15-1 Duong
15-1 Duong
15-1 Duong
I. SUMMARY
On a limited scope, this Article provides a reassessment of the “Law
and Literature” movement1 in legal academic discourse. On a much broader
scope, the Article attempts to join the ongoing dialogue among authors who
have written on jurisprudence and philosophy,2 as well as on the esoteric
field called “the philosophy of legal language.”3 This dialogue has
consisted of, inter alia, topics such as law and philosophy,4 law and
linguistics,5 law and art,6 rhetoric and legal interpretation,7 or legal
1
2 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
eds., Univ. Chicago Press 1999). See also Roger Berkowitz, Rriedrich Nietzsche, The Code of Manu,
and The Art of Legislation, 24 CARDOZO L. REV. 1131 (2003) (discussing artistic creation in the context
of analyzing Nietzsche’s art of legislation); J.M. Balkin & Sanford Levinson, Interpreting Law and
Music: Performance Notes on the ‘Banjo Serenader’ and ‘The Lying Crowd of Jews’, 20 CARDOZO L.
REV. 1513 (1999) (discussing and comparing law and music); Jonathan Turley, Art and the
Constitution: The Supreme Court and the Rise of the Impressionist School of Constitutional
Interpretation, 2004 CATO SUP. 69 (2004) (using various schools of the visual art to discuss
constitutional theories).
7
See, e.g., LAW’S STORIES – NARRATIVE AND RHETORIC IN LAW (Peter Brooks & Paul Gerwirtz eds.,
Yale Univ. Press 1996); Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Theory of Legal Interpretation, 12 HARV. L. REV.
417 (1899); DONALD DAVIDSON, INQUIRIES INTO TRUTH AND INTERPRETATION (Clarendon Press
Oxford 1984). See also, e.g., Patterson, supra note 3; Neil MacCormick, Argumentation and
Interpretation in Law, 6-1 RATIO JURIS 16 (1993); Dworkin, Interpretive Concepts, in LAW’S EMPIRE
(Harvard Univ. Press 1986); LAW AND INTERPRETATION: ESSAYS IN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY (Andrei
Marmor ed., Clarendon Press London 1995); Delia B. Conti, Narrative Theory and the Law: A
Rhetorician’s Invitation to the Legal Academy, 39 DUQ. L. REV. 457 (2001).
8
See, e.g., LAW, INTERPRETATION AND REALITY – ESSAYS IN EPISTEMOLOGY, HERMENEUTICS AND
JURISPRUDENCE (Patrick Nerhot ed., Kluwer Academic Publishers 1990).
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 3
law. The art of persuasion and its natural product — social activism — help
influence judicial officers and legislators, who are the principal and official
drafters of legal language. In that sense, the elements and attributes of the
literary art have their place in law.
4. Notwithstanding the obvious social utility of the literary craft when
it is used as part of law, the creative process involved in each discipline
remains antagonistic to each other. This notion should ring a note of
caution for the responsible lawyer, drafter, and user of legal language. In
this regard, the Law and Literature (L&L) movement of the past decades
has not done justice to the scholarly discourse. Nor has it enhanced the
understanding of practitioners in either field — law or art. (By
practitioners, I mean those who must engage in the relevant creative
process; I do not mean just the legal practitioners of the law profession.)
The reason for this shortcoming is explained in my fifth proposition below.
5. Although scholars in the L&L movement recognize the differences
and similarities between law and art, they all stand in the shoes of the
readers and speak from the perspective of interpretation. They neglect the
perspective of the artist, the nature of the artistic creative process, and the
incompatibility inherent in legal creation versus artistic creation. This
oversight is due, inter alia, to the fact that L&L scholars are all thinkers,
lawyers, readers, even literary critics or connoisseurs of art, but they
probably don't live their lives as creative artists. Missing from the debate is
the voice of the serious creative artist who actively and on a daily basis
becomes involved in the creation of art as the essence of existence. The
L&L scholars should recognize and examine these two antagonistic
creative processes because they add to the understanding of interpretation
and help set constraints when law borrows the craft of the literary art for
advocacy and persuasion.
6. Gradual changes and the expansion of legal scholarships in past
decades have created new dimensions for the interplay between law and the
literary art. The art of storytelling — the cornerstone of fables, folklores,
mythologies, and fiction — is making its way into the “narrative” form of
legal scholarships as this form emerges under great scrutiny, suspicion, and
controversial debates. But in order to gain and retain acceptance, the
“narrative” form must be done extremely well, with dignity, responsibility,
9
and the kind of ethical constraint that typifies the role of a jurist. At the
same time, the narrative must be well-crafted to create the sense of
“suspended disbelief” expected of the audience of the arts. This remains the
most complex challenge for the “narrative” advocate and practitioner
because the two antagonistic creative processes — law versus art — must
somehow be reconciled and harmonized into a final product that represents
the relative quest for truth (characteristic of law), rather than the freedom of
imagination (characteristic of novelistic writing). Hence, the marriage
between law and art in the “narrative” form is indeed a paradox.
Nonetheless, the narrative legal writer must undertake this internally
9
Jack L. Sammons, The Radical Ethics of Legal Rhetoricians, 32 VAL. U. L. REV. 93 (1997).
4 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
10
See DAWN B. SOVA, BANNED BOOKS: LITERATURE SUPPRESSED ON SEXUAL GROUNDS (Ken
Wachsberger ed., Facts On File, Inc. 1998).
11
See DONALD DAVIDSON, Belief and the Basis of Meaning, in INQUIRIES INTO TRUTH AND
INTERPRETATION 141-54, 183-98, 245-64 (Clarendon Press Oxford 1984); Donald Davidson, A Nice
Derangement of Epitaphs, reprinted in TRUTH AND INTERPRETATION: PERSPECTIVES ON THE
PHILOSOPHY OF DONALD DAVIDSON 433-446 (Ernest LePore ed., Basil Blackwell Ltd. 1984).
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 5
the artistic creative process that prompts artists to stretch limits, blind
themselves against moral norms, and explore or articulate social and
political taboos at tremendous risk?
The list also strikes a note of discordance between law and art,
portraying literary artists as breakers of norms and defiants of culture —
those exhibitionists who disrobe the human soul and lay bare its nakedness.
On the other hand, law is seen as the gloved hand: that well-groomed,
uniform-clad social agent who suppresses artistic expressions and molds
human conduct. Artists are deviants; lawyers, conformists, and judges
speak the voice that dictates behavior. At the same time, the United Nations
Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR)12 speaks of freedom and
liberty for all humankind, by declaring the unequivocal space the state must
preserve as inviolate for the universal human (the UDHR’s concept of right
universalizes what a human can do, and what the state cannot do). So,
where is the declaration and invite of freedom? Law or art?
In the 1970s, James Boyd White's The Legal Imagination appeared to
mark the birth of the Law and Literature (L&L) movement,13 initiating,
perhaps, the scholarly debate on the divergence, analogies, and similarities
between the two disciplines. Concurrently, there has been a breed of
lawyers–turned–novelists, of which Harvard Law School supplied its share
of the species (Richard Henry Dana, James Russell Lowell, Henry James,
Owen Wister, Arthur Train, Archibald MacLeish, Scott Turow, J. Osborne,
James Alan McPherson). But long before these phenomena, Cardozo's Law
and Literature14 had already analyzed the literary properties of judicial
opinions, and Wigmore had already declared that lawyers should learn from
great literary works to understand human nature.15 The interplay between
law and literature in Anglo-Saxon society has historical roots dating back to
depictions of the legal system by Shakespeare and Dickens.
