater overall bar-
gaining power. It requires attention to the specific issue left open and
the parties’ special concerns regarding this issue. Recognizing that a bar-
gain usually involves some concessions even by the overall stronger party,
and recognizing that some leverage has already been spent on other, ex-
pressly drafted terms, the court must figure out how the parties would
have used their remaining bargaining power over this specific term.
Daunting as this task might first appear, it is probably not more com-
plicated than other gap-filling principles. For example, under the sur-
plus-maximizing principle, figuring out which term is most efficient re-
quires a sophisticated account of costs and benefits, an understanding of
how different terms and issues interact, and a perception of what each
party values more—all with an eye to idiosyncratic preferences.47 Here,
too, some terms cannot be supplemented without careful attention to
other aspects of the deal. Still, the surplus-maximization criterion has
broad appeal because it makes normative sense, despite the fact that it is
harder to implement than other, simpler default rules. It is socially desir-
able to instruct courts to make the effort to apply the surplus-maximiza-
tion criterion, even crudely, because the benefit arising from more effi-
cient obligations is worth the adjudicative cost. In the next section, I
propose a normative defense of the bargain-mimicking criterion, sug-
gesting that here too it is a worthy effort to trace the bargain that parties
would have struck. And, at the very least, when courts do have accurate
information about the bargain-mimicking term, it ought not be ignored.
46. See Ben-Shahar, Agreeing to Disagree, supra note 5, at 402–05 (arguing that gaps R
in contracts often result from failed attempts to agree on negotiated provision).
47. See, e.g., Mkt. St. Assocs. Ltd. P’ship v. Frey, 941 F.2d 588, 593–95 (7th Cir. 1991)
(demonstrating various factors that need to be evaluated in figuring out how to interpret
gap in contract).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 16 23-FEB-09 11:10
A. Transaction Costs
When a contract gap involves an issue affecting the size of the sur-
plus, a well-rehearsed argument explains why the gap filler ought to be a
surplus-maximizing provision.48 It is an argument of exceptional appeal
because it sidesteps any distributive implications. Surplus-maximizing
gap fillers indiscriminately increase the well-being of both parties to the
contract. If the law were to provide off-the-shelf terms that were anything
but surplus-maximizing, it would have the effect of inducing parties to
write explicit provisions which, other than occasional indirect benefits, as,
for example the exposure of private information, would merely increase
transaction costs.49 But once the price or other distributive term is ad-
justed appropriately to divide the savings in transaction costs, each party
ends up with a greater net payoff.
One might assume that in the context of bargain-mimicking terms
this same distributive-neutral defense is inapplicable. In other words, if
the law provides a gap filler that is more favorable to one of the parties,
without affecting the size of the surplus, how can it be said that this term
accords both parties a greater surplus to divide? If it is a term that mimics
one party’s will, against the will of the other party, how could the other
party benefit from it?
Moreover, upon first reflection, bargain-mimicking terms might
seem to encounter an objection that surplus-maximizing terms avoid—
namely, that they conflict with social concerns and intuitions regarding
the fairness of distribution. While surplus-maximizing terms need not
have any distributive effect—they merely secure more value to divide—
bargain-mimicking terms do not create a greater surplus and do have a
clear distributive effect in favor of the stronger party. Why, one might
ask, should it be the law’s objective to resolve distributive ambiguities and
gaps in favor of the stronger party when the overall welfare of the parties
is not enhanced? Surely, this party can take good care of herself and
48. See, e.g., Robert E. Scott, Rethinking the Default Rule Project, 6 Va. J. 84, 94 n.4
(2003) (“[C]hoosing a default rule on the basis of some normative conception of fairness
would be wrong, in the sense that it would not increase the amount of fair contracts in the
world, but it would increase the amount of contracting costs . . . .”); see also sources cited
supra note 3. R
49. Posner, supra note 3, at 96–99 (“[C]ontract law cannot readily be used to achieve R
goals other than efficiency, as a ruling that fails to interpolate the efficient term will be
reversed by the parties in their subsequent dealings.”).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 17 23-FEB-09 11:10
50. See, e.g., id. at 95–96 (explaining mutual benefit to parties of leaving gaps in
contract for contingencies that are unlikely to occur).
