Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine To Organizational Ethics
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine To Organizational Ethics
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine To Organizational Ethics
Writing Sample submitted for the Application for PhD in Religion, Ethics and Public Life at the
Northwestern University
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
Ethics Defined
Taylor (1975) defines ethics as inquiry into the nature and grounds of morality where
the term morality is taken to mean moral judgments, standards and rules of conduct. Hsing –
Chau Tseng et al (2009) defines ethics as the study and philosophy of human conduct with an
emphasis on the determination of either right or wrong. Accordingly, ethics involves defining,
evaluating and understanding concepts of right and wrong behaviour. Contrary to popular
opinion, ethical and legal constructs are not always the same thing. Ethical often outline conduct
that exceeds what may be the legal requirements of society. Hsing – Chau Tseng adds that
business ethics can be both a normative and a descriptive discipline [ CITATION Hsi20 \p 587 \l 4105
].
With these definitions in mind, this study seeks to investigate the implications of Kant’s
moral doctrine to businesses and organizations. It simply asks the question, what are the
measurement tool – its meaning, obligations, objections and implications for organization are
explored. Secondly, the study investigates the relationship between moral codes and the
categorical imperative in business and organization management. Finally, this study explores the
question of responsibility in organizations. Two models are investigated in the light of Kantian
hybrid of both.
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
Kant lived and wrote during a period in European intellectual history called the
“Enlightenment” which stretched from the mid-seventeenth century to the early nineteenth
century. This is period that produced the ideas about human rights and democracy that inspired
that is, in humanity’s ability to solve problems through logical analysis. Enlightenment thinkers
like Kant felt that history had placed them in the unique position of being able to provide clear
arguments for their beliefs (Philips, 2002, p. 4). The ideas of earlier generations, they thought,
had been determined by myths and traditions; though their own ideas were based on reason.
Kant’s philosophical goal was to use logical analysis to understand reason itself. He
argued that before we embarked on the process of analyzing our world, we must have a good
grasp of the mental tools we would be using. Thus in the Critique of Pure Reason (Kant, 1900)
he set about developing a comprehensive picture of how our mind-our “reason” – receives and
processes information.
Kant mentioned that his inspiration towards the undertaking of such a project was David
Hume (1711-76), the Scottish philosopher who woke him up from intellectual “slumber.” The
further with this idea, arguing that it is not just an idea that we employ to make sense of our
perceptions. Rather, it is a concept that we cannot help but employ [ CITATION Bri02 \p 5 \l 4105 ].
According to Kant, causation and a number of other basic ideas – time and space, for instance –
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
are hardwired, as it were, into our minds. Thus whenever we try to understand what we see, we
cannot help but think in terms of causes and effects (Kant, 1979).
In the Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant (1979) applies the technique of
using reason to determine what moral choices we should make. He tries to develop a moral
philosophy that depends only on the fundamental concepts of reason. He contends that just as we
cannot rely on our picture of the world for knowledge about how the world really is, so we
cannot rely on our expectations about events in the world in developing moral principles.
This thinking has not gone without question. Recent philosophers and scholars have
criticized Enlightenment philosophers like Kant for placing too much confidence in reason,
arguing that rational analysis isn’t the best way to deal with moral questions [ CITATION Foo72 \l
4105 ]. Others have argued that the Enlightenment thinkers were, in fact pompous to think that
they could discover the timeless truth of reason and that in fact, their ideas were determined by
their culture just as all other people’s are[ CITATION Mar95 \l 4105 ].
Further, some have gone to the extent of associating Enlightenment with the crimes of
imperialism, noting a similarity between the idea of reason dispelling myth and the idea that
western people have a right and a duty to supplant less “advanced” civilizations [ CITATION
Lou00 \l 4105 ].
The goal of the Grounding for Metaphysics of Morals was to develop a clearer
understanding of moral principles, so that people may better avert distractions [ CITATION Bri02 \l
4105 ]. Accordingly, as it is, people generally assume that moral principles must apply to all
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
rational beings at all places and all times. Thus moral principles must be based on concepts of
Several general principles about moral duties may be advanced. First, actions are moral if
and only if they are undertaken for the sake of morality alone – that is, without any ulterior
motive. Second, the moral quality of an action is judged, not according to the action’s
consequences, but according to the motive that produced it. Third, actions are moral if and only
if they are undertaken out of respect for the moral law [ CITATION Alt07 \l 4105 ][ CITATION Bri02 \p
7 \l 4105 ].