This “coming together” of law and literature reminds me of the cliché
saying, “Tous les chemins se mènent a Rome” (all routes lead to Roma). I
think of words, or language, as one such "Roma capital” for the two
disciplines — the meeting point of law and the literary art.16 Language and
the author's function become the common domain for law and art.17 In
12
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217A (III), U.N. Doc A/810 (Dec. 10, 1948).
13
JAMES BOYD WHITE, THE LEGAL IMAGINATION: STUDIES IN THE NATURE OF LEGAL THOUGHT AND
EXPRESSION (Little Brown & Company 1973). Other distinguished contributors to the movement are
Richard A. Posner and Richard Weisberg. See, e.g., RICHARD POSNER, LAW AND LITERATURE: A
MISUNDERSTOOD RELATION (Harvard Univ. Press 1988); RICHARD POSNER, LAW AND LITERATURE
(1998); Richard A. Posner, Law And Literature: A Relation Reargued, 72 VA. L. REV. 1351 (1986);
Richard A. Posner, Judges’ Writing Styles (And Do They Matter?), 62 U. CHI. L. REV. 1421 (1995);
RICHARD WEISBERG, POETHICS AND OTHER STRATEGIES OF LAW AND LITERATURE (Columbia Univ.
Press 1992).
14
BENJAMIN N. CARDOZO, Law and Literature, in LAW AND LITERATURE AND OTHER ESSAYS AND
ADDRESSES 3 (1931).
15 JOHN WIGMORE, INTRODUCTION TO JOHN MARSHALL GEST, LAWYERS IN LITERATURE vii (1913).
16
I distinguish between “visual art” (where a medium like paint/canvas becomes the tool of expression),
“performing art” (where the artist’s body and physical facilities become the tool of expression), and
“literary art” (where words become the tool of expression). Although the tools are different, in the
purest form of artistic creation, they should all serve the same function.
17
Piyel Haldar, Literature Within the Law, 32 NEW FORMATIONS 183 (1997).
6 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
language, the artist and the lawyer meet, where they are greeted by the
philosopher, who raises questions such as whether the normative rules of
language should be imported substantively into law beyond grammar and
syntax,18 or whether law inherits the indeterminacy of language and hence
the open-endedness of interpretation.19 But just because they can all find
and share Roma, does this mean that they can be friends? In some ways,
yes. (In fact, they have borrowed crafts, techniques, and material from each
other.) In other ways, I suggest no. This is because in the process of
creating their work products, lawyers and philosophers travel courses that
are different and even counter-productive to the creative process of the
artist — whose journey can also do havoc to law and philosophy when
applied there.
Another “Roma capital” exists for law and literature. It is in (i) the
domain of the reader or interpreter of text — the receiving end of the work
product; and in (ii) the task of advocacy or persuasion — that which will
influence and shape the end result, produce consequences, impact and
prompt the reader or interpreter to action, or induce a change of belief. As
law professor Wetlaufer points out, rhetoric is the art (as per Aristotle) or
craft (as per Plato) of persuasion, which has been treated as synonymous
with lawyering.20 Here, I agree with Richard Posner, the judge and law
professor whose book, Law and Literature, brought the L&L movement
into focus.21 Posner thinks that the study of literature has very little to
contribute to the interpretation of constitutions and statutes. Yet, it can
contribute to the understanding, improvement, shaping, and hence,
interpretation of judicial opinions. But just because the study of literature
can be relevant in the shaping of judicial opinions, does it mean the
creative process is the same for judges, who write opinions, as it is for
literary artists, who write fiction? I submit, no. I would even venture to say,
absolutely not, because these two creative processes are mutually exclusive
and antagonistic to each other.
18
See generally KENT GREENWALT, LAW AND OBJECTIVITY (Oxford Univ. Press 1992).
19
See, e.g., Linda Ross Meyer, When Reasonable Minds Differ, 71 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1467 (1967)
(examining legal indeterminacy via the use of language and meaning of Rule 11 and the qualified
immunity doctrine). See also LAW AND INTERPRETATION: ESSAYS IN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY, supra note 7.
20
Gerald Wetlaufer, Rhetoric and its Denial in Legal Discourse, 76 VA. L. REV. 1545 (1990). Wetlaufer
teaches law at the University of Iowa, known as the nation's best training ground for creative writers.
The University of Iowa initiated the Project on the Rhetoric of Inquiry. See also THE REPUBLIC OF
PLATO (A.D. Lindsey trans., 1950) (In the allegory of the cave, Socrates used light and dark to discuss
the physical and the intellectual. Fiction was used to develop an argument, and storytelling was used to
create one of the best known stories of classical philosophy).
21
Interestingly, Posner wrote not only about law and literature, but also law and economics. See, e.g.,
RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW (2003); RICHARD A. POSNER, THE ECONOMICS OF
JUSTICE (1981). As Wetlaufer correctly points out, Posner’s work was from the perspective of the reader
of literature. See Wetlaufer, supra note 20, at 1564 n.50. Posner did not compare literature to law from
the standpoint of the creator, although he recognized some differences in the creative processes between
law and art. See generally, RICHARD POSNER, LAW AND LITERATURE: A MISUNDERSTOOD RELATION,
supra note 13; RICHARD POSNER, LAW AND LITERATURE, supra note 13.
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 7
Law in this Article refers to the legal system as a whole (and not just
the legal profession, the practice of law, legal authority/precedents, legal
concepts, or legal documents). Law is viewed by Wetlaufer as a "serious
business . . . conducted on a field of ‘pain or death.’"24 Thinking like
lawyers, therefore, is important to the legal pedagogue, as the process may
reinforce the legitimacy and dignity of the legal system itself. So, argues
Wetlaufer, the rhetoric often chosen for the law profession is the
anti-rhetoric!25
On the other hand, the text that matters to law often encompasses more
than just legal precedents. Quite often, in the congested court docket, the
winning brief provides the roadmap of legal authorities and supplies the
persuasion force for the judicial opinion to sustain appellate review and to
aid public understanding. Judges (as human beings with passion, emotions
and prejudices, living in a multi-faceted society), also read and hear other
things besides legal precedents. They listen to the voices of social
movements, and bring their total experience and beliefs into the bench — a
“synthetic” model of judicial decision-making confirmed by the pragmatist
school of thought in language philosophy. According to Holmes, the life of
law has not been logic; it has been experience.26 The Anglo-American legal
22
See Julius M. Moravcsik, Art and “Art,” in MIDWEST STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY VOL. XVI:
PHILOSOPHY AND THE ARTS 302 (Peter French, Theodore Uehling, Jr. & Howard Wettstein eds., Univ.
of Notre Dame Press 1991).
23
Definitions may be the beginning point for the drafter of a complex commercial contract, which often
includes a “definition of terms” section, and even for an appellate lawyer handling a complex litigation
and a massive record (an appellate brief may also contain “defined terms.”) Definitions, however, are
of little concern to the artist, who leaves the job of defining and labeling her vision to readers.
According to Barthes, the “death” of the author is the “birth” of the reader; the “evaporation” of
meaning as textual matters are interpreted: “A text’s unity lies not in its origin but in its destination.”
ROLAND BARTHES, The Death of the Author, in IMAGE-MUSIC-TEXT 142-148 (Stephen Heath trans.,
1977).
24
See Wetlaufer, supra note 20, at 1545 (quoting Robert Cover, Violence and the Word, 95 YALE L.J.
1601 (1986)).
25
See id.
26
See OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES, JR., THE COMMON LAW 5 (Mark DeWolfe Howe ed., 1982) (1963);
Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Theory of Legal Interpretation, 12 HARV. L. REV. 417 (1899).
