Empathy and The Novel PDF
Empathy and The Novel PDF
Empathy and The Novel PDF
3
2007
3
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford University’s objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.
9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper
for Fran,
soulmate
This page intentionally left blank
PREFACE
the debates about the positive and negative results of feeling with fiction
contextualize the current vogue for empathy, arising from two sources. We
are living in a time when the activation of mirror neurons in the brains of
onlookers can be recorded as they witness another’s actions and emotional
reactions.3 Contemporary neuroscience has brought us much closer to an
understanding of the neural basis for human mind reading and emotion
sharing abilities. The activation of onlookers’ mirror neurons by a coach’s
demonstration of technique or an internal visualization of proper form,
and by representations in television, film, visual art, and pornography, has
already been recorded.4 Simply hearing a description of an absent other’s
actions lights up mirror neuron areas on fMRI imaging of the human brain.5
The possibility that novel reading stimulates mirror neurons’ activation can
now, as never before, undergo neuroscientific investigation.
Neuroscientists have already declared that people scoring high on empa-
thy tests have especially busy mirror neuron systems in their brains.6 For
the first time we might investigate whether human differences in mirror
neuron activity can be altered by exposure to art, to teaching, to litera-
ture. This newly enabled capacity to study empathy at the cellular level
encourages speculation about human empathy’s positive consequences.
These speculations are not new, as any student of eighteenth-century moral
sentimentalism will affirm, but they dovetail with efforts on the part of
present-day virtue ethicists, political philosophers, educators, theologians,
librarians, and interested parties such as authors and publishers to connect
the experience of empathy, including its literary form, with outcomes of
changed attitudes, improved motives, and better care and justice. Thus a
very specific, limited version of empathy located in the neural substrate
meets in the contemporary moment a more broadly and loosely defined,
fuzzier sense of empathy as the feeling precursor to and prerequisite for
liberal aspirations to greater humanitarianism. The sense of crisis stirred up
by reports of stark declines in reading goes into this mix, catalyzing fears
that the evaporation of a reading public leaves behind a population incapa-
ble of feeling with others. Yet the apparently threatened set of links among
novel reading, experiences of narrative empathy, and altruism has not yet
been proven to exist. Empathy robustly enters into affective responses to
fiction, but its role in shaping the behavior of emotional readers has been
debated for three centuries. Chapter 2 surveys those debates, and chapter
6 revisits them by way of considering contemporary critiques of empathy
by false empathy and failed empathy critics.
Unlike these critics, I regard human empathy as a precious quality of
our social natures. Despite the disrepute of generalizations about univer-
sal human traits among postcolonial and feminist theorists, I observe that
women writers and novelists from around the world endorse the notion of
shared human emotions when they overtly call upon their readers’ empa-
thy. I sympathize with their ambition, while remaining skeptical about con-
Preface ix
in inviting (or retarding) readers’ empathic responses. This means that for
some readers, the author’s use of the formulaic conventions of a thriller
or a romance novel would increase empathetic resonance, while for other
readers (perhaps better educated and attuned to literary effects), unusual or
striking representations promote foregrounding and open the way to empa-
thetic reading.17
Psychologist Marjorie Taylor has demonstrated that a group of fiction
writers score higher on empathy tests than the general population.18 (Their
high empathy may be innate, or the activity of fiction writing may culti-
vate novelists’ role-taking skills and train them in habits of empathy.) If it
were to be verified beyond the original study, Taylor’s discovery has several
implications for the study of narrative empathy. Most important, it sug-
gests why authors themselves so often vouch for the centrality of empathy
to novel reading and believe in the power of narrative empathy to change
the minds and lives of readers. The belief mirrors their own experiences as
ready empathizers. Yet even the most fervent employers of their empathetic
imaginations realize that this key ingredient of fictional world-making does
not always transmit to readers without interference. Authors’ empathy can
be devoted to socially undesirable ends that may be rejected by a disap-
proving reader. Indeed, empathic distress at feeling with a character whose
actions are at odds with a reader’s moral code may be a result of successfully
exercised authorial empathy. Both authors’ empathy and readers’ empathy
have rhetorical uses, which come more readily to notice when they conflict
in instances of empathic inaccuracy (discordance arising from gaps between
a author’s intention and a reader’s experience of narrative empathy). Expe-
riences of empathic inaccuracy may contribute to a reader’s outraged sense
that the author’s perspective is simply wrong, while strong concord in
authors’ empathy and readers’ empathy can be a motivating force to move
beyond literary response to prosocial action.
Some scholars of discourse processing believe that readers’ empathy
could produce verifiable results in the beliefs and actions of populations
of actual readers. Psychologists such as Martin Hoffman, whose theory of
empathy and altruism is treated in detail in chapter 1, believe that novel
reading may participate in the socialization and moral internalization
required for the transmutation of empathic guilt into prosocial action. In
other words, reading experiences may indirectly lay the groundwork for
real-world transmissions of empathy from fleeting feeling to willed steps
taken on another’s behalf. This would make the effects of reading difficult to
measure because the altruistic actions might be taken at some distance from
the reading experience, a point that emphasizes the need for longitudinal
studies of readers’ lives. My own research suggests that readers’ perception
of a text’s fictionality plays a role in subsequent empathetic response, by
releasing readers from the obligations of self-protection through skepticism
and suspicion. Thus they may respond with greater empathy to an unreal
xiv Preface
situation and characters because of the protective fictionality, but (if Hoff-
man is right) still internalize the experience of empathy in a way that prom-
ises later real-world responsiveness to others’ needs.
While a full-fledged political movement, an appropriately inspiring social
context, or an emergent structure of feeling promoting change may be nec-
essary for efficacious action to arise out of internalized experiences of nar-
rative empathy, readers may respond in those circumstances as a result of
earlier reading. The position of the reader with respect to the author’s stra-
tegic empathizing in fictional world-making limits these potential results.
I theorize that bounded strategic empathy operates with an in-group, stem-
ming from experiences of mutuality and leading to feeling with familiar
others. Ambassadorial strategic empathy addresses chosen others with the
aim of cultivating their empathy for the in-group, often to a specific end.
Broadcast strategic empathy calls upon every reader to feel with members of
a group, by emphasizing common vulnerabilities and hopes through univer-
salizing representations.
In the course of exploring this theory of narrative empathy, I also subject
the existing theories of narrative empathy and its effects, including those
offered by philosophers and psychologists, to critical scrutiny. Too often
these theories have been marred by bias or by a tendency to confound the
effects of teaching with those of reading. So, for instance, I suggest that if
narrative empathy is to be better understood, then women’s reading and
popular fiction must be accorded the respect of experimental inquiry. It
will not do to allow introspective accounts of reading (or teaching) canoni-
cal works of nineteenth-century fiction to substitute for broad inquiry into
the effects of more popular, widely read fiction that succeeds with a female
readership. This is not to say that trained readers’ empathetic experiences
with complex, experimental, difficult, and high literary texts hold no inter-
est, rather that a theory of narrative empathy that cannot explain com-
monplace, frequent, and readily repeated experiences of feeling with fiction
leaves a lot to be desired. While this criticism aims to expand the scope of
inquiry into narrative empathy, another seeks to narrow it. Too often the
discussion of effects of novel reading combines the social and pedagogical
outcomes of group discussion and classroom experiences. If the value of
discussion and the contributions of teachers in the intellectual and moral
growth of readers are to be understood, then these elements must not be
hidden within accounts that claim to study “effects of reading” but actually
conflate reading, discussion, role-taking activities, writing tasks, and teach-
ing. To conclude, as I do, that scant evidence exists for active connections
among novel reading, experiences of narrative empathy, and altruistic action
on behalf of real people only emphasizes the importance of discussion,
directed introspection, and leadership through questioning and providing
examples. Books can’t make change by themselves—and not everyone feels
certain that they ought to. If, however, a society judges that its peoples’
Preface xv
novel reading ought to invoke empathy that yields in committed action for
others, then it should be willing to invest in the teachers who will help read-
ers make connections between their feeling responses to fiction and their
subsequent behavior as citizens of the world. Rather than jumping to this
conclusion, Empathy and the Novel asks its readers to consider that we have
a great deal more to understand about narrative empathy before we place
the novel in service to social goals, no matter how laudable they appear.
Bold claims have been made for the positive consequences of novel reading,
and these contentions grow more urgent as the practice of literary reading
in Anglo-American culture undergoes startling declines. This book ques-
tions the contemporary truism that novel reading cultivates empathy that
produces good citizens for the world. I affirm the robustness of narrative
empathy, as an affective transaction accomplished through the writing and
reading of fiction, but I hesitate to tether readers’ empathy to certain out-
comes of altruistic action. Still, novel reading does a lot for readers. Few
would doubt that a habit of consuming narrative fiction in prose improves
the vocabulary and informs the reader about subjects, times, people, and
places (real and imagined) in a way that extends knowledge beyond indi-
vidual experience. Some studies of fantasy empathy suggest that people
who readily imagine fictional others’ perspectives also grasp the variety and
individuality of real others, but this discovery about empathetic disposi-
tions may simply explain why certain people gravitate toward novel reading
(Stotland, Empathy 89). Do empathetic people make good readers, or do
good readers become empathetic people? Both may be true without guar-
anteeing that novels routinely do more than entertain, inform, soothe, or
excite their readers.
For immersed readers, entering fictional worlds allows a refreshing escape
from ordinary, everyday pressures and preoccupations.19 Encountering the
routine enigmas that drive fictional plots may enhance a reader’s fluency
and comfort with print communication. Widely read popular novels give
readers something to talk about and can contribute to the formation of
those little ad hoc communities of fellow-feeling that arise when several
who love a particular novel or novelist meet and share their enthusiasm.
The contemporary phenomenon of book groups testifies to the social and
personal benefits of novel reading, mainly enjoyed by women.20
Fictional characters can become mental companions to last a lifetime,
and relationships across generations can be built around affection for a
character or a fictional world. To this list of benefits we might add the
potential for social advancement: the person who can casually chat about
serious fiction may impress employers and those in circles with preten-
xvi Preface
sions to culture. The unusual college student who reads fiction for plea-
sure enjoys not only the books themselves, but also the approbation of her
academic elders. Many an English professor or librarian received encour-
agement to pursue a career path as a result of her enthusiasm for books.
Because of their complexity and thematic links to history, politics, eco-
nomics, and many other aspects of our embodied experience, novels make
good objects of academic study, though one hopes this remains a second-
ary consequence of fiction’s continued existence. Rarely, but vitally for the
continuity of cultural forms, novel readers sometimes become novelists.
What dedicated reader would question the importance of novel reading if
it produces the vocations of writers themselves? That all of these desirable
effects of novel reading fall into jeopardy when a nation stops reading cer-
tainly ought to give us pause.
In the summer of 2004, when I began writing this book, the National
Endowment for the Arts released a sobering report, entitled Reading at Risk.
It describes a nation sliding into a state of indifference to literature, of func-
tional aliteracy. At the behest of the NEA, in 2002, the United States Cen-
sus Bureau interviewed seventeen thousand adult Americans about their
reading habits. They inquired whether these citizens had read a single work
of poetry, drama, or fiction in the prior year. Keeping in mind that a reader
who had turned the pages of a single volume of the Left Behind series would
count as a literature reader by the survey’s definition, the results may even
be considered frightening. The NEA reports that over the past two decades,
both book reading and literature reading have declined sharply. Only 46.7
percent of respondents had read at least a single work of literature, and the
news about men, minorities, and younger people was especially disheart-
ening: only 37.6 percent of males admitted to literary reading (balanced
out by 55.1 percent of females); among Hispanics, only 26.5 percent were
self-declared literary readers; and of 18–24 year-olds (a group that includes
many of the nation’s college students, who may be presumed to read at
least a little under compulsion), only 42.8 percent admitted to recreational
reading. As Dana Gioia, Chairman of the NEA, puts it, the report presents a
“detailed but bleak assessment of the decline in reading’s role in the nation’s
culture.” He goes on to suggest that “anyone who loves literature or values
the cultural, intellectual, and political importance of active and engaged
literacy in American society will respond to this report with grave concern”
(Reading at Risk vii).21
The reaction to the report highlights the benefits believed to accrue to
individuals and the nation as a result of literary reading. Gioia worries about
the increased passivity of Americans, whose short attention spans and desire
for accelerated gratification lead them to video games, the Internet, televi-
sion, and DVDs, rather than to books. According to Gioia, the active atten-
tion, engagement, and practice required by reading are in jeopardy, and the
loss of contemplative engagement with complex works of literature impov-
Preface xvii
lem is an insufficient number of new books” (Weber, “Poet Brokers” B1, B5).
The gloomy prognosis and call to action have worked to garner conserva-
tive support and funding for the arts (“Poet Brokers” B1, B5). If Congress
and the public take the report seriously, it is to be hoped that the nation’s
libraries will receive a similarly enriched infusion of support. The rhetorical
groundwork has been laid by a variety of cultural commentators who weigh
in on the importance of reading. Three voices from the fields of philosophy,
psychology, and history represent here the common argument that novel
reading results in civic good.
The influential philosopher Martha Nussbaum sees novel reading as
one of the core strategies for building better world citizens capable of
extending love and compassion to unknown others. Encountering Henry
James or George Eliot (not coincidentally two canonical writers of Leavis’s
Great Tradition) helps the would-be world citizen become “a sensitive and
empathic interpreter” of others.23 Though Nussbaum’s examples in Culti-
vating Humanity (1997) and Poetic Justice (1995) show a bias toward real-
ism and canonical works (she stoops only so low as Dickens), she states
her claims for the exercise of the narrative imagination broadly: “Habits
of empathy and conjecture conduce to a certain type of citizenship and a
certain form of community: one that cultivates a certain kind of responsive-
ness to another’s needs, and understands the way circumstances shape those
needs, while respecting separateness and privacy” (Cultivating 90). One
builds these habits, starting in early childhood, through literary imagining,
which “inspires intense concern with the fate of characters and defines those
characters as containing a rich inner life, not all of which is open to view”
(90). Nussbaum, following the lead of Lionel Trilling, believes that learning
respect for the hidden inner life of fictional characters leads readers “to attri-
bute importance to the material conditions of happiness while respecting
human freedom” (90). This in turn leads to empathy, compassion, and social
justice (91, 94). In the strongest terms, Nussbaum claims that reading must
be consequential: “It is impossible to care about the characters [of Dickens
and Eliot] and their well-being in the way the text invites, without having
some very definite political and moral interests awakened in oneself” (104).
Whether anyone, let alone large numbers of people, actually acts in trace-
able ways as a result of this conscientious prompting Nussbaum does not
wonder: she assumes it must be so. Her strenuous efforts to promote reform
in liberal education emphasize her faith in the efficacy of the right kind of
novel reading.
For Steven Pinker, human beings need not be in school studying canoni-
cal writers to enjoy the benefits of what he names a “moral technology,”
storytelling. The evolutionary psychologist argues in a recent interview in
Seed magazine that storytelling has made the human species “nicer” (“Seed
Salon” 48); Pinker sees moral emotions as evolved traits that account for
the statistical decline in the murder rate from the time of hunter-gatherer
Preface xix
societies. In Pinker’s rosy long view, “Much of the world has seen an end to
slavery, to genocide for convenience, to torture as a routine form of criminal
punishment for property crimes, to human sacrifice, to rape as the spoils of
war, to the ownership of women. We seem to be turning into a nicer spe-
cies” (“Seed Salon” 48). Most gratifyingly for those of us who spend our
comfortable lives contemplating novels, Pinker attributes to storytelling the
extension of the “moral circle” to include “other clans, other tribes, and other
races” (48). He concedes that our near universal capacity for empathy does
seem to be limited to a narrow compass of relations or villagers, but he holds
that by allowing our projection “into the lives of people of different times
and places and races, in a way that wouldn’t spontaneously occur,” fiction
can change our perspectives on unlike persons “who might otherwise seem
subhuman” (48). Thus fiction offers not only the “cognitive advantages of
seeing how hypothetical scenarios play out,” but also “the emotional plea-
sures of empathizing with a character” (97), and a payoff in understanding
and better behavior.
The distinguished historian Lynn Hunt extrapolates from personal to
political improvements. She argues that eighteenth-century novels played
an important part in advancing the concept of human rights.24 Indeed, if fic-
tion can do what Nussbaum and Pinker believe, then why wouldn’t history
record some pretty dramatic effects of the rise of the novel? Hunt argues
that the novel “disseminated a new psychology and a new social and politi-
cal order” through its narrative form and “made the point that all selves
are fundamentally similar because of their inner psychic processes” (“Para-
doxical” 14). The eighteenth-century novel accomplished this by drawing
readers in and making them feel “passionately” involved in the story. This
new experience of empathy with characters gave new political concepts
purchase: “Reading a novel (in the eighteenth century and not before) a
reader identified with an ordinary person unknown to him or her personally
but with whom the reader empathized thanks to the narrative form itself”
(14). Hunt especially prizes the effect of novels on spreading the notion of
women’s subjectivity, but her conclusions take her beyond the renovation of
opinion of mainly British and European middle-class readers about females
and servants (who were not, she acknowledges, immediately granted full
rights [15]). Novels trained readers to a broader conception of humanity,
through “new forms of empathetic identification with individuals who are
now imagined to be in some fundamental way like you” (13).
Well, it depends. Anyone who has read a fair number of eighteenth-cen-
tury novels will be able to think of examples of stigmatized characters who
are held up for ridicule and humiliation, to the delight of protagonists and
implied readers alike. The elderly, the fat, and the gout-ridden all seem to
be fair game. Eighteenth-century novelists often invite readers to laugh at
rebarbative characters’ misfortunes, often in support of general satiric aims,
but sometimes just for fun. For instance, Frances Burney’s Evelina (1778), a
xx Preface
Sometime during the Bosnian war, I was watching the news in my comfort-
able study. The camera showed refugees picking their way down a rough
path, out of the mountains they had crossed to flee the conflict. I saw a
professionally dressed woman in her thirties carrying a child about eighteen
months old. I suddenly felt the weight of that toddler in my arms, the ten-
sion in my calves that governs slipping feet, and the spinal awareness that I
might suddenly be thrown off balance. I felt not pity, but the apprehension
the woman’s face and movements showed. This was empathy—a sponta-
neous sharing of feelings, including physical sensations in the body, pro-
voked by witnessing or hearing about another’s condition. Human beings
and other primates frequently experience fleeting empathetic sensations,
which can be observed and measured by physical signs, including facial
expressions, decreased heart rate, altered skin conductance, and palm sweat.
These signs can be captured by observation and, in the lab, by electromyo-
graphic (EMG) recordings and even fMRI imagery of brain activity.26 These
Preface xxi
among others. Though the long-term political, social, and ethical conse-
quences of empathetic reading experiences have yet to be demonstrated,
the ardency of readers and the perseverance of novelists give pause to the
skeptic who would argue that literature makes nothing happen. Simple
accounts of the utility of novel reading, I argue, should be replaced by more
nuanced study of the consequences of experiencing aesthetic emotions.30
The affective transaction across boundaries of time, culture, and location
may indeed be one of the intrinsic powers of fiction and the novel a remark-
ably effective device for reminding readers of their own and others’ human-
ity. Narrative empathy is not an inconsiderable element of the creation and
reception of fiction, and it should be resituated to a central place in twenty-
first–century aesthetics.
This book pursues the question of what a habit of novel reading does
to the moral imagination of the immersed reader. Unlike the authorities
mentioned earlier, I do not assume from the outset that empathy for fic-
tional characters necessarily translates into what Stephen Pinker calls “nicer”
human behavior. I ask whether the effort of imagining fictive lives, as George
Eliot believed, can train a reader’s sympathetic imagining of real others in
her actual world, and I inquire how we might be able to tell if it happened.
I acknowledge that it would be gratifying to discover that reading Henry
James makes us better world citizens, but I wonder whether the expen-
diture of shared feeling on fictional characters might not waste what little
attention we have for others on nonexistent entities, or at best reveal that
addicted readers are simply endowed with empathetic dispositions. Like
most professors of literature, I would be delighted to affirm the salutary
effects of novel reading, but I am not prepared to take them on faith. How
might we verify when empathetic reading experiences have shaped our
behavior? We should begin by understanding what psychologists mean by
empathy, a term bedeviled by conflicting definitions.
This page intentionally left blank
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
A book about what happens to readers when they experience empathy for
fictional characters (or other aspects of novelistic worlds) depends, first and
foremost, on the generosity of readers. One can impose on one’s students
(and believe me, I did!), but the voluntary testimony of a variety of read-
ers, including the pseudonymous posters at Amazon.com, made this project
possible.
Exemplary among my informants were VICTORIA listserv correspon-
dents. Without necessarily knowing me personally, they gamely responded
to my query about empathetic reading experiences. I thank Diana Archibald,
Alison Booth, Sarah Brown, Michel Faber, Richard Fulton, Sheldon Gold-
farb, Kerryn Goldsworthy, Valerie Gorman, Jill Grey, Martha Stoddard Hol-
mes, Susan Hoyle, Jack Kolb, Robert Lapides, David Latane, Mary Lenard,
Anna Lepine, Margot K. Louis, Rohan Maitzen, Timothy Mason, Sara L.
Maurer, Michael Hargreave Mawson, Pat Menon, Kathryn Miele, Ellen
Moody, Deborah Denenholz Morse, Heather Morton, Lee O’Brien, Diana
Ostrander, Meri-Jane Rochelson, Anne B. Rodrick, Heather Schell, June W.
Siegel, Ann Shillinglaw, Suzanne Shumway, Kathleen O’Neill Sims, Beth
Sutton-Ramspeck, Tamara S. Wagner, and Michael Woolf.
Many friends and colleagues supplied “true confessions” about what
novels made them do, asked me those invaluable stumping questions, and
provided ways into the daunting bibliographies of unfamiliar disciplines.
For that and for responses to my work in progress, I thank Edward Adams,
John Armstrong, Claudette Artwick, Theresa Braunschneider, Pam Burish,
Gwyn Campbell, Marc Conner, Elizabeth Heckendorn Cook, Ed Craun,
Kevin Crotty, Doug Cummings, Kelly Boyle Dailey, Scott Dransfield, Fran-
coise Fregnac-Clave, Art Goldsmith, Jim Hentz, Sarah Kennedy, George
Landow, Timothy Lubin, Nancy Margand, Richard Marks, Yolanda Merrill,
David S. Miall, Brian Murchison, Nan Partlett, Domnica Radulescu, Brian
Richardson, Elizabeth Samet, Lad Sessions, Kary Smout, Asali Solomon,
Scott Sundby, Jim Warren, and Lesley Wheeler. I benefited from the public
discussions and private conversations that went on at the Institute for Eng-
lish Studies conference, The Languages of Emotion, in London (October
2004), and at the Cognition in Literary Interpretation and Practice confer-
xxviii Acknowledgments
in this regard to Fakrul Alam, Carolyn Allen, Roy Blount Jr., Ian Duncan,
Amy Elias, Michael Gorra, Jianjun Ma, Franco Moretti, Claude Rawson, and
Robyn Warhol for their suggestions about novels and reading. Needless to
say, the work that appears in these pages (and the inevitable errors) are my
responsibility alone.
This page intentionally left blank
CONTENTS
3. Readers’ Empathy 65
Notes 173
Index 235
This page intentionally left blank
Empathy and the Novel
This page intentionally left blank
1
from empathy to sympathy in real life? Or does the testimony about the
role of fiction reflect the aesthetic preferences of readers already inclined
to respond empathetically? As these questions show, much of the debate
about empathy described in this chapter has relevance for the questions of
narrative ethics raised in the preface, matters of narrative technique treated
in chapter 3, and reader responses discussed throughout the book.