The moral law must be a general formula that is applicable in all situations. This is
because, rather than command specific actions; it must express the principle that actions should
be undertaken with pure motives, without consideration of consequences, and out of pure
reverence for law. The formula postulated for this is: we should act in such a way that we could
want the maxim of our action to become a universal law[ CITATION Alt07 \l 4105 ]. Even though
the operating assumption is that people generally have a decent intuitive sense for this law, Kant
(1979) argued that it would be helpful for philosophy to state the law clearly so that people can
keep it in mind.
Moral principles, Kant posed, should come from reason, not from experience for all
experiences depend on particular circumstances, whereas moral principles must have absolute
This general formula – which is reason’s fundamental moral principle, is what Kant
according to the same formula as the moral law: act only in such a way that you could want the
maxim of your action to become a universal law. Thus when people violate the categorical
imperative, they apply a different standard to their own behaviour than they would want applied
to everyone else in the form of a universal law[ CITATION Bri02 \p 7 \l 4105 ] . Kant (1979)
The Categorical imperative may also be formulated as a requirement that we must not
treat other rational beings as mere means to our own purposes[ CITATION Bri02 \p 8 \l 4105 ].
The argument so far has established what the moral law is, but has not demonstrated why
we feel we should be moral. Accordingly, the basis of morality is the concept of freedom – the
Kant holds that the fundamental principle of our moral duties is a categorical imperative.
It is an imperative because it is a command (e.g., “Leave the pen. Take the paper.”) More
precisely, it commands us to exercise our wills in a particular way, not to perform some action or
rational wills, without reference to any ends that we might or might not have. It does not, in other
words, apply to us on the condition that we have antecedently adopted some goal for
Kant defines virtue as “the moral strength of a human being's will in fulfilling his duty”
(6:405) and vice as principled immorality. Thus it may seem that for virtue to prevail the
individual must master the moral strength to fulfill his duty. Duty, being inseparable from human
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
life therefore provides fertile ground for Kant’s enforcing his moral doctrine. The categorical
imperative, therefore, binds every rational being to make moral judgments and consequent
actions. It is not suggestive, but rather demands, only this time a rational process is involved in
both the decision making and the execution of the desirable action. Thus every human is obliged
Since an individual is the same when jogging and when eating, then they must be the
same when working, doing business, swimming and shopping too. Hence one must always act
with the same moral law. The categorical imperative, therefore, obliges even businesses and
organizations to act morally. It would be argued that without a moral social backdrop business
would not be able to function. Corporations are an integral part of our society, and they reflect
our values as surely and as well as any of our other institutions. Yet, there is great confusion
when it comes to discussing values -- especially moral or ethical values -- and business. People
in business rarely do so publicly, and non-business people who raise the issues seem to do so
Critics of the Categorical Imperative argue that organisations do not have the
predispositions that would make them bound to it. Their first argument is that an artificial,
nonmaterial entity is not subject to natural laws or affected by desires, and as such cannot be
tempted to act wrongly[ CITATION Alt07 \p 257 \l 4105 ]. By way of example, Altman contends:
Despite its seeming similarity to our desire for happiness, a company cannot be said to
have the profit motive anymore than the state can crave tax revenues. Members of the
congress may want the money to spend, and majority of the citizens may support tax
increase, but the state itself cannot want anything. Similarly, employees may be
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
motivated to increase profits, even at the expense of their moral obligations, but to say
that the business desires profit is imprecise. For states and corporations, there is no self-
interest to attempt them away from the demands of duty [ CITATION Alt07 \p 257 \l 4105 ].
The second objection posited against use of the Categorical Imperative in Organizations
is that, having no rational nature, they can neither be said to reason nor legislate moral
laws[ CITATION Alt07 \p 257 \l 4105 ] . They do not have the capacity to perform moral actions or
make moral decisions. Any attribute towards morality may only be used in a metaphorical sense
just in the same way we can say a school needs to be investigated or a cow wants to be washed.