8 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
27
See DWORKIN, supra note 7, at 45-86, 176-224; H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law
and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1958); HART, supra note 2, at 124-53; Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.,
The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 465-66 (1897).
28
Art can also be an institution or a practice, just like law or medicine, although society does not
officially license artists. The privileges and recognition bestowed — the name recognition and label-
fixing that render prestige and acceptance in the artistic circle — all set constraints and institutionalize
art. See Moravcsik, supra note 22. The institutionalized meaning of art is not part of this Article.
29
Accord Roger Berkowitz, Rriedrich Nietzsche, the Code of Manu, and the Art of Legislation, 24
CARDOZO L. REV. 1131 (2003) (discussing artistic creation in the context of analyzing Nietzsche’s art of
legislation); Alfred C. Aman, Jr., Celebrating Law and the Arts, 2 GREEN BAG 2D 129 (1999)
(comparing lawyers to artists by referring to the craft of law: “Lawyers, like artists, must have the
techniques of their craft well in hand, but the goal is not technique for technique’s sake...”).
30
See Wetlaufer, supra note 20.
31
See Wetlaufer, supra note 20.
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 9
But the art found in any craft well done is a narrow, yet more popular
and concrete notion of art as the term is used in ordinary language. Such art
should be distinguished from the art expressed in the specific work
products of creative artists — that direct "rare vision" and manifestation of
beauty (which often expresses not only the artist's vision and her internal
struggle, but is also universalized into the human quest for beauty). The art
of Van Gogh, Mozart, or Baudelaire falls under the latter category. For the
purpose of this Article, this universal notion or expression of the human
quest for beauty is manifested in the specific end product of a creative
artist, called Art (capitalized).
32
See RICHARD A. POSNER, LAW AND LITERATURE: A MISUNDERSTOOD RELATION, supra note 13, at
270-81. Accord Brett G. Scharffs, The Character of Legal Reasoning, 61 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 733
(2004) (discussing craft and rhetoric). See also WILLEM J. WITTEVEEN, Cicero Tells a Story On
Narration and Rhetorical Reflection, in LAW AND LITERATURE PERSPECTIVES (Bruce Rockwood ed.,
Peter Lang Publishing 1996); Michael Frost, Greco-Roman Analysis of Metaphoric Reasoning, 2 LEGAL
WRITING J. LEGAL WRITING INST. 113 (1996); Michael Frost, Introduction to Classic Legal Rhetoric: A
Lost Heritage, 8 S. CAL. INTERDISC. L.J. 613 (1999); Michael Frost, Ethos, Pathos & Legal Audience,
99 DICK. L. REV. 85 (1994); Linda Berger, Applying New Rhetoric to Legal Discourse: The Ebb and
Flow of Reader and Writer, Text and Context, 49 J. LEGAL EDUC. 155 (1999); Kristen K. Robbins,
Paradigm Lost: Recapturing Classical Rhetoric to Validate Legal Reasoning, 27 VT. L. REV. 483 (2003)
(discussing classic rhetoric and exploring styles and substantive aspects of rhetoric as applied to legal
reasoning, legal writing, and legal interpretation).
33
RICHARD A. LANHAM, THE MOTIVES OF ELOQUENCE: LITERARY RHETORIC IN THE RENAISSANCE 1-
35 (1976).
34
Id. at 4.
35
See generally Posner, Law and Literature: A Relation Reargued, supra note 13.
10 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
36
See Wetlaufer, supra note 20, at 1548-1550.
37
Id.
38
Scott Brewer, Note, Figuring the Law: Holism and Tropological Inference in Legal Interpretation, 97
YALE L.J. 823 (1988).
39
See Donald Davidson, A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs, supra note 11, at 434-36.
40
See LANHAM, supra note 33. Accord KENNETH BURKE, A RHETORIC OF MOTIVES (1960) (the theory
of dramatism establishes man as a symbol-using creature); WALTER R. FISHER, HUMAN
COMMUNICATION AS NARRATION: TOWARD A PHILOSOPHY OF REASON, VALUE AND ACTION 5 (1987)
(extending Burke’s premise that man is fundamentally a symbol-using creature; arguing that man’s
dramatic nature makes him a storytelling animal beyond the use of symbols).
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 11
example, Martin Luther King, Jr.’s speech, which has helped transform a
nation and, since then, has continued to resonate).
Posner stops at style and does not reexamine the search for truth
fundamental to law. In contrast, Wetlaufer, hints at the possibility of
rethinking jurisprudence in analyzing the rhetoric of law.46 I read in
Wetlaufer an implicit challenge to lawyers’ commitment to the rhetoric of
law — specifically their dignified, consistent denial of rhetoric. This “anti-
rhetoric” commitment predisposes them toward the direction of closure,
coercion, rationality, and the rigid ascertainment of one true meaning of
text that shuts out the relationship between law and “compassion,
reciprocity, . . . community . . . truth . . . and possibility of justice.”47
Similarly, Holmes’s “anti-logic theory” resonates with this complex
multiplicity of law and legal decision-making, pointing out the significant
role that the “inarticulate” and “intuitive” play in judges’ discernment of
law.48
The pragmatist language philosopher also hints at the possibility that
rhetoric can be more than just style or form. Rhetorical declarations can
have their own meaning or truth, even in the Davidsonian “literal
meaning.” Admitting the dramatic quality of rhetoric, Lanham nonetheless
sees the rhetorical ideal as integral to us (rather than as a mere constructed
phoniness for the sake of discussion). He sees the struggle between our two
selves: We cannot be free of our rhetorical self, as the rhetorical self is part
of the central self that balances our social self and makes our social life
amusing and tolerable. The rhetorical ideal allows for a revision of truth, or
a creation of a new reality.49 As such, rhetoric has the capacity of becoming
the substantive truth to the performer as well as the recipient, and no longer
just a question of form or style. When used in law, rhetoric has the potential
of creating legal reality.50 As Lanham suggests, what people cannot get in
their daily life, they get elsewhere. For example, it can be obtained in a
rhetorical reality where ornament can be more honest than plainness, and
rhetoric sincerity is possible when “we become maximally self-conscious
about the artifice which rules us.”51 Language has the property of “rich
resources for play,” and style is the essential ability to draw connections
when constructing reality — the fundamental components of life.52
On the other hand, because emotions, feelings, and sentiments are
intangible, they cannot be verified empirically the way we can ascertain
that snow is white and coal is black. Hence, the rhetoric style can become,
46
See id.
47
Id. at 1597.
48
See HOLMES, THE COMMON LAW supra note 26, at 5 (“The felt necessities of the time, the prevalent
moral and political theories, intuitions of public policy, avowed or unconscious, even the prejudices
which judges share with their fellow men…”).
49
See LANHAM, supra note 33, at 28 (“From serious premises, all rhetorical language is suspect; from a
rhetorical point of view: transparent language seems dishonest, false to the world.”).
50
See David M. Zlotnick, The Buddha’s Parable and Legal Rhetoric, 58 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 957
(2001) (using Buddhism’s concept of relative truths to rethink constructed legal reality in
jurisprudence).
51
See Lanham, supra note 33, at 31.
52
Id.; KENNETH BURKE, THE PHILOSOPHY OF LITERARY FORM 139-67 (2d ed. 1967) (1941).