This chapter initiates that project by describing a collection of reactions
to three brief texts that attempt to invoke emotional responses in read-
ers. The discussion here leads to several baseline assertions about narrative
empathy. Empathetic response to fiction is less consistent than it might at
4 Empathy and the Novel
first seem. No one text evokes the same responses in all of its readers, and
not all texts succeed in stimulating readers to feel and act as their authors
apparently wish. I argue here that the very fictionality of novels predisposes
readers to empathize with characters, since a fiction known to be “made up”
does not activate suspicion and wariness as an apparently “real” appeal for
assistance may do.5 I posit that fictional worlds provide safe zones for read-
ers’ feeling empathy without experiencing a resultant demand on real-world
action.6 This freedom from obligation paradoxically opens up the channels
for both empathy and related moral affects such as sympathy, outrage, pity,
righteous indignation, and (not to be underestimated) shared joy and satis-
faction. Before returning to my central topic of narrative empathy, however,
the definitions of empathy and related responses demand attention.7
What Is Empathy?
可通过目睹他人的情感状态,获悉他人的境况和阅读来激发共情。三大途径。
Empathy, a vicarious, spontaneous sharing of affect, can be provoked by
witnessing another’s emotional state, by hearing about another’s condition,
or even by reading. It need not be a conscious response: the neonates who
cry at the sound of other babies’ cries are almost certainly unaware of their
primitive empathy. Equipped with mirror neurons, the human brain appears
to possess a system for automatically sharing feelings, what neuroscientists
call a “shared manifold for intersubjectivity.”8 More complex cognitive
responses to others’ mental states layer atop this initial spontaneous shar-
ing of feelings. Mirroring what a person might be expected to feel in that
condition or context, empathy is thought to be precursor to its semantic
close relative, sympathy.9 Although the word empathy is a relatively young
term, entering English in the early twentieth century as a coined translation
of the German word Einfühlung, aspects of empathy have been described
by philosophers since the days of Adam Smith and David Hume under
the older term sympathy. Throughout this book I distinguish the spontane- 即刻、回
应的适当
ous, responsive sharing of an appropriate feeling as empathy, and the more 情感共享
complex, differentiated feeling for another as sympathy (sometimes called ——共
empathic concern in psychological literature). 情;更复
Personal distress, an aversive emotional response also characterized by 杂、有区
apprehension of another’s emotion, differs from empathy in that it focuses 别的感觉
——同情
on the self and leads not to sympathy but to avoidance.10 The distinction
between empathy and personal distress matters because empathy is associ-
ated with the moral emotion sympathy (also called empathic concern) and 同情=共
情的关心
thus with prosocial or altruistic action. Empathy that leads to sympathy is 是道德情
by definition other-directed, whereas an over-aroused empathic response 感?
that creates personal distress (self-oriented and aversive) causes a turning-
away from the provocative condition of the other. I hazard that personal
distress caused by novel reading leads people to stop reading, to put the
进一步区分personal distress和empathy:前者会让读者放弃阅读,将书丢在一边,不断地略
过或者粗略草草地看。
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 5
Empathy: Sympathy:
I feel what you feel. I feel a supportive emotion about your feelings.
I feel your pain. I feel pity for your pain.
socially by doing the voices and facial expressions of characters, but also tac-
itly trains young children and members of the wider social group to recog-
nize and give priority to culturally valued emotional states.20 This education
does not create our feelings, but renders emotional states legible through
their labels, and activates our expectations about what emotions mean. Nar-
ratives in prose and film infamously manipulate our feelings and call upon
our built-in capacity to feel with others. We need not be present in the
immediate audience to catch the feelings of others, as anyone who watched
the events of 11 September 2001, on television will recall. (Remember also
how many people said of that day, “It was like a movie,” an evaluation that
catches both the intensity of feeling and the sense of unreality that beset us
then.) We humans can “feel with” fictional characters and faraway strangers
when we are exposed to storytelling prose narrative and film fiction, or mass
media broadcasts that call upon our emotions. It makes sense for all citizens
to understand the circumstances and techniques that elicit our shared feel-
ings, especially if an empathetic response does develop into more complex
responses that contribute to (or impede) our moral development and civic
engagement.
Humans feel empathy. We aren’t the only animals to do so,21 but empathy
seems so basic a human trait that lacking it can be seen as a sign of inhu-
manity. Blade Runner (1982, 1992), Ridley Scott’s film version of Philip K.
Dick’s Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep? (1968), popularizes and trou-
bles a notion of empathy as the one essential, recognizable trait of human-
ity. Blade Runner’s dystopic future world imagines society penetrated by
nearly unidentifiable cyborgs engineered to believe in their wholly invented
human lives, memories, and feelings, which have been supplied by their
maker. These persecuted machines reveal themselves as cyborgs by failing
an empathy test. Lacking empathy in this context means revealing oneself
as a machine.
Popular culture represents empathy as a human and often also as a typi-
cally female trait, understandings to which science contributes. For instance,
Cambridge scientist Simon Baron-Cohen’s The Essential Difference: The Truth
about the Male and Female Brains (2003) advances a theory about female
empathy that confirms contemporary gender stereotypes and has received
widespread coverage in the press due to its speculations about autism rates.22
Baron-Cohen suggests that the capacity for empathy differs between men
and women, specifically, that “the female brain is predominantly hard-wired
for empathy” while “the male brain is predominantly hard-wired for under-
standing and building systems” (Essential 1). Baron-Cohen describes empa-
thy by its behavioral consequences: for him it entails automatically feeling
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 7
concern, wincing, and feeling “a desire to run across and help alleviate” the
victim’s pain (2).23 He proposes that empathy “arises out of natural desire to
care about others,” and he argues that human females spontaneously empa-
thize more than males (on average) (2).24 This is not a new idea in socio-
biology, philosophy, or politics.25 For instance, it is axiomatic that women
generally prefer reparative, humane solutions to social problems, while men
prefer punishment and preventative measures.26 Folk understanding of the
gender gap in politics suggests that emotionality and empathy on the part
of women incline them to caring solutions.
Real differences in the structures of female and male brains might seem
to support this popular view with evidence from neuroscience.27 Some
aspects of emotional response are lateralized differently in men and women,
and some brain areas involved in emotion differ in relative size between
the sexes. Speculations about the evolutionary origin of human empathy
often point toward the caregiver-infant relationship as a source for develop-
ing empathy.28 It is important not to confound underlying structures with
outcomes that may express cultural assumptions rather than biological
fact, however. Some developmental psychologists and cognitive scientists
reviewing the evidence question the assumption that empathy is a “female
trait.” Martin Hoffman believes that “mimicry is probably a hard-wired neu-
rologically based empathy-arousing mechanism whose two steps, imitation
and feedback, are directed by commands from the central nervous system”
(Empathy and Moral Development 44). This means for all of us: human
beings and other animals possess this fundamental “hard-wiring,” evolved
from primitive communication mechanisms that enhance cooperation with
other organisms in the group.
Though some studies have shown gender differences (not all skewing
toward females), in their second comprehensive review of the literature,
Eisenberg and Lennon find that gender differences may arise from the
methods of measurement rather than from genuine differences. Paper and
pencil self-report studies produced large differences; picture/story indices
yielded small differences; and physiological measures resulted in no differ-
ences. To Eisenberg and Lennon, this suggests that the subjects’ assump-
tions about their own gender roles and appropriate emotional responses,
especially when directly reported to a questioner, skewed results toward
showing gender difference.29 They conclude that fine-tuned definitions and
methodology that guard against influence by cultural assumptions must be
developed before any conclusions can be made about gender and empathy.
Writing a decade later, social psychologists Tiffany Graham and William
Ickes agree, although their use of empathy indicates cognitive perspective
taking rather than affective empathy with others’ feelings.30 In their review
of the evidence about “women’s intuition,” Graham and Ickes decide that
“gender differences in empathic skills and dispositions appear to be small
rather than large, and specific rather than general in their scope” (“Intuition”
8 Empathy and the Novel
139–40). Motivation rather than ability accounts for women’s skills in judg-
ing others’ thoughts and feelings.
Humanists and literary scholars are more familiar with feminist and post-
colonial critiques of the essentializing universals that have often been used
to narrow the definition of the human or to allocate traits rated low on a
scale of values to subject races or to groups considered inferior. This per-
spective, too, brings into question any simple assignment of emotional traits
to a gender or other group of humans. Certainly we should want to know
what historical circumstances or social conditions influence the assignment
of “caring” to women and “understanding” to men before we assume that a
biological basis for a distinction exists. Despite critical reservations about
claims such as Baron-Cohen’s, however, the notion of gender difference in
empathy persists in popular cultural representations of empathic individu-
als. Often such claims rely on a notion of the “natural” that does not always
receive confirmation in the laboratory.
One clue that there may not be a biological basis for strong gender
difference in empathy lies in the evidence of empathy among other pri-
mates. Though male and female monkeys may indeed have different sex
roles in some areas, the account of empathy among bonobos published by
Ellen J. Ingmanson about her observations at the San Diego Zoo features
a young male bonobo’s response to an older male’s dejection. Ingmanson
also reports cases in which male bonobos in the wild have taken over infant
care of orphaned or neglected infants.31 Male primates may not have gotten
the social message that empathy is supposed to be a female trait! Recent
work by Stephanie Preston and Frans B. M. de Waal reports many striking
examples of empathy, including apparent cognitive perspective taking and
sympathetic behavior, in both male and female animals. Chimpanzees con-
sole one another, responding to distress; macaques help handicapped group
members; and as dog owners will anticipate, some animals respond to the
distress of individuals from other species (“Communication” 283). Preston
and de Waal regard empathy as “a general class of behavior that exists across
species to different degrees of complexity” (285). Reviewing the experi-
mental and behavioral data of empathy in rodents, monkeys, and apes, they
conclude, “continuous contact and coordinated activities are characteristic
of a bond that develops a physiologically adaptive response to stress, accu-
rate communication of affect with others, and the capacity for empathic
responding” (301). This bond may express itself in caregiver-child relations
or in the coordinated activity of the hunt (though, to be sure, our capacity
to disengage empathetic reaction may stem from the need to avoid feeling
with the prey animal, where empathy would impede success). The uses
to which we put our empathy may be subject to cultural influences, but
the response itself, Preston and de Waal argue, occurs in humans and other
animals. They argue that modern life inhibits the expression of empathy
humans share with our primate and mammal cousins (301–2). Becom-
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 9
ing more like apes would be a gain for disconnected and alienated human
beings, regardless of gender.
Whether or not we feel comfortable with our empathy as an inheri-
tance from our common primate ancestors depends on our attitudes toward
evolution and the degree to which we regard humans as separate, special
beings who are distinguished from the rest of living creatures. To those who
regard empathy as primarily a matter of cognitive perspective taking (a view
treated below), the homologous empathy of apes and humans may seem
more difficult to accept. Apes cannot use language to confirm the motiva-
tions for their behavior. However, Preston and de Waal provide instances of
animal behavior indicating perspective taking as well as affective empathy.
A monkey that provides an appropriate tool to another after observing its
struggles to solve a problem demonstrates perspective taking, and an ape
that holds and strokes an unconscious human child who has fallen into her
enclosure shows caring. That we share instinctive caring with our primate
cousins need not diminish the uses to which humans put their empathetic
responses. As Darwin’s contemporary Herbert Spencer argued in 1855, our
underlying sociality contributes to our group survival. Emotional response
to others’ condition has been seen as providing a basis for mature sympathy,
morality, and social arrangements that seek the common good. Philosophers
since David Hume and Adam Smith have argued this point, and recent evo-
lutionary psychology has embraced the notion of the adaptive function of
reciprocal altruism. A great deal more than shared sensations is attributed
to human empathy.
Deficiencies in empathy impair human relationships and contribute to
psychopathology. The difficulty may stem from a reduced ability to recog-
nize others’ sad, fearful, or distressed emotions.32 Emotionally “tone-deaf”
individuals who recognize neither their own nor others’ feelings, may suf-
fer from alexithymia, a dispositional deficit that shows in their inability to
describe emotions verbally. Alexithymics’ condition can interfere with rela-
tionships and their ability to use their imaginations. Lacking feeling rarely
benefits the individual in popular representations (though the cold-blooded
individualist gets credit for a successful strategy when he ignores others’
feelings). Certainly, a complete freedom from empathy might be admired as
a feature of ruthless competitiveness or hyperrationality, but in popular cul-
ture, characters exhibiting no empathy seem like monsters or machines. At
best they seem odd to ordinary people. Mr. Spock of Star Trek and Data of
Star Trek: the Next Generation represent two widely recognized pop culture
versions of the emotionless being. Tellingly, the sophisticated robot Data
wishes for nothing more than the acquisition of emotions, for he recognizes
his lack of feelings as a cognitive disability that undermines his capacity to
comprehend others’ behavior. In popular culture, lacking empathy often
correlates with sociopathic behavior, with the profiles of serial killers, and
with developmental disorders such as autism.
10 Empathy and the Novel
To place an autistic child in the same list as a sociopath and a serial killer
suggests one of the many disturbing consequences of emphasizing empathy
as an intrinsic human trait. Certainly, suffering from autism does not predict
a career of criminality (several recent novels have in fact emphasized the
autistic child’s gifts as a crime solver or a clever adversary of evil!).33 No one
disputes that autistic children are human beings. It helps to know that every
psychologist studying empathy acknowledges the range of caring disposi-
tions in people. Within every category, men, women, girls, and boys vary in
their disposition to empathize.34 The most serious impairments in empathic
ability indicate disorders. For instance, Lorna Wing places lack of empathy
at the beginning of her list of the main clinical features of Asperger’s syn-
drome, and this problem appears to be at the root of some of its sufferers’
other clinical indications, such as their poor nonverbal communication, dif-
ficulty in forming friendships, and inappropriate or one-sided interactions in
conversation.35 Having no empathy does not necessarily indicate low intel-
ligence, however: Asperger’s sufferers can be exceptionally bright.
Though understanding of Asperger’s syndrome helps mitigate a preju-
dicial view of low-empathy individuals, the popular representation of the
warped master criminal as simultaneously brainy and uncaring dominates
in mass culture. Like many stereotypes, this one has its roots in reality. The
fact that some criminals may be described as suffering from a syndrome
known as antisocial personality disorder, which combines unlawful behav-
ior with lack of remorse, or indifference to the pain, suffering, or material
losses of their victims, reinforces the association of empathy with good
citizens and the lack of it with problem cases. Worst of all are the well-
publicized emotional failings of psychopaths such as serial killers. Psycho-
paths cannot construct mental and emotional facsimiles of other people
effectively, so the feelings of others are of no concern to them.36 This does
not mean that they lack emotion, for these sadists may take joy from the
suffering of their victims, but it underscore their lack of empathy.37 All
these understandings add up in the negative side of the tally. In the popu-
lar cultural view, lack of empathy spells social problems, danger to others,
criminality, and inhumanity.
Being empathetic receives hearty endorsements from diverse voices in
popular culture. The “empath” of popular science fiction represents the far
extreme: unlike her unemotional opposite, she cannot help receiving and
feeling the sensations of those around her. For fictional characters as well as
many real people, empathy provides the basis for vocations in the helping
professions. One can see figures such as Counselor Deanna Troi of Star Trek:
The Next Generation as the direct descendent of real-world client-centered
therapists whose therapeutic versions of empathy are widely diffused in
popular culture.38 As in the negative representations, a legitimate link to
real-life practices exists. The successful psychotherapist needs to be able to
harness empathy, using it to therapeutic ends without being overwhelmed
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 11
these “true lies.” As I will argue below, narrative fiction may in fact enhance
the potential for subjects to respond feelingly to situations and characters,
disarming them of their customary suspicions and learned caution. Liter-
ature professionals like myself may begin by respectfully comprehending
psychology’s methodologies.
Psychologists test and record empathy in a variety of ways. Physiological
measures, sometimes combined with self-reports, can show the strength
or weakness (or presence and absence) of empathic responses.47 Psycholo-
gists measure changes in heart rate and skin conductance (palm sweat).
They collect data on perceptible and imperceptible facial reactions, the
latter captured by EMG (electromyographic) procedures.48 They ask sub-
jects how they feel or how they would act in certain situations, gathering
responses through self-reports during or immediately after experiments
and through surveys. Specialized surveys known as “empathy scales” are
used to assess subjects’ strength of empathic feeling.49 As Nancy Eisenberg
has repeatedly observed, cultural influences such as sex-role differentiation
show up more in the kinds of tests that rely on surveys and interviews and
much less (or not at all) in tests using physiological methods.50 An unex-
amined bias originating from definition of terms or from methodology can
skew results, and when those results happen to endorse a widely held view
(such as the innate caring disposition of females), they can be hard to dis-
lodge. As new tools come along that revolutionize knowledge by providing
an entirely new way of collecting data, such as Functional Magnetic Reso-
nance Imaging (fMRI), the need for careful analysis of methods and find-
ings does not diminish.51
Understandably new fMRI studies of the brain excite speculation about
empathy. Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging allows dynamic records
of oxygen use in whole brains to be made. The patterns in these records
are associated with the cognitive tasks undertaken by the subjects. Tania
Singer and her colleagues at the Wellcome Department of Neuroimaging at
the University of London recently published a study in Science document-
ing empathetic responses to witnessing another’s pain, supported by fMRI
data. This study broke new ground in demonstrating why a person perceives
that she feels another’s pain, while not literally experiencing the identical
sensation. Singer compared what happened in a subject’s brain when she
was actually shocked, when pain regions in the limbic system (the anterior
cingulate cortex, the insula, the thalamus, and the somatosensory cortices)
lit up on the fMRI, with what the brain looked like during observation of
another’s pain. When watching a loved one in the same room receiving a
sharp shock, subjects showed active responses in the affective parts of the
brain’s pain matrix (in the anterior insula and anterior cingulate cortex, the
lateral cerebellum, and the brainstem), but not in the somatosensory corti-
ces of the brain. The affective brain areas responded to both real and imag-
ined pain. A person not actually experiencing pain but observing a loved one
14 Empathy and the Novel
that the beneficiary of helping would assist the helper if the situation were
reversed, has eight times the impact on helping intentions than “the most
powerful traditional predictor, empathic concern” (“Evolution and Altru-
ism” 122). Though this one experiment affirms the “small but significant”
role of empathy in a helping response, it does not address the inhibiting
force of personal distress reactions. It may, however, indirectly clarify why
the link between narrative empathy and altruism is so tenuous.
For a novel reader who experiences either empathy or personal dis-
tress, there can be no expectancy of reciprocation involved in the aesthetic
response. The very nature of fictionality renders social contracts between
people and personlike characters null and void. Unlike the children held
hostage in Beslan who wished that Harry Potter would come to their rescue,
adult readers know that fictional characters cannot offer us aid. Similarly,
we accept that we cannot help them out, much as we may wish to inter-
vene: Don’t marry him, Dorothea! We may feel intense interest in charac-
ters, but incurring obligations toward them violates the terms of fictionality.
Kruger’s results may explain why the intense empathetic experiences of
novel readers do not lead more often to prosocial behavior: the impossibil-
ity of reciprocation may interfere. That is, an empathetic response can be
diverted from a prosocial outcome through interfering cognition.
up emotions skew toward the negative options of guilt, anger, and distress.
Hoffman describes five possibilities for the shaping of empathy into differ-
ent moral affects, each related to the perceiver’s evaluation of causes. If the
victim has caused her own distress, she may no longer seem like a victim,
and empathy may halt right there. If the victim has no control over the dis-
tress he experiences, he may invoke sympathetic distress in the perceiver,
pity for his plight. If the perceiver actually has caused the victim’s distress,
the perceiver’s empathy may morph into guilt; if the observer does nothing
to relieve the suffering individual, she may feel guilt over inaction; and if
the perceiver belongs to a group believed to be responsible for causing suf-
fering, he may feel guilt by association.
These real transformations of empathy into a variety of guilty feelings
may or may not impel a perceiver toward altruism or helping—guilty feel-
ing may in fact incline a perceiver toward a feeling of helplessness in the
face of others’ suffering. Hoffman believes, however, that guilty feeling can
be channeled into patterns of helping, but concedes that without teaching
by parents or others, this outcome is less likely to develop (Empathy and
Moral Development 9). He believes that empathy-based guilt is the key pro-
social motive (113), but he describes a process that requires both socializa-
tion and moral internalization.
A question that I consider later in this book is whether novel reading might
participate in the socialization and moral internalization required to trans-
mute empathic guilt into prosocial action. One option would be to examine
whether induction, as developmental psychologists understand it, plays a role.
Readers might obtain socialization experience through characters’ reactions
to fictive situations, translating recognitions about characters back to their
own lives. The parental strategy of induction, or taking victims’ perspective
and asking children to think about “how they would feel if they were in the
victims’ place” does bear a family resemblance to identification with fictional
characters. Books often tacitly ask readers to step into a character’s shoes.
Induction differs from character identification, however, because induction
occurs after a parent perceives a child’s injury of another. Missing from the
reading situation is the important sense—for induction and the writing of an
internalized moral script—that the reader has somehow wronged the char-
acters whose perspective he takes (cf. Empathy and Moral Development 151).
Parental induction responds to wrongdoing by a child; reading involves volun-
tary imagining by an innocent reader (at least so far as the relationship to the
text is concerned!). The unprompted application of lessons garnered through
reading to the self would support the connection of induction and character
identification, but the contempt in which many readers (including many chil-
dren) hold overtly didactic fiction suggests that resistance also exists.
Hoffman sees two moral affects potentially arising from empathy that
could lead to the outcomes posited by Martha Nussbaum. Empathic anger
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 19
and an empathic sense of injustice can each lead to personal, social, and
ideological responses based on understandings of unfairness or evocation of
righteous indignation on behalf of victims. Yet even here, Hoffman prom-
ises no inevitable leap between the perception and action in the world.
Many people feel others’ distress but do nothing to alleviate it. Limits on
empathy exist: for instance, people feel empathy for family members or for
those who are close, but not to faraway others (Empathy and Moral Devel-
opment 197). Even in circumstances in which helping others is affirmed
as a core activity, as in churches, we can grow so used to appeals that the
very familiarity of the suffering reduces an empathic response. Adults in the
helping professions, whose lives are dedicated to making effective responses
to others’ needs, sometimes report developing compassion fatigue, a kind
of empathy burnout (199–200). People experiencing empathic overarousal
may react with aversion to the source of the negative feelings, as studies of
personal distress indicate.61
Too much empathy can lead to an aversion to the victims or to the source
of information. For instance, my seven-year-old expressed a desire not to
go into the room if the radio was on, because the day before he had heard
an NPR story about the many Russian schoolchildren killed in Beslan after
being held hostage by Chechan militants. His empathetic distress of the day
before had turned into what Hoffman calls empathic overarousal (Empathy
and Moral Development 198). The novel reader discomforted by empathic
overarousal might well simply stop reading and might avoid similar fiction
in the future. If, however, a novel reader persisted in reading a text that ini-
tially caused overarousal and avoided the dead end of an aversive response,
might that reader benefit from reduction of aversive distress in the future?
This hypothesis, like many to be offered in subsequent chapters, could be
subjected to empirical testing.
Experiments in social psychology have already taught us a great deal
about limitations on empathy. Some of them have at their root biases,
or in their strong form, prejudices. Whether it is construed as familiar-
ity, similarity, or “in-group” bias, the reduction of response to those who
seem strange, dissimilar, or outside the tribe has been attributed to human
evolution (Empathy and Moral Development 206). This phenomenon can
be read as prejudice or ethnocentrism or possibly as a practical response to
a social world that makes too many demands on our feelings—we have to
use some kind of sorting mechanism. We tend to choose to respond to the
needs of those who are nearest us—flood victims in the Shenandoah Valley
command my attention more readily than those rendered homeless by a
typhoon in Bangladesh.
However, the “here and now” bias can be complicated by mass media
broadcasting, as in the startling images of the 26 December 2004 tsunami,
which can intermittently focus the nation’s or world’s attention on a par-
20 Empathy and the Novel
With all of television’s faults, has it, by depicting victims close-up, con-
tributed to an enlarged awareness and empathic feeling toward vic-
tims around the world? Or, does exposure to victims repeatedly over
time result in habituation and a lowering of people’s empathic distress
to the point of making them feel indifferent to another’s suffering? Or
. . . does depicting people in one’s primary group as victims of another
group foster ethnic hatred? Possibly all of the above apply and the net
effect of television on “mass empathy” depends on the frequency and
context of one’s exposure. Only research will tell. (Empathy and Moral
Development 214)
Versions of these troubling ideas have been in circulation since the eigh-
teenth century. We should not assume that character identification medi-
ated by video, film, or novels leads directly to empathy, altruism, and a com-
mitment to human rights.