The contention is that an organization has no “faculty of freedom” in the relevant sense of the
term[ CITATION Kan \l 4105 ] . Thus the organization, being merely a legal entity, has no
consciousness of moral constraint and thus no humanity in the sense that Kant understands it
[ CITATION Alt07 \p 257 \l 4105 ]. This makes sense particularly if Kant’s thinking is clearly
understood: that is, the fact of reason proves that one is a moral agent who is necessitated by the
ethics because the categorical imperative rules out actions such as deceptive advertising and
exploitative working conditions, both of which treat people merely as means to an end (2007, p.
253).” To him, those who apply Kant this way often hold businesses themselves morally
accountable (2007, p. 253). He even posits that the conception of collective responsibility
Altman’s (2007) central argument is that businesses [and organizations in general] have
neither the inclinations nor the capacity to reason thereby lacking the conditions necessary for
When an organization is viewed as an instrument for the achievement of one’s own ends
then it appears that a person is simply using the organization for their own ends. This
would violate the second formulation of the categorical imperative (Bowie, 1999, pp. 83-
84).
Bowie argues that a business must be treated as an end in itself and never as a means. He
stakes his claim in the argument that a business is a moral agent and owing to that capacity to be
But Altman rebuts that it may be argued that placing ethical constraints on business
decisions is misguided, that business is a game with its own rules, where deception is not only
Many authors claim that social obligations should in certain cases restrict the profit
motive… and Kantian ethics has been used to support this view: wealth is conditionally
good, but a good will is the only thing that is good without qualification. The actions of
business people can thus be judged against moral principles, which are unsurprising,
since business decisions are a kind of human action and all human actions are morally
constrained…. By Contrast, many theoretical orientations in business ethics, including
supposedly Kantian approaches, depend on the assumption that we can assess the
morality of corporate actions apart from the decisions of particular business people –
praising Johnson & Johnson or condemning Philip Morris rather than the members of
their ever changing board of directors [ CITATION Alt07 \p 254 \l 4105 ].”
Implications for Organizations
The categorical imperative has far reaching implications to organizations. In the first
case, it contends that we ought not to treat people merely as a means but as instead with respect
for personhood and humanity. Since organizations are run by people, it logically ensues that the
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
way people are treated in an organization determines whether it (the organization) is ethically
upright or not.
It is also argued that organizations have the capacity to make transactions and thus
Because a business has its own characteristic decision procedures, and because it acts in
ways that are morally relevant, it seems that the business itself is subject to moral
scrutiny. This is true primarily because responsibility is diffused across a number of
different corporate positions, such that assigning responsibility is often unfeasible except
in terms of the corporation as a whole.[ CITATION Alt07 \p 255 \l 4105 ]
By example, he (Altman) argues that when a business contaminates drinking water, it is
the result of what is produced and how it is produced, as well as corporate policies regarding the
disposal of chemical waste – and all the workers, administrators, and investors who contribute to
this lengthy process. There are many causes that give rise to the eventual effect [ CITATION
Alt07 \p 255 \l 4105 ] . He however adds that although evaluating corporate actions does not
preclude individual responsibility, there are some cases in which responsibility cannot be
attributed to any particular agent(s). In this sense therefore, personal responsibility may not
If businesses act in the morally relevant sense, we can apply the different versions of the
policies for the formula of universal law rules out deceptive business practices [ CITATION Alt07 \p
255 \l 4105 ]. Ultimately, it is agreeable that personal moral philosophies quite uniquely
thus:
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
We have shown that personal moral philosophies have a direct impact on the perception
of ethics and moral responsibility. Again, more idealistic individuals tend to follow more
universal moral rules of behaviour, whereas the more relativistic individuals feel that a
moral action is defined by the nature of the situation and the person confronted by an
ethical dilemma.[ CITATION Placeholder1 \p 478 \l 4105 ]
Thus the more aligned individual philosophies are, the more coherently they will pull
together to achieve the organizations goals and objectives. If a disparity exists as noted by Vitell
would thus be fitting in the pattern of the categorical imperative to design a pattern of reasoning
that allows for consistency indecision making. A pattern of reasoning would effectively control
the disparity created by different individual philosophies within the organization. Whether
idealistic or relativistic, decision-making will have the benefit of reflection within a clearly
defined pattern thereby bringing the most desirable results. Such a pattern is found in the
Organizations are inseparable from their stakeholders, who are in fact, moral agents
subject to ethical choices. This inevitably subjects every organization to ethical scrutiny. Altman
admits that this is especially true primarily because responsibility is diffused across a number of
different corporate positions, such that assigning responsibility is often unfeasible except in
terms of the corporation as a whole[ CITATION Alt07 \p 255 \l 4105 ]. He adds that although
evaluating corporate actions does not preclude individual responsibility, there are some cases in
which we cannot attribute responsibility to any particular agent(s). Thus personal responsibility
seems inadequate to address the morality of at least some business decisions [ CITATION Alt07 \p
255 \l 4105 ].