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 13
as Lanham and Burke suggest, the way to construct the reality of the
“heart” elements such as emotions or sentiments.53 In the Western
Shakespearean culture, a man in love may repeat that Juliet is the sun. In a
Buddhist culture, an Eastern poet sees his lover's face as the only reality
and the rest of the world as an illusion that fades away. (A Buddhist, the
poet tends to see his world through filmy eyes, with fog covering all four
corners of Earth and only dissolving when his lover's face comes into focus
before the lens of his blurred eyes. The Buddhist culture views life as an
illusion such that enlightenment means stepping out of such fog!) Standing
an ocean apart, both men seem to describe the same truth: the depth of their
emotion toward an object of love. Both draw connections to construct a
reality that is real to them and true to their feelings, but there is no way to
verify their declarations empirically, and so, under the Davidsonian
standard of “literal meaning,” the poetic truth may fail.54
Legal language may resist rhetoric, but the law is also the profession of
rhetoric.55 Wetlaufer suggests that the particular rhetoric embraced by the
law operates through the systematic denial that rhetoric is being used, and
this “rhetorical” denial is purposely made to build credibility.56 Wetlaufer’s
rhetoric of law, therefore, is the contrast in form to other dramatic,
novelistic, or poetic rhetoric that may characterize the creative arts. If this
is so, shouldn’t we watch out for potential falsehood, not in rhetoric, but in
the denial of rhetoric? Isn’t this an affirmation of Lanham’s theory that
ornament (in his example of a woman wearing makeup to draw attention to
her eyes) may be more honest than plainness (i.e., a woman without
makeup whose eyes are not looked to)? I think that seeing the multiplicity
and relativity of truths asserted in law rather than a “literal” approach
focusing solely on empirical validation is in effect a rethinking of
jurisprudence.
B. SOCIAL ACTIVISM AND THE ELEMENT OF PERSUASION
Persuasion and advocacy are also the business of law. In social
activism, an advocate can describe empirically that 1000 men have been
killed (empirically verifiable), and/or he can express, or add, his passion for
justice and his outrage at brutality by way of rhetoric (non-verifiable). Is
the latter less truthful or having less realism than the former, simply
because it deals with his honestly felt intensity of emotion? Isn’t it
disheartening to think of Martin Luther King, Jr.’s speech as merely a
clever tool of persuasion, a style of enticing support, and a less than truthful
rendition of his aspiration, passion, and desire for a better world? These are
dimensions of the intangible that cannot otherwise be expressed without the
freedom afforded by emotion-driven rhetoric.57 The creative literature
embraces the depiction of human emotions as dimensions of truth that
53
See id.
54
See Davidson, supra note 39.
55
See Wetlaufer, supra note 20, at 1554.
56
Id., at 1555.
57
Id.
14 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
70
See id.
71
See RONALD DWORKIN, How Law is Like Literature, in LAW AND LITERATURE: TEXT AND THEORY
29, 32, 34 (Leona Ledwon ed., 1996).
72
Id. at 40-41.
73
See POSNER, LAW AND LITERATURE: A MISUNDERSTOOD RELATION, supra note 32, at 218.
74
Id.
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 17
75
See generally Dworkin, supra note 71.
76
BARTHES, , supra note 23, at 142-47. See also DWORKIN, supra note 7, at 45-86, 176-224; MICHEL
FOUCAULT, What is an Author?, in TEXTUAL STRATEGIES: PERSPECTIVES IN POST-STRUCTURALIST
CRITICISM 141-60 (Josue V. Harari ed., 1979).
77
See Dworkin, supra note 71, at 39.
78
See id. at 44-46.
79
See generally FOUCAULT, supra note 76, at 141-60.
18 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
80
See generally Stanley Fish, Working on the Chain Gang, 60 TEX. L. REV. 551 (1982).
81
See STANLEY E. FISH, DOING WHAT COMES NATURALLY: CHANGE, RHETORIC, AND THE PRACTICE OF
THEORY IN LITERARY AND LEGAL STUDIES, supra note 62, at 1-33; FISH, IS THERE A TEXT IN THIS
CLASS: THE AUTHORITY OF INTERPRETIVE COMMUNITIES, supra note 62, at 303-21, 356-71.
82
See BARTHES, supra note 23, at 142-47.
83
See Ronald A. Dworkin, “Natural” Law Revisited, 334 U. FLA. L. REV. 165 (1982); RONALD
DWORKIN, supra note 58; DWORKIN, Interpretive Concepts, in LAW’S EMPIRE, supra note 7.
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 19
of mind and vision, whereupon the artist's eyes see movements and travel
with the fluidity of scenes.86 To journey the sensual/sensory path, the
literary artist must submerge herself in her subconsciousness and allow her
senses, vision, and emotions to lead her. The destination is often a surprise.
The rational mind is abandoned. Emotions, visions, and senses take over.
The mind only stays to synthesize for the purpose of utilizing language and
constructing sentences, and even so sentences are often spoken through
characters or narrators in their mood, state of mind, culture, and
perspective, as characters take on lives of their own separate from the
creator-artist. The reality created is analogous to Lanham's “rhetorical
ideal,” and characters are often described as "living outside" the author
during the creative process.87
My hypothesis above is not entirely without support from the existing
literature. Although the L&L scholars and philosophers have not focused
concretely and specifically on the antagonistic creative processes between
law and art, they have recognized the uniqueness of spontaneity and the
subconsciously driven nature of artistic creation, which together segregate
art from law. For example, as an avid reader, Posner recognizes the
subconscious impulses of the creative literature. He acknowledges that
literature is prompted by emotion, not by knowledge, and that the great part
of literary creation occurs unconsciously — invention often results in "an
unconscious blur," and painstaking revisions often do not follow a
conscious plan.88 Quite frequently, Posner points out, the author cannot
explain why she did what she did.89
Dworkin acknowledges, too, the spontaneous and boundless nature of
artistic creation. The meaning and nature of artistic works are not fixed, and
that is the characteristic of art.90 The artist's submergence into the
subconscious mind has also appeared in Davidson's work, and is
encompassed in a phenomenon called "James Joyce refining himself out of
existence." Although Davidson recognizes the spontaneity and bypassing of
rationality that artists like Joyce embrace, Davidson (being the philosopher)
tries to rationalize it within his semantic theory. He observes that "James
Joyce's conception of artistic freedom required that he not be the slave of
settled meanings, . . . established styles and tastes . . . ."91 The artistic
bypassing may also apply to grammar and spelling. The semanticist in
Davidson cannot stand this, so he rationalizes that the writer (unlike a
painter) cannot ignore what his readers already know or assume about the
86
JAMES BOYD WHITE, The Judicial Opinion and the Poem: Ways of Reading, Ways of Life, in LAW
AND LITERATURE TEXT AND THEORY, (Lenora Ledwon ed., Garland 1996).
87
An extreme example of this segregation between author and imagined characters is typified in the
classic short story, La Horla, by the French “king” of short stories, Guy de Maupassant. In La Horla, a
man’s imagination becomes his reality – an entity that is born out of his internal journey and descending
into madness. See GUY DE MAUPASSANT, La Horla, in THE NECKLACE AND OTHER SHORT STORIES
(Foachin Neugroshel trans., Dover Publications 2003).
88
See POSNER, supra note 58, at 69-71.
89
Id.
90
See DWORKIN, supra note 7, at 45-86, 176-224.
91
DONALD DAVIDSON, James Joyce and Humpty Dumpty, in PHILOSOPHY AND THE ARTS 1, 4 (Peter
French, Theodore Uehling & Howard Wettstein eds., 1991); DONALD DAVIDSON, INQUIRIES INTO
TRUTH AND INTERPRETATION 141-54, 183-98, 245-64 (1984); DAVIDSON, supra note 11, at 433-45.