The two biases in empathy of “familiarity” (which impedes response to
strangers) and “here-and-now” (which dilutes responsiveness to faraway or
unseen claimants, sometimes interfering with justice) can be altered by edu-
cation, according to Hoffman, but he and other scientists working on empa-
thy believe that the response is a product of natural selection, and thus
operates most powerfully in humans for those who share more of our genes
(Empathy and Moral Development 4, 13).62 He acknowledges that empathy
may work best in homogeneous groups (216), and that in complex, multi-
cultural, or (if I may extrapolate) global contexts, “empathic morality alone
may not be enough” (original italics, 216). Hoffman believes, however, that
empathy supports both caring and justice when it is embedded in moral
principles adopted by a society.63
If novels do cultivate readers’ empathy, and if empathy undergirds both
caring and justice in society, then fiction apparently has a vital job to do
today. However, the tethering of fiction (or novels, or narrative) to car-
ing also shows a wish to raise the status of fiction and to boost a minority
activity, reading. Linking novel reading to a widely shared moral princi-
ple—caring—without demanding that fiction be about caring allows broad
claims about the medium to exist without evaluating content. This is a
neat trick. Novels, by this logic, do not need to articulate the principle that
people ought to care for one another. Didacticism is not required. Instead,
the very action of reading fiction—any fiction—supposedly trains people
to care for one another. (Martha Nussbaum offers a more canonical set
of recommended readings; though classics, however, her favorite texts shy
away from didacticism.) Then, the relationship among reading, empathy,
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 21
and caring justifies (by back formation) the cultural centrality, even neces-
sity, of novels for a healthy society. These appealing connections may not
be justified, but they clearly have their attractions for defenders of the
humanities.
Fiction becomes even more implicated in socially beneficial processes
when Hoffman demonstrates the evident relationship between empathy
and caring. He writes, apparently of real people, “The link between empathy
and caring is reflected in the prosocial moral reasoning that accompanies
people’s behavior when they encounter someone in distress” (Empathy and
Moral Development 225). This view has been substantiated by psycholo-
gists working on the relationship between empathetic responses and moral
reasoning, especially the judgments people make about moral dilemmas.64
However, Hoffman directs his reader’s attention not to evidence from labo-
ratory studies of prosocial moral judgment, but to exhibits from nineteenth-
century fiction. He recounts anecdotes of fictional characters’ reasoning
about their helping behavior, drawn from Harriet Beecher Stowe’s Uncle
Tom’s Cabin (1852) and Mark Twain’s The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn
(1884–85). Novels themselves thus provide Hoffman’s evidence for affir-
mation of moral development as a result of empathizing, and he does not
acknowledge the fictionality of his examples. Hoffman slides right back to
the real world in his conclusion: “That is, empathizing with particular vic-
tims led to both affirming the caring principle and using the principle as a
premise for judging laws that violate it as morally wrong” (225). This will
not do. Fiction cannot document the effects of empathy as if the events
recorded happened to real people. The evidence Hoffman offers for the
function of empathy in cultivating caring and judgment tells us instead
what two nineteenth-century American novelists hoped for their readers.
True, both novels emphasize how unusual these helpers seem, and they
hold up their exceptional actions for praise and imitation. Regardless of
whether Uncle Tom’s Cabin and Huck Finn changed the hearts and minds of
readers, however, the fictional characters’ testimony simply cannot be con-
sidered evidence about empathy’s real world efficacy. We cannot attribute
both causal effects and evidence of those effects to the same fictional texts,
especially when attempting to describe the grounds for moral development
in living human beings.
Hoffman could well have gone to Stowe’s historical sources for legiti-
mate accounts of real people’s motivations to help fugitive slaves, but he
errs in making fictional characters stand for real people. Nonetheless, his
theory of moral development makes a strong case in favor of empathy’s role
in justice and caring. His work openly acknowledges barriers to expressions
of empathy in prosocial action, barriers not always acknowledged by those
who cite him as an authority on the empathetic sources of altruism. In
addition to Hoffman’s careful qualifications, alternative views weaken the
22 Empathy and the Novel
the outpouring of support for victims of 9/11 with the lack of response to
UNICEF’s announcement that an estimated 30,000 children died of disease
and malnutrition on 11 September 2001 (One World 151–52). Unjust, cer-
tainly, but understandable. In a world where so many people exhibit indif-
ference to others and respond only to egoistic desires, an increase in altruism
or even simple helping certainly seems like a good thing, even if multitudes
of needy people still experience neglect. Some cast aspersions on voluntary
helpers by suggesting that they donate time, treasure, and talent only to
feel good about themselves, or worse, in an insulting exercise of noblesse
oblige that degrades recipients of charity. (The squeamish may conveniently
avoid these criticisms by not helping at all.) Truly selfless and unrewarded
altruism, though rare, is harder to criticize without seeming churlish. The
special case of holocaust rescuers offers a model of this true altruism, that
is, helping that occurs in situations in which no benefit can accrue to the
helpers, who may even risk their lives and those of their families to respond
to another’s need. Holocaust rescuers couldn’t help every victim equally,
but few would contest the value of their altruistic actions for survivors and
their descendents.
Samuel and Pearl Oliner’s studies of the altruism of holocaust rescuers
offer a description of the personalities and motivations of these unusual
individuals.69 They were in a dramatic minority: less than half of one percent
of the population of those Nazi-occupied European countries the Olin-
ers studied participated in authenticated rescuing (Embracing the Other 6).
Some others were active in the resistance, but the vast majority of people
were bystanders or even collaborators. While we may agree that not every-
one can live up to the example of these heroic rescuers and acknowledge
that their more numerous nonresponding counterparts may have had prac-
tical reasons not to risk helping, rescuers surely exemplify the “good world
citizen” imagined by Nussbaum and others. Did empathy motivate them?
Did novel reading play a part in forming their characters?
The second question should be dealt with up front. The Oliners’ inter-
viewers inquired about education and religion of the rescuers and their par-
ents, but not about reading habits. We may assume that education correlates
with literacy, but no evidence emerges from the Oliners’ study that would
support a judgment about the importance or insignificance of novel read-
ing in cultivating the sympathetic imaginations of people who helped Jews
during the holocaust. Bystanders and active nonrescuers also offer no obser-
vations about the books that may have contributed to their life choices dur-
ing the war years. They were not asked. This lack of information does not
preclude influence through fiction reading, to be sure, but it does warrant
caution when making claims about the formation of these particular good
world citizens. To the Oliners and those who assisted in the research on the
altruistic personality, other factors seemed more central. Prominent among
these were education level, religious conviction, political affiliation, prior
24 Empathy and the Novel
knowledge of Jews, and, most importantly, the example set by parents and
other adults in the household of the future rescuer.70
The Oliners’ work does verify the importance of empathy for some
rescuers, but they did not find it a universal feature of the altruistic per-
sonality. Using an empathy scale to rate rescuers and nonrescuers, the
Oliners found that the two groups did not differ in experiencing primi-
tive emotional contagion when confronted with the feelings of others,
but they differed markedly in terms of their sympathy. We may infer that
widespread personal distress (and fear) account for the lack of altruistic
responsiveness of most of the rescuers’ contemporaries. Among the can-
didates for “rescuer status,” people with substantiated anti-Nazi activities,
the Oliners found striking differences. Those who reacted angrily to the
Nazis were more likely to become active in resistance movements than
in rescuing (Altruistic 148). Rescuers were more aroused by victims’ pain
(174). Rescuers did not show higher or lower levels of self-esteem than
nonrescuers (178), but they were more affected by an internal compul-
sion to help when aroused to sympathy or compassion (169). Rescuers
were more likely to perceive similarities with others, while nonrescuers
reported perceptions of differences (176), and rescuers aroused by the
pain of others also showed a general sense of responsibility and a tendency
to make commitments (175).
More than 90 percent of rescuers assisted at least one person who was a
total stranger (170). Nonetheless, the Oliners found that victims perceived
as attractive and innocent were more likely to receive help than others
(149). Religious affiliation did not distinguish rescuers from nonrescuers
(156), but felt religious conviction correlated weakly to rescuing. A far more
profound marker, the Oliners discovered, lay in egalitarianism and demo-
cratic political beliefs. Whether learned from parents or respected adults,
at church, or from exposure to democratic ideas, the egalitarianism of res-
cuers marked them as different from nonrescuers. Eighty-seven percent of
the rescuers interviewed by the Oliners’ team described their motivations
in terms of equity (fairness) or caring (163). Words expressing caring about
others and terms characterizing victims as fundamentally similar dominate
rescuers’ descriptions of their wartime situations (168, 178).
The Oliners concluded that four different groups contributed rescu-
ers. (1) Some were religious people with strong, cohesive family bonds. (2)
Some found themselves in close contact with Jewish people through work
or living situations. Others (3) had an abstract sense of connectedness or (4)
believed in egalitarian principles (Altruistic 188). These different conditions
contributed to the opportunity to help, but personal disposition also played
a role. Some rescuers acted out of principle; that is, they responded to a situ-
ation that clearly violated a norm that they had internalized as individuals.
Some responded to what they perceived as the breach of a social rule; these
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 25
people believed that as members of a group, they had the obligation to react
to violation of a norm. Some rescuers responded mainly because of their
empathic orientation to others (188).71 If we recall that emotional conta-
gion shows up to a similar degree in rescuers and nonrescuers, this empathic
orientation must combine with other factors to produce a stronger motive
force. For the Oliners, the key trait that combines with prior shared feeling
was egalitarianism.
Does novel reading inculcate egalitarian ideas? As I have already noted,
the Oliners’ team asked no questions about the reading habits of rescuers or
nonrescuers. If they had, their focus might well have been on the sources of
deeply held convictions, for they emphasize models and sources for beliefs
in their questions about family, friends, religion, and politics. Novels can
convey egalitarian ideas (though they may also contain strong represen-
tations of rank, hierarchy, or superiority over others). We should inquire,
rather than assuming, whether novels make effective vehicles for messages
of egalitarianism. This is a very different question from the point about
novel reading and character identification made by Nussbaum, Lynn Hunt,
and others. These theorists emphasize the moral renovation of the reader
through the very experience of novel reading. They argue that the process
of identifying with a fictional character leads to a revised view of other real
human beings. Thus Lynn Hunt links the growth of human rights discourse
to the rise of the novel.
This sort of argument avoids making judgments about the content of fic-
tion. According to Steven Pinker, storytelling has made the human species
nicer. Yet powerful stories about the racial supremacy of Aryans and the
contaminating presence of Jews provided a rationale for genocide. The con-
tent of stories is not a neutral matter. If narrative fiction has the capacity to
alter readers’ characters for the good, it may also possess darker powers. If
we were really to discover the whole impact of novel reading on Europeans
of the Second World War period, we would need to know whether reading,
like religious affiliation, cut across categories, or distinguished them from
one another. Might novels have provided retreats from reality for bystand-
ers? Elizabeth Bowen depicts such an escape into fantasy in her brilliant
wartime short story, “The Happy Autumn Fields,” in which the absorbing
adventures of an imagined Victorian family overcome the reality, for the
main character, of living under bombardment during the London Blitz.72
Bowen’s story offers an extreme case, but becoming absorbed in reading so
far as to enter a trancelike state is not abnormal: Victor Nell describes it as
“ludic reading,” in a study offering a compelling account of the psychology
of pleasure reading (Lost in a Book 73–83). Wartime may make that mental
disappearing act all the more appealing.
Given that less than half of one percent of people living in Nazi-occupied
Europe demonstrated their altruism by rescuing Jews, the impact of novel
26 Empathy and the Novel
The idea that emotion and cognition (or thinking, or reason) oppose each
other has a long history, not quite overlapping the venerable mind/body
distinction, though sometimes confused with it.78 The treatment of emo-
tions and rationality as separate and dichotomous features of our experience
has been challenged in recent decades. Thinking and feeling, for Antonio
R. Damasio, are part of the same package.79 In a series of academic articles
and popular books, he has shown that clinical patients suffering from emo-
tional disorders have cognitive difficulties. Ronald DeSousa has advocated
recognition of the rationality of emotions and Joseph LeDoux’s cognitive
neuroscience focuses on The Emotional Brain.80 Evolutionary psychologists
Leda Cosmides and John Tooby81 speak for a growing group of scientists
who believe that “one cannot sensibly talk about emotion affecting cogni-
tion because ‘cognition’ refers to a language for describing all of the brain’s
operations, including emotions and reasoning (whether deliberative or non-
conscious), and not to any particular subset of operations” (“Evolutionary
Psychology” 98). Some neuroscientists informally refer to “cogmotions” to
emphasize the fusion of the two concepts in their research.82 Nonethe-
less, many experts in cognition carry out their work without regard to the
emotions, and basic textbooks on cognition rarely refer to emotions.83 The
younger hybrid discipline of Social Cognition is more likely to reflect the
understandings of affect and cognition as intertwined.84 In the new field
known as Cognitive Approaches to Literary Studies, in which the work of
LeDoux and Damasio has virtually canonical status, matters of affect are
generally considered to fall under the umbrella of the term cognitive. Few lit-
erary cognitivists acknowledge that a psychologist might not readily accede
to the centrality of emotions to cognition. The subdisciplinary boundaries
within the extremely diverse field of psychology result in different empha-
ses and perspectives on the place of the emotions. Empathy studies have
from the start challenged the division of emotion and cognition.
Human empathy clearly involves both feeling and thinking. Memory,
experience, and the capacity to take another’s perspective (all matters tra-
ditionally considered cognitive) have roles in empathy. Yet the experience
of empathy in the feeling subject involves the emotions, including sensa-
tions in the body. Most experts consider empathy a phenomenon involving
both emotion and cognition, but subtle differences in the phrasing of their
definitions suggest their emphasis of one area over the other. For instance,
philosophers Susan Feagin and E. M. Dadlez stress the role of the imagina-
tion in empathy: in Dadlez’s words, “to empathize is to imagine having the
thoughts and beliefs, the desires and impulses of another” (What’s Hecuba
7). This view, like those of many philosophers’, tilts in the direction of think-
ing or cognition, as the keyword imagination signals. Some psychologists also
28 Empathy and the Novel
As Victor Nell observes, “we willingly enter the world of fiction because the
skepticism to which our adult sophistication condemns us is wearying: we
long for safe places—a love we can entirely trust, a truth we can entirely
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 29
a harrowing life story, it formally resembles the two documents that appear
above. Generically, it differs: it is not a letter, but a story within a story (an
interpolated tale, embedded within a primary fictional world). Though fans
of Alexander McCall Smith may well know that the orphanage that fea-
tures in Motholeli’s narrative has a real-world counterpart in Botswana, the
appearance of this first-person account within a popular detective novel
makes it easy to read as fictional. However, Motholeli’s story ends with
these words: “This story is true. I have not made any of it up. It is all true”
(Morality for Beautiful Girls 86). I hypothesized that my students would
respond feelingly to McCall Smith’s skilful recreation of an African voice
in his novel.
How did a cluster of real readers respond to the emotional appeals made
by these three texts? To what degree did their fictionality or nonfictional
status alter readers’ ways of evaluating them? One is a lying, fraudulent
appeal for assistance that, appealing to the recipients’ greed, could lead to
their fleecing. Another offers a possibly genuine but unverifiable appeal,
written out by hand, for a fairly modest sum. It is a traditional begging let-
ter. The third, contained inside a novel, claims in a first-person voice to be
a true story and makes no demand on the reader’s pocketbook. This con-
trast dramatizes fiction’s freedom to evoke feeling and readers’ option to
feel without following through with action. In the discussion that follows, I
quote the written reactions of my own college-age students, who read and
then reported how they felt about the three texts. While virtually all the
students rejected the scam e-mail’s appeal, many felt confused by the ball-
point pen letter, and for most readers, the third text seemed most true and
elicited the strongest feelings. Nonetheless, as I suggest below, empathetic
response was uncommon.
My student Caitlin evaluated the texts as follows:93
The e-mail. “Half of me believes that most of the scheme is true since I
know little about the country but the letter seems to go along with the
few stereotypes I am familiar with—that he is poor, his family is gone
and he needs aid from a Western person. When he asked that whoever
set up the account also be his guardian, that made the letter more
believable. But the rational side of me is louder than the compassion-
ate side—I would delete the e-mail.”
The ballpoint pen letter. “The handwriting of the letter and the talk
of parents who died of AIDS rouses some compassion—this I could
believe was true. But my guard is still up, especially with the tran-
script. I’d throw away the letter.”
The excerpt from Morality from Beautiful Girls. “Her story is so
believable, immediately I feel compassion for the young girl. It makes
me feel like no little girl should endure these things. I don’t know
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 31
what I would do other than dwell on her story, when I would not
dwell on the other 2 letters.”
Caitlin’s response captures well how the novel excerpt strikes readers as
truthful, while the appeals from African correspondents puts them on
guard. Martin Hoffman would identify Caitlin’s response to the Motholeli’s
story as exhibiting her sense of empathic injustice. For now, let us note that
Caitlin offers to “dwell on” Motholeli’s story, while planning to discard or
delete the other texts. Fiction demonstrates its capacity to command the
reader’s attention through feelings of compassion. Yet Caitlin’s prospective
actions as a result of reading are limited to ignoring or “dwelling on,” a good
phrase for the daydreaming thought that readers of fiction add to their com-
prehension of narratives.
Ian, one of very few male students in the group, posited more activist
responses to the three texts:
The e-mail. “It just constitutes another reason why my trust in human-
ity has fallen to an all time low. I only wish there was some authority
that I could forward this letter to, so that the perpetrator of this scam
could be prosecuted. Unfortunately that is not an option.”
The ballpoint pen letter. “This one seems even worse because it is so
deceptive. A handwritten note, so seemingly trustworthy, and with
such good intentions, could have such a scam behind the façade.
There is little to do in this case other than ignore this shameless plea
for funds.”
The excerpt from Morality from Beautiful Girls. “It is obviously a
dramatized story, however it almost seemed more genuine than the
other two letters. If it were a real scenario, I would possibly donate
money to the orphanage that took the children in.”
Ian reacts angrily to the e-mail, with irritation to the ballpoint pen letter,
and with slightly more openness and trust to the novel excerpt. The condi-
tional actions Ian imagines include ignoring, like Caitlin, but he also thinks
about donating money (if Motholeli’s story were real) and wishes that he
could bring down the force of the law upon the email scammer. Interest-
ingly, Ian rules out forwarding the e-mail to “some authority,” perhaps not
realizing that the Attorney Generals’ Offices of most states in the United
States operate fraud-alert hotlines and Web sites. Just possibly, if Ian learned
the web address of the fraud prevention Web site or the name of the actual
orphanage, the SOS Children’s Village at Tlokweng, upon which Alexander
McCall Smith bases Mma Potokwane’s fictional orphan farm, then perhaps
his disposition to act would result in responses in the real world.94 His base-
line assumption, however, holds that action is impossible—he rules it out.
32 Empathy and the Novel
ing that her lack of information had prejudiced her against it in the past. If
reading a single light detective novel can have such a result, then the real-
world effects of novel reading may be considerable.
Two students responded to Motholeli’s story with judgments of them-
selves.95 While Courtney projected outward from the orphan girl to the
continent of Africa, revising her view to emphasize its peoples’ innate good-
ness, Amanda and Paige reflected on what the story revealed about them-
selves and their own inadequacies. Amanda writes, “This letter makes me
angry and at the same time a little ashamed. Supposing this were a real
letter, and I’m getting it for a good reason, I would be angry about her mis-
treatment and also ashamed that I am not able to handle the problems in
my life with such humility and acceptance. The letter doesn’t call for action,
but I guess I would try to keep a better perspective.” Of all the students I
surveyed, only Amanda responded to the character’s abuse by malefactors
clearly described by Alexander McCall Smith. Amanda clearly engages in
perspective taking when she applies a lesson from Motholeli’s response to
her own life. Similarly, Paige puts herself in Motholeli’s shoeless footprints:
“I don’t know what the action would be here,” Paige confesses,
Yet, the letter makes me say: “wow”—for lack of a better word. Here
is this girl, removed from situations of “comfort” 3 times to live what
she calls “3 lives.” If anything happened to me as it happened to her, I
would be so devastated that I probably would be completely helpless.
The fact that such a small girl was able to overcome such hardship
and take care of not only herself, but also her brother at such a young
age really speaks to my heart—and she is not cynical and upset, as I or
many privileged Westerners would be, but she is grateful.
Noor N.’s authenticity. Though nearly half still felt Noor was worth help-
ing, none of my students responded to the explicitly religious content of
Noor’s appeal. The effort made in the letter to connect writer and recipient
through faith made little impact, but the deaths from AIDS and the writer’s
status as a student (albeit a student of tailoring) resonated with these col-
lege students. Chapter 3, “Readers’ Empathy,” discusses in detail the narra-
tive techniques that contribute to empathetic responses from readers. An
important one appears here, in Noor’s construction of her autobiographical
persona as a student whose family members have died. She makes of her-
self what I call a bridge character, with whom faraway readers can feel they
have something in common. Nonetheless, Noor’s appeal received cautiously
compassionate responses, at best, and some students rejected the ballpoint
pen letter as obviously fraudulent.
Fiction, as we know, depends upon its persuasive lies for its world-mak-
ing powers. But fictional world-making is only ever as effective as the partic-
ipatory reader makes it, through active cocreation. The capacity of human
beings to engage intellectually and emotionally with imaginary worlds and
their denizens places narrative empathy at the intersection of aesthetics,
psychology, and philosophy. As the cognitive literary theorist Lisa Zun-
shine speculates, “The enjoyment of fiction may be predicated—at least in
part—upon awareness of our ‘trying on,’ so to speak, mental states (of the
characters) potentially available to us but at a given moment differing from
our own” (“Richardson’s” 132). For Zunshine, Theory of Mind theory sug-
gests that “the very process of making sense of what we read appears to be
grounded in our ability to invest the flimsy verbal constructions that we
generously call ‘characters’ with a potential for a variety of thoughts, feel-
ings, and desires” (132). Vitally for this conception, fictional characters play
a different role for readers than the regard of real others encountered in
the world. While the fact of human others’ perspectives and motivations
activates our caution, the fictiveness of characters’ mental states invites our
participation and playful engagement. This view was borne out by my stu-
dents’ responses. The very fictionality of the excerpt from Alexander McCall
Smith’s Morality for Beautiful Girls overcame the guarded reading habits
of my students and permitted emotional responses to emerge. As we have
seen, the language of sympathy and compassion appeared in several of their
responses. Did Motholeli’s story invoke empathy, however? The novel suc-
ceeded in getting two students to engage in perspective taking. One leapt to
a perception of injustice. One taught herself to regard Africa and Botswana
as good. None of the students wrote anything in the empathetic register of
“I feel what Motholeli feels.” The closest to come to that was the West Afri-
can respondent, who wrote of a sense of recognition: “It is reminiscent of so
many African Stories.”
Does exposure to just a few of the many African stories cultivate the
empathy of readers who might otherwise regard Africans (in all their diver-
Contemporary Perspectives on Empathy 35
The fact that novel reading receives credit from policy makers and bureau-
crats for renovating potential marks a noteworthy development in the his-
tory of a form that has not always been celebrated for its positive influence
on civic life.1 In 1749, the London Magazine suggested that the vogue for
novel reading resulted in the loss of human spirit in the pursuit of a non-
entity, exchanging reasonable delight for “negligence and folly” (Novel and
Romance 127). Many reviewers worried that readers’ appetite for frivolity
would drive out useful and serious (nonfictional) works and that “obscene”
works pouring in from France would corrupt the young (209). In 1791, the
Reverend Edward Barry warned that novel reading ranked among the incen-
tives to seduction. Fiction could prime an explosion of the reader’s inner
bulwarks of virtue and reputation by agitating unrelieved sensations (375).