51. See, e.g., David A. Lax & James K. Sebenius, The Manager as Negotiator 112–13
(1986) (highlighting cooperative bargainer’s concern for preservation of “self-esteem” and
“helping counterparts to save face when necessary”); Robert H. Mnookin, Scott R. Peppet
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 18 23-FEB-09 11:10
their counterparts a sense that the pie is equally divided, even when it is
not, to make it easier for their opponents to acquiesce.52 A default rule
that eases the need for stronger parties to openly “stick it” to weaker par-
ties has this cost-mitigating effect.
& Andrew S. Tulumello, Beyond Winning: Negotiating to Create Value in Deals and
Disputes 44–68 (2000) (asserting that expressing “concern and respect” during
negotiations “tend[s] to defuse anger and mistrust, especially where these emotions stem
from feeling unappreciated or exploited”).
52. See Richard H. Thaler, The Winner’s Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of
Economic Life 21–35 (1992) (surveying experimental research that shows that parties with
less bargaining power will nevertheless refuse to accept deals in which they are treated
unequally).
53. See, e.g., Alan Schwartz, Relational Contracts in the Courts: An Analysis of
Incomplete Agreements and Judicial Strategies, 21 J. Legal Stud. 271, 284–90 (1992)
(analyzing reasons for incompleteness of long-term contracts).
54. This technique is common in auto manufacturing contracts. The big auto
manufacturers stipulate in long-term contracts with their suppliers that replacement parts
will be sold at a price that will be agreed upon later. See, e.g., Gen. Motors, General Terms
and Conditions § 20 (rev. Sept. 2004) (“[T]he price(s) during the first 3 years of this
period shall be those in effect at the conclusion of current model purchases. For the
remainder of this period, the price(s) for goods shall be agreed to by the parties.”); Toyota
Motors Mfg. N. Am., Inc., supra note 27, § 4.2(d) (“[Toyota] will establish, after good faith
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 19 23-FEB-09 11:10
negotiations with Supplier, a price for Service Parts.”). Due to the confidential nature of
these contracts, the Columbia Law Review does not have copies of them on file.
55. White & Summers, supra note 33, at 231. R
56. For example, in the case law favorite Feld v. Henry S. Levy & Sons, Inc., 335
N.E.2d 320, 321 (N.Y. 1975), the parties had an output contract for breadcrumbs. The
seller was entitled to set the quantity but did not have much bargaining power and indeed
failed to induce the buyer to agree to pay for a cost increase of one cent per pound. Id.
57. See, e.g., Mathis v. Exxon Corp., 302 F.3d 448, 452–54 (5th Cir. 2002) (illustrating
that oil companies follow one-sided pricing practices); Shell Oil Co. v. HRN Inc., 144
S.W.3d 429, 432–33 (Tex. 2004) (same).
58. U.C.C. § 2-305(2) & cmt. 3 (2004); White & Summers, supra note 33, at 226–34 R
(surveying cases in which courts applied good faith limitation to scrutinize price
adjustment).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 20 23-FEB-09 11:10
59. U.C.C. § 2-305(1)(c) & cmt. 4 (applying to cases in which a particular person is
chosen to set price); White & Summers, supra note 33, at 232 (providing examples for R
such formulae).
60. U.C.C. § 2-309(2).
61. Id. (“[U]nless otherwise agreed [the contract] may be terminated at any time by
either party.” (emphasis added)).
62. See, e.g., Corenswet, Inc. v. Amana Refrigeration, Inc., 594 F.2d 129, 131 (5th Cir.
1979) (describing manufacturer’s termination of distribution contract and holding
“arbitrary termination . . . permissible under both the contract and the law of Iowa”).
63. Id. at 132 (detailing distributor’s claim that it made investment in relationship
that would be squandered if contract was terminated). Indeed, this nowhere-to-go
problem is often the case in termination of franchise contracts. See, e.g., Gillian K.
Hadfield, Problematic Relations: Franchising and the Law of Incomplete Contracts, 42
Stan. L. Rev. 927, 951–53 (1990) (discussing problem of relationship-specific investment).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 21 23-FEB-09 11:10
of the stronger party. With this safeguard in place, the stronger party is
free to use a variety of terms she could not otherwise use. First, she is free
to use an open-ended duration. Second, she can give the other party
leeway and control over aspects of performance without specifying them
in the contract, since she knows that if these privileges are abused she can
simply terminate the contract. Finally, she can choose a lesser-known
bidder.
A final example where a bargain-mimicking criterion might affect
the way parties design their bargain is a prenuptial agreement. Imagine a
situation in which a billionaire is about to marry a person with no assets.