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 21
words he uses, concluding that Joyce has not "refined himself out of
existence," but rather, by the “violent originality” of his language, has
simply “shifted the burden of understanding and insight onto his bemused
readers.” The creative energy is thus forced upon the reader by the writer's
abrupt and original use of language. By engaging his reader, the author
appears invisible, and the interpreter becomes involved in the creative task
— a recreation of the original creation! According to Davidson, Joyce only
doubles his distance from the reader. He does not really “refine himself out
of existence.”92
Lanham likewise recognizes the difference in the creative processes of
the two disciplines. Quoting Buffon, he describes a method of writing in
which:
[Y]ou (the writer) possess your subject fully, reflect upon it sufficiently to
see clearly the order of your thoughts, to put them in a continuous order of
which each point represents a single idea. And once you have taken up
your pen, it must follow from point to point without wandering . . . It is
this that makes a style rigorous, lends it unity, paces it and this alone will
render it exact and simple, balanced and clear.93
This kind of methodical writing is more indicative of the type of
rationality and logic that predominates legal work products, akin to
Wetlaufer's “rhetoric of law.” Having described this type of rational
writing, in defense of his “rhetorical ideal,” Lanham then poses the
question, "Who writes this way?"94 He points to a different kind of writing
in which the writer "depends on the suggestive powers of language,"
"surrender[s] [herself] to language,” and "shuttle[s] continually between a
nominalist universe and a realistic one."95 Lanham's distinction and
description of his "rhetoric reality" — where intuition becomes the new
form of objectivity and opaqueness may substitute for clarity, outlines the
periphery of the divergence between law and art.
Wetlaufer also sets out the premises that separate law from art. Judicial
opinions emphasize the rule of law, and seek closure and dispute resolution.
Literature, on the other hand, invites open texture, presents multiple voices,
and appeals to contingency, emotions and imagination. In legal writing, the
goal is to render black or white that which is gray. Literary writing, on the
other hand, is the pursuit of a vision, wherever it leads.96 Wetlaufer also
leads us to the divergence that exists in scholarship, pedagogy, and critical
studies between the two disciplines.97 Unlike legal scholarship, literary
scholarship does not seek to identify one true meaning, one objective truth,
or a right answer. Arguments in literary scholarship are usually less
92
See Davidson, James Joyce and Humpty Dumpty, supra note 91, at 10-12.
93
LANHAM, supra note 33, at 23.
94
Id.
95
Id.
96
See Wetlaufer, supra note 20.
97
See generally Wetlaufer, supra note 20.
22 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
coercive, less linear, and less exertive of step-by-step control over readers
and audience.98
Law is cerebral. Art is sensory. Law tells. Art shows. Law rationalizes.
Art feels. Law renders definitude. Art explores infinity. The
characterizations can go on and they may not be new. Artists are trained to
get in touch with their senses and show them in language. Lawyers are
trained to be rational and to will or pattern logic into language. “The
training of lawyers is a training in logic. The processes of analogy,
discrimination, and deduction are those in which they are most at home.
The language of judicial decision is the language of logic . . . . The logical
method and form flatter that longing for certainty and for repose which is in
every human mind . . . .”99
The key differences, therefore, lie principally in the creative processes.
However, the L&L movement of the past decades might have skipped the
incompatibility in order to make law and literature into a "happy couple,"100
or at least “an odd couple” with reconcilable differences!
The overlapping zone between law and art is possible, as identified by
the L&L movement, only because the artist must use language to put her
audience in fictive time and place and achieve what is known in the
performing arts as a sense of suspended disbelief, where "success . . . is
measured by the faithfulness of the imitation."101 The same test of
believability exists in the literary art. This explains why rhetoric, when
applied to law, is often characterized as the ethical appeal of truth -- the
advocate who persuades must win the audience's confidence in her
commitment and conviction, in the truth of her speech, and in the sense of
personal identification with the ills or threat of harm she seeks to eradicate.
While the goals may be shared, lawyers who are rhetoricians get there by
consciously arranging their discourse, a task that involves logic, rationality,
planning, and conceptualization. The artist, on the other hand, gets there by
surrendering to the impulses of the senses. The difference in the path
traveled is too fundamental to envision a happy marriage between the two.
The lawyer's path to successful persuasion is more like an accomplished
mission, a purpose set and achieved. In contrast, the artist's path to
persuasion — the attainment of believability in the great art — is natural
and spontaneous like a discovery. Art then becomes as broad as an attitude,
a way of living and working, an existence, a manner of traveling, and an
approach to creation that sets it far apart from structured legal thinking and
writing that can be planned and shaped ahead of its own birth.
Those who advocate an interdisciplinary approach to art and law often
resort to the observation that the two disciplines should naturally intertwine
98
For example, Wetlaufer describes the traditional Kingsfieldian or D'Amatoian legal pedagogue's
viewpoint as follows: Legal education should mean assault of the mind, exposing the students' sloppy
ways of thinking and lazy mental attitude, capitalizing on their mental and psychological insecurity, the
humiliation of not knowing the answer, and their anti-pleasure experiences. Wetlaufer calls this method
of law teaching the “pedagogy of assault” See id. at 1578-79.
99
Holmes, supra note 26, at 465-66.
100
THE HAPPY COUPLE: LAW AND LITERATURE (J. Neville Turner & Pamela Williams eds., 1994).
101
LANHAM, supra note 33, at 1, 18.
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 23
102
See WHITE, supra note 86, at 5.
103
Id. at 9.
104
Id. at 6-7.
24 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
105
Id.
106
See id. at 17.
107
See Lanham, supra note 33.
108
Lochner vs. New York, 198 U.S. 45, 74 (1905) (Holmes, J., dissenting).
109
POSNER, supra note 58, at 77-82.
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 25
Yet, under close scrutiny, the Lochner dissent is not at all a statement of
art, but at best an illustration of the art of law (using the terminologies and
definitional concepts that I set forth under Part II of this Article). To begin,
its author, Oliver Wendell Holmes, states a generalization: "This case is
decided upon an economic theory which a large part of the country does
not entertain."110 The statement, as Posner points out, exudes confidence
and serenity, immediately drawing readers' attention by putting them on the
defense, and building suspense by invoking their curiosity. Ethical appeal,
the plain style, the simple man's style are all rhetorical tools — the artifice
of sophisticated intellectuals who seek to persuade or Wetlaufer’s rhetoric
of law discussed earlier. Yet, Justice Holmes’s beginning sentence is
precisely what artists would avoid — the generalization of a concept
devoid of sense-memory recollection. Even with all of its strong points,
Holmes's opening sentence is not, and cannot be based on the senses.
Let us compare it with the opening of Nabokov's famous-infamous
Lolita, which consists of pure deliberate exploration of the senses, images,
and emotions, all in a moment-to-moment rendition: "Lolita, light of my
life, fire of my loins. My sin, my soul. Lo-lee-ta: the tip of the tongue
taking a trip of three steps down the palate to tap, at three, on the teeth. Lo.
Lee. Ta."111 The writing of Holmes is intellectual deliciousness, while
Nabokov's prose is sensual. Setting aside the obvious incompatibility in the
subject matter addressed, the generalization of Holmes's rhetoric versus
Nabokov's deliberate, elaborate exploration of the senses, sound, and vision
are irreconcilable and require different states of mind as well as different
preparation. For law, the preparation is rationalization and organization. For
art, it is subconscious submergence. At best, law may borrow from art its
appeal to emotions and playfulness with language achieved as a craft
consciously applied. But law cannot, and should not, borrow the creative
process from which springs the beauty that makes a piece of writing the
literary art.
A likely place where art and law can meet is the statement of facts in
lawyers' briefs. Teachers of courtroom and appellate advocacy stress the
need for the statement of facts to be persuasive, advising lawyers to use
innovative narratives, and to cast facts in the best light for their position,
although they must trace the "neutral" factual record. But even there, in the
freer format of the statement of facts, the moment-to-moment nature of art
cannot dictate the style for the factual summary demanded by law.