The official disrepute of the popular form registers in the somewhat defen-
sive claims made by the now-canonical heavyweights of the eighteenth-cen-
tury novel. In his Preface to Robinson Crusoe (1719), Daniel Defoe insists:
“The Story is Told with Modesty, with Seriousness, and with a religious
Application of Events to the Uses to which wise Men always apply them
(viz) to the Instruction of others by this Example, and to justify and honour
the Wisdom of Providence in all the Variety of our Circumstances” (56).
Testimonial advertisements for Samuel Richardson’s Pamela (1740) affirm,
“As to Instruction and Morality, the Piece is full of both. It shews Virtue in
the strongest light and renders the Practice of it amiable and lovely” (96).
The influence of the romantic experiences of fictional females on unmar-
ried women readers was an especially sensitive point, as cultural watchdogs
fretted that novel reading would lead not to the imitation of Pamela’s virtue,
but to unrealistic expectations about marriage. The perverted imagination
would devolve to wasted lives and bitter disappointments. Novels threat-
ened to make readers do too much, stirring up passions that could find sat-
isfaction only in illicit sexual activity, and too little, inducing indolence and
indifference to real life.
These eighteenth-century criticisms of novel reading persisted well into
the Victorian period, receiving a boost from the evangelical distrust of fic-
38 Empathy and the Novel
tion and the religious convictions of librarians such as Mr. Mudie. De facto
censorship of the more licentious aspects of fiction set in as circulating
libraries such as Mudie’s bought most of the print runs of Victorian nov-
els and enforced a representational code that ostensibly prevented a blush
from rising to the cheek of the young person. Editors of family magazines
colluded in the cultural project of cleaning up a form that had the reputa-
tion of tending toward inappropriate, even scandalous, representation. Eigh-
teenth-century novels fell into disrepute as reading for respectable women.
Even a bestseller such as Jane Eyre (1847) received reviews cautioning read-
ers that it was appropriate fare only for grown men and married women.
Sensation fiction of the 1860s freshened the sense that novel reading could
be dangerous and corrupting.
The reinvention of the novel as a form that might do something positive
in the world by swaying readers’ minds rather than activating their passions
we may also date to the Victorian period, particularly to the mid-century
when social-problem novelists used fiction to diagnose the condition of Eng-
land. Charles Dickens’s Oliver Twist (1837–38) permanently tarnished the
image of the New Poor Law and its workhouse system. Benjamin Disraeli’s
now largely unread Coningsby (1844) and Sybil (1845) outlined a political
program and described the division of Britain into two nations. Elizabeth
Gaskell’s Mary Barton (1848) urged well-off Christian readers to bridge
the growing gulf between the rich and the poor in a homiletic fiction that
invoked the fear of revolution as well as the threat of perdition. Gaskell, a
Unitarian minister’s wife, had the credentials to offer her sermon, but the
most eloquent advocate for the moral usefulness of fiction was the unbeliev-
ing and officially immoral George Eliot (Mary Ann Evans lived in sin with
a married man, George Henry Lewes). Eliot’s novels, most especially Adam
Bede (1859) and Middlemarch (1871–72), articulated a project for the cul-
tivation of the reader’s sympathetic imagination. Novel readers might learn,
by extending themselves into the experiences, motives, and emotions of
fictional characters, to sympathize with real others in their everyday lives.
Thomas Hardy notoriously pushed the envelope in the last generation of
Victorian fiction by presenting for sympathetic imagining characters such
as Tess, a fallen woman, and Jude, a member of the disenfranchised working
class. We owe to these Victorian novelists the notion that novel reading can
be a personally improving activity and one that may even, as in the famous
case of Harriet Beecher Stowe’s bestseller Uncle Tom’s Cabin (1852), inspire
allegiance to a political cause, in that case the eradication of slavery.2
The appearance in the twentieth century of difficult and relatively inac-
cessible high literary modernist fiction such as James Joyce’s Ulysses (1922)
raised the status of a form whose more ordinary instances still commanded
little respect. By this time, serious fiction had achieved critical sanction as
literature, while the numerous descendents of romance devolved into the
popular subliterary genres that commanded an increasing share of the fic-
The Literary Career of Empathy 39
tion market after the 1880s. The modes of criticism that followed the iden-
tification of a Great Tradition in English fiction (by F. R. Leavis in 1948)
enforced the process of separating the novel from its origins as a consumer
product sustained by buyers (or paying borrowers) in a commercial mar-
ketplace. The novel’s reputation and generic status had risen higher by mid-
century, in part as a result of the academic study of English literature. Yet
popular fiction—and writing lives sustained by its sale—persisted. Despite
the remaining distinctions of (higher, more culturally valued) literary fiction
and (lower, mass market) genre fiction and the serious challenge posed by
film and television, the novel has made it to the twenty-first century, during
which it has become a global commodity, thanks in part to the European
empires that spread both languages and cultural forms worldwide. Even
though the number of readers continues its lamented decline, the novel as
a form currently enjoys the best press of its three-century career. Novels get
credit for the character-building renovation of readers into open-minded,
generous citizens.
The key term in the transformation of novel reading from a morally sus-
pect waste of time to an activity cultivating the role-taking imagination,
empathy, appeared in English as a translation of Einfühlung in the early twen-
tieth century.3 Since then, its verb form, “to empathize,” and its interchange-
able adjectival spin-offs “empathic” and “empathetic,” have passed into com-
mon parlance. In the twenty-first century, real human empathy enjoys good
press as a concept and a desirable character trait (given the improved cul-
tural status of emotional intelligence [Goleman, Emotional Intelligence 96–
110]). Its application in representational empathy, through the invocation
of shared feelings through words, sounds, and images, leaps forward with
the newer entertainment technologies. Film effectively exploits empathy—
it is at least a happy coincidence that the invention of motion pictures and
the modern term empathy occurred in the same decades.4 Imax theatres are
wonderful places to observe people engaged in motor mimicry, especially
while they watch 3-D films. Empathy’s lexical spread in the realms of high-
tech gear, gaming, and fantasy and science fiction reaches its apotheosis in
virtual reality machinery. In popular fictions of virtual reality, and even in
the real world, commercially available goggle and glove sets make it possible
for consumers to replace their own experiences and sensations with sensory
inputs that construct entirely computer-generated worlds. This extreme
case of voluntary exchange of one’s own reality for the sensations of another
takes to its furthest logical extension the fusing with another object that
aesthetics’ Einfühlung set out to describe in the 1890s. It also raises worrying
questions about the purposes of fictive representation: does virtual reality’s
evident usefulness in training jet pilots or producing green screen animation
make up for the unseemly pornographic possibilities foreseen by science
fiction? The reputation of narrative empathy is tainted by association with
popular technologies for sharing feelings. This goes a ways toward explain-
40 Empathy and the Novel
ing why advocates of the ethical benefits of novel reading nearly always
insist that great literature—Greek tragedies, Shakespeare’s plays, canonical
novels, and serious literary fiction—best stimulates literary empathy.
When I see the effects of passion in the voice and gesture of any per-
son, my mind immediately passes from these effects to their causes,
and forms such a lively idea of the passion, as is presently converted
into the passion itself. In like manner, when I perceive the causes of
any emotion, my mind is convey’d to the effects, and is actuated with
a like emotion. Were I present at any of the more terrible operations
of surgery, ’tis certain, that even before it began, the preparation of
the instruments, the laying of the bandages in order, the heating of
the irons, with all the signs of anxiety and concern in the patient and
assistants, wou’d have a great effect upon my mind, and excite the
strongest sentiments of pity and terror. No passion of another discov-
ers itself immediately to the mind. We are only sensible of its causes
or effects. From these we infer the passion: And consequently these give
rise to our sympathy. (Human Nature 576, italics in original)
and become in some measure the same person with him, and thence form
some idea of his sensations, and even feel something which, though weaker
in degree, is not altogether unlike them” (9). Smith even anticipates the
problem of projection, writing, “we sometimes feel for another, a passion of
which he himself seems to be altogether incapable; because, when we put
ourselves in his case, that passion arises in our breast from the imagination,
though it does not in his from the reality” (12).
Both Smith and Hume link sympathy to the organizational principles
of society. Smith believed our sympathy made us good citizens, and Hume
insisted that our sympathy tempered our self-interest: “Thus self-interest is
the original motive to the establishment of justice: but a sympathy with pub-
lic interest is the source of the moral approbation, which attends that virtue”
(Human Nature 499–500, emphasis in original). The sympathy and social
feeling for fellow creatures described by Hume and Smith constitute core
elements of subsequent English utilitarian philosophy, and they are linked
through that tradition with aims of social reform. The nearly automatic
association of spontaneously shared feelings with socially beneficial action
in the world owes a great deal to this transmission from the eighteenth
century to the Victorians, who were to develop the romantic idea of the
sympathetic imagination into a device for personal and social renovation.
As we will see, some Victorians especially prized the novel as a popular
narrative form well suited to cultivate the feelings of readers and instruct
them in political and social issues. Though their fiction—and indeed the late
twentieth-century fiction fiction that is the subject of this book—employs
very different representational strategies than the eighteenth-century novel,
the novel of sensibility contributes an important positive vision of the moral
force of reading.
Sensibility refers to responsiveness both to others’ emotions and to inan-
imate features, such as sublime landscapes. The novel of sensibility was
regarded by its appreciators as sowing the seeds of virtue in the hearts of
responsive readers.11 Between the time of Hume and Smith’s two philo-
sophical treatises, the English novel had made a good start in gaining its first
wide audience, including many women readers. Sympathy features promi-
nently in the themes and effects of the literature of sensibility. Novels that
invoked strong feelings enjoyed widespread popularity,12 in part because
such fellow feeling was esteemed as the source of social bonds: sensibility
was believed to lead to compassion and active benevolence. Sensibility in a
reader showed in her feeling responses; in a fictional work, sensibility sug-
gested its capacity to invoke feeling reactions.
Fiction was especially esteemed for its capacity to extend a reader’s imagi-
native capacity beyond a narrow circle of acquaintance, as in Henry Home,
Lord Kames’s observations about the emotions caused by fiction from his Ele-
ments of Criticism (1762).13 Henry Lord Kames appreciates the power of lan-
guage to call up ideal representations that lead to readers’ virtuous actions:
The Literary Career of Empathy 45
That extensive influence which language hath over the heart; an influ-
ence, which, more than any other means, strengthens the bond of soci-
ety, and attracts individuals from their private system to perform acts
of generosity and benevolence. Matters of fact, it is true, and truth in
general, may be inculcated without taking advantage of ideal presence;
but without it, the finest speaker or writer would in vain attempt to
move any passion: our sympathy would be confined to objects that
are really present; and language would lose entirely its signal power
of making us sympathize with the beings removed at the greatest dis-
tance of time as well as of place. Nor is the influence of language, by
means of ideal presence confined to the heart; it reacheth also the
understanding and contributes to belief. (“Emotions Caused by Fic-
tion” v. 1. 74)
Much has been said in favour of [such representations], and they are
generally thought to improve the tender and humane feelings; but
this, I own, appears to me very dubious. That they exercise sensibil-
ity is true, but sensibility does not increase with exercise. By the con-
stitution of our frame our habits increase, our emotions decrease, by
repeated acts; and thus a wise provision is made, that as our compas-
sion grows weaker, its place should be supplied by habitual benev-
olence. But in these writings our sensibility is strongly called forth
The Literary Career of Empathy 47
Aiken’s critique echoes down through the centuries to the present day,
when it has become a critical commonplace in some schools of thought to
see the novel as dulling readers’ sense of responsibility to real people, either
by habituating them to the idea of faraway others’ suffering, or by providing
representative fictional characters who replace real others, and (being fic-
tional) make no demands on readers.16 Other eighteenth-century detractors
of sympathy saw different risks because they felt, in contrast to Aiken, that
sympathy was all too effective: it spread alarmingly from person to person.
For the influential William Godwin of An Enquiry Concerning Political Jus-
tice (1798 edition), the social nature of sympathy conflicts with individu-
ality. The enthusiasm generated by crowds spontaneously sharing feelings
evokes the spectre of the out-of-control mob or the contagious disease.17
Though Godwin felt that the fleeting moods of sensibility that resulted in
momentary tearful reactions had no staying power, he still wrote propagan-
distic fiction that attempted to channel human sympathy of readers into
useful courses of action.
Twentieth- and twenty-first–century readers tend to notice additional
bothersome features of sympathy and the literature of sensibility. While
sympathy in Hume and Smith emphasizes mutuality of feeling, for later
readers, the fiction of sensibility presents excessive scenes of compassion
and pity that can seem condescending to the suffering recipient. Sympathy
becomes tainted with a sense of social as well as moral superiority, and the
suspicion that it exists only to shore up middle-class identity taints its exer-
cise.18 Empathic scenes of shared feeling can seem vampiric, as if the person
of sensibility feeds on the pain of others. It gets worse. A recent historical
rereading of the late eighteenth-century literature of abolition sees the rep-
resentations of suffering slaves as pornographic, appealing to the sadomas-
ochistic appetites of persons of sensibility. In a direct confutation of the
claim that empathy for fictional characters started human rights discourse,
Marcus Wood writes that “the dirtiest thing the Western imagination ever
48 Empathy and the Novel
The Romantic poets not only believed in the powers of sympathy, but they
also attempted to bring their readers into contact with others, animate and
inanimate, in order to guarantee the conversion of feeling into benevolent
action. Though some Romantic writers felt qualms about the conversion
of others’ suffering into aesthetic pleasures for readers, they emphasized
the beneficial opportunity to engage in imaginative transport beyond the
bounds of the self.21 Despite their oppositional stance toward the earlier
generation of poets, the Romantics belonged still to a philosophical tradi-
tion that linked self-love to love of community and regarded the human
race as an extended family:
depends upon the experience of loving others (4–5). Hazlitt sees sympa-
thetic imagining as the more persuasive account of self-knowledge (over
self-interest), writing
Every one has experience of the fact, that to sympathize with the suf-
ferings of another, is to enjoy a transitory oblivion of his own. . . . The
inhabitant of a highly civilized community will more acutely sympa-
thize with the sufferings and enjoyments of others, than the inhab-
itant of a society of a less degree of civilization. He who shall have
cultivated his intellectual powers by familiarity with the highest speci-
mens of poetry and philosophy, will usually sympathize more than
one engaged in the less refined functions of manual labour. . . . The
only distinction between the selfish man and the virtuous man is that
the imagination of the former is confined within a narrow limit, while
that of the latter embraces a comprehensive circumference. (“Treatise
on Morals” 188–89)
For Wordsworth, Coleridge, and Shelley, poetry did the best job of the
varieties of available literature in extending the sympathetic circle and cul-
tivating the capacity to feel with others, in what is now described as empa-
thetic connection. Though my account of early nineteenth-century ideas
has observed the convention of using the contemporary terminology, ele-
ments of empathy embedded within nineteenth-century sympathy (as in
the eighteenth-century sources) should be clear: the spontaneous overflow
of powerful feeling, prompted by memory, landscape, or personal encoun-
ters, involves what contemporary psychologists call emotional contagion.
The questionable accuracy of the empathetic projections of Wordsworth,
in poetic conversation with his sister, laborers, or vagrants, should not
obscure the centrality of spontaneous emotional sharing to the Romantics’
The Literary Career of Empathy 51
thought.22 For Wordsworth, exercising this faculty aided moral growth and
repaired the wounded soul.
For the Romantics, the emotionally involved reader and the sympatheti-
cally imagining writer joined in a mutually reinforcing process of cultivating
feeling selves.23 Indeed, because of the powerful invocation of sympathetic
responses to people and scenes in Romantic poetry, literary texts (particu-
larly poetry) become the preeminent place of sympathy in the early nine-
teenth century. This is not to say that real individuals living in the 1800s
ceased to experience the psychological phenomena of spontaneous shared
emotion, fellow feeling, sympathy, or pity for real people—quite the con-
trary—but that literary representations of sympathetic encounters became
so influential in the culture at large that the evidence of textual and real-
world sympathy become difficult to disentangle. A lyric poem offering an
account of sympathy on the part of the speaker that also records the poet’s
sympathy (and elicits it from readers) offers a complex of sympathies, some
of which continue to operate outside of their original historical moment.
This fusion and ongoing transmission of sympathies complicates our view
of nineteenth-century sympathy in many ways, not only because we rely
on textual sources as records of real (but no longer living) people’s feel-
ings. Texts articulating theories of emotional connections between self and
other become erstwhile records of moments of sympathy in history. Yet the
status of a poem as a record of a lived feeling depends in part on a theory
of poetry, still vigorous today, that emerges in the Romantic period through
intertwined poetic and emotional practices.
The circulation of sympathy through author, reader, real world, and text
still underwrites most of the boldest claims for the consequences of read-
ing and writing. This legacy of romanticism passes directly to theories of
Victorian fiction. By the Romantics’ logic, writers invite readers to fuse with
themselves and with the objects of their representation. Readers feel with
writers and with characters or representations, and readers in the real world
regard the objects of their gaze as if they were representations. Writers in the
real world do the same thing with their subjects, recognizing and represent-
ing them as material for sympathetic identification—the loop goes on. In
testifying to the effects of fiction, readers’ responses to characters in novels
often elide the difference between fictive constructions and actual experi-
ence: the training in sensibility offered by fiction often becomes evidence of
its own efficacy. Whether one judges the net effect of this aesthetic practice
as the stimulus for the changes of heart that accompanied or brought about
the social changes of the nineteenth century, or as a phenomenon ultimately
isolating, selfish, and dehumanizing to others, depends on temperament and
opinion, not established fact.
There is no doubt that Victorians had high hopes for the moral con-
sequences of novel reading, though editors, publishers, and proprietors of
52 Empathy and the Novel
libraries also presided over an informal censorship that kept fiction safe
for young people. Raised in status by the productive career of the popular
poet Walter Scott, novels in the Victorian period dominated the collections
of circulating libraries and were widely disseminated through weekly and
monthly periodical publications. Serialized fiction appeared in the com-
pany of nonfictional essays in many of the magazines of the day, and editors
exploited the connections between fictional representations and the topics
or issues they raised. Sympathy for fictional characters (including animals)
could be turned to persuasive advantage by editors advancing causes of the
day, or so they believed.24
By the end of the Victorian period and the first 150 years of the novel,
slavery had been abolished, child labor had been curtailed, free public edu-
cation had been established, factories had been made safer for workers, the
franchise had been extended, and a host of other reforms had occurred.
Literary representations calling upon the sympathetic imaginations of
readers had been marshaled to these and other causes in an outpouring
of didactic and sensational fictions. Both the social-problem novels of the
earlier part of the Victorian period (up until the 1848 climax of the Char-
tist movement) and the sensation fiction of the 1860s–70s depended upon
moving readers’ feelings about topical problems. The earlier industrial or
social-problem fiction gravitated toward the plight of workers or the rift
between the two nations of the rich and the poor, while sensation fiction
drew its lurid topics of bigamy, false imprisonment, madness, and divorce
from scandals of the day.
Whether the fiction on these topics appealed because it connected
to concerns of the present or recent past, confirming readers’ previously
formed opinions, or because it offered new ways of thinking that chal-
lenged complacency, it is difficult to know. Literary critics and novelists of
the day often deplored open didacticism (a legacy of the use of fiction in
tracts and pamphlets produced by various reform-minded societies), but
successful forms of didacticism included those that exemplified political or
religious arguments through convincing characters.25 Thus, Harriet Beecher
Stowe’s Uncle Tom’s Cabin, condemning slavery, and Elizabeth Gaskell’s
Ruth (1853), about a fallen woman, both received approving reviews
even from periodicals otherwise hostile to fiction of overt didactic pur-
pose (Stang Theory 70). The contemporary reviews offer at least a record
of paid opinion. Whether novels-with-a-purpose actually swayed readers,
changed minds, and resulted in different behavior is difficult to ascertain
at a far remove. On the one hand, strong claims of efficacy include the
critical commonplace that Charles Dickens’s condemnation of the New
Poor Law’s workhouse system in Oliver Twist (1837–38) prevented the full
implementation of the law, so prejudiced against the system were his read-
ers. Further, the depiction of a Yorkshire orphanage, Dotheboys Hall, and
its sadistic headmaster, Wackford Squeers, in Dicken’s Nicholas Nickleby
The Literary Career of Empathy 53
role of art and letters in actively shaping the reader’s imaginative capacity.
The views of Wordsworth about the renovating virtue of extended sympa-
thies receive in Eliot’s version a reworking that applies to narrative fiction,
as this extract makes plain:
In the beginning of the twentieth century, the English novelist Vernon Lee
brought Einfühlung and empathy to a broader literary audience. In a public
lecture followed by a magazine piece in a popular journal,32 she advanced
a theory of aesthetic perception of form involving empathy, though not
(at first) so named. Originally Lee’s aesthetics focused on bodily sensations
and muscular adjustments made by beholders of works of art and architec-
ture and downplayed emotional responsiveness. By the time she revised and
expanded her ideas for presentation in book form as The Beautiful (1913),
Lee had adapted Lipps’s understanding of empathy, a parallel development
from common sources in German aesthetics. Defining the purpose of art as,
in part, “the awakening, intensifying, or maintaining of definite emotional
states” (Beautiful 99–100), Lee makes empathy a central feature of our col-
laborative responsiveness (128). In an account that combines motor mim-
icry, memory, and psychological responsiveness to inanimate objects, Lee
argues that empathy enters into “imagination, sympathy, and also into that
inference from our own inner experience which has shaped all our concep-
tions of an outer world, and given to the intermittent and heterogeneous
56 Empathy and the Novel
sensations received from without the framework of our constant and highly
unified inner experience, that is to say, of our own activities and aims” (68).
An explanation for our figurative language (62), empathy for Lee is ubiq-
uitous, a matter of cognition. She remarks, “If Empathy is so recent a dis-
covery, this may be due to its being part and parcel of our thinking; so that
we are surprised to learn of its existence, as Molière’s good man was to hear
that he talked in prose” (69). No sooner had the term been announced and
situated so centrally in aesthetic theory for an English-language audience,
however, than it received brisk challenge from high modernist quarters.
Literary modernism took on sympathy, empathy, and sensibility not by
questioning the claims of social and personal benefit that earlier writers
ascribed to these psychological experiences of emotion. Instead, it sought
to break with the aims that Philip Sidney framed in the Renaissance, Henry
Lord Kames recast in the eighteenth century, and the Romantic poets and
Victorian novelists such as Dickens, Gaskell, and Eliot sought to implement
in the nineteenth century. Modernists revised the purposes of art, broadly
conceived. Appeals to sentiment and feeling fell out of favor as merely con-
ventional. Poets eschewed empty phrasing. Experimental techniques dis-
rupted the surface of discourse so that it could not be read by getting “lost in
a book,” with the reader submerged in an unchallenging, absorbing, reading
trance. Inducing readers to work as strenuously thinking collaborators meant
depriving them of the emotional effects they had come to rely upon get-
ting from literature.33 To see how the critical evaluation of empathy changes
just as the term itself begins to gain an audience in the fields of aesthetics
and psychology, we turn to the areas of poetry and drama, where highbrow
cultural arbiters expressed disdain for the empathetic effects of character
identification and crude appeals to emotion.