It is plausible to suggest that the billionaire has greater bargaining power
regarding the financial consequences of divorce. In the event of divorce,
a gap filler that tracks this bargaining advantage would differ significantly
from one that provides a more generous distribution to the less affluent
spouse. It is true that in noncommercial settings bargaining power may
be particularly elusive because bargaining power is not simply equivalent
to financial prowess. There are obvious factors other than wealth that
affect each party’s relative eagerness to enter the relationship and thus
his or her relative power to say “no” to versions of the prenuptial agree-
ment proposed by the other party. And yet, bargaining power surely ex-
ists—it is often played out in express prenuptial bargains. Allowing the
parties to leave some aspects vague, by assuring them that their relative
bargaining power will be reflected ex post, might relieve them of the
costly and often damaging need to punctuate who has the upper hand ex
ante.
C. Ex Ante Investment
The analysis so far has assumed that the relative bargaining power of
the parties is an exogenous factor, determined before the parties enter
the negotiations. In reality, many features may affect bargaining power:
outside options, impatience to reach a deal, reputation, financial distress,
negotiation savvy, and more.64 The implicit assumption so far was that
none of these factors depend on the gap-filling methodology. Thus, the
premise was that gap fillers could be a function of the relative bargaining
power of the parties, but not vice versa. But can the cause-and-effect be
reversed? Is it possible that the gap-filling rule would induce parties to
make investments in increasing their bargaining power?
Theoretically, a bargain-mimicking regime could create incentives
for parties to make investments that affect their bargaining power. Of
course, parties already have a motive to invest in strengthening their bar-
gaining power because such actions will help them secure better express
terms in the deal. But in the shadow of bargain-mimicking gap fillers, the
incentive to manipulate bargaining positions would be bolstered. Invest-
64. See supra note 13 and accompanying text (exploring factors that affect bargaining R
outcomes).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 22 23-FEB-09 11:10
ing in stronger bargaining power would now affect not only the explicit
provisions, but also the gap fillers.
It is not clear what to make of these potential effects. Prima facie,
much of the investment in bargaining leverage is a social waste—it is a
social cost that redistributes value without creating a corresponding social
benefit.65 This could suggest that a bargain-mimicking regime would
have the undesirable effect of further distorting already excessive
investments.
But the picture is more complex. There are other types of precon-
tractual investments—such as those having an effect on the total surplus
of the potential bargain, and not on relative bargaining power—that are
often set too low. Specifically, where parties are exposed to the holdup
problem, the anticipation that some of the fruit of this investment will be
appropriated by the other party may induce them to set investment too
low.66 If the party who makes the surplus-enhancing investment is also
the one who is in a position to make the bargaining-leverage investment,
it is no longer clear that the latter investment is a social waste. Investing
in greater bargaining leverage would have an indirect positive effect: It
would diminish the other party’s ability to engage in hold up and would
thus lead to a more efficient level of surplus-creating investments. For
example, a builder who successfully acquires an exclusive position in a
specific market would be able, in the course of negotiating a project with
a client, to make precontractual investments in plans and materials since
he knows his bargaining leverage will shield him from hold up.
Moreover, sometimes the same investment has both a surplus-en-
hancing effect and a bargaining-leverage effect. For example, a potential
employee who invests in learning a specialized skill increases the overall
surplus from the employment arrangement, but at the same time gains
more leverage in negotiating her wages and securing a bigger slice of the
surplus for herself. The incentive to invest too much to enhance bargain-
ing leverage is at least partially offset by the incentive to invest too little
because of the holdup problem. The bargain-mimicking legal regime,
which amplifies the “too much” side of this trade off, is not necessarily
bad.
In the end, though, whatever effect the bargain-mimicking gap-fill-
ing regime has on ex ante investment, one should doubt whether this
effect is significant. Parties have strong incentives to make investments
that increase their bargaining power even in the absence of this gap-fill-
ing regime. Such investments secure greater payoffs through the more
65. See, e.g., David M. Frankel, Creative Bargaining, 23 Games & Econ. Beh. 43,
49–50 (1998) (proving parties overinvest in creative strategies that improve their
bargaining position).
66. See, e.g., Lucian Arye Bebchuk & Omri Ben-Shahar, Precontractual Reliance, 30 J.
Legal Stud. 423, 431 (2001) (showing parties will make insufficient investments in
relationship in absence of precontractual liability).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 23 23-FEB-09 11:10
favorable express terms that the investing party can draft. Ex ante, the
incremental effect of a gap-filling regime would probably be negligible.