Returning to Holmes, even with all its rhetorical power and conscious
disregard of conventional legal writing principles, the Lochner dissent did
not exhibit the moment-to-moment approach found in the following
passage from Albert Camus’ L'Etrangere. Here, Camus depicts a senseless
murder on a sun-drenched Algerian beach, the site of a tragedy that he
describes as "the nakedness of man faced with the absurd:”112
110
Lochner, 198 U.S. at 75 (Holmes, J., dissenting).
111
VLADIMIR NABOKOV, LOLITA 9 (NY Penguin 1996).
112
I have chosen Camus’s "L'Etrangère" because of its heavy philosophical and moral orientation
(exploring issues of choices, coincidences, and the human conditions in the background of a criminal
26 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
[T]he Arab drew his knife and held it up to me in the sun. The light shot
off the steel and it was like a long flashing blade cutting at my forehead.
At the same instant the sweat in my eyebrows dripped down over my
eyelids all at once and covered them with a warm, thick film. My eyes
were blinded behind the curtain of tears and salt. All I could feel were the
cymbals of sunlight crashing on my forehead and, indistinctly, the
dazzling spear flying up from the knife in front of me. The scorching
blade slashed at my eyelashes and stabbed at my stinging eyes. That's
when everything begin to reel. The sea carried up a thick, fiery breath. It
seemed to me as if the sky split open from one end to the other to rain
down fire. My whole being tensed and I squeezed my hand around the
revolver. The trigger gave; I felt the smooth underside of the butt; and
there, in that noise, sharp and deafening at the same time, is where it all
started. I shook off the sweat and sun. I knew that I had shattered the
harmony of the day, the exceptional silence of a beach where I'd been
happy. Then I fired four more times at the motionless body where the
bullets lodged without leaving a trace. And it was like knocking four
quick times on the door of unhappiness.113
Such a moment-to-moment rendition of facts, focusing on senses and
imageries, has not been characteristic of the factual description that
typically makes its way into a statement of fact in a brief. The inherent
constraint of law consciously disregards and discards the
moment-to-moment description and concentrates, instead, on thrift and
emphasis.
Holmes, however, was known to be more daring with the aesthetic
aspect of his legal writing. In one of his speeches, he spoke of "a ragbag
full of general principles — a throng of glittering generalities, like a swarm
of little bodiless cherubs fluttering at the top of one of Correggio's
pictures."114 Here he was employing the craft of a creative artist by
bringing particularized images to life. But art is more than just the creation
of imageries. Where desired, the imageries connect to reactive emotions,
pushed to the limit, explicit or implied, leading to exploration of
dimensions not readily verifiable by science such as dream sequences and
even the unproven — an adventure the law may not be willing to embrace.
The imaginative and creative forces of legal argument, no matter how
brilliant, simply are curtailed and cannot be allowed to surpass the logical
structure of thoughts built on empirical truths; otherwise, the system of
regulated conduct breaks down. Art expands dimensions of imagination by
following impulses. Law restricts them to rationality and literal reality.
The difference between art and law is not one of fiction versus
non-fiction. The following passage of creative non-fiction writing,
illustrates the connection of images to reactive emotions laid bare, even if
justice system). On its face, this orientation seems to lend the work more readily to law. Yet, as Camus's
passage illustrates, similarities in contents and subject matter are totally irrelevant to the incompatibility
in the mental products.
113
ALBERT CAMUS, ESTRANGER, (Matthew Ward trans., First Vintage International Edition 1989).
114
OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES, JR., The Use of Law Schools, in COLLECTED LEGAL PAPERS 35, 42
(1920).
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 27
I could not forget those big blooms of whitish, ivory petals, large
enough to fill up a porcelain winter melon soup bowl that could
feed five adults. My aunt would place the blue and white
translucent bowl out on the mossy porch to collect rainwater. She
would pick a fresh bloom, severing it from its grainy, long stem
with a pair of scissors. I could still hear the tiny, shrieking sound
of the blades, opening and closing in the midair. She would put
the bloom inside the bowl and place it on the rosewood table that
faced the ancestral altar. The scent filled up the room, lingering
upon white lace curtains and alongside the edges of dark
furniture that shone with lemon juice. Every day, my aunt
squeezed lemon on the wood and polished it with a damp cloth,
so I could smell lemon in the air, along with the sweet scent of
the fresh, white bloom. I always thought the dark furniture
looked so sad behind those closed shutters, sorrowful and stern
like the pair of eyes of my dead mandarin grandfather, staring
from his black and white picture down to the porcelain bowl
where the flower floated. I imagined the flower would turn into a
woman's face, smooth and white, with painted brows like two
slanting ink strokes. Like a faint stream of smoke, she curled
herself out of the bowl and materialized into my mother, with all
that long, black hair floating behind her back. She wore white
silk pajamas, the soft fabric reminding me of the velvety, light,
smooth texture of the white bloom petals. Her naked feet, rosy
and slender, raised above the floor as she floated through the
darkroom. She walked around me, circling me with the shadows
of her arms. And then my dead grandfather, too, would come
alive, walking out of his black-and-white frame to place his
dehydrated, freckled hand on my forehead, the long, curled
fingernails dragging across my temples like the touch of a dry
bamboo branch. And I would faint.
115
Anonymous, The Coffins of Cinnamon, unpublished manuscript, on file with author.
116
See Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.S. 184, 197 (1963) (Stewart, J., concurring) (“I know it [pornography]
when I see it, and the motion picture involved in this case is not that.”).
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 29
Posner agrees that art does not always preach nor aim to make readers
into better persons, recognizing, therefore, the dubious issue of morals in
art.117 For example, descriptions of Satan can borderline on blasphemy, and
artists are frequently drawn to the political extremes, stretching and
challenging norms, not necessarily because they want to preach, but simply
because of the artistic urge to pursue visions endlessly. A sense of amorality
can attach to artistic creation. Artists want admiration of their self-
expression and audience involvement in the reality of their vision, but a
moral end is not necessarily the raison d'etre of art. As overused as it has
been, the phrase "L'Art pour L'Art" (art for the sake of art) still has
significance in the realm of the creative field, serving to defend the
amorality of art.118 In contrast, the concept of justice is clearly at the core of
law. For example, Dworkin is adamant that politics is at the heart of law.119
With his advancement of the aesthetic hypothesis-political hypothesis
dichotomy, Dworkin frowns upon the intentionalists, criticizing them for
narrowing interpretation by restraining it to the author's intention (a
possible rival against his “aesthetic hypothesis”).120 Applying this to law
means that Dworkin would belittle the importance of legislative intent.
Posner appears offended by Dworkin's suggestion that literary
interpretation can work for constitutional or legislative interpretation. In
expressing his displeasure, Posner contributes to the contrast between law
and art by comparing legislative interpretation to literary critiques. Too
many differences exist between the raison d'etre of literature and the
enactment of legislation to permit fruitful analogies or disciplinary crossing
to broaden interpretation.121 Considering the incompatibility in the creative
processes and output discussed above, I wholeheartedly agree with Posner.
To illustrate, Posner contrasts the deciphering of the drafter's intention
in constitutional interpretation against the reading of a political or social
intention into a poem by Yeats.122 The same contrast can be made in
reading a patriotic motive into Chopin's Mazurka or Valse Polonaise for the
purposes of enjoying Chopin; neither Yeats nor Chopin created his art with
the intention to dictate principles or provide authoritarian guidance to
anyone. Nor do we read Yeats or listen to Chopin to find political
messages. On the other hand, the framers of the Constitution wrote words
117
See Posner, supra note 13; Posner, supra note 21.