Perhaps the best known assault on empathy as an aspect of artistic recep-
tion in the modern period comes from Bertolt Brecht’s so-called alienation
effect, a translation of the Verfremsdungseffekt (V-effekt), which can be bet-
ter rendered as an estrangement effect.34 Brecht offered his theory in essays
and interviews, but critics have also singled out aspects of his theatrical
practice that reach for the defamiliarization or making strange that would
promote a rational response and deflect viewers’ emotional reactions. In
particular, Brecht sought to discourage his audience from identifying with
characters. He took an interest in plays from non-Aristotelian traditions that
were “not dependent on empathy” (“Chinese Acting” 91). Brecht wanted
playgoers to experience detachment, rather than absorbed suspension of
disbelief. His techniques included the rejection of both the illusion of the
fourth wall and Stanislavskian acting. By reversing the conventions in both
these areas of dramaturgy, Brecht attempted to interfere with “the auto-
matic transfer of the emotions to the spectator,” a phenomenon Brecht
deplored as “emotional infection” (94). He wished instead for the presenta-
tion of dramatic figures “quite coldly, classically and objectively. For they are
The Literary Career of Empathy 57
The old A-effects quite remove the object represented from the spec-
tator’s grasp, turning it into something that cannot be altered; the new
are not odd in themselves, though the unscientific eye stamps anything
strange as odd. The new alienations are only designed to free socially-
conditioned phenomena from that stamp of familiarity which protects
them against our grasp today. (“Short Organum,” section 43, 192)
the late 1920s onward. First, the demanding nature of high modernist liter-
ary fiction meant that novel reading (and novel writing) became a more dig-
nified activity. This change in the status of fiction accompanied the growth
of a new category, literary fiction, which split off from the mass of publica-
tions in areas now labeled as subliterary “genres.”42 A person such as Virginia
Woolf could be a celebrity, with her picture in Vogue, even if her novels
were read by relatively few. Eager to read for pleasure and edification, but
insufficiently invested in the strenuous interpretative work to make a steady
diet of high literary modernism, middlebrow readers patronized bookshops
and circulating libraries in large numbers. They read excellent short fiction
in popular magazines, especially in the United States. They read the advice
of book reviewers writing for the weeklies and dailies. Despite the disdain
of cultural arbiters, best-seller lists became powerful devices for the rec-
ommendation of reading material, fictional and nonfictional, to numerous
middlebrows attentive to fashion.
Several publishing houses, such as the Modern Library and Penguin
Books, were founded to reach this readership. Book clubs such as the
National Book League, the Literary Guild, and the Book of the Month Club
capitalized on middlebrow readers’ willingness to have their reading cho-
sen for them, particularly as books became part of the appropriate furnish-
ings of the middle-class home. Advertisers emphasized novels as consumer
products. In the meantime, literary criticism split off from book reviewing
as a newly professionalized class of interpreters trained university students
(including growing numbers of women and working-class students) in the
technical analysis and judgment of literature. Women had always made up
a large part of the audience for novels, but now more college-educated and
professional women brought their disposable income to the bookshop or
to the automatic billing subscription service. For these middlebrow read-
ers, aims of escapist pleasure reading needed not conflict with the desire to
stretch a little intellectually, so long as the work was not so demanding as
to interfere with immersion reading habits. Aims of self-improvement and
social awareness were not absent from the middlebrows’ vision of what
reading might do for them.43 Fiction was valued for introducing readers to
new worlds and experiences. Indeed, the use of literature in the secondary
schools as a vehicle for teaching values, history, heritage, and civics laid the
groundwork for a later generation’s use of fiction to promulgate values of
tolerance and cultural understanding (Pinsent, Children’s Literature 5).
Reading fiction was esteemed throughout the century, especially as it was
regarded as a personally improving activity. Writing in 1926, just around the
time when Virginia Woolf’s first volume of Common Reader essays brought
her work for the periodicals and her vision for a spiritual modernism to a
wider audience, the American professor Frank Luther Mott articulated the
value of novels for ordinary readers in his Rewards of Reading. Thought-
ful men, according to Mott, benefited in practical fashion from the empa-
62 Empathy and the Novel
and literary critic Robert Scholes, the task at hand is to persuade his readers
(mainly those benighted, jaded professors) to teach literature in such a way
that readers make connections with their real lives and actions: “reading,
though it may be a kind of action, is not the whole action but a part of it,
remaining incomplete unless and until it is absorbed and transformed in the
thoughts and deeds of readers” (Protocols x). Scholes believes that “reading
can and should answer to social and ethical concerns” (x). Wayne Booth
puts faith in what he calls the coduction enacted by readers discussing their
appraisals of literary works. The comparative, communal evaluation of the
work, “a thoroughgoing particular engagement with this narrative, consid-
ered neither as based on nor leading to general rules but as an ever-growing
awareness of what is humanly possible” could make novel reading and even
literary criticism ethical activities (Company 76). Booth also believes that
novel reading can have moral consequences. He collects dozens of examples
of witnesses who testify to the power of fiction to change lives, from the
Austen reader who learned to stand up for herself by reading Mansfield
Park (1814), to the repentant racist brought to guilty consciousness by Toni
Morrison’s Song of Solomon (1977), to those who treated Jews, or female
academics, or Africans, or Southerners, differently because they’d taken to
heart a novel (Company 278–79). Booth candidly points out the inherent
untrustworthiness of such reports (though they are legion), and he does not
censor the regrettable effects of fiction—those Ayn Rand readers, swearing
off charitable giving!—but he believes, at least, that the reports of real read-
ers about the effects of novels on their lives deserve critical reflection.
As each literary period treated in this brief survey of the effects of
empathetic reading experiences has had its skeptics, let not the recent past
be represented only by those who see, or wish for, a defense of fiction in
terms of its virtuous actions. Writing in the 1980s, novelist Elizabeth Hard-
wick observed that the emphasis on resonance with readers’ experiences
might in fact narrow the reach of literature: “the personalization of fiction,
the reduction of it to the boundaries of the reading self, often one who
has lived for only a few decades in the twentieth century, is an intensive
democratization not quite so felicitous for the spread of literature as one
might have predicted” (“Reading” 15). This is not simply a version of the
antiegalitarian sentiments that often undermine the arguments of defend-
ers of literature, as in this extract from the late Victorian Andrew Lang:
“People who deserved to be able to read, did read, and now that every
one can read, few people deserve to do so, for few go beyond a newspa-
per. It is but a small minority who even aspire to study a novel. What is
the result? The result is that authors endeavour to reach that vast public
which, in no age and in no country, has cared for the pleasures of literature.
We hear it said of a book that it does not appeal to a man on an omnibus,
or to a man lunching in a public-house. That condemns a book, therefore
authors debase their wares, to captivate indolent women, and the man on
64 Empathy and the Novel
READERS’ EMPATHY
When large numbers of readers are consulted about their empathetic read-
ing experiences, a strong pattern emerges supporting the notion that char-
acter identification lies at the heart of readers’ empathy. These characters
need not be human:
The first novel that came to my mind was Black Beauty. Some might
see it as problematic to claim that one can feel empathy with an ani-
mal (real or fictional), but I think it is very possible to do so.4
As a child, my favourite book was Black Beauty, which I read six times.
I fear this means I identified with a horse, albeit a highly anthropomor-
phized horse who greatly resembled a powerless child.5
I also deeply identified with Jane Eyre, especially during her child-
hood. I also identified with the young David Copperfield, when my
mother read that book aloud to me when I was about twelve. In both
cases my strongest empathetic responses were aroused by the scenes
of abuse by cruel relatives and abusive school teachers, even though
70 Empathy and the Novel
All four readers emphasize the cruelty, injustice, and victimization of the
children in their reports, though only one directly identifies with the fic-
tional character’s experiences. These mature readers remember strong fel-
low feeling even as they acknowledge differences from characters’ situa-
tions. They testify that a reader does not have to be an orphan, a maltreated
victim, or a beaten animal to experience a strong empathetic response
through character identification. My second hypothesis can be drawn from
these readers’ observation: character identification often invites empathy, even
when the character and reader differ from each other in all sorts of practical
and obvious ways. Indeed, the opportunity to share feelings underwrites
character identification that transcends difference: I am not an orphan, but I
feel with Jane Eyre. This nearly ubiquitous readerly experience suggests that
the opposite hypothesis also deserves exploration: spontaneous empathy for a
fictional character’s feelings opens the way for character identification (even in
the face of strong differences, e.g.: the protagonist is a rabbit). This chicken-
and-egg pair of proposals has important implications for the way teachers
and narrative ethicists understand the consequences of reading fiction. If,
on the one hand, empathy precedes (and invites) character identification,
then empathy may be better understood as a faculty that readers bring to
their imaginative engagement with texts—a human default setting—rather
than as a quality gained from or cultivated by encounters with fiction. (The
Readers’ Empathy 71
tractive characters actually strengthens the case for the idea of minimal
requirements for identification: a name (or a pronoun), a situation, and an
implicit feeling might be all that is required to spark empathy. The character
need not be admirable. The characterization may indeed be quite sketchy.
The author need not like the character nor lavish representational attention
on the character’s state of mind to invoke a reader’s empathy.
By no means do authors completely control the range of available reac-
tions to their fictional people, nor should readers feel limited to identifying
with a central character (either a center of consciousness in a third-person
fiction or a self-narrator in first person). A participant in the VICTORIA-L
online discussion correctly observes:
Even when the narrative technique employed by the author says, “I’m
Pip—travel with me,” real readers may waywardly feel with Estella, or Miss
Havisham, or (as Peter Carey demonstrates) Magwitch. Indeed, a vigorous
subgenre of contemporary fiction takes a misunderstood, disreputable, or
demonized character from an earlier writer’s novel and recenters a revi-
sionist fiction upon the marginalized other.25 This imaginative procedure is
honored as a creative practice, but for a regular reader, identifying or feeling
with the “wrong” character may produce discomfort, shame, or self-censor-
ship. In the twenty-first century, our book talk often takes place in class-
rooms, libraries, auditoriums, and online chatrooms: spaces of the public
sphere that invite performance of our most admirable guises.
Under these circumstances, self-consciousness about being judged for
having a naïve, sentimental, or socially unacceptable reaction to a novel can
alter readers’ self reports about reading. One member of the VICTORIA-L
listserv discussion noticed this phenomenon:
I’m also interested that there were a few people on the list who felt
the need to “apologize” for having been moved by characters like Beth
in Little Women. Why apologize? Why cling to the remnants of the
New Critical hostility to sentimentality? Surely it’s that hostility—
I. A. Richards went so far as to compare sympathetic emotional reac-
tions to a disease—that has resulted in the degradation of so much of
Readers’ Empathy 77
This strong comment draws attention to the social aspect of novel talk: we
say who we are, and we reveal our training and taste, when we confess our
feelings about characters. David Bleich, an early advocate of reader-response
criticism, believes that “when tastes are publicly presented on the basis of
response statements, it is possible to distinguish between tastes based on
motives for compliance or for self-satisfaction” (Subjective Criticism 166).
Mary Lenard’s challenge to the listserv discussion members suggests that
our different kinds of taste and the social aspirations that shape them do
show and that we share them fully conscious that we will be judged by
others. Bleich offers what I regard as a utopian account of what will hap-
pen when real readers disclose their true likes and dislikes. He believes that
if motives of self-pleasing are “taken seriously in public, the principles of
public taste-formation are altered, since the element of compliance is sig-
nificantly reduced” (166). Lenard’s comment suggests that thirty years of
reader-oriented criticism has not brought about this change, at least not yet.
Bleich’s subjective paradigm puts a great deal of weight on “collective simi-
larity of response” to a symbolic object, which, he acknowledges, depends
upon “each individual’s announcement of his response and subsequent com-
munally motivated negotiative comparison” (98). Bleich concludes that the
“investigation of the nature of popularity in this way is likely to change what
is considered popular,” and this may turn out to be true, over time (166). In
the short term, public disclosure about our feelings for fictions still places
us into categories, generic, gendered, and marked by education and social
class. This phenomenon becomes all the more personal and revealing when
we admit sharing feelings with fictional characters.
Certain fictional characters even possess the power to resist professional
technical analysis, so strongly do readers identify with them. One teacher
reflects:
For sheer intensity of the readerly relationships she inspires, Jane Eyre
stands by herself, among my students. They are expert at explaining
her motivations, defending her faults, applauding her decisions, and
analyzing her romances. There’s something generously empathetic in
the work they do to protect Jane from the professor who wants to
talk about her as just an effect of a literary work. None of my stu-
dents, by the way, are British orphans facing a world in which edu-
cated women have precious few channels for making money or acting
independently.27
78 Empathy and the Novel
Individual readers do dissent from the critical consensus, and in this class-
room they clearly feel empowered to articulate their own positions. Often
discussion situations move toward a shared interpretation; sussing out the
implied author’s intentions is a common strategy for arriving at a reading
acceptable to a group. Those presented with a received interpretation may
resist professional literary analytical explanations for their feelings about a
character or an author. These readers may be encouraged to speak up, but
they may also fall silent in the face of an authoritative interpretation offered
by a teacher, a critic, or an articulate participant in a discussion. A caution
to researchers pursuing information about readers’ responses through their
self reports (the methodology of this chapter) would be: discussion of fiction
that takes place in public settings, while extremely valuable in itself, may not
be the most reliable source of evidence for emotional responses to fiction. The
effects of conscious or unconscious desires to please can even occur when
anonymity and privacy are guaranteed. As Nancy Eisenberg and her collab-
orators observe about research on gender difference in empathy, question-
naire and interview methods that allow subjects conscious control of their
performance appear to skew results toward cultural norms (see 7–8 above).
A challenge for future scholars of emotional response to literature will be
to develop, in collaboration with colleagues in psychology, methodologies
that can overcome the effects of social expectations on reports about read-
ing experiences. As reader’s empathy is valorized by our culture at large and
connected (whether justifiably or not) with social goods such as tolerance,
volunteerism, and altruism, the pressure to respond acceptably to a fictional
character may increase. In a worst-case scenario modeled by Blade Runner,
identifying and empathizing with a featured character could become a test,
in which readers who gravitate toward other textual features (or simply
dislike the novel!) reveal their moral failings or inhumanity. This sort of
adjudication of right empathy and wrong empathy should be avoided, if we
hope to learn how empathy for characters and other textual features works
in real readers.
Professionally trained readers are more likely than regular readers to
recount experiences of empathy with other aspects of fictional worlds: the
projected “implied author,” particular situations, settings, atmosphere, and
(much more rarely) the language or style of a novel. Authors (the real
people or the imaginary figures that readers construct out of the effects
of their works) command empathy as if they were characters, even when
colossal differences between text and creator exist. Ellen Moody describes
this well:
Where does empathy stray into narcissism? When does the mir-
ror cease to be a magic portal into another life, another dimension,
another view, and become merely a self-serving portrait of our own
desires and aspirations?31
It is possible for readers—even relatively discerning readers—to feel
empathy with characters in poorly written books. All that’s necessary
is that the characters go through experiences resembling (or symboli-
cally encapsulating) the reader’s own. . . . The literary characters with
whom we feel empathetic thus reveal more about our own psychol-
ogy and our own personal histories than they do about the author’s
conceptions or skills.32
Now one Dickens scene has been teasing me ever since I read the
question: the wonderfully rich and terrible scene in Little Dorrit in
which Mr. Dorrit, at the height of his fortune and social success, cracks
and goes into a delusion, before all his guests, that he’s back in the
82 Empathy and the Novel
I suppose everyone wants to believe that the books they love most
passionately are great works of literature. As adults, we don’t like to
think that we have been “taken in” by shoddy, perfunctory fictions for
no better reason than that we could relate to the characters/situations.
However, it may be helpful to remember that all literature “takes us
in.” Every author seeks to manipulate us with artificial inventions.
It’s not as though bad authors seek to deceive us into empathy while
good authors channel real life for us, unmediated and pure. Fiction is
a crafty business and most writers, whether they’re good or bad, will
use “every trick in the book.”44
Risk, produce the broadest kind of study of reading habits, but these ques-
tionnaires are necessarily retrospective and tell us nothing directly about
either the experience or effects of reading. Studying reading “online,” espe-
cially with long texts like novels, has proven a challenge. A small number
of experiments conducted in the 1970s measured skin conductance (read-
ers’ sweating) as works about racial others were perused.48 Computers have
enabled eye movements to be measured and reading speeds quantified. Vic-
tor Nell observed subjects in a laboratory setting as they immersed them-
selves in self-selected pleasure reading and combined his observations with
interviews of subjects. Though new brain imaging techniques (fMRI and
diffusion tensor imaging) hold out the promise of understanding the read-
ing brain better, such a research program has not been a priority among
neuroscientists.49 What little is known about the neural networks involved
in symbolic text processing has yet to be correlated with questions about
emotions evoked by reading.50 In particular, the question of whether read-
ers’ empathy resembles fMRI images of the empathetic brain (activated in
the anterior insula and anterior cingulate cortex, the lateral cerebellum, and
the brainstem) remains to be investigated. Because this body of work rarely
receives attention from post-secondary literature specialists, I review it in
some detail here.
To represent empirical approaches to literary reading, which typically
blend basic concepts from literary study with social-psychological methods
(including questionnaires and self-reports, delivered aloud or composed in
writing), I draw here on the work of several of its most respected practi-
tioners. These include David S. Miall and Don Kuiken of the University of
Alberta (in literature and psychology, respectively) and the Utrecht Uni-
versity scholar Jèmeljan Hakemulder, whose research into the effects of
reading treats both social perceptions and morality. I augment this group
with a report on the work of Tammy Bourg, a psychologist at California
State University at Sacramento, for Bourg focuses tightly on empathy. Miall,
Kuiken, and Hakemulder pursue broader research programs, each of which
addresses the role empathy plays in literary reading.51 In this section I review
their insights about empathy and point out some of the assumptions that
underlie each researcher’s questions and methodology.
A primary assumption, with implications for the study of fiction, holds
that reading literature differs from reading generally. I argue above that
readers’ empathy may have little to do with the quality of fiction as affirmed
by professionals, that is, on the distinction of serious from popular fiction
(including the often-dismissed categories of “junk reading,” “trash,” “airport
books,” and genre fiction such as romances). This does not eliminate kinds
of fiction from consideration, for testimony of readers suggests that generic
differences are likely to play a role in inviting (or retarding) empathic response.
Certain fictional genres should not be equated with higher literary status
if empathy is to be a factor in value. The scholars who study literary read-
86 Empathy and the Novel
ing often assume and sometimes describe this kind of distinction in level or
quality.52 To some extent their assumption mirrors commonsense under-
standings of literature as qualitatively different from texts in general. Few
would contest the observation that a modernist lyric poem makes special
demands on a reader, compared, say, to the ads on the back of a cereal
box. There are lots of different kinds of reading other than perusing literary
texts. Reading, for the fluent literate person, ranges from automatic com-
prehension of instructions and signs, to scanning for specific information, to
speedy consumption of narrative, to slower, more meditative engagement
with texts.
Two kinds of reading seem especially desirable to specialists: slow, care-
ful reading represents one ideal (once the halting pace of the beginner is
no longer necessary); and the trancelike absorption of the immersed reader
(when not being disparaged as an advanced form of idleness) often results
in a faster page-turning pace. These practices make possible literary reading.
However, as Leah Price has described beautifully in The Anthology and the
Rise of the Novel (2000), even literary reading involves a great deal of skip-
ping and skimming. In contrast, reading literature analytically, with an aim
of sharing or comparing insights with others or producing interpretations,
is a highly specialized activity that (for most people) requires training. This
education disrupts students’ habitual reading patterns with new demands—
attention to privileged details and patterns, to symbolic objects, to loose
ends, to contextually relevant information—depending on the approach.
The rarified form, academic reading, moves beyond appreciation to analysis
in its now quite various modes. Nonetheless, this last kind of reading, “read-
ing” as analytical interpreting, is what most literature specialists mean when
they use the word.
The scholars whose work I describe here focus on reading defined more
broadly than literary interpreting, but their location in universities, their
reliance on college students as research subjects, and to some extent their
research agendas conspire to preserve literary reading’s position in the hier-
archy of types of reading. The role of interpretation and the importance of
training students to interpret literature more acutely receive challenges in a
body of work that focuses more directly on reading, but the values of liter-
ary reading are very much embedded in this scholarship.53 Whether it stands
out from ordinary reading because it defies convention, employs defamiliar-
izing techniques, slows the reader’s pace, or flirts with open-endedness or
indeterminacy, “literature” seems to these researchers a legitimate category
of its own.54 If we were able to agree where the boundary between trash
and literary fiction lies (a line ignored by the National Endowment for the
Arts’ Reading at Risk), it might well be worthwhile to investigate readers’
emotional responses to see if the assumptions about the values of quality
literature indeed hold up under empirical scrutiny.
Readers’ Empathy 87
David S. Miall and Don Kuiken have an interest in discerning the effects
of literary reading through empirical studies, and to that end Miall in partic-
ular has sought to define the qualities of literariness.55 Indeed, most research-
ers in the field distinguish the effects of particular kinds of texts from oth-
ers (literary from nonliterary texts; narratives from descriptive prose) in an
effort to establish the consequences of reading culturally valued literature,
or to understand how that reading differs from reading in general. Since my
concern is empathy in particular, not literariness, I focus here on the role
of empathy as Miall and Kuiken’s work invokes it: a central feature of their
experiments and a key trait of literary experience in their accounts. Miall
writes that the two principal features responsible for the reader’s engage-
ment (through imagery and emotion) with a literary text “appear to be the
dehabituating power of literary forms, and empathic projection into the lives
of others through narrative” (“Necessity” 50). This pairing, which makes of
empathy a companion to defamiliarization (Miall’s “dehabituating power”),
brings formal traits into conversation with readers’ behavior. Supported by
experiments done in collaboration with Don Kuiken, Miall sees foreground-
ing as a means for slowing the reader’s pace, gaining his or her attention,
and allowing for empathy as well as other insights into texts to transpire. In
essence, following Miall, unusual or striking representations in the literary text
promote foregrounding and open the way to empathetic reading.
This thesis might imply that the more difficult and discontinuous texts
promote empathy more effectively than their simpler relatives. Miall and
Kuiken take care to avoid this assertion, and indeed investigation of the range
of responses evoked by works arranged on a scale of difficulty (particularly
longer works) remains to be done. Virtually all of the empirical research
on actual readers’ responses uses literary short stories, very brief excerpts
from novels, or lyric poetry. The application of findings from this research
to the experience of immersion novel reading makes a leap that may not
be substantiated by research in the future. Nonetheless, some findings may
suggest relevant questions to pose about novel reading. For instance, on the
question of difficulty’s relation to empathy, one might ask whether it ever
acts as a barrier to empathy? Is there a point at which alienation effects
impede empathetic response, as Brecht believed. Some research reveals that
a reader’s ability to understand cause and effect precedes role taking and
empathizing with characters.56 This suggests that relatively basic aspects of
narrative (coherent plot units and/or the relation between characterization
and characters’ actions) must be met for empathy to occur.
Psychologist Tammy Bourg proposes that comprehension of causal rela-
tions in literary stories assists cognitive empathy and that empathy with fic-
tional characters leads to greater comprehension. Her experimental results
from work with both adults and children confirm what others have also
observed in studies of children, that empathizers make better readers in
88 Empathy and the Novel
the first place than nonempathetic people. Not only does empathic ability
at eight to nine years predict reading achievement at ten to eleven years,57
but also sixth graders instructed in role-taking strategies better comprehend
literary short stories. This research suggests that readers’ innate or cultivated
capacity for empathy helps their reading succeed and that obstacles to com-
prehension may be overcome by employing empathetic strategies. Further,
individual dispositional differences among readers will affect which ones
achieve narrative empathy during particular reading experiences and which
ones do not. Some texts may be too strange to invite empathy in many read-
ers. Defamiliarization may, as Brecht intuited, throw up obstacles to empa-
thizing if it blocks or delays comprehension. The habitual role taker, or suc-
cessful empathic reader, may possess the means to overcome these obstacles,
but the techniques may not work: hence the reaction, “I just couldn’t get
into this story.” Thus empathy in this research looks less like a phenomenon
arising from readers’ response to texts and more like a disposition that may
be employed as a reading strategy. Tammy Bourg’s research supports David
S. Miall’s contention in “Beyond the Schema Given” that emotional respon-
siveness enables understanding, but it also suggests that overall, texts may
do more to get in the way of most readers’ innate empathic tendencies than
the other way around.
Human empathy, with its roots in primate behavior, developed long
before we began mediating emotions through inscribed symbols. Indeed,
as Paul Ekman observes, “Although there is no doubt that we can become
emotional by reading about a stranger, it is amazing that something that
came so late in the history of our species—written language—can generate
emotions.”58 Ekman hypothesizes that written language changes into sensa-
tions, pictures, sounds, smells, and even tastes in our brains, subsequently
to be “treated like any other event by the automatic-appraisal mechanisms
to arouse emotions” (Emotions Revealed 35).59 This is only one view of
many on the highly contentious subject of the literary emotions.60 It is
important to keep in mind as we review the research on readers’ emotional
responses to literature that the underlying brain processes accounting for
both empathic disposition and emotional responsiveness to fiction are still
little understood.