71. See, e.g., C & J Fertilizer, Inc. v. Allied Mut. Ins. Co., 227 N.W.2d 169, 176–81
(Iowa 1975) (analyzing interpretation doctrines for insurance contracts); Kenneth S.
Abraham, The Expectations Principle as a Regulative Ideal, 5 Conn. Ins. L.J. 59, 63–64
(1998) (exploring foundations of reasonable expectation doctrine).
72. See, e.g., Kenneth S. Abraham, Insurance Law and Regulation 33–37 (3d ed.
2000) (discussing value of interpreted terms); Michelle E. Boardman, Contra Proferentem:
The Allure of Ambiguous Boilerplate, in Boilerplate: The Foundation of Market Contracts
176, 180 (Omri Ben-Shahar ed., 2007) (discussing reasons why insurance companies do
not redraft).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 25 23-FEB-09 11:10
B. Examples
This section demonstrates instances in which courts explicitly recog-
nize a bargain-mimicking criterion for gap filling and reach decisions in
line with it. It does not argue that the bargain-mimicking criterion is uni-
versally applied. Instead, the argument—by way of examples—is more
modest, asserting that the bargain-mimicking criterion is not as alien to
the task of judicial gap filling as might otherwise seem.
1. Termination Terms. — When parties have an open-ended contract
duration, section 2-309 of the U.C.C. allows each party to terminate at
will.73 Even when the contract guarantees a minimum duration, termina-
tion can occur prior to the expiration of this period if there is miscon-
duct by one of the parties, even if this misconduct does not rise to the
level of total breach.74 In this context, courts are often asked to deter-
mine whether a particular event or misconduct by the franchisee provides
legitimate grounds for termination by the franchisor. A powerful exam-
ple of the application of the bargain-mimicking principle comes up in a
case that called for interpretation of a termination clause in a franchise
contract. In the casebook favorite, The Original Great American Chocolate
Chip Cookie Co. v. River Valley Cookies, Ltd., 75 Judge Posner discusses the
power of the franchisor to terminate the franchise. He rejects the claim
that “in a dispute between franchisee and franchisor the judicial thumb
should be on the franchisee’s pan of the balance.”76 He made this deter-
mination despite the fact that the franchisee was clearly the party with the
weaker bargaining power and should therefore have been the natural re-
cipient of any redistributive sentiment. Such a tilt, he explains, will not
help franchisees as a group: “The more difficult it is to cancel a
franchise, the higher the price that franchisors will charge for franchises.
So in the end the franchisees will pay for judicial liberality . . . .”77 Posner
continues, invoking the logic underlying bargain-mimicking terms:
The idea that favoring one side or the other in a class of con-
tract disputes can redistribute wealth is one of the most persis-
tent illusions of judicial power. It comes from failing to con-
sider the full consequences of legal decisions. Courts deciding
contract cases cannot durably shift the balance of advantages to
the weaker side of the market; they can only make contracts
more costly to that side in the future, because franchisors will
demand compensation for bearing onerous terms.78
73. U.C.C. § 2-309(2) (2004) (noting that contract with indefinite duration “may be
terminated at any time by either party”).
74. Antony W. Dnes, A Case-Study Analysis of Franchise Contracts, 22 J. Legal Stud.
367, 370–74 (1993) (analyzing termination of franchise agreements).
75. 970 F.2d 273 (7th Cir. 1992).
76. Id. at 282.
77. Id.
78. Id. In a somewhat mocking dissent, Judge Cudahy agrees that franchisees have
less bargaining power than franchisors but responds to Judge Posner’s bargain-mimicking
default rule by saying:
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 26 23-FEB-09 11:10
Apparently, the legislators had not read enough scholarly musings to realize that
any efforts to protect the weak against the strong would, through the exhilarating
alchemy of economic theory, increase rather than diminish the burden upon the
powerless. I agree that the thumb of judges ought not be placed on the scales of
justice. But judges have no obligation to ignore the numerous thumbs already
put down on the side of economic power . . . .
Id. at 283 (Cudahy, J., dissenting).