John Bruhn (2009) has said that every organization has formed a moral identity, that is, it
boundaries of moral and amoral behaviour (2009, p. 206). He (Bruhn) adds that an organization
takes a stand, by its own actions or inactions, by asserting how it collectively will act and how
individuals in it are expected to act. It would be expected, therefore, that a code of ethics is quite
necessary for ensuring the maintenance of such positions. As Scott et al would put it: We assume
that by employing a code of ethics, one can reduce the likelihood of unethical practices through
communicating expectations to all the participants and providing an effective method for
reporting abuse. (Scott, John, Vitell, 2010, p. 471) …in this way, he adds, “The importance of
instituting a code of ethics to formalize ethical behaviour is supported” (Scott, John, Vitell, 2010,
p. 471).
According to Mitchell et al, researchers have consistently argued that the ethical climate
of the work context is largely shaped by organizational managers. Thus, to assist managers in
establishing and maintaining an ethical climate, organizations have implemented formal systems
of ethical codes, corporate ethics audits, standardized procedures and ethics training programmes
documents through which corporations hope to shape employee behaviour and produce change
by making explicit statements as to desired behaviour” [ CITATION Lui09 \p 188 \l 4105 ] . He adds
that “they clarify the objectives that the company pursues, the norms and values that it upholds
and those things for which it may be accountable. Luis Rodriguez-Dominguez et al further states
that more recently, according to Luis Rodriguez – Dominguez et al, Kaptein and Schwartz
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
defined a code of ethics as “a distinct and formal document containing a set of prescriptions
developed by and for a company to guide present and future behaviour on multiple issues for at
least its managers and employees toward each other, the company, external stakeholders, and/or
society in general”[ CITATION Lui09 \p 188 \l 4105 ] . Cynthia et al on the other hand defines codes
of ethics as formalized public statements of corporate principles and rules of conduct that govern
4105 ].
In terms of the codes objectives, there may be a somewhat instrumental reason for
adopting codes, because they can help preserve or legitimate a reputable public image and
prevent public criticism (Bondy et al., 2004, p.450). A code of ethics is a guide to both present
and future behaviour and specifies corporate ethical values and the responsibility of employees
to one another and to organizational stakeholders (Cynthia, Stohl, 2009, p. 607). Fleege and
Adrian (2004, p. 1) have mentioned that codes can be reasonably designed to prevent wrong-
1. Honest and ethical behaviour, including the ethical handling of actual or apparent
Noting Peters and Waterman’s discovery, Scott et al asserts that successful companies
typically have a well defined code of values that are shared throughout the
A code of ethics helps to define borders within the organization, thereby clearing the gray
areas that may create conflict or lead to misconduct within the organization. According to Bruhn,
the occurrence of gray area dilemmas are usually more common in organizations where ‘ethics is
not ‘integrated all the way through’ the organization and the organization does not function as a
Most authors seem to be in agreement that there ought to be a code of ethics for every
organization. What seems unsettled is whether each organization should set up its own code of
ethics or whether there should be a universal canon. However, a code of ethics, whether
organizational or universal defies Kantian theory that calls for a rational approach to ethical
decision – making. The rule theory, He (Kant) would argue just like Rene ten Bos (1997) does,
Bureaucrats are not basically interested in debating the goals of the organization they are
working for, but narrowly focuses on the task that is to be carried out: they accept that the
significant of the job is never related to the person who carries it out, but rather to what
other people believe the job is meant for; they see the world as a bundle of problems
which are solvable in a rational and scientific way; they abhor unpredictability,
spontaneity and chance; and they refrain form personal opinion and accept whatever the
‘organization’ claims to be true[ CITATION Bos97 \p 998 \l 4105 ].