Writing is a fairly recent development in human history, but our propen-
sity for narrative and fiction may run nearly as deep as our use of language.
As I argue earlier, readers’ perception of a text’s fictionality plays a role in
subsequent empathetic response, by releasing readers from the obligations of self-
protection through skepticism and suspicion. David Miall has noticed a similar
effect. The fiction reader who suspends disbelief, Miall argues, encounters
devices that vouch for a novel’s fictionality and that are “capable of elicit-
ing the decentering response of empathic projection” (“Necessity” 54). As
a consequence of this fusion of fictional technique and reader response,
novels and short stories have a special role in theories about readers’ empa-
Readers’ Empathy 89
thy. Miall and Kuiken have developed the Literary Response Questionnaire
(LRQ) to discover the role of empathy, among seven features, in readers’
orientation toward narrative fictional texts.61 The questions rating empathy
of the reader all focus on character identification and indicate the reader’s
strength of projective identification:
Sometimes I feel like I’ve almost “become” a character I’ve read about
in fiction.
I sometimes have imaginary dialogues with people in fiction.
When I read fiction I often think about myself as one of the people
in the story.
I sometimes wonder whether I have really experienced something
or whether I have read about it in a book.
I actively try to project myself into the role of fictional characters,
almost as if I were preparing to act in a play.
Sometimes characters in novels almost become like real people in
my life.
After reading a novel or story that I enjoyed, I continue to won-
der about the characters almost as though they were real people.
(LRQ 56)
reading stories may also introduce biases into social perceptions (54, 143,
162), invite cruel (unjust) responses to those perceived as harming victims
(54), or teach incorrect beliefs about others (162), Hakemulder maintains
that readers’ empathy stimulates moral reflection and the adoption of a
“habitual empathic attitude towards fellow humans” (154). Hakemulder
keeps readers’ empathy at the center of his Moral Laboratory by exagger-
ating the conclusiveness of the link between human empathy and altruis-
tic behavior (93, 167). Even psychologist Martin Hoffman and others who
investigate the empathy-altruism thesis describe a variety of responses to
others’ feeling states that often fail to lead to prosocial action. Hoffman
does suggest in Empathy and Its Development that a particular subvariety
of empathy, empathic guilt, may be excited by readers’ exposure to fic-
tion, making actual responsiveness to real people in need more likely. Hoff-
man thus argues that novel reading may participate in the socialization and
moral internalization required for transmutation of empathic guilt into proso-
cial action. Hakemulder takes his inspiration not only from psychology, but
also from philosopher Martha Nussbaum’s endorsement of literary reading
(167). Hakemulder’s empirical approach checks his enthusiasm for Nuss-
baum’s project, however, and he quite rightly calls for an effort to falsify
theories of literature that promise positive outcomes (167). Scrutiny of the
available research on the specific narrative techniques associated by theo-
rists and actual readers with empathetic responses carries the project of
cautious evaluation of the causes and consequences of readers’ empathy a
step further.
Character Identification
To begin with the necessary clarification, character identification is not a
narrative technique (it occurs in the reader, not in the text), but a conse-
quence of reading that may be precipitated by the use of particular tech-
niques of characterization, as listed above.78 These qualities have not been
investigated in a comprehensive fashion. Marisa Bortolussi and Peter Dixon
emphasize aesthetic qualities of narrative that open the way to personal
involvement.79 In contrast, Jèmeljan Hakemulder suggests that readers
experiencing strong admiration of an author’s writing style may engage less
readily with the fictional world and its inhabitants (Moral Laboratory 73–
74). Readers’ personal involvement with a fictional character may (or may
not) be contingent upon the use of a particular technique or the presence
of certain representational elements that meet with their approval.80 Keith
Oatley believes that readers’ personal experiences of patterns of emotional
94 Empathy and the Novel
the use of present tense (over the usual past tense) really create effects of
immediacy and direct connection, as many contemporary authors believe?
The old “show, don’t tell” shibboleth of creative writing class remains to
be verified: direct description of a character’s emotional state or circum-
stances by a third-person narrator may produce empathy in readers just
as effectively as indirect implication of emotional states through actions
and context.92 David S. Miall has suggested that characters’ motives, rather
than their traits, account for the affective engagement and self-projection
of readers into characters,93 though it remains unclear when, and at which
cues, readers’ emotional self-involvement jump-starts the process of inter-
pretation. Bortolussi and Dixon believe that “transparency,” or the judgment
of characters’ behavior as sensible and practical, contributes to identification
(Psychonarratology 240). This may be too simple: even traditional novels are
complex, polyvocal, and various, and Wayne Booth offers this sensible cau-
tion: “What we call ‘involvement’ or ‘sympathy’ or ‘identification,’ is usually
made up of many reactions to author, narrators, observers, and other charac-
ters” (Rhetoric 158, my emphasis). Some way of accounting for the multi-
plicity of reactions making up a normal novel-reading experience needs to
be devised in order to study the transition from distributed characterization
in narrative fiction and readers’ everyday synthesis of their reactions into an
experience of character identification.94
This may require setting aside some common value judgments about
techniques. For instance, E. M. Forster’s famous distinction between flat and
round characters operates within virtually every fictional world populated
by more than one character. The typical critical preference for psychological
depth expressed by roundness, in those characters ‘capable of surprising in a
convincing way’ (Aspects 78), does not preclude empathetic response to flat
characters, minor characters, or (as we have seen in the earlier discussion)
stereotyped villains and antagonists. Drawing on the literature of cognitive
social psychology, Richard J. Gerrig has suggested that readers are likely to
make category-based judgments about fictional characters and to empha-
size attributed dispositions of characters over their actual behavior in situa-
tions.95 This theory suggests, as Forster intuited, that flat characters—easily
comprehended and recalled—may play a greater role in readers’ engage-
ment in novels than is usually understood. Fast and easy character identi-
fication suffers in theorists’ accounts of the reading process, which often
privilege more arduous self-extension and analogical reasoning.
Patrick Colm Hogan, for instance, regards categorical empathy (with
characters matching a reader’s group identity) as the more prevalent form,
while situational empathy, the more ethically desirable role taking, depends
upon a reader’s having a memory of a comparable experience, which is
never guaranteed.96 If situational empathy alone, as Hogan argues, leads
to the ethics of compassion, then quick-match categorical empathy looks
weaker and more vulnerable to bias through ethnocentrism or exclusion-
96 Empathy and the Novel
ary thinking. We do not know, however, that categorical empathy does not
lead to compassion, no more than we know the ethical results of situational
empathy for fictional characters. Neither hypothesis has yet been tested.
While literary critics and professionals value novels that unsettle convic-
tions and contest norms, readers’ reactions to familiar situations and for-
mulaic plot trajectories may underlie their genuinely empathetic reactions
to predictable plot events and to the stereotyped figures that enact them.97
The fullness and fashion by which speech, thoughts, and feelings of char-
acters reach the reader are very often supposed by narrative theorists to
enhance character identification, as I discuss below, but relatively external-
ized and brief statements about a character’s experiences and mental state
may be sufficient to invoke empathy in a reader. Novelists do not need to
be reminded of the rhetorical power of understatement, or indeed of the
peril of revealing too much. Indeed, sometimes the potential for character
identification and readers’ empathy decreases with sustained exposure to a
particular figure’s thoughts or voice.98
Narrative Situation
A commonplace of narrative theory suggests that an internal perspective
best promotes character identification and readers’ empathy. Achieved
through first-person self-narration, figural narration (in which the third-per-
son narrator stays covert and reports only on a single, focal center of con-
sciouness located in a main character), or authorial narration that moves
omnisciently inside many characters’ minds, an inside view should increase
the chance of character identification. Wayne Booth, for instance, writes, “If
an author wants intense sympathy for characters who do not have strong
virtues to recommend them, then the psychic vividness of prolonged inside
views will help him (Rhetoric 377–78, emphasis in original). Of course, the
technique also works for characters in which readers have a natural rooting
interest, and Booth’s detailed account of how Jane Austen uses the inside
view to promote sympathy for the flawed Emma is a classic of narrative the-
ory (245–56). Booth asserts, “By showing most of the story through Emma’s
eyes, the author insures that we will travel with Emma rather than stand
against her” (245). It is not an accident that Austen is one of the early mas-
ters of the technique of representation of characters’ consciousness, nar-
rated monologue, to allow smooth transitions between the narrator’s gener-
alizations about characters’ mental states and transcriptions of their inner
thoughts.99 Also called free indirect discourse, narrated monologue presents
the character’s mental discourse in the grammatical tense and person of the
narrator’s discourse.
Subsequent theorists have agreed that narrated monologue has a strong
effect on readers’ responses to characters. David Miall specifically men-
tions free indirect discourse as a means of providing “privileged informa-
Readers’ Empathy 97
tion about a character’s mind” likely to cue literariness and invite empathic
decentering (“Necessity” 54). Sylvia Adamson arrives independently at a
similar point, arguing that narrated monologue should be understood as
“empathetic narrative.”100 In Adamson’s language, the representational tech-
nique and its ostensible effects fuse. Quoted monologue (also called interior
monologue, the direct presentation of characters’ thoughts in the person
and tense of their speech) also has its champions, who regard the move into
first person as invariably more authentic and direct than the more medi-
ated or double-voiced narrated monologue. Psycho-narration, or the nar-
rator’s generalizations about the mental states or thoughts of a character,
has fewer advocates perhaps because it is associated with traditional narra-
tives such as epics. However, both Wayne Booth and Dorrit Cohn suggest
that psycho-narration can powerfully invoke character identification, and
Cohn points out that both poetic analogies and metaphors for feeling states
(as Virginia Woolf often employs) require the use of psycho-narration.101
Despite the frequent mention of narrated monologue as the most likely to
produce empathy,102 quoted monologue and psycho-narration also give a
reader access to the inner life of characters. Most theorists agree that purely
externalized narration tends not to invite readers’ empathy.103
In addition to these speculations about modes of representing inner life,
the person of the narration often seems likely to effect readers’ responses
to narrative fiction and its inhabitants. In particular, first-person fiction, in
which the narrator self-narrates his or her own experiences and perceptions,
is thought to invite an especially close relationship between reader and nar-
rative voice. For instance, Franz Stanzel (a major theorist of narrative situa-
tion) believes that the choice of internal representation of the thoughts and
feelings of a character in third-person fiction and the use of first-person self-
narration have a particularly strong effect on readers.104 Novelist and literary
theorist David Lodge speculates that historical and philosophical contexts
may explain the preference for first-person or figural third-person narrative
voice: “In a world where nothing is certain, in which transcendental belief
has been undermined by scientific materialism, and even the objectivity of
science is qualified by relativity and uncertainty, the single human voice,
telling its own story, can seem the only authentic way of rendering con-
sciousness” (Consciousness 87).
However, the existing experimental results for such an association of
technique and reaction are not robust. In several studies of Dutch teenagers,
W. van Peer and H. Pander Maat tested the notion that first-person narration
creates a “greater illusion of closeness . . . allowing the reader a greater and
better fusion with the world of the character.”105 It did not. They conclude
“it remains unclear why point of view has no more powerful and no more
overall effect on readers, given the effort devoted by authors in order to
create these devices that produce a point of view” (“Perspectivation” 152).
While noting that readers certainly express preferences about point of view
98 Empathy and the Novel
Generations of novel readers have believed that books open up to them the
perspectives of others who are markedly different, to their enrichment, and
this belief has been woven into the literary history of the novel.1 In a typical
recent example, Mark Edmundson writes, “The rise of the novel coincides
with a realization expressed, or perhaps created, by the development of
democracy. That realization is of the great span of individuals to be found
in the world, of the sheer proliferation of divergent beings” (Why Read?
69). The fiction reader, who in Edmundson’s formulation is likely to be a
citizen of a democratic state, develops virtuous understandings of otherness
and diversity. Certainly, a reader uninterested in people will be unlikely
to develop a habit of novel reading. Through fictional characters, we can
imaginatively inhabit the circumstances, dilemmas, and desires of person-
like figures, some of whom represent socially or temporally remote people.
We often respond to characters as if they were human beings like us, and we
have to learn the professional convention of treating them as “word masses”
rather than as people.2 Some, of course, like the characters of fantasy, don’t
even resemble humans, but that seems to prove no obstacle to our imagin-
ing and feeling for them.
The range of fictional characters (synthetic, thematic, and mimetic,
according to James Phelan) affords readers many different kinds of oppor-
tunity to stretch imaginatively.3 I argue in the preceding chapter that char-
acters need not be realistic, particularly lifelike, or even fully rounded to
invite engagement on the part of readers. Whether we feel with characters
in the emotional accord of empathy, identify with them through deliberate
role taking, or experience spontaneous character identification, we come
away from engrossed reading with the sense of knowing more about others,
and sometimes also about the alien cultures and times called up by fictional
worlds. I recall feeling that way in different decades of my reading career
about Arthur Golden’s The Memoirs of a Geisha (1997), Nevil Shute’s The
Pied Piper (1942), and Henry Treece’s Horned Helmet (1963), so I associate
the sensation with historical fiction, a hybrid of realism and romance. For
my mother, an avid reader, nineteenth-century Russian novels in translation
102 Empathy and the Novel
not the only alternatives, but the descendents of romance (fantasy, sci-
ence fiction, thrillers, horror, westerns, many mysteries and historical nov-
els, and of course women’s romances) vie with varieties of realism, and
with hybrid forms in which elements of romance and realism mix, for the
attention of readers.6
It is not beyond us to know that success in the marketplace more often
correlates with lowbrow status, that respectful reviews and small sales to
educated readers suggest highbrow status, and that widespread adoption by
book groups labels a novel as middlebrow. Even in a commercial context in
which a significant percentage of books bought are works of fiction, a very
tiny percentage of all the books published receive the official approbation
of a review in a magazine, journal, or paper.7 Gender inflects estimations
of cultural status, with male majorities among both book reviewers and
authors of books reviewed in the major weeklies and dailies.8 Sales figures
and library circulation data provide us with a rough sense of adult fiction
readers’ preferences: in Great Britain, general fiction is the most popular
category overall, with mystery and detective stories and light romances fol-
lowing, and historical fiction coming in a more distant fourth.9 These cat-
egories of borrowing accounted for about 93 percent of the total of fiction
checked out in the U.K. (according to statistics compiled in 1999). In order
of their significantly lesser popularity, war stories, science fiction, westerns,
horror fiction, humor, and short stories made up the remaining 7 percent
(Bestsellers 247). These statistics do not separate ambitious literary fiction
and canonical novels from “general fiction,” but very few books of these
kinds become bestsellers.
The exceptions to this general rule deserve attention. Film adaptations can
propel literary fiction, including classics, onto best-seller lists. For instance,
Michael Cunningham’s novel The Hours, which had won several prestigious
awards and had been enthusiastically reviewed when it came out in 1998,
sold 636,000 copies in 2003. A year earlier, the celebrated 2002 film version
of The Hours, starring Meryl Streep and Nicole Kidman, had collected half
a dozen Oscar nominations (Kidman won for best actress). Perhaps even
more impressively, the film version of Virginia Woolf’s life contained within
The Hours sent 425,000 buyers back to Woolf’s 1925 novel Mrs. Dalloway
(McEvoy and Maryles, “Paperback Bestsellers” 584). I speculate that many
book groups and college students read the two novels back-to-back in 2003,
but Amazon.com’s automated recommendation system, which pairs books
and offers a discount on joint purchases, may well have played a role in
boosting Woolf’s sales. The annual Booker Prize winner normally sells very
well, but not always well enough to reach the top 10 in the paperback best-
seller list.10 Other prizes, early notices in mass-market outlets such as Good
Morning America, and adoption by Book of the Month Club can give a novel
a chance to catch on: Alice Sebold’s The Lovely Bones (2002) and Sue Monk
104 Empathy and the Novel
Kidd’s The Secret Life of Bees (2002) went from modest first print runs to
million sellers in just a year.11 Exceptionally, Oprah Winfrey’s selection of
a novel for her Book Club can propel even a quite difficult literary novel
(such as Toni Morrison’s Beloved [1987] and Song of Solomon [1977]) right
to the top the best-seller lists. Winfrey’s imprimatur grants middlebrow
status to works that would otherwise seem either too difficult or beneath
notice.12 However, as Jonathan Franzen notoriously emphasized when he
wished to keep Oprah’s signature sticker off the cover of his novel The Cor-
rections (2001), becoming an Oprah book also brands a work as especially
suitable for female readers. For a DeLillo manqué, increased readership does
not necessarily compensate for the association with the topicality and emo-
tional invitation that Oprah books promise their empathetic readership.
No individual has more influenced the book purchasing and reading of
adult Americans in recent years than Oprah Winfrey.13 At a conservative
estimate, she was responsible for the purchase and reading of twenty-one
million copies of works of adult fiction in the United States, between 1996
and 2002. The figure soars when one adds library patrons and international
buyers to the tally. Now that Oprah’s Book Club has returned after a brief
hiatus, in a new form featuring backlisted books by dead authors, the evi-
dence of Winfrey’s power to shape Americans’ reading has become clearer
than ever. When she selected John Steinbeck’s 1952 novel East of Eden, it
immediately shot to the #1 spot on the best-seller list and sold 1.6 mil-
lion copies in 2003 (McEvoy and Maryles, “Paperback Bestsellers” 584). A
less dramatic but still impressive result occurred when Winfrey chose Alan
Paton’s Cry, the Beloved Country (1948), a novel that had sold a respect-
able 80,000 copies in 2002, no doubt as a result of its presence on school
and university syllabi. With Winfrey’s attention, Paton’s novel sold 617,000
copies in 2003 (584). Sales figures and television ratings combine to suggest
that around half a million adults, mostly women, read each of her selec-
tions. An astonishing thirteen million viewers tuned in to her book club
segments, and anecdotal evidence suggests that Winfrey influenced some
of these viewers to resume reading or to become novel readers for the first
time (Rooney, Reading with Oprah 126).
Given the dramatic drop in the number of novel readers, especially
among men, rational inquiry into the effects of reading ought not to be lim-
ited to the putative effects of serious literary fiction, a thin slice of the action
by any measure. Attention to the interests of the middlebrow reader, who
populates the book clubs and buys most of the fiction sold in the United
States and Great Britain, suggests that she seeks empathetic reading expe-
riences.14 I propose that novels inviting empathy do better in the market-
place (perhaps because they get better word-of-mouth recommendations)
and that empathetic reading habits make up a core element of middlebrow
readers’ self-image. This self-reinforcing pair of observations (empathy sells
Empathy in the Marketplace 105
books; empathetic readers seek books that will allow them to feel with char-
acters) complicates the attempt to discover what novel reading does to and
for readers. Narrative empathy may be less influential as an effect of reading
and more important as a sought-after experience—tantamount to a pre-
condition for success with a large segment of the book-buying and novel-
reading public. The opportunity to read empathetically certainly seems to
matter to tastemaker Oprah Winfrey.
Before turning to a case study of one of the last of the original Oprah
Book Club selections, Rohinton Mistry’s novel A Fine Balance (1995,
selected in 2002), this chapter examines a belief about fiction that is nor-
mally presented as a baseline assumption: Does novel reading really extend
the empathetic circle? The emphasis by readers, authors, and the novels
themselves on a common emotional heritage and the universality of human
feelings promises that novel reading can bridge social, cultural, economic,
and geographical gaps that might otherwise impede empathy. Though the
sharing of feeling with fictional characters may not translate into verifiable
prosocial action on behalf of suffering others, as some authors and psycholo-
gists hope,15 people validate their reading by honoring novels’ renovating
virtue, which is understood to operate through imaginative extension. The
potential of fiction to open readers’ hearts and minds to markedly different
others invites an understanding of storytelling as a moral technology. Does
it work?
resolution to the Cuban Missile Crisis, this kind of empathy exercised for
strategic purposes differs from the socially beneficial imaginative exten-
sion as a source of altered attitudes, upon which Hakemulder focuses in
The Moral Laboratory. Hakemulder’s own experiments suggest that read-
ing stories featuring positive depictions of members of “outgroups” leads to
a reduction of social distance. Like the empathy studies he discusses, how-
ever, his own work complicates literary response by engaging subjects in
role-taking tasks, which may in fact cause the reductions in social distance
he records (Moral Laboratory 98–100). Hakemulder’s study of the empa-
thetic effects of story reading, in which he employs standardized empathy
tests and omits role-taking exercises, produced no evidence of a correla-
tion, though it did suggest that stories can introduce biases into social per-
ceptions (143). Empathy with persecuted victims can increase hatred of
their tormenters, which may then be extended wholesale to a whole group,
including to innocent members.
A positive way of putting Hakemulder’s findings emphasizes the boost
that the incorporation of role-taking exercises into the teaching of fiction
gives (“Foregrounding” 195). Reading alone, or reading brief extracts or short
stories, may well be insufficient to extend the empathetic circle to include
members of outgroups. Hakemulder found that reading short (translated)
excerpts from Salman Rushdie’s novel The Satanic Verses (1988) (and para-
phrases that deleted Rushdie’s baroque language) failed to influence a group
of sociology students’ opinions about immigrants (“Foregrounding” 204).
Literature students showed different responses to the literary version (as
opposed to the manipulated summary), but their scores on scales measur-
ing perceptions of immigrants’ adaptation problems, experiences of intoler-
ance and low acceptance, and motivation by necessity were not altered by
reading Rushdie (206). An earlier study conducted by Canadian education
specialists John Kehoe and Charles Ungerleider found neither reduction
in dogmatism nor increase in empathy as a result of reading passages from
John Marlyn’s novel Under the Ribs of Death (1957), a book about the expe-
riences of Hungarian immigrants in Winnipeg (“Effects of Role Exchange”
48–52). Changing students’ empathic perceptiveness to include ethnically
diverse others, and reducing their discriminatory attitudes and intolerance
seem to require more than simple novel reading. These preliminary stud-
ies do not disprove the widely held belief that novel reading extends read-
ers’ sense of the humanity of members of outgroups, but they fail to lend
empirical support to the popular theory.
Other kinds of evidence may be brought to bear on the question, how-
ever. I have suggested above that the very fictionality of novels licenses our
feeling responsiveness because it frees us from responsibility to protect our-
selves through skepticism and suspicion. Fiction may evoke empathy in part
because it cannot make direct demands for action. We readers find ourselves
Empathy in the Marketplace 107
Oprah: Has anybody read a book like this before? I’ve never encoun-
tered pages that took me so far, and removed me from my own way
of life and way of thinking the way A Fine Balance did.28
world: “After September 11, I started taking more time for myself. I read [A
Fine Balance] and thought ‘This will do, in some ways, what September 11
has done. Take us out of our own little shell. Expose us to a whole other
world out there going on beyond our backyards.’ And it did exactly that”
(“Discussion”).
A Fine Balance provides an unremittingly grim depiction of life in an
unnamed Indian seaside city (recognizably Bombay) during the 1975–1977
State of Emergency. This disruption of democratic governance occurred
when Indira Gandhi, having been convicted of election fraud, ruled by dic-
tatorship, suspended civil liberties, and dealt with overpopulation by steril-
izing eleven million people, many of them by force. Most Americans do not
recall this traumatic period for India. As Winfrey comments on the show,
“That’s the year I graduated from college . . . we were all in our own little
worlds in 1975 . . .” (“Discussion”). A Fine Balance’s confronting of contem-
porary events that transpired during many of her viewers’ lifetimes, but
failed to make a lasting impression, assists in Winfrey’s goal of “breaking
us out of our comfort zones.” Winfrey’s treatment of the novel emphasizes
role taking with its sympathetic characters and the difficult search for an
adequate moral judgment about social evils affecting those characters. Her
show also elucidates the realities lying behind Mistry’s representation of
poverty, violence, and caste prejudice.