79. “Material breach” was defined in the contract to include, among other things:
“failing to maintain and operate the Cookie System Facility in a good, clean,
wholesome manner and in strict compliance with the standards then and from
time to time prescribed by” the Cookie Company; selling any product not
authorized by the Cookie Company; failing to pay any service fee within 10 days
after it is due; failing to pay any of the company’s invoices within that period;
underreporting gross sales (on which the Cookie Company’s royalty from its
franchisees royalty is based) by 1 percent or more; or failing to maintain certain
insurance coverage. . . . Any three breaches, whether or not material, entitle the
company to terminate the franchise within a 12-month period without giving the
franchisee notice or an opportunity to cure.
Id. at 278 (majority opinion).
80. White & Summers, supra note 33, § 3-10 (analyzing U.C.C.’s force majeure R
jurisprudence).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 27 23-FEB-09 11:10
cused against the buyer when the seller’s source of supply defaults, must
the seller assign its remedial rights against its own defaulting supplier to
the disappointed buyer? Usually, when the grounds for excuse are in the
gap-filling list of section 2-615 of the U.C.C., the answer is yes: The disap-
pointed buyer, while unable to get redress from the excused seller, can
instead step into the seller’s shoes and recover from the interfering party
(the defaulting upstream supplier).81 Put differently, the U.C.C. attaches
to its excuse gap fillers an assignment gap filler: Unless stated otherwise,
the rights against the interfering party are automatically assigned from
the excused seller to the buyer.
But what if the grounds for excuse are not in section 2-615 and in-
stead appear in the expressly drafted force majeure clause? Are the rights
of the excused party against the interfering party assigned here too? Is
the disappointed buyer entitled to any recovery rights against the default-
ing upstream supplier? Or does the seller get to keep the right to recover
against his own defaulting supplier, despite being excused against the
buyer? The U.C.C.’s assignment gap filler does not speak to this situation
and so the answer is less clear and must be provided by courts.
In a leading case, Interpetrol Bermuda Ltd. v. Kaiser Aluminum
International Corp., the Ninth Circuit decided that the seller does not have
to assign the recovery rights against the supplier to the disappointed
buyer.82 The court based its decision on a bargain-mimicking principle.
It noted that the seller used its bargaining power to extract a force
majeure clause from the buyer, and that the seller’s supplier was unable,
“because of market forces,” to require a similar excuse provision against
the seller.83 Accordingly, the seller was excused even though his supplier
was not. The court held that it saw
no reason to award the windfall of recovery against the supplier
to the buyer, who agreed to excuse the seller, instead of the
seller, who was able to insist on better protections . . . . We find
no reason to transfer the benefit of [the seller’s] superior nego-
tiating position to [the buyer] by giving [the buyer] rights
against [the defaulting supplier]. We do find that it serves the
forces of natural market adjustments not to transfer [the
seller’s] rights.84
The court’s decision in Interpetrol hinged on mimicking the parties’
likely bargaining outcome. While the parties did not stipulate who, in the
event of excuse, would be entitled to recover from the defaulting sup-
plier, only one party could recover this right, and the court chose to
award it to the party with the greater bargaining power. This decision did
81. U.C.C. § 2-615 cmt. 5 (2004) (“[E]xcuse should not result in relieving the
defaulting supplier from liability nor in dropping into the seller’s lap an unearned bonus
of damages over.”)
82. 719 F.2d 992, 999–1001 (9th Cir. 1983).
83. Id. at 1000.
84. Id. at 1000–01.
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 28 23-FEB-09 11:10
C. Peevyhouse
The bargain-mimicking idea can also help explain case outcomes in
another important area: the selective application of the cost-of-comple-
tion damages in cases of defective performance. In the classic case
Peevyhouse v. Garland Coal & Mining Co., the court had to determine what
85. Id. at 1000 (stating that future parties might hesitate to move into the “more
contractually secure part of the market”).
86. See Bank of N.Y. v. Janowick, 470 F.3d 264 (6th Cir. 2006).
87. Id. at 267–68.
88. Id. at 272.
89. The court stated that:
Were we to attempt to discern the term to which the parties to the annuity
contracts would have agreed (the less-favored mode of analysis under § 204’s
comment d), we would reach the same conclusion. . . . [U]nder the “hypothetical
model of bargaining” approach, [the employees’ trustee] would have demanded
that any unanticipated proceeds . . . inure to the Employees to compensate them
for this additional risk. Prudential would not have been in a position to favor
either the Employees or Southwire, and would not have objected to this term.
Id. at 272 n.7.