Sounding good as it may be, a code of ethics is inconsistent with Kantian philosophy if it
is projected as a set of rules to be followed without individual reflection on the purpose and
result. Kant would object to the reduction of individuals into moral robots who follow some
legalistic pattern of behaviour as if they had no capacity to reason. For organizations to develop
meaningful and agreeable1 ethical codes that follow the Kantian pattern they must first learn the
1
The argument is agreeable according to Kantian thinking. Kant was a deontologist; deontological theories are duty based. What
makes actions right or wrong are not the consequences. The categorical imperative states: “Act according to a maxim which can,
at the same time, be valid as a universal law.”
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
moral norms. As Peck (2007) has written, his (Kant) categorical imperative does not provide a
robot-like test for the untutored, as some critics suggest[ CITATION Pec07 \p 209 \l 4105 ].
(1964/1797)… where one will find Kant’s beliefs about moral education – an education
necessary for using the categorical imperative [ CITATION Pec07 \p 209 \l 4105 ] . Indeed Kant
himself wrote virtue is the product of pure practical reason in so far as reason… [ CITATION Imm79
\p 477 \t \l 4105 ]
Peck is not alone as Leslie et al calls for an education that builds moral courage in
individuals rather than enforce regulations as a means of ensuring adherence to ethical codes.
They write:
Collective Responsibility
At the heart of the categorical imperative is the case for individual responsibility.
Individuals are suppose to make ethical decision after a careful processing of facts that involves
thinking through and coming up with a solution based on the criteria set afore. This is where a
major objection to the applicability of Kant’s moral doctrine in business begins. Altman (2007)
writes that the fact that, for Kant, only fully autonomous reasoning is morally praiseworthy
Even as Altman argues that the principle of collective responsibility denies Kant a place
We can take a clue here from legal responsibility. [The corporation] can be sued, fined,
forced to make reparations, desist from certain activities, and undertake others, and so on.
If the corporation is to take affirmative action, then the corporation as a whole is
evaluated as to whether such action has been taken. All this views the corporation as an
entity from the outside. The action can be viewed from a moral point of view as well….
[I]t seems perfectly plausible to ascribe moral responsibility to corporations even if they
do not have moral feelings. This is because it is proper and useful to speak of the actions
of corporations, and since they affect society and its members, to evaluate those actions
from a moral point of view. [ CITATION Geo81 \p "61 - 62" \l 4105 ]
However, Altman (2007) is not at ease with De George and says, he seems to be
assuming a consequentialist moral position, which judge action (rather than maxims) based on
their effect on others. He further accuses De George of blurring the distinction between legality
and morality – something he believes is fundamental for Kant. This argument makes sense
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
especially when we consider the fact that legality only limits a person’s actions, not motives –
Altman further argues that there is no appropriate analogy between a corporation’s legal
responsibility and moral responsibility. It is only a subject to the law because it acts, but it cannot
be judged morally because it has no intentions. This should be true, since for Kant, something
must have the requisite characteristics – the capacity to reason and the ability to act purely for
organizations. It fails to go deep enough into creating a general ethics upon which organizations
in general can be held accountable. This is so because his moral doctrine can not make sense of
collective responsibility, and more so, when this doctrine depends on a strict criteria for what
Does this mean that Kant is absolutely lame in so far as business ethics is concerned?
One would therefore seek a different application for Kant’s categorical imperative in business
and only one option is left: the Individual responsibility within the organization, to which we
turn to.
Personal Responsibility
Altman (2007) suggests that although Kant’s ethics precludes corporate moral
responsibility, it does not imply that people can never be blamed when they act on behalf of a
company[ CITATION Alt07 \p 261 \l 4105 ] . He however, adds that this can only happen under
certain conditions:
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
In order to be fully responsible for a given action, we must be aware of what we are
doing. We must see that a decision needs to be made, or that we are facing a moral
dilemma; we must recognize that we need to reach a conclusion; we must understand the
oppositions that are available; and we must have the information to make a well-informed
decision.
Altman insists that from a Kantian perspective, a corporation can have no responsibility
at all. While the present write might agree with him on this statement, there is reason enough to
disagree with his analogy. Altman (2007) writes, insofar as it is a tool, and a good tool performs
its designated function well, a good corporation maximizes profits for its shareholders. The
statement should be, and in fact is true but it cannot be used to take away moral responsibility
from the actors within the corporation. Take for instance the privilege of driving a vehicle. The
driver is expected to drive carefully in a manner that respects both himself and other road users.