Mistry’s narrator provides an overarching perspective on the period of
the Emergency through focus on four major characters, the widow Dina,
the student Maneck, and the tailors Ishvar and Om. Within individual sec-
tions, the third-person narrative reflects a tighter focus on the perspective of
a particular character or pair, so the novel provides a variety of opportuni-
ties for character identification. Dina, who struggles against cultural expec-
tations for widows, and Maneck, who strives to justify his parents’ sacrifice
in sending him to school, make fairly accessible bridges for American read-
ers. However, the two untouchable tailors and their acquaintances on the
street push these readers to extend the empathetic circle to suffering oth-
ers who would normally seem remote and incomprehensible. Mistry insists
on linking the four lives he narrates, and he uses the emblem of a quilt to
make their connection vivid. Dina creates this frugal artwork out of scraps,
recording the friends’ good times and bad, and defying the barriers of caste
that would normally separate them. She intends it to give it as a wedding
present to Om. Unfortunately, when Ishvar and Om get rounded up in a
sweep of the slums, Om is not given a simple vasectomy in the sterilization
camp. Instead, he suffers castration. Ishvar, who has only been sterilized,
gets infected and loses his legs. Mistry’s last mention of the hopeful emblem
of the quilt occurs when it can be glimpsed cushioning the legless beggar
on his wheeled cart.
In A Fine Balance, Mistry’s claustrophobic determinism leaves its lov-
ingly depicted central characters Ishvar and Om no escape routes. Mistry
112 Empathy and the Novel
relates their attempt to improve their lot from leatherworking, the task
of the untouchable caste to which they are born. Ishvar and Om succeed
for a while, but true to the naturalist logic that governs Mistry’s story, they
get pounded down into degraded conditions and end the novel as maimed
beggars. We read on, horrified, as Mistry loads yet another tragedy, gleaned
from newspaper accounts of atrocities, abuses, corruption, and crime, onto
Ishvar and Om’s frail shoulders. This runs a risk of compromising the novel’s
realism, as a contributer to a SASIALIST listserv discussion complains: “The
novel telescopes dozens of experiences suffered by many from the disad-
vantaged groups into the lives of two people, and by making it all happen to
the two, it transforms the tale into melodrama. It made the suffering appear
so commonplace as to be dismal.”32 Another contributor to the SASIALIST
discussion laments that the powerful representation of suffering emphasizes
how little has changed in over two decades: “What bothers me is that these
things happened, and unfortunately still happen. . . . Nothing has changed,
no lesson has been learnt due to the ‘emergency.’ That is what I find to
be extremely disturbing, because it nullifies any hope I would have other-
wise had.”33 These readers, knowledgeable about India and familiar with its
modern history, respond to the novel’s ambitious representation of injustice
with ambivalence. Both complaints, that hope suffers nullification and that
melodrama mutes the response to suffering, assume that successful repre-
sentation might do something positive with readers’ emotional responses,
but deny that A Fine Balance achieves that goal.
For Oprah viewers, the show anticipates a different kind of response:
simple disbelief. In film sequences of the slums of Bombay and in discus-
sions of the condition of India’s poorest citizens, the show insists upon the
verisimilitude of Mistry’s novel. Discussions with participants chosen for
their first-hand knowledge of India pass on to Winfrey’s viewers some of the
nitty-gritty details about caste prejudice, for instance, and forcible steriliza-
tion during the internal Emergency. The task that remains is to forge a mean-
ingful response to this unwelcome knowledge. The characters may have no
escape routes, but Winfrey emphasizes the moral value of struggling to feel
kinship with despised others. In a discussion with Mistry, Winfrey exclaims,
“It’s different, though, when you have to open your home, your porch, your
veranda, to someone who you didn’t even think was in your touching zone.
That’s a whole bigger thing.” Rohinton Mistry responds with a gloss of his
intentions, “It’s a big stretch, what you just mentioned. It’s a big stretch. And
many big stretches will reduce the amount of injustice in the world. There’s
no other way than making the big stretch” (Oprah and Rohinton, “Discus-
sion”). Winfrey’s presentation of A Fine Balance thus enables the viewer to
connect the dots between an emotional response through character identi-
fication and the goal of reducing injustice in the real world. Her represen-
tative readers, featured on the show in conversation with Winfrey and the
author, strive to make that connection, with varied results.
Empathy in the Marketplace 113
Among Winfrey’s featured readers, “Madhavi” has the closest ties to India
and struggles with the difficulty of assigning blame or finding solutions to
the problems Mistry describes: “This book was really hard for me. I felt like
everyone who struggled and tried in this book failed. And I had a hard time
understanding, because I can’t get through my day thinking that no mat-
ter what you do, it isn’t going to help in the end. . . . And the fact that no
one is responsible. There’s no clear villain!” (Madhavi, “Discussion”). Mad-
havi’s original letter to Winfrey emphasizes the difficulty of pinning down
right and wrong. The letter shows a strong sense of shared humanity but
honestly comments on the impulse to distance oneself from others’ suf-
fering: “Every page was emotionally exhausting. . . . This book opened my
eyes to how difficult it is to define wrong and right on an individual level.
It showed me the remarkable interconnectedness of everyone and every-
thing and the complex, multifaceted nature of human beings, particularly
where there is rampant poverty, with religious and social norms that allow
human suffering to be reasoned away. But maybe that’s what one needs to
be able to [do to] survive” (Madhavi, “Discussion”). Perhaps because Mad-
havi feels closer to the country and culture being described, the pressure to
understand root causes and address real suffering results in an impasse. The
empathetic response of this reader reaches the mature phase that Martin
Hoffman describes as an empathic sense of injustice, but it does not result
in a clear program for action. Ironically, the compelling representation of
injustice frustrates this reader’s wish to blame a villain.
For “Mohammed,” a second participant in Oprah’s show on A Fine Bal-
ance, the novel’s scene was familiar as a result of four periods of service in
the slums of Bombay. Having actually met and worked with real people like
the characters in the novel, Mohammed asserts confidently, “I know them
intimately. They are real. They are still there” (Mohammed, “Discussion”).
Mohammed also shies away from a prosocial response to the novel, perhaps
because he has already given of himself in earlier years, as his original let-
ter suggests. Mohammed’s particular experience of the realism of Mistry’s
representation leads him to insist, in that letter, on the universality of the
emotions experienced by the characters: “The book is deeply entrenched
in Indian themes, peppered with Indian slang and set in contemporary and
local political events indigenous to the Indian sub-continent. Yet the appeal
of the book is universal. Look at its worldwide sales. . . . Human emo-
tions, regardless of nationalities, are universal. Grief, joy, hope and despair
know no cultural boundaries. Herein lies Mistry’s skill. Though the events
may be foreign and some linguistic references incomprehensible, the reader
rarely stumbles, because the emotions that the characters elicit are intui-
tively recognizable, thus making the characters archetypal” (Mohammed,
“Discussion”). For Mohammed, the novel succeeds because it presents rec-
ognizable, verisimilar characters in situations that not only resonate with his
experience, but also reach out to a wider audience through feelings that any
114 Empathy and the Novel
Fog (1999), Sol T. Plaatje’s Mhudi (1930), Tolstoi’s Anna Karenina (1878),
and Lalita Tademy’s Cane River (2001). Winfrey encourages her audience to
employ empathy in their life-improving efforts, including in their reading.36
In turn, the Oprah audience constructs an ideal author with whom they can
empathize and seeks a way of understanding the challenge of reading pain-
ful fiction by empathizing with characters. That they do not inevitably reach
the desirable end point of prosocial action, engaging in altruistic helping or
working to end injustice, does not diminish the centrality of empathetic
feeling as an aspect of a fulfilling emotional life. Feeling with others, includ-
ing fictional others, can be an end in itself. It draws some of its power from
the analogous experience of compassion, experienced in a religious context,
for Oprah’s show owes a great deal to the forms and function of testimonial
religion.
Oprah Winfrey’s very influential guidance on how to read a novel contrib-
utes to the contemporary scene’s unprecedented cultural valuation of empa-
thy, which in turn participates in an optimistic understanding of the process
of social formation. This emphasis has become widespread in the cultural
commentary on books. The choices that readers make for themselves, and
perhaps even more importantly, for children, are felt to contribute to social
renovations that stem from empathy. We find this emphasis even in the
religious press, in which compassion, forgiveness, and loving one’s neighbor
might be considered the more traditional goals (Donnelly, “Studies Abroad”
22–24). One may ask whether this social formation through reading reaches
everyone. If novel reading does open readers up to the perspectives of mark-
edly different others, as many teachers believe, then women and girls may
disproportionately benefit from this exercise of their sympathetic imagina-
tions. Though Oprah Winfrey does not exclude men from the beneficial
effects of empathetic reading, her audience is mainly female. This matches
up to the well-documented observation that women do most of the novel
reading today.
Does women’s novel reading then exaggerate the culturally sanctioned
gender roles of “feeling women” and “thinking men”? If so, then the efforts of
individuals such as Oprah Winfrey exercise considerable cultural influence
by bringing particular texts to the attention of a broad potential readership
and reminding that readership how to use the novel-reading experience.
Winfrey acts as a teacher in her Book Club segments, encouraging role tak-
ing, judgment making, and application of life lessons from novels to the real
lives of her viewers. Whether novels on their own can actually extend read-
ers’ empathetic imagination and make prosocial action more likely remains
uncertain, but Winfrey’s advocacy for the force of fiction creates the cir-
cumstances that have been shown to increase empathetic understanding of
others. By dignifying empathetic response to fiction, Winfrey may increase
the role-taking efforts of her considerable readership, and that may change
attitudes, if not actions.
Empathy in the Marketplace 117
When a reader commits herself to an Oprah book, she joins a vast audience.
If she heeds Winfrey’s recommendations on how to read, she may feel that
the novel presses her to respond in the real world. In the case of Rohinton
Mistry’s A Fine Balance, the emotions invoked may impel a reader to feel-
ings of helplessness in the face of insuperable injustices, as we have seen
above. More positively, it may provoke self-evaluation that leads to action in
a purely personal realm. It may provide an opportunity for cathartic healing
and expanded understanding. However, social psychology suggests another
possibility. Becoming a reader of a bestseller means joining a crowd, though
not the kind of throng that surrounds a person physically. The best recent
example of this phenomenon occurs when J. K. Rowling issues one of her
Harry Potter books: readers all over the world simultaneously obtain and
then read the novel together, conscious that millions of others are doing
the same thing. Harry Potter books, engrossing and excellent as they are,
make few direct demands on readers’ behavior.37 When Winfrey chooses a
novel that centrally addresses questions of injustice, she opens the way for
socially committed responses. However, joining the crowd of readers of A
Fine Balance may also activate the psychological response known as diffusion
of responsibility: the assumption on the part of individuals, that because they
are part of a crowd, that they need not take responsibility for acting. By this
logic, if everyone else—hundreds of thousands of other readers, and millions
of other viewers—becomes aware of caste prejudice, oppression of the poor,
and the cruel treatment of widows in India, then surely someone else must
already be doing something.
Researchers on altruism in the real world have already demonstrated the
rarity of a truly risk-taking altruistic response to others’ needs (see 22–23
above). Latane and Darley’s classic research on “diffusion of responsibil-
ity,” or bystander apathy, suggests that in some circumstances, being part
of a crowd reduces the speed of response to another in need, and in some
cases thwarts responding at all.38 A bestseller that galvanized a large group
into taking action would confute this observation. To the degree that liter-
ary history ever notices bestsellers, it honors a scant few novels with hav-
ing made a significant impact on public opinion and subsequent legislation.
The locus classicus for a bestseller “changing the world” would be the out-
cry against food impurity in the wake of Upton Sinclair’s novel The Jun-
gle (1906). Though Sinclair hoped to sway his readers’ political views, his
graphic descriptions of the meatpacking industry had the unintended effect
of spurring lawmakers to regulate the purity of food. His readers, after all,
were also eaters. Nowadays, investigative journalists and documentary film-
makers aspire to reach a wide public in order to effect change, but very few
novelists attempt to use their medium to sway the opinions of a mass read-
ership. (I treat Alice Walker, a provocative exception to this generalization,
118 Empathy and the Novel
in the following chapter.) After all, very few fiction bestsellers can live up
to the oft-cited exemplars, The Jungle, Uncle Tom’s Cabin, and Oliver Twist.
The number of bestsellers that have distinguished themselves simply by
selling extremely well suggests that most readers do not look to their fiction
reading to suggest programs for action in the real world.
When a novel does make explicit demands on its readers, as I believe
Rohinton Mistry’s A Fine Balance does, the responses of those readers do
not necessarily oblige the author by channeling into the fight against injus-
tice. At the end of January 2005, 411 readers had spontaneously shared
their responses to A Fine Balance through Amazon.com’s Web site. Accom-
panied by a rating in numbers of stars, readers wrote in their reasons for
recommending (or much more rarely, not recommending) the novel to
other readers. All of the responses are in English (like the novel), but the
readers write from all over the world. A significant proportion comes from
American readers. Approximately one third of the responses provide a
simple recommendation. The remaining two thirds are more expansive,
elaborating on their reactions to the novel. Forty-six percent of all respon-
dents emphasize the emotional experience of reading the novel, frequently
describing empathetic responses and even tears. Twenty-eight write about
their improved comprehension of the historical circumstances of Mistry’s
characters; in other words, they testify to an intellectual expansion of sym-
pathetic understanding. Ten percent come to moralized conclusions about
the message of the novel (as when one reader condemns moral relativism
and urges Christian faith on other Amazon users).39 Two reviewers, both
writing after 11 September 2001, feel inspired by Mistry’s depiction of the
suspension of civil rights during the Emergency to comment on the fragil-
ity of the rights that American citizens enjoy. Many come to the conclusion
that privileged readers ought to “count their blessings,” the most common
of the moralizing responses. Not a single soul reports doing something spe-
cific in the real world as a result of reading the book, other than recom-
mending the novel to others, reading more about India, or seeking out
other works by Rohinton Mistry.
Just because more than four hundred readers omit mention of the spe-
cific prosocial actions they have taken as a result of reading an extremely
moving, absorbing, and eye-opening novel does not prove that A Fine Bal-
ance fails to inspire altruism. Modesty may be a factor. Readers of Mistry’s
novel may be more likely to give money to tsunami victims. They may be
more likely to extend a hand to someone outside their “touching zone,” as
Winfrey puts it. They may react with compassion rather than indifference
to the next indigent person who asks them for spare change on the street.
They may indeed already be the kind of people who routinely do all these
things, in which case their affinities may predispose them to the novel’s invi-
tation to feel and even act. We must confront the possibility, however, that
an experience with a book leads most readily to other bookish activities,
Empathy in the Marketplace 119
AUTHORS’ EMPATHY
We laymen have always been intensely curious to know . . . from what sources that
strange being, the creative writer, draws his material, and how he manages to make
such an impression on us with it and to arouse in us emotions of which, perhaps, we
had not even thought ourselves capable.
—Sigmund Freud, “Creative Writers and Day-Dreaming” (1907)
not only for women readers. Sue Monk Kidd, author of the best-selling The
Secret Life of Bees (2002), writes, “While, as a writer, I want to affect the
reader’s mind—to educate and enlighten—what I wish for even more is to
jolt the reader’s heart. I want my words to open a portal through which the
reader may leave the self, migrate to some other human sky and return ‘dis-
posed’ to otherness” (“Common Heart” 9). For Kidd, the Emersonian quest
for the common heart motivates fiction that “creates empathy” in even the
most resistant (male) readers (9). She cites with pride an encounter in a
bookstore with a well-dressed forty-nine-year-old business executive. A
reluctant reader of The Secret Life of Bees, he told Kidd that he now feels
“disposed to the South, to black women and to white girls who need their
mothers” (9). For Kidd, this encounter epitomizes the value of “seeing the
world through someone else’s eyes, feeling it with someone else’s heart” (9).
For novelist Jane Smiley, the loss of male readers by the sidelining of the
novel to “the seraglio” threatens to brutalize and coarsen our society (13
Ways 177). She writes, “When we talk about the death of the novel, what
we are really talking about is the possibility that empathy, however mini-
mal, would no longer be attainable by those for whom the novel has died”
(176). Men in particular lose access to the “inner lives of their friends and
family members” if the novel dies for them (176–77). For Smiley, the loss
of empathetic reading experiences threatens apocalypse: “In a world where
weapons of mass destruction are permanent features of the landscape, I can-
not help believing that a lively sense of the reality of other consciousnesses
on the part of those whose fingers are on the trigger is essential to human
survival” (176).4
Male novelists also participate in the celebration of narrative empa-
thy. David Lodge, a prolific novelist as well as a respected literary theorist,
writes, “One might suggest that the ability novelists have to create charac-
ters, characters often very different from themselves, and to give a plausible
account of their consciousnesses, is a special application of Theory of Mind.
It is one that helps us develop powers of sympathy and empathy in real
life” (Consciousness 42). Like many novelists, Lodge equates the value of
advanced role-taking imagining on the part of writers with the end result
garnered by readers: authors’ use of their imagination to create fictional
beings with persuasive inner lives somehow helps “us”—readers operating
in “real life”—develop sympathy and empathy. By now it should be clear
that the empirical evidence for causal links between fiction reading and
the development of empathy in readers does not yet exist, though inge-
nious studies are underway to shore up the case that novel reading assists in
moral development by training readers in empathy. Lodge’s statement can
be chalked up alongside Smiley’s jeremiad and Kidd’s hopes for the com-
mon heart as evidence of a still unsubstantiated but prevalent belief in a link
between fiction reading and the cultivation of the empathetic imagination.
Authors’ Empathy 125
the world of art, constructing from their persons, their passions, and their
adventures a novel, a drama, or at least a story” (preface). Though his status
as an innovative dramatist whose work anticipates aspects of theater of the
absurd may impede such a reading, Taylor’s research emboldens us to take
Pirandello’s report at face value. He may indeed have been reporting an
imaginative experience as much as a frame-breaking invention.
Literary history records many such remarks of authors regarding the ori-
gins and fates of their fictional characters. Long before her Alzheimer’s dis-
ease set in, Iris Murdoch was well known for referring to the continued
post-novel existences of her creations and would sometimes inform her visi-
tors or correspondents about what the characters had been up to recently.
Because Pirandello and Murdoch are reputable writers, their self-reports of
what might otherwise seem to be delusions or hallucinations are taken as
perfectly normal. Indeed, the experience of “having a character in your head
who won’t go away” is widely regarded as a common reason for writing fic-
tion in the first place.6 Not only famous writers feel this way, although suc-
cess as a fiction writer may be in part dependent on experiencing inspiration
by way of characters who appear in the mind’s eye, demanding attention.
That they “go on existing” after the author finishes the books helps explain
the drive to write sequels, as well as Murdoch’s counterfactual assertions.
In a remarkable study of fifty fiction writers, Taylor and her collaborators
discovered not only that 92 percent of the authors reported some experi-
ence of the illusion of independent agency, but also that the more suc-
cessful writers (those who had published their fiction) had more frequent
and more intense experiences of it. Taylor and her group hypothesize that
the illusion of independent agency could be related to writers’ expertise in
fantasy production (“Illusion” 361, 376–77), suggesting that it occurs more
easily and spontaneously with practice, or that writers naturally endowed
with creative gifts may experience it more readily. Writers report looking at
and eavesdropping on their characters, engaging in conversations with them,
struggling with them over their actions, bargaining with them, and feeling
for them. Taylor writes, “The essence of this conceptual illusion is the sense
that the characters are independent agents not directly under the author’s
control” (366). Though clearly novelists still do exercise their authority by
choosing the words that end up on the page, they may experience the cre-
ative process as akin to involuntarily empathizing with a person out there,
separate from themselves. Several tests administered by Taylor to her sub-
jects support this connection.
Taylor found that the writers as a group scored higher than the norm (in
the general population) in empathy (“Illusion” 361). Using Davis’s Inter-
personal Reactivity Index (IRI), a frequently used empathy scale, Taylor
and her colleagues measured her subjects’ tendency to fantasize, to feel
empathic concern for others, to experience personal distress in the face of
others’ suffering, and to engage in perspective taking (369–70). Both men
Authors’ Empathy 127
and women in her sample of fiction writers scored significantly higher than
Davis’s reported norms for the general population, with females scoring
higher in all four areas than males. Writers of both genders stood out on all
four subscales of Davis’s IRI, but they were “particularly off the charts” for
fantasy and perspective taking. Taylor speculates that “these two subscales
tap the components of empathy that seem most conceptually related to IIA
[the Illusion of Independent Agency] and might be seen as ‘grown-up’ ver-
sions of variables associated with children who have imaginary companions
(pretend play and theory of mind skills)” (377). The work of Taylor and
her group leads to the first hypothesis about narrative empathy from the
authors’ side: novelists as a group may be more empathetic than the general
population. A second hypothesis must follow immediately, acknowledging
the difficulty of pinning down the difference between innate dispositions
and results of practice and habitual use in groups of people: the activity of
fiction writing may cultivate novelists’ role-taking skills and make them more
habitually empathetic.
These proposals do not imply that the actual behavior of novelists is any
better than the population at large. Even the most ardent advocates of nar-
rative ethics hesitate to argue that being a novelist correlates with being a
better person. Literary biographies provide too many counterexamples to
risk going down that path. Novelists known to be nice people may exer-
cise their empathy on behalf of nonexistent beings and indeed on behalf of
nasty characters. Furthermore, nasty people may become novelists! Noth-
ing prevents a novelist with appalling personal convictions from employing
his creative empathy to render, for instance, the plight of white suprema-
cists in a fashion designed to stir the feelings of those who fear having their
guns taken away. This is precisely what William Pierce, founder of the white
supremacist organization The National Alliance, did when he published a
novel under the pseudonym Andrew MacDonald. The Turner Diaries (1978)
is credited by the FBI and the Anti-Defamation League for having stirred up
race hatred and anti-Semitic activities in the United States.7 Most notably,
Timothy McVeigh, the bomber of the Federal Building in Oklahoma City
(in 1995), had apparently made a careful study of The Turner Diaries and
emulated its protagonist by building a fertilizer bomb to explode a govern-
ment building. The novel provides a careful account of how such a bomb
might be made and deployed in a small truck.
Pierce’s hateful representations of blacks, Jews, homosexuals, and so-
called mud people, all of whom face extermination in his paranoid near-
future world, have all but obscured his representational success in cre-
ating a long-suffering white revolutionary character, to whom a certain
kind of reader (in all likelihood much more passive than McVeigh) clearly
responds.8 These readers report being thrilled by the novel, even when
they disagree with some of the attitudes it expresses. As F. R. Conway, an
Amazon reviewer observes, “The target audience for this book is a person,
128 Empathy and the Novel
usually young, who’s already on the edge. . . . Take a kid that’s already angry
at the world, at the government, show him this book with these things
that already tick him off, highly exaggerated and he’ll feel a connection
with it. Then the story is an engaging and empowering one with a fright-
ening message.”9 Though William Pierce (who died in 2002) was not a
violent criminal like Timothy McVeigh, he indulged his genocidal revenge
fantasies in a future-world thriller that clearly has the capacity to stir the
feelings of some readers. The notion that empathy could not be involved in
such an act of creation should be treated with skepticism, for empathy and
ethnocentrism have often been fellow travelers. This unpleasant example
prompts the observation that authors’ empathy can be devoted to socially
undesirable ends. Even then, it takes a McVeigh to transform a novel into
an action plan for terrorism. Most readers recognize the novel, whether or
not it appeals to them, as fiction and therefore see it as exempt from attri-
butions of cause-and-effect agency. It may be especially an author’s fantasy
to believe that readers will be prone to implement the programs embedded
within fiction.
Intriguingly, in the same research project described above, Taylor and
her collaborators also discovered that fiction writers as a group showed
higher scores of dissociation than the norms for the general population.