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 29 23-FEB-09 11:10
some plaintiffs get the former, usually higher, measure, while others re-
ceive the latter, stingier recovery? Criteria such as the willfulness of the
breach and the disproportionality of the cost of completion are only par-
tial and ad hoc organizing factors. The bargain-mimicking principle, I
argue, can bolster our understanding of case outcomes. Promisees who
had the superior bargaining power to insist on a completed performance,
like the Peevyhouses, should be entitled to the more generous measure.
Providing higher damages to parties with superior bargaining powers
mimics the high-end liquidated damages clauses they would have bar-
gained for.
This idea, focusing on the ex ante bargaining power of the transac-
tors, underlies Cardozo’s famous but cryptic distinction between “com-
mon chattel” and “a mansion or a skyscraper.”98 Why did Cardozo think
courts should allow the margin of noncompletion to be greater (and the
remedy smaller) in the case of common chattels or, as understood by a
later court, when the client purchased a stock floor plan house,99 but
require stricter compliance and award the higher cost-of-completion
measure for mansions? Plausibly, clients who purchase common chattel
and stock floor plan homes have less bargaining power against sellers and
little ex ante leverage to demand strict adherence to detailed specifica-
tions or the cost-of-completion remedy when tender is less than perfect.
But when mansions and skyscrapers are designed, the client is often in a
stronger bargaining position. Hence, when the aggrieved party had the
ex ante bargaining power to insist on precise tender of performance,
courts award the more generous measure.100
Remedies for breach of contract are not the sort of gap fillers that
have solely distributive effects. A long and distinguished literature has
shown that, through their effect on performance and reliance decisions,
remedies significantly influence the overall surplus.101 Thus, there is a
strong argument that contract gaps concerning remedies ought to be fil-
led with surplus-maximizing—rather than bargain-mimicking—terms.
Indeed, in the context of Peevyhouse, commentators have expressed con-
cerns about how the cost-of-completion measure would influence incen-
98. Jacob & Youngs, Inc. v. Kent, 129 N.E. 889, 890 (N.Y. 1921).
99. Plante v. Jacobs, 103 N.W.2d 296, 298–99 (Wis. 1960) (holding that in stock floor
plan house, a small shift of a wall does not entitle buyer to cost of repair measure).
100. See, e.g., Groves v. John Wunder Co., 286 N.W. 235, 238 (Minn. 1939) (finding
cost of performance to be appropriate measure of damages even though this cost was
much higher than decrease in value caused by breach); O.W. Grun Roofing & Constr. Co.
v. Cope, 529 S.W.2d 258, 262–63 (Tex. Civ. App. 1975) (noting that homeowners
contracting for amenities can insist on perfect tender to their specifications); see also
Marvin A. Chirelstein, Concepts and Case Analysis in the Law of Contracts 174 (4th ed.
2001) (arguing that recovery should equal amount promisee could have bargained for at
agreement stage); Robert A. Hillman, Principles of Contract Law 140 (2004) (explaining
that court should have considered “nature of the parties’ bargaining over the restoration
clause at the time of contracting” since this “would have shed light on Groves’ motives”).
101. See, e.g., Steven Shavell, Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law 304–12
(2004) (analyzing effect of remedies on overall surplus).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 31 23-FEB-09 11:10
102. See, e.g., Posner, supra note 3, at 121 (suggesting that overcompensatory R
remedies would make efficient breach more costly).
103. Ian Ayres & Kristin Madison, Threatening Inefficient Performance of Injunctions
and Contracts, 148 U. Pa. L. Rev. 45, 95–98 (1999) (discussing effect of damage measure
on subsequent rounds of bargaining over release from inefficient performance and
inefficient breach).
104. For background on the concept of maximally tolerable terms, see generally Omri
Ben-Shahar, How to Repair Unconscionable Contracts (Univ. of Chi. Law Sch., John M.
Olin Law & Economics, Working Paper No. 417, 2008), available at http://ssrn.com/
abstract=1082926 (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 32 23-FEB-09 11:10
sided, still favorable to the drafting party, but which falls just within the
range that is considered tolerable. Once the offensive term is replaced by
a term that is within the tolerable range, even if only barely so, there is no
remaining justification for intervention.