If the driver, through careless driving causes an accident, then he is held responsible for his
action or inaction – whichever applies in the situation. In other words, a tool may not be held
responsible for whatever it does but the handler(s) of the tool cannot escape responsibility.
Thus within the corporation, the workers may be obligated to maximize profit but only
within the moral framework that is agreeable – according to Kant, by reason. If they, by any
means, ignore or undermine ethical conditions in the process of their operations then they must
Moreover, like Altman mentions elsewhere, Kant would claim that even the person’s
pursuit of corporate profits depends on its moral permissibility. Altman claims that there is only
one duty in any given situation, not competing duties to the company and the community. Thus
in taking on their professions they do not cease to have moral obligation to others – to the larger
Altman (2007) believes that this is the point where Kant gives guidance in business
ethicists. He writes:
corporation have an obligation to maximize profit for shareholders… but they also have a
number of other duties, including the duties of beneficence and nonmaleficence. He gives this
analogy:
Altman’s analogy is good but insufficient insofar as applying Kantian ethics to business
is concerned. Kantian ethics has even more implications than just opting for the morally right
action against another. It is not just confined to preference but is obligatory. Sometimes, it may
run against the corporation’s profit-making process. Some unique ethical situations like whistle
blowing require moral courage. Though they may come with far reaching consequences, the
morally right thing to do, according to Kant is to blow the whistle even if it means losing ones
institute a behavioural shift, calling for a revolution of character and reintroduction of personal
conscience, responsibility and values[ CITATION Les09 \p 565 \l 4105 ] . Those who respond to
professional and organizational values, extending one’s value system [ CITATION Les09 \p 569 \l
4105 ].
Since for Kant, moral responsibility can only rest with the rational individual, the
problem is that responsibility tends to be diffused in a corporate setting. Altman (2007) writes
that if employees are only involved in isolated aspects of a larger project, they can fail to see that
there is a moral dilemma at hand. They may not understand when a decision needs to be made,
because they do not know when the corporation has come close to a crossing line, or they may
not have information about how what they are doing will be used. Consequently, some corporate
actions may occur that cannot be judged because they cannot be attributed to anyone [ CITATION
Conclusion
This article concludes that Kant’s moral doctrine can be applied in business or
organization ethics. There are particular limitations to it. For instance, it does not support the
idea of codes of conduct and this is rightly argued that universal standards of rights versus
wrongs are futile given that each person has his/her own moral philosophy, religion or culture.
The article also considers the fact that Kant judges people’s actions with reference to their
motives and that businesses are not the sorts of things that choose maxims upon which to act. It
however, finds a soft landing in the personal responsibility. It seems, therefore, that the
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
categorical imperative can be applied to the actions of the particular individual actors in the
business or corporate environments. This would mean a surrender of the collective responsibility
theory.
It is also instructive to note that further investigations should be made to find out if there
are other moral theories that can be applied alongside the categorical imperative in order to bring
on board the whole corporate entity into taking ethical responsibility. The implications of results
of such investigations should then be spread across teaching, research and practice. Teachers
would know whether to put emphasis on the Kantian Doctrine of virtue or to disregard it en toto.
Research should investigate the place of Kantian education in developing greater work ethic and
consequent productivity in organizations: both corporate and public. Finally, the implications of
the findings would be of paramount importance to the practitioner. It would be hoped that
organization leadership and staff would act with regard to the highest good for all in mind,
Bibliography
Altman, Matthew C. "THe Decomposition of the Corporate Body: What Kant Cannot Contribute
to Business Ethics." Journal of Business Ethics 74 (2007): 253-256.
Baron, Marcia. Kantian Ethics Almost Without Apology. Cornell: Cornell U.P., 1995.
Bos, Rene ten. "Essai: Business Ethics and Bauman Ethics." Organization Studies (Walter de
Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG.) 18, no. 6 (1997): 997-1014.
Bowie, Norman E and Denis Arnold. "Sweatshops and Respect for Persons." Business Ethics
Quartely 13 (2003): 221-242.
Brian, Philips, Jeremy Zorn and Julie Blattberg. "Study Guide for Grounding for Metaphysics of
Morals." New York: SparkNotes, 2002. 1 - 38.