Dissociation, in psychological terms, means an abnormal separation of men-
tal processes from conscious awareness and can be involved in an array of
disorders, including amnesia, memory loss, and schizophrenia. In its least
pathological forms, dissociation takes place during intense daydreaming,
especially the kind during which the absorbed subject loses track of time
and bodily awareness. Taylor and her team used a standard questionnaire,10
as in the empathy component of her study, and discovered that the fiction
writers scored significantly higher than the average, due especially to high
scores on daydreaming and absorption. Taylor comments that the writers’
scores are closer to the average Dissociative Experiences Scale (DES) score
for a sample of schizophrenics (“Illusion” 373–74) but hastens to reassure
readers that scoring in this range does not constitute a diagnosis of a disso-
ciative disorder. Indeed, she and her colleagues conclude that “the profile of
our writers . . . is that of a group of people who readily adopt other people’s
perspectives, and who revel in the imaginative worlds of fictional characters,
fantasy, and daydreams” (377). Fantasies and daydreams, delightful though
they may be, however, do not inevitably contribute to the social good, and
they may sometimes allow a person to indulge in imagined actions that
would be judged criminal, immoral, or dangerous if carried out. This is part
of the attraction of fiction for many readers, even sophisticated ones, and
should not be dismissed from a broader consideration of narrative ethics.
The comments of authors about their craft of character creation affirm
the connections discovered by Taylor and in the process highlight more
problems with authors’ empathy. First among these problems is the neces-
Authors’ Empathy 129
ing to do the thing properly that needed to happen for plot reasons. If
people have read the book, they will know Harry had to find out how
that mirror worked. But when I re-read the chapter, it became very
clear to me that I had given Harry almost entirely my own feelings
about my mother’s death.13
of video games, which require advanced gaming skill even fully to preview,
are assumed to have a corrupting influence on the young people who play
them, but few literary fictions, no matter how transgressive, achieve the
spotlight of public reprobation.
Keri Hulme’s Booker Prize–wining novel the bone people (1983)14 makes
a useful case study of a work that violates taboos in its empathetic presen-
tation of a child abuser. The novel’s violence has attracted quite a lot of
comment, not all of it disapproving,15 for out of the breakdown of her three
central characters, Hulme forges a new beginning and way of living, which
she labels commensalism (bone people 434). Hulme goes so far as to suggest
that the victim of child abuse, a mute European child (Simon), invites his
beatings from his adoptive alcoholic Maori father (Joe). Her representa-
tion goes far beyond contemporary understandings of codependency, imply-
ing that the child victim incites violence against himself in order to bring
peace, healing, and reconciliation to the wounded adults who harm and love
him. Her brief glimpses into Simon’s consciousness show him intention-
ally provoking fights, and her depiction of his behavior (he is a sneak thief
and disobedient to the point of self-endangerment) suggests how he drives
his caregiver to distraction, then to assault. Hulme naturally also plays up
Simon as a sympathetic character, gradually revealing the layers in his his-
tory of abuse, from the funny marks he has on him already, as a half-drowned
toddler, when his foster parents take him in, to his near obliteration at Joe’s
hands late in the novel. Abandoned by his natural parents, drugged-out aris-
tocratic Eurotrash, Simon serves as a self-sacrificial catalyst of Maori healing
through reconstitution of (nonbiological) family.
As one might expect from this bald summary, the novel has received
some negative criticism, though it won both the Pegasus Prize (1984) and
the Booker Prize (1985). Responding to the fact that Keri Hulme is one
eighth Maori, C. K. Stead took her to task for speaking inauthentically about
Maori legends and practices and for receiving an award designated for Maori
writers.16 This ham-handed appraisal of the novelist’s identity and authority
has all but obscured the rest of Stead’s critique. In the same article, Stead
identifies the novel’s “bitter aftertaste, something black and negative deeply
ingrained in its imaginative fabric” (“Pegasus” 107) with the bone people’s
representation of “extreme violence against a child” (108). The failure of the
novelist adequately to punish the child abuser (he does serve a brief prison
term after nearly killing Simon) provokes some readers: Stephen Fox of
Gallaudet University reports that “in classes or discussion groups the usual
reaction is horror and anger at the situation, the hope that Simon (the vic-
tim) will be allowed to escape his tormentor, and the expectation that Joe
will eventually be punished. When no such outcome occurs, readers can
become quite upset, as I know from having used this book in college lit-
erature classes” (“Beneficial” 46). Amazingly, very few professional critics
after Stead have explored the extent to which Hulme’s representation of
Authors’ Empathy 133
violence invites the reader to inhabit the position of the abusive adults.17
An exceptional view comes from Mark Williams, who notices that “we are
made to identify emotionally with the victim of an evil” (“Negative” 86),
but also to understand Simon’s abuser Joe sympathetically. Williams argues,
“At this point the novel’s relation to the social evil it dramatises comes dan-
gerously close to complicity” (108). I acknowledge that the scarcity of crit-
ics who agree with Stead and Williams suggests that empathizing with Joe
may well not be a common response, but the author’s evident empathy for
Joe certainly plays a role in scripting one of the most disturbing novel-read-
ing experiences that I can recall encountering in my adult life. I didn’t like
it, but I felt with Joe.
At the time of Simon’s most vicious beating at the hands of Joe, the child
has just broken all the plate glass shop windows in town. Just prior to this
act of destruction, Kerewin has hit him, after he attacks her. He has stolen
a precious knife from Kerewin and damaged her guitar. Arguably, being hit
by Kerewin sets off his window-breaking spree. In any case, she is still angry
when the authorities hand Simon over to Joe. Over the phone, Kerewin
communicates her disgust to Simon:
In effect, Kerewin gives Joe permission to beat Simon, as she later real-
izes (325).
In this excruciating brief scenes that follow, Hulme conveys in terse, lyri-
cal lines the consciousness of Simon as he receives a nearly fatal beating,
which he brings to an end by stabbing his assailant Joe with a shard of glass.
Among the most difficult pages of the entire novel, these passages con-
vey the anger and pain of a triple-bound situation. Hulme not only invites
empathy for the victim, Simon, but also brings her readers close to the infu-
riated adults in the triangle. While the character Kerewin ostensibly “has
every sympathy” for the long-suffering Joe, the author Hulme asks not just
for sympathy but for a more painful sharing in the emotions that drive Joe
to violence. She charts the escalation from exasperation to shame to money
anxiety (“you have ruined me”) to unleashed rage. As other critics have
observed, she describes Joe’s racial and socioeconomic position in such a
134 Empathy and the Novel
I’ve been fascinated by you two these past few months. You’ve got,
you had genuine love between you. You’ve given him a solid base of
love to grow from, for all the hardship you’ve put him through. You’ve
been mother and father and home to him. And probably tomorrow
they’ll read you a smug little homily, castigating you for ill-treatment
and neglect. And they’ll congratulate themselves quite publicly for
rescuing the poor urchin from this callous ogre, this nightmare of a
parent. . . . (bone people 325)
times they tell me things I didn’t actually want to hear. . . . Not infrequently,
I see my characters as much as I hear them; but I don’t hear words—the
trick for me is putting it into words” (59). Hulme recognizes the alarming
congruence of this writerly experience and mental illness in her description
of her worries about the illusion as a “private nightmare”:
What would you say if one of your characters came to the door? Would
you say “piss off, I killed you ages ago”?—because some of my charac-
ters seem to come from nowhere, and they are very real. I’m delighted
to hear that other writers think this too; you wonder if you’re making
it up or not. You get to live with them—once they inhabit you for a
long while, they become as real as anybody else. I once got jumped on
quite heavily by a person who belonged to a Schizophrenia Fellow-
ship, by saying that Schizophrenia is a writers’ disease. But actually,
quite seriously, it is. I have met writers who no longer maintain the
borders and are no longer sure of what’s real and what’s not. (65)
her character Monica at the hands of jealous wives in order to stage a com-
munal healing ritual of reintegration near the end of the novel. This healing
extends beyond the circle of women (a point to which some feminist critics
have objected, arguing that Adisa lets complicitous males off too easily).20
Adisa comments in an interview:
My first objective in this novel was to look at healing and try to under-
stand why there is so much pain among black people apart from the
issue of slavery. What I realized is that we have not healed from slavery
because we have not done any rituals. . . . In all cultures, not just Afri-
can cultures, whenever there is some kind of trauma there is a ritual
performed to bring back balance to the community.21
The aftermath for the perpetrators (expulsion, pain, and death) and the
positive turns in community life leave no room for doubt that Adisa aligns
herself with traumatized black people generally (and their healers). This
novel leaves no room for empathic inaccuracy.
My reading of empathic cues in Adisa’s fiction may appear to essentialize
female readers as especially capable of accurate response; this is a function
of my gender and the relative comfort of my female students in discussing
the novel. I assume that most male readers would also follow Adisa’s direc-
tions in reading the novel, though they might feel offended by or impli-
cated in the novel’s attack on patriarchal values. One must take care not to
reinscribe gender distinctions with respect to the capacities of imaginative
extension, just because the social circumstances of book discussion favor
the contributions of one gender over the other. Female and male readers
sometimes differ in their tastes, and this may have an impact on publicly
confessed empathetic responses. No work yet verifies, however, that adult
female readers are better readers than their male counterparts, though in
the United States, Europe, and the United Kingdom, women apparently
like reading fiction more than men do. Liking to read emotionally evocative
fiction does not guarantee that an individual reader responds accurately to
a novel’s invitation to feel. Female readers, myself included, can still be ter-
ribly mistaken in their empathy.
Empathic inaccuracy can be an effect of cultural background as well as
gender. Flora Nwapa’s Efuru provides an example of a novel almost certain
to create confusion through the empathic inaccuracy of Western readers.
Nwapa’s text presents the experience of genital cutting in preparation for
childbearing in a positive light.22 This “bath,” as Nwapa refers to the Female
Genital Cutting of her central character, does carry the risk of excessive
bleeding (Efuru 13), but the female elders emphasize the graver risks of
childlessness or child mortality associated with the failure to undergo the
ritual surgery. Nwapa does not deny the pain involved in the straight razor
Authors’ Empathy 139
operation (on the clitoris and sometimes the labia).23 The description of
the event invites the reader to join with Efuru to share the agony: “Efuru
screamed and screamed” and “Efuru’s husband was in his room. He felt all
the pain. It seemed as if he was the one being circumcised” (14). Thus far
any readers who recognize what the surgery involves may flinch in tan-
dem with the feelings of the fictional characters. However, the novel rapidly
moves to convey the benefits of undergoing “circumcision.” Efuru grows
plump and beautiful with the feasting and grooming that follows the pain-
ful genital cutting. She enjoys the admiration of those in her society. Efuru
goes out with the other circumcised women, dressed in the honorable outfit
of the mature females: “They were objects of attraction; men, women and
children stopped to watch and to admire them” (17). At this point in the
narrative, readers who have joined with the suffering Efuru several pages
earlier are not always ready to make the rapid transition to follow her into
the states of happiness and pride so clearly signaled by the text. Indeed,
they sometimes react with outrage at what they regard as an unjustifiable
or implausible turn of events in the emotion cues offered by the novel.
Some readers resort to ironic explanations, as indeed Efuru later enters the
despised state of childlessness against which the ritual is supposed to guard
a woman.
Nwapa herself does not make the point ironically, choosing instead to
celebrate Efuru’s dedication of herself to the childless goddess of the lake.24
Nwapa’s message in this novel and others concerns the value of economic
independence for all adult women (Nwapa and Umeh, “Poetics” 22–30). She
does not directly contest practices (such as female circumcision and polyg-
amy) that many Western readers would regard as interfering with women’s
rights in traditional societies. Understandably, students in the United States
find themselves empathizing inaccurately, for their own cultural context
condemns female genital cutting (FGC). Indeed, the United States has leg-
islated against the practice of FGC as child abuse or torture. It is illegal to
perform FGC on an American girl under the age of eighteen.25 The histo-
rian Sandra E. Greene, who teaches Nwapa’s Efuru, confirms my sense of
the difficulties emerging from students’ responses. Greene writes, “How are
we to understand a novel that so resolutely challenges a culture yet also
takes for granted certain practices—female circumcision, bridewealth, and
polygyny—that most of my students understand as degrading to women and
therefore anti-female?” (“Flora Nwapa’s” 220). Greene struggles to bring her
students to the point at which they may “contend with the fact that there is
no one legitimate perspective on these issues” (223).26 Experiences of nar-
rative empathy, accurate or inaccurate, may make such a relativist insight
more difficult to achieve, if it is indeed the goal of instruction. Empathy
often underwrites readers’ convictions about the universality of human
nature, as the case study of Oprah’s readers shows. A reader persuaded that
140 Empathy and the Novel
she has felt with a fictional character may defy the stated or implicit inten-
tions of an author, as we have seen in an earlier chapter. When the author’s
intention matches the reader’s feelings and the agreement resonates with
empathic accord, then the introduction of alternative perspectives on the
matter at hand may meet with disbelief or outrage. Empathic inaccuracy, to
craft a hypothesis out of this circumstance, may then contribute to a strong
sense that the author’s perspective is simply wrong.
Rather than attempting to eliminate empathic inaccuracy by arguing
with readers’ feeling responses, recognizing the conflict between author’s
empathy and reader’s empathy opens the way to an understanding of nar-
rative empathy as rhetorical: both authors’ empathy and readers’ empa-
thy have rhetorical uses, which may be more noticeable when they conflict
in instances of empathic inaccuracy. By using their powers of empathetic
projection, authors may attempt to persuade readers to feel with them
on politically charged subjects. Readers, in turn, may experience narrative
empathy in ways not anticipated or intended by authors, as we have seen
earlier. When those readers articulate their differences with a text’s and
author’s apparent claims, they may call upon their empathetic response as
a sort of witness to an alternative perspective. Arguments over empathic
differences between authors and readers, or among readers with different
emotional reactions to a shared text, give feeling responsiveness to fiction
a status it has not often been granted in academic analysis of literature.
Feeling responsiveness can impede or assist arguments about an issue that
transpire in the public sphere. The existence of an empathetic novel-read-
ing experience, whether accurate or not, can enter into debates without
even being identified as a response to fiction. These untraceable influences
upon readers’ passions cannot be documented, but every so often, a novel
leaves a mark.
Occasionally, a text so resonates with its readers and their knowledge of
the author’s intentions that it has the power to draw the world’s attention
to an issue or problem. Throughout this book I have emphasized the rela-
tive rarity of such occurrences. The impressive social and political impact of
Stowe’s Uncle Tom’s Cabin and Dickens’s Oliver Twist, for instance, should
be set against the sixty thousand or more works of fiction published in Brit-
ain alone in the Victorian period. Few would nominate the nineteenth-cen-
tury novel en masse for the honors heaped on the unusual representatives
by Stowe and Dickens. Documented examples of successful interventions
in the public sphere by novelists are cherished but scarce. In the few cases
that literary history documents, the novelist appears to succeed by evoking
empathy for suffering characters while delivering salient information to the
reading public. Personal celebrity on the part of the author may also be an
essential ingredient. This was certainly the case when Alice Walker turned
her attention to the practice of Female Genital Mutilation (FGM, the term
Walker uses for FGC).
Authors’ Empathy 141
By the time that Alice Walker published Possessing the Secret of Joy (1992),
she was already the world famous author of The Color Purple (1982). Linked
to that earlier text by a character in common (Tashi), Walker’s Possessing the
Secret of Joy makes a direct plea to readers, in an afterword, on behalf of the
millions of women and girls who have been subjected to genital mutilation.
Walker assists readers in informing themselves by providing bibliography
and announces that a portion of the profits of the novel will be “used to
educate women and girls, men and boys, about the hazardous effects of
genital mutilation, not simple on the health and happiness of individuals,
but on the whole society in which it is practiced, and the world” (Possess-
ing 283). Within a few years of publication, Walker’s stated intention of
publicizing FGM had been realized, though the practice of genital cutting
still persists. Walker used her novel to raise the Western world’s awareness.
Since the publication of Possessing the Secret of Joy, Amnesty International
has emphasized FGM as torture, the World Health Organization and UNI-
CEF have taken steps to eradicate FGM, and both state and federal laws in
the United States have been enacted banning the practice. Walker’s novel
has also been vigorously criticized for its very success when African activists
were ignored27 and for the elitist representation of an imaginary Africa,28
apparently in need of an external messiah,29 but its impact remains indis-
putable.
Preston N. Williams, a legal scholar, recalls how the novel raised his con-
sciousness of the issue: “A reading of Alice Walker’s Possessing the Secret of
Joy shortly after its publication persuaded me that the custom of female cir-
cumcision should no longer be considered the possession of any one people
or continent. Travel, migration, immigration, and a host of other interac-
tions among peoples, cultures, and traditions have made female circumci-
sion a matter of international concern” (“Personal” 491). Even her critics
concede that Walker has brought the world’s attention to the issue: “By vir-
tue of Alice Walker’s accomplishments as a powerful, well known feminist
writer—taken seriously by most people who read her writings across the
globe—her views on female ‘genital mutilation’ have come to constitute the
last word of the subject of female circumcision” (“Elitist” 464). Walker’s sen-
sational novel may persuade Western readers to take her version of genital
cutting as authoritative, and criticism of its inaccuracies and exaggerations
may never reach as broad an audience. This situation can be a frustrating one
for activists, who want the world’s attention and recognize that Walker has
brought them that but hope to inform the world without interference from
a fictional character. This case shows that concord in authors’ empathy and
readers’ empathy can be a motivating force to push beyond literary response to
prosocial action (if the potential for change exists). It also draws attention to
the irritation caused by empathic inaccuracy on the one hand (no, that’s not
how we feel about it at all!) and the imposition of Western values on other
cultures in the name of a universalizing feeling response on the other.
142 Empathy and the Novel
Strategic Empathizing
CONTESTING EMPATHY
Up until this point, I have been making the case that the evidence for a rela-
tionship between narrative empathy and the prosocial motivation of actual
readers does not support the grand claims often made on behalf of empathy.
Far from denying the centrality of empathy to an accurate description of
emotional responsiveness to fiction, however, I have described in detail the
factors that appear to evoke readers’ empathy. These may be dispositional,
contextual, keyed to knowledge or experience, or they may hinge on mat-
ters of literary taste. I have placed my exploration of potentially empathetic
narrative techniques in the contemporary context, in which narrative empa-
thy is typically highly valued; but women’s reading and subgenres associated
with female readerships are often devalued. I have suggested that if narra-
tive empathy is to be understood, all genres of fiction and all kinds of read-
ers should be taken into consideration. A theory of the prosocial value of
empathetic response to A Portrait of a Lady (1881) that cannot also account
for the consequences of far more numerous empathetic readings of The
Bridges of Madison County (1992) should be regarded with wariness.
It will not suffice, I have argued, to rely on the assertions of authors,
on introspection, or on personal conviction to prove that reading certain
canonical works of fiction inevitably yields the cultural and civic good of
altruism and engaged world citizenship. Indeed, I note that even advo-
cates of the empathy-altruism hypothesis, who see less fickle helping, less
aggression, more cooperation, and improved attitudes toward outgroups as
benefits of empathy-induced altruism, also document its liabilities, such as
harming the target of help, addressing some needs better than others, and
inducing empathy-avoidance. Most seriously of all, empathy-induced altru-
ism can lead to actions showing partiality rather than care for the common
good and can result in injustice and immorality (Batson, “Empathy-Induced
Altruism” 380). These studies concern real-world empathy; the evidence for
effects of literary empathy, I have argued, appears even weaker. By drawing
on empirical studies conducted by psychologists and experts in discourse
analysis, I have sought to mitigate the effects of exaggerating the proso-
cial value of narrative empathy. Unlike most of the critics discussed in the
146 Empathy and the Novel
ensuing pages, however, I do not quarrel with the intrinsic value of human
empathy, nor do I regard narrative empathy as a cheat or a fake. Readers’
empathy clearly exists and quite likely contributes to the success of emo-
tionally evocative fiction in the marketplace. Through strategic empathiz-
ing, authors’ empathy may join with readers’ empathy to raise awareness
of issues through resonant feeling responses. Especially when literary texts
explicitly recommend empathetic procedures, as the character Atticus Finch
does in Harper Lee’s To Kill a Mockingbird (1960), some readers respond
to the importance of being urged to climb inside another’s skin and walk
around a bit. Most empathetic fiction calls less didactically for emotional
engagement, and many novels stir the emotions of readers without having
an explicit message. These novels, too, result in feeling responses that by no
means always or even often lead to prosocial actions in the real world. When
a novel becomes a popular bestseller, I have suggested, the psychological
effect of diffusion of responsibility may deter readers from acting upon their
empathetic reading. The link between feeling with fictional characters and
acting on behalf of real people, I have argued, is extremely tenuous and has
yet to be substantiated either through empirical research into the effects of
reading or through analysis of demonstrable causal relationships between
novel reading as a cultural phenomenon and historical changes in societies
in which novel reading flourishes.
Though novel reading certainly involves role-taking imagination, for nov-
els to change attitudes about others and inspire prosocial action requires
more than just reading. Larry P. Nucci’s research, summarized in Educa-
tion in the Moral Domain (2001), reveals that the development of social
and moral understanding requires discussion (173). This conclusion echoes
the narrative ethics of Wayne Booth, who regards the active coduction that
follows reading as a valuable step in connecting novel reading with the for-
mation of readers’ characters. The affirmation and challenge to convictions
that can occur when readers discuss fiction, especially with the guidance of
a teacher who connects the dots between reactions to fiction and options
for action in the real world, can be considerable. The belief in the power of
a teacher to influence at least those of her students who arrive in a state of
readiness to the task of reading animates both the moralists who hope to
teach through literature1 and the cultural conservatives who fear that politi-
cally correct indoctrination occurs in the literature classroom. Indeed, argu-
ments about the contemporary canon often thinly disguise interventions on
one side or another of the culture wars. The reading list can embody a wish
to win the hearts and minds of readers to a favored cause. In the culture
wars, books, including novels, apparently possess extraordinary persuasive
and motivational power, but without passionate teachers (parents, librar-
ians, and other book lovers) even classics remain inert.
I suggest that when we set the rare narratives of autodidacts who report
conversions that came about through private reading into a broader context
Contesting Empathy 147
of all literary readers, the strongest testimony about the influence of books
arises from circumstances during which teaching or active discussion accom-
panies reading. Even the remarkable working-class readers—Welsh miners,
English weavers, and Scottish mechanics—who sought to educate them-
selves through books did so in social networks of mutual improvement.2
This does not mean that reading circles result in unanimous responses to
books: indeed, a group discussion may come closer to eliciting what Paul B.
Armstrong calls the disjunctive tension between readers’ experiences and
the assertions of a fictional world (Play and the Politics of Reading xi). We
respond to novels differently; novels do not subject us to uniform conclu-
sions. Armstrong sees reading as an exercise in “nonconsensual reciprocity,”
which may help model peaceful, rational, democratic interactions among
citizens. Larry P. Nucci argues that “effective educational use of . . . fictional
characters depends on the engagement of students in reflective activities”
such as writing, oral analysis, and especially discussion (Education 209).
Fostering the development of moral selves in readers requires more than
offering a reading list of novels and stories embodying specific character
traits or virtues (including empathetic responsiveness!). What empathetic
reading by itself may not accomplish, however, a teacher or guide may still
achieve, if one considers the link between novel reading and active steps on
behalf of real others desirable. Thus, while fiction reading alone may not
form citizens committed to justice, democracy, and nuanced understandings
of other cultures, pedagogical practices could respond to narrative empathy
as an opportunity to transform “ideological and cultural conflicts into mutu-
ally beneficial and enlightening exchanges,” as Armstrong puts his call for
reformed language arts instruction (177). Conscious cultivation of narra-
tive empathy by teachers and discussion leaders could at least point toward
the potential for novel reading to help citizens respond to real others with
greater openness and consciousness of their shared humanity.
Critics of empathy and, to a lesser extent, of empathetic reading quarrel
with that very goal. For these critics, empathy is amoral (Posner, “Against”
19), a weak form of appeal to humanity in the face of organized hatred,3 an
obstacle to agitation for racial justice (Delgado, Race War? 4–36), a waste of
sentiment and encouragement of withdrawal (Raymond Williams, Culture
and Society 109), and even a pornographic indulgence of sensation acquired
at the expense of suffering others (Wood, Slavery 36). To some feminist
and postcolonial critics, empathy loses credence the moment it appears to
depend on a notion of universal human emotions, a cost too great to bear
even if