Thus, for example, if the excessive term were an intolerably high
price, the legal intervention would be to lower the price. If we analogize
the process of judicial intervention in the contract to a force that pulls
the price from its currently intolerable level toward the permissible re-
gion, the force gradually weakens as the price gets closer to the tolerable
level, and vanishes entirely once this level is hit. The point at which this
adjustment process is no longer justified is not the midrange,
majoritarian, most balanced term. Instead, the justification disappears at
the maximally tolerable price, which, though it remains one-sided, is not
as intolerable as the original term. Once this term is set, the weaker party
no longer has a reasonable basis for demanding additional redress.105
There are numerous instances in which courts apply maximally toler-
able terms. The doctrine of partial enforcement is one such example.106
Under this doctrine, a court is authorized to reform an unreasonable
term in a contract and enforce it to the extent necessary to avoid the
unreasonableness.107 The most common application of this technique
involves noncompete clauses that are excessive in either duration or geo-
graphic scope. In most states, courts repair excessive noncompete terms
by reducing them to the maximally tolerable level.108
At times, the maximally tolerable level is defined explicitly by statute.
Some states have enacted bright line rules stating the maximal duration
of noncompete clauses in employment contracts.109 There, only the in-
crement of the restraint that is socially intolerable is eliminated; the rest
stands.110 In other states there is no bright line statute. There too, courts
reduce the noncompete term, bringing it down to a level that is maxi-
mally tolerable. The restraint “is not enforceable beyond the time or area
considered reasonable by the [c]ourt.”111
measure were the one agreed upon in the first place, the court
would not have been justified in reducing it.119
This, in other words, is the maximally tolerable level, the term within
the reasonable range that comes closest to mimicking the parties’ bar-
gaining power.
CONCLUSION
When we think about courts interpreting contracts and supplying
missing terms, we do not usually regard it as a distributive task. Unless
there is clear evidence about actual but imperfectly specified intent,
courts are instructed to identify the “reasonable” term, the most efficient
term, the majoritarian term, or some other uniquely distinguished con-
tent. Yet none of these criteria are defined with respect to their distribu-
tive effect. This Essay suggests that in fact the gap-filling task of courts is
often purely distributive. In many contexts—as in the case of a missing
price—there are several potential provisions courts can choose from, all
of which satisfy the reasonable or efficient criteria, but differ in their dis-
tributive allocation. Thus, contract law needs to provide an appropriate
criterion for choosing the default rule in these instances of distributive
gaps.
It is one thing to argue that we are faced with a recurring contractual
gap that needs a systematic solution, for which existing gap-filling princi-
ples do not apply. It is quite another to propose a bargain-mimicking
solution that favors the stronger party. Some readers may object to this
proposed criterion as morally unjust. If there is a distributive aspect to
gap filling, they would argue, why not turn it into an opportunity to favor
the weaker party? Should not the law reverse the outcomes of unfettered,
unequal bargaining power?120 The answer I provide in this Essay is that
distributive gaps cannot effectively become an occasion for redistribution.
I argue that gap fillers cannot effectively favor the weak party. Gap fillers
that go against the background allocation of bargaining power will only
induce stronger parties to exert express, self-favoring terms. The more
redistributive gap fillers are, the less likely it is they will come into play.
Identifying the division of bargaining power between parties can be
difficult and error prone. In this Essay I suggest that the problem might
not be as challenging as it initially appears, but nonetheless concede that
119. Uri Yadin, Hok Hahozim: Terufot Beshel Hafarat Hozeh 1970 [Contract Law:
Remedies for Breach of Contract 1970] 132 (2d ed. 1979) (Hebrew text); see also Eyal
Zamir et al., Haperush Hakatsar Lehukim Bamishpat Haprati [Brief Commentary on Law
Relating to Private Law] 302 (2d ed. 1996) (Hebrew text) (stating, as translated, that “the
measure of reduction of liquidated damages ought to be to the level for which the element
of excessiveness no longer applies . . . [such that] if that level was set in the first place, it
would not have been reduced by the court”).
120. See, e.g., Symposium, Power, Inequality and the Bargain: The Role of
Bargaining Power in the Law of Contract, 2006 Mich. St. L. Rev. 841 (describing various
approaches to dealing with bargaining power asymmetries).
\\server05\productn\C\COL\109-2\COL204.txt unknown Seq: 35 23-FEB-09 11:10
121. See Einer Elhauge, Statutory Default Rules: How to Interpret Unclear
Legislation 5–12 (2008).
122. Ocean Accident & Guarantee Corp. v. Indus. Comm’n of Ariz., 257 P. 644, 645
(Ariz. 1927) (“Our enlightened modern thought realizes that an equality of bargaining
power between two such unequal parties is impossible, and has attempted to equalize the
balance . . . .”).