118
Existentialist philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre suggests, however, that pure aesthetic is not an adequate
test for good literature. "[N]obody can suppose for a moment that it is possible to write a good novel in
praise of anti-Semitism . . . I’d like to know a single good novel whose express purpose was to serve
oppression, a single good novel which has been written against Jews, negroes [sic], workers, or colonial
people.” JEAN-PAUL SARTRE, WHAT IS LITERATURE? 64, n.1 (Bernard Frechtman trans., Philosophical
Library 1949) (1948). Thus, the morally vicious cannot be aesthetically great.
119
Dworkin raises the inquiry whether politics should be part of art or literature interpretation. See
RONALD DWORKIN, A Matter of Principle (1985), reprinted in How Law is like Literature, in LAW AND
LITERATURE: TEXT AND THEORY, supra note 71, at 29, 45. Fish says that it is not, concluding that art,
politics, and law unite in philosophy. See STANLEY FISH, DOING WHAT COMES NATURALLY: CHANGE,
RHETORIC, AND THE PRACTICE OF THEORY IN LITERATURE AND LEGAL STUDIES (Duke Univ. Press
1989), reprinted in Working on the Chain Gang: Interpretation in Law and Literature, in LAW AND
LITERATURE: TEXT AND THEORY 47 (Lenora Ledwon ed., Garland 1996).
120
See Dworkin, supra note 71, at 36-39.
121
See RICHARD POSNER, LAW AND LITERATURE 218-19 (1998).
122
See Posner, supra note 58, at 1363.
30 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
To the extent the L&L movement casts judicial opinions and legal
writing as a literary experience, it can be misleading and create the risk that
the literary artistic creative process will be misunderstood. This
misunderstanding can predispose legal drafters to disregard the constraint
of law, enable lawyers to belittle the restraining nature of the legal process,
and distract them, not only from the purpose of closure in dispute
resolution, but also in the development of precedents for future application
in a common law system. In judicial drafting, it may mean the unnecessary
creation of dicta that confuse future litigants and undermine the doctrines
of justiciability or case-in-controversy. The L&L movement thus brings
risks, as well as benefits, into the law. To understand the risks, it is
worthwhile to explore several observations about the movement.
123
See Barthes, supra note 23, at 142-47. See also Michel Foucault, supra note 76, at 141-60.
124
See Holmes, supra note 7.
125
See WALT WHITMAN, Preface to the 1855 edition of Leaves of Grass, COMPLETE POETRY AND
COLLECTED PROSE 17-18(3d prtg. 1982); Wetlaufer, supra note 20, at 1597 n.166.
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 31
133
See HEIN, supra note 95, at 118.
134
Id.
135
See HEIN, supra note 130.
136
See Posner, supra note 58; Brook Thomas, Cross Examination of Law and Literature (Cambridge
Univ. Press 1987). See also HEIN, supra note 130.
137
See Posner, supra note 13; Posner, supra note 21.
138
See HEIN, supra note 130, at 119.
139
Id. at 122.
140
See Lynne Marie DeCicco, Women and Lawyers in the Mid-19th Century English Novel, in 25
STUDIES IN BRITISH LITERATURE (Edwin Mellen Press 1996). For a broader perspective of rethinking
feminist jurisprudence based on theories of language beyond the contours of the L&L movement, see
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 33
love of literature with their love of law.142 On the other hand, the
excitement of feminists over the prospect of using art innovatively to
improve feminist legal education and to enhance understanding of issues
such as motherhood and child abuse is an implicit recognition of the
existing "emotionless" nature and status of law.143
Fifth, how law and art meet in the commercial world of entertainment
is a case of human nature: our love, taste and flare for the sensational, the
unusual, the profane, and the absurd. Authors who surveyed historical legal
development note that the fascination with sex and violence narrated in the
law was documented as early as the 18th century — passages from 18th
century court transcripts were at times oddly reminiscent of novels.144 One
author called these coincidences the “fictions of law,”145 a title that
paradoxically combines two mutually exclusive concepts.146 The
commercialization of law has blurred the line between the legal and literary
experience for an unknowing consumer public, while the television era and
the growth of the entertainment industry have increasingly intensified the
public’s interest in the sensational. Trials have become a source of audience
fascination, and law can be as notoriously exciting as action novels, veiling
the mundane nature of the majority of the practice. The fascination has
transcended national boundaries — the world has always held certain
curiosity for affluent America's criminal justice system and its various
social issues such as race or gender conflicts, which have become the topic
of artistic treatment even internationally since the 1950s and 1960s.147
Last, as Posner recognizes, the players of the law are competent
professionals, eloquent and skilled in language and orator performances,
but are not necessarily the geniuses of literature.148 Art, in its truest sense, is
not a field for the mediocre; nor does it offer a comfort zone for the
well-trained. Infusing the standard of one into the other can easily result in
unintended disingenuousness. The L&L movement has the potential either
to hurt or to help the public image of lawyers and the profession as they are
portrayed in more popularized art or entertainment avenues. In summary,
the L&L movement should aim to perfect the art of law by incorporating
the craft of art into law, rather than undertaking the incongruent task of
reconciling and balancing the incompatible creative processes of art and
law.
Bruce A. Arrigo, Rethinking the Language of Law, Justice, and Community: Postmodern Feminist
Jurisprudence, in RADICAL PHILOSOPHY OF LAW: CONTEMPORARY CHALLENGES TO MAINSTREAM
LEGAL THEORY AND PRACTICE 88, (David S. Caudill & Steven Jay Gold eds., Humanities Press 1995).
141
See TOBIN, supra note 128, at 140.
142
See BEYOND PORTIA: WOMEN, LAW AND LITERATURE IN THE UNITED STATES, supra note 126.
143
See MELISSA HARRISON, A Time of Passionate Learning, Using Feminism, Law, and Literature to
Create a Learning Community, in BEYOND PORTIA, supra note 126, at 327.
144
See BETH SWAN, FICTIONS OF LAW: AN INVESTIGATION OF THE LAW IN 18TH CENTURY ENGLISH
FICTION 13 (1997).
145
See id.
146
See id.
147
One example was Sartre's “Le Putain Respectueuse,” which has been criticized as a poor attempt by
an outsider-philosopher to depict America and its racial relations in stereotypic terms. See JEAN PAUL
SARTRE, The Respectful Prostitute, in NO EXIT AND THREE OTHER PLAYS 249 (L. Abel trans., Vintage
Books 1949).
148
See Posner, supra note 13; Posner, supra note 21.
34 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
156
See Ellen K. Solender, The Story of A Self-Effacing Feminist Law Professor, 4 AM. U. J. GENDER
SOC. POL’Y & L. 249 (1995) Ellen Solender was Professor Emerita of Law at Southern Methodist
University at the time her article was published.
157
Id. at 263.
158
See Susan Estrich, Rape, 95 YALE L.J. 1087 (1986).
159
See William Eskridge, Jr., A History of Same-Sex Marriage, 79 VA. L. REV. 1419 (1993).
160
See generally PATRICIA J. WILLIAMS, THE ALCHEMY OF RACE AND RIGHTS (1991); PATRICIA J.
WILLIAMS, THE ROOSTER’S EGG (1995).
161
See Richard K. Sherwin, A Matter of Voice and Plot: Belief and Suspicion in Legal Storytelling, 87
MICH. L. REV. 543 (1988); Conti, supra note 7.
162
See Luz E. Herrera, Challenging a Tradition of Exclusion: The History of an Unheard Story at
Harvard Law School, 5 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 51 (2002).
163
See, e.g., Van Praagh, supra note 151; Elizabeth J. Samuels, Stories Out of School: Teaching the
Case of Brown v. Voss, 16 CARDOZO L. REV. 1445 (1995).
164
See Toni M. Massaro, Empathy, Legal Storytelling, and the Rule of Law: New Words, Old Wounds?
87 MICH. L. REV. 2099 (1989).
36 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
165
See, e.g., Nancy B. Rapoport, Dressed for Excess: How Hollywood Affects the Professional Behavior
of Lawyers, 14 NOTRE DAME J.L. ETHICS & PUB. POL’Y 49 (2000) (discussing the portrayal of lawyers
in films).
166
See Carrie Mendel-Meadow, Feminist Legal Theory, Critical Legal Studies, and Legal Education or
The Fem-Crits Go to Law School, 38 J. LEGAL EDUC. 61, 62 (1988); Daniel A. Farber & Suzanna
Sherry, Telling Stories Out of School: An Essay on Legal Narratives, 45 STAN. L. REV. 807, 810-11
(1993).
167
See Kathryn Abrams, Hearing the Call of Stories, 79 CAL. L. REV. 971 (1991) (examining feminist
narrative scholarship as distinctive form of critical legal discourse).
168
See CAROL GILLIGAN, IN A DIFFERENT VOICE: PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY AND WOMEN’S
DEVELOPMENT (1982).
169
See, e.g., Alex M. Johnson, Defending the Use of Narrative and Giving Context to the Voice of
Color: Rejecting the Imposition of Process Theory in Legal Scholarship, 79 IOWA L. REV. 803, 804,
806-07 (1994) (criticizing Professors Farber and Sherry’s attempts to evaluate Narratives and Critical
Race Theory legal scholarships against conventional standards).
170
See Farber & Sherry, supra note 166, at 809-10.
171
See, e.g., Robert S. Chang, Toward an Asian American Scholarship: Critical Race Theory, Post-
Structuralism, and Narrative Space, 1 ASIAN L.J. 1 (1994); Anthony S. Chen, Beyond Modernism and
Postmodernism: Working Notes Towards an Asian American Legal Scholarship, 4 ASIAN L.J. 97 (1997).
2005] Law is Law and Art is Art and Shall the Two Ever Meet? 37
172
Richard Delgado, Rodrigo’s Final Chronicle: Cultural Power, the Law Reviews, and the Attack on
Narrative Jurisprudence, 68 S. CAL. L. REV. 545 (1995); Delgado, Storytelling for Oppositionists and
Others: A Plea for Narrative, supra note 150, at 2411-12.
173
See Delgado, supra note 150, at 2412, n.8.
174
See id. at 2412-13.
175
Id. at 2413 (emphasis added).
176
Id.
177
Delgado, Storytelling for Oppositionists, supra note 150, at 2414.
178
Id. at 2415.
179
Id.
180
Id. at n.22 (citing David O. Friedrichs, Narrative Jurisprudence and Other Heresies: Legal
Education at the Margin, 40 J. LEGAL EDUC. 3 (1990)).
38 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
to her. The story serves as a bridge to those who share a similar vision, or
as a means for inciting change among those who do not. Without the
audience’s suspended disbelief, the actor, the novelist and the “narrative”
legal writer all fail. It is in this highly demanding and successful creation of
the audience’s suspended disbelief that law and art meet.
Put differently, in the process of communication and interpretation, the
end result of persuasion must be accomplished via the creation of a change
in the attitude and belief system of the message recipient. In a way, the
storytelling must somehow fill a conscious or subconscious need and desire
to know in the readers, no matter how unpopular, unfamiliar, or unexpected
the story may seem to be. If the story told does not meet this emotional
need or invoke this intellectual curiosity, the story will fall upon deaf ears
and the task of advocacy will not be accomplished.
At the same time, the narrative must be restrained with a sense of
mission and adherence to truth. For example, feminist narratives may
contain certain aesthetic value and features like creative nonfiction, yet
they cannot lose sight of the overall political agenda or their social
objectives. As more literary techniques are employed in the writing of legal
narratives and statement-of-fact advocacy, greater constraint must be
exercised to preserve the analytical component of legal scholarship.186
Storytelling must be accompanied with legal analysis and/or concrete
suggestions for legal reform, and must be tested against standards of
truthfulness and typicality. At the same time, the writer-advocate must be
ready to challenge those standards and create new ones in order to change
the status quo, and to abolish or rewrite unchallenged assumptions taken as
justifications in themselves.187 In Delgado’s words, “the task is akin to
making the bed while still lying in it.”188 But in the end, the aesthetic order
of law must prevail as the total ambiance for written work, and the craft of
fictional art must be tempered with the value of truth, because law reviews
are not meant to be novels, no matter how heart-wrenching or beautifully
created. Legal writing is, after all, about the relative search for truth and the
mission of law. “Creative” legal writing is about new statements of
intellectual honesty in stretching the limits of acceptability and normative
formation. As suggested by Mary Coombs, at the end of the day, outsider
scholarship is judged in its ability to advance the interests of the people of
that discrete community.189 It is “art for that discrete society” and not “art
for the sake of art.”
186
See id. at 1016-17.
187
See Farber & Sherry, supra note 166 (evaluating standards for assessing storytelling legal
scholarship, including validity issues and truthfulness). But see Jane B. Baron, Resistance to Stories, 67
S. CAL. L. REV. 255 (1994) (challenging Farber and Sherry’s views as accepting the status quo standards
of truthfulness as valid, which is the very assumption the narrative form seeks to abandon). Cf. Johnson,
supra note 169 (criticizing Farber and Sherry’s attempts to evaluate Narratives in Critical Race Theory
legal scholarships against conventional standards).
188
Delgado, supra note150, at 2439 n.83.
189
See Mary I. Coombs, Outsider Scholarship: The Law Review Stories, 63 U. COLO. L. REV. 683, 713
(1992) (noting that in judging quality of outsider scholarship, one must include the analytical
component).
40 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
192
See Richard A. Posner, Against the Law Reviews, LEGAL AFFAIRS, Nov.-Dec. 2004, at 57.
193
See id.
194
See id. at 58.
195
Id.
196
See Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Theory of Legal Interpretation, 12 HARV. L. REV.. 417 (1899).
197
See, e.g., PETER BROOKS, TROUBLING CONFESSIONS: SPEAKING GUILT IN LAW AND LITERATURE
(2000) (using law and literature to explore the place of confessions within Anglo-American
criminology).
42 Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal [Vol. 15:1
Neither art nor law is a discipline in which one can dabble and hope to
achieve greatness. Those who claim they are successfully combining both
are reducing the pursuit to a hobby, or a means of making a living, no more
ennobling, no less demeaning than writing a commercial murder thriller or
running a restaurant. The incompatibility in the creative processes demands
forceful choices and utmost devotion to one field to the exclusion of the
other. Any illusion that Art is Art and Law is Law but the two can meet
successfully in one life as “dual professions,” in most cases, is the mere
consolation of one who is blessed with the skills and talent for dancing with
words, but cannot make a commitment to a full-time artistic career nor take
its consequences. To protect the sanctity and integrity of the
sensual/sensory path to her art, which, under my hypothesis, is antagonistic
to the generalization and rationalization of the lawyer's mind, even the most
gentle artist would probably agree with Shakespeare: "The first thing we
do: Let's kill all the lawyers."200
198
I am not talking about another John Grisham here, but rather another John Steinbeck, who took on
many blue-collar jobs before he received the Nobel Prize.
199
Farber & Sherry, supra note 166, at 845.
200
WILLIAM SHAKESPEARE, THE SECOND PART OF HENRY VI 100 (William Montgomery ed., Penguin
Books 2000) (1967).