Bruhn, John G. "The Functionality of Gray Area Ethics in Organizations." Journal of Business
Ethics (Springer) 89 (2009): 205-214.
Cynthia Stohl, Michael Stohl and Lucy Popova. "A New Generation of Corporate Codes of
Ethics." Journal of Business Ethics, 2009: 607 - 622.
D. K. Bondy, Matten and J. Moon. "The Adoption of Voluntary Codes of Conduct in MNCs: A
Three-Country Comparative Study'." Business and Society review 45 (2004): 235 - 248.
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
David Kim, Dan Fisher and David McCalman. "Modernity, Christianity, and Business Ethics: A
Worldview Perspective." Journal of Business Ethics, 2009: 115 - 121.
Doorn, Neelke. "Applying Rawlsian Approaches to Resolve Ethical Issues: Inventory and
Setting of a Research Agenda." Journal of Business Ethics, 2009: 127 - 143.
George, T. R. " Can corporations have moral responsibility? ." In Ethical Theory and Business,
by Beauchamp and Bowie. New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1981.
Goldsby, Brian K. Buron and Michael G. "The Moral Floor: A Philosophical Examination of the
Connection Between Business and Ethics." Journal of Business Ethics 91 (2009): 145-
154.
Hardwig, John. "The Stockholder - A Lesson for Business Ethics from Bioethics?" Journal Of
Business Ethics 91 (2010): 329-341.
Hsing - Chau Tseng, Chi - Hsiang Duan, Hui - Lien Tung and Hsiang - Jui Kung. "Modern
Business Ethics Research: Concepts, Theories and Relationships." Journal of Business
Ethics, 2010: 587 - 597.
Leslie E. Sekerka, Richard P. Bagozzi and Richard Charnigo. "Facing Ethical Challenges in the
Workplace: Conceptualizing and Measuring Professional Moral Courage." Journal of
Business Ethics, 2009: 565 - 579.
Louden, Robert. Kant's Impure Ethics. New York: Oxford U. Press, 2000.
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics
Lu, Xiaohe. "Business Ethics and Karl Marx's Theory of Capital - Refelctions on Making Use of
Capital for Developing China's Socialist Market." Journal of Business Ethics 91 (2009):
95-111.
Luis Rodriguez - Dominguez, Isabel Gallego - Alvarez and Isabel Maria Garcia - Sanchez.
"Corporate Governance and Codes of Ethics." Journal of Business Ethics 90 (2009):
187-202.
Mitchell J. Neubert, Dawn S. Carlson, K. Michele Kacmar, James A. Roberts and Lawrence B.
Chonko. "The Virtuous Influence of Ethical Leadership Behaviour: Evidence from the
Field." Journal of Business Ethics 90 (2009): 157-170.
Modarelli, Michael. "A Kantian approach to the dilemma of part-time faculty." Changing
English 13, no. 2 (August 2006): 241 - 252.
Name, Author. What's 'Too Graphic'? How To Photograph Disaster. February 01, 2010.
Pan, John R. Sparks and Yue. "Ethical judgments in Business Ethics Research: Definition and
Research Agenda." Journal of Business Ethics 90 (2010): 405-418.
Peck, Lee Anne. "Sapere Aude! The Importance of Moral Education in Kant's Doctrine of
Virtue." Journal of Mass Media Ethics (Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc) 22, no. 2 &
3 (2007): 208 - 214.
Promislo, Robert A. Giacolone and Mark D. "Unethical and Unwell: Decrements in Well-Being
and Unethical Activity at Work." Journal of Business Ethics 91 (2010): 275-297.
Scot John Vitell, Encarnacion Ramos, Ceri M. Nishihara. "The Role of Ethics and Social
Responsibility in Organizational Success: A Spanish Perspective." Journal of Business
Ethics 91 (2010): 467-483.
Scott John Vitell, Encarnacion Ramos, Ceri M. Nishihara. "The Role of Ethics and Social
Responsibility in Organizational Success: A Spanish Perspective." Journal of Business
Ethics 91 (2010): 467-483.
Sean Valentine, Philip Varca, Lynn Godkin and Tim Barnett. "Positive Job response and Ethical
Job PPerformance." Journal of Business Ethics, 2020: 195 - 206.
Implications of Kant's Moral Doctrine to Organizational Ethics