Noam Chomsky: Life and Basic Ideas
Noam Chomsky: Life and Basic Ideas
Noam Chomsky: Life and Basic Ideas
American linguist
WRITTEN BY
James A. McGilvray
Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, McGill University. Editor
of The Cambridge Companion to Chomsky; author of Chomsky:
Language, Mind, and Politics.
See Article History
Alternative Title: Avram Noam Chomsky
Noam Chomsky, in full Avram Noam Chomsky, (born
December 7, 1928, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, U.S.), American
theoretical linguist whose work from the 1950s revolutionized the
field of linguistics by treating language as a uniquely human,
biologically based cognitive capacity. Through his contributions to
linguistics and related fields, including cognitive psychology and
the philosophies of mind and language, Chomsky helped to initiate
and sustain what came to be known as the “cognitive revolution.”
Chomsky also gained a worldwide following as a political dissident
for his analyses of the pernicious influence of economic elites on
U.S. domestic politics, foreign policy, and intellectual culture.
TOP QUESTIONS
What was Noam Chomsky’s early life like?
How did Noam Chomsky influence the field of linguistics?
What are Noam Chomsky’s politics?
Noam Chomsky
QUICK FACTS
View Media Page
BORN
NOTABLE WORKS
SUBJECTS OF STUDY
language
philosophy of language
rationalism
innate idea
transformational grammar
Linguistics
“Plato’s problem”
A fundamental insight of philosophical rationalism is that human
creativity crucially depends on an innate system of concept
generation and combination. According to Chomsky, children
display “ordinary” creativity—appropriate and innovative use of
complexes of concepts—from virtually their first words. With
language, they bring to bear thousands of rich
and articulate concepts when they play, invent, and speak to and
understand each other. They seem to know much more than they
have been taught—or even could be taught. Such knowledge,
therefore, must be innate in some sense. To say it is innate,
however, is not to say that the child is conscious of it or even that it
exists, fully formed, at birth. It is only to say that it is produced by
the child’s system of concept generation and combination, in
accordance with the system’s courses of biological and physical
development, upon their exposure to certain kinds of
environmental input.
In the late 1970s and early 1980s Chomsky and others developed a
better solution using a theoretical framework known as “principles
and parameters” (P&P), which Chomksy introduced in Lectures
on Government and Binding (1981) and elaborated in Knowledge
of Language (1986). Principles are linguistic universals, or
structural features that are common to all natural languages;
hence, they are part of the child’s native endowment. Parameters,
also native (though not necessarily specific to language, perhaps
figuring elsewhere too), are options that allow for variation in
linguistic structure. The P&P approach assumed that these options
are readily set upon the child’s exposure to a minimal amount of
linguistic data, a hypothesis that has been supported
by empirical evidence. One proposed principle, for example, is that
phrase structure must consist of a head, such as a noun or a verb,
and a complement, which can be a phrase of any form. The order
of head and complement, however, is not fixed: languages may
have a head-initial structure, as in the English verb phrase (VP)
“wash the clothes,” or a “head-final” structure, as in the
corresponding Japanese VP “the clothes wash.” Thus,
one parameter that is set through the child’s exposure to linguistic
data is “head-initial/head-final.” The setting of what was thought,
during the early development of P&P, to be a small number of
parametric options within the constraints provided by a
sufficiently rich set of linguistic principles would, according to this
approach, yield a grammar of the specific language to which the
child is exposed. Later the introduction of “microparameters” and
certain nonlinguistic constraints on development complicated this
simple story, but the basic P&P approach remained in place,
offering what appears to be the best solution to Plato’s problem yet
proposed.
RELATED BIOGRAPHIES
Plato
René Descartes
Aristotle
John Locke
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
Benedict de Spinoza
Hilary Putnam
Søren Kierkegaard
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
John Searle
BRITANNICA QUIZ
Philosophy Of Mind And
Human Nature
Human conceptual and linguistic creativity involves several
mental faculties and entails the existence of some kind of mental
organization. It depends on perceptual-articulatory systems and
conceptual-intentional systems, of course, but on many others too,
such as vision. According to Chomsky, the mind comprises an
extensive cluster of innate “modules,” one of which is language.
Each module operates automatically, independently of individual
control, on the basis of a distinct, domain-specific set of rules that
take determinate inputs from some modules and yield determinate
outputs for others. In earlier work these operations were called
“derivations”; more recently they have been called
“computations.” The various modules interact in complex ways to
yield perception, thought, and a large number of
other cognitive products.
The views common to Quine and the hermeneutic tradition were opposed
Politics
Chomsky’s political views seem to be supported to some extent by
his approach to the study of language and mind, which implies
that the capacity for creativity is an important element of human
nature. Chomsky often notes, however, that there is only an
“abstract” connection between his theories of language and his
politics. A close connection would have to be based on a fully
developed science of human nature, through which fundamental
human needs could be identified or deduced. But there is nothing
like such a science. Even if there were, the connection would
additionally depend on the assumption that the best form of
political organization is one that maximizes the satisfaction of
human needs. And then there would remain the question of what
practical measures should be implemented to satisfy those needs.
Clearly, questions such as this cannot be settled by scientific
means.
The studies in these and other works made use of paired examples
to show how very similar events can be reported in very different
ways, depending upon whether and how state and corporate
interests may be affected. In The Political Economy of Human
Rights, for example, Chomsky and Herman compared reporting
on Indonesia’s military invasion and occupation of East
Timor with reporting on the behaviour of the communist Khmer
Rouge regime in Cambodia. The events in the two cases took place
in approximately the same part of the world and at approximately
the same time (the mid- to late 1970s). As a proportion of
population, the number of East Timorese tortured and murdered
by the Indonesian military was approximately the same as the
number of Cambodians tortured and murdered by the Khmer
Rouge. And yet the mainsteam media in the United States devoted
much more attention to the second case (more than 1,000 column
inches in the New York Times) than to the first (about 70 column
inches). Moreover, reporting on the actions of the Khmer Rouge
contained many clear cases of exaggeration and fabrication,
whereas reporting on the actions of Indonesia portrayed them as
essentially benign. In the case of the Khmer Rouge, however,
exaggerated reports of atrocities aided efforts by the United States
to maintain the Cold War and to protect and expand its access to
the region’s natural resources (including East Timorese oil
deposits) through client states. Indonesia, on the other hand, was
just such a state, heavily supported by U.S. military and economic
aid. Although ordinary Americans were not in a position to do
anything about the Khmer Rouge, they were capable of doing
something about their country’s support for Indonesia, in
particular by voting their government out of office. But the media’s
benign treatment of the invasion made it extremely unlikely that
they would be motivated to do so. According to Chomsky, this and
many other examples demonstrate that prominent journalists and
other intellectuals in the United States function essentially as
“commissars” on behalf of elite interests. As he wrote
in Necessary Illusions (1988):
The media serve the interests of state and corporate power, which are
closely interlinked, framing their reporting and analysis in a manner
supportive of established privilege and limiting debate and discussion
accordingly.
Some of Chomsky’s critics have claimed that his political and
media studies portray journalists as actively engaged in a kind
of conspiracy—an extremely unlikely conspiracy, of course, given
the degree of coordination and control it would require.
Chomsky’s response is simply that the assumption of conspiracy is
unnecessary. The behaviour of journalists in the mainstream
media is exactly what one would expect, on average, given the
power structure of the institutions in which they are employed,
and it is predictable in the same sense and for the same reasons
that the behaviour of the president of General Motors is
predictable. In order to succeed—in order to be hired and
promoted—media personnel must avoid questioning the interests
of the corporations they work for or the interests of the elite
minority who run those corporations. Because journalists
naturally do not wish to think of themselves as mercenaries (no
one does), they engage in what amounts to a form of self-
deception. They typically think of themselves as stalwart defenders
of the truth (as suggested by the slogan of the New York Times,
“All the news that’s fit to print”), but when state or corporate
interests are at stake they act otherwise, in crucially important
ways. In short, very few of them are willing or even able to live up
to their responsibility as intellectuals to bring the truth about
matters of human significance to an audience that can do
something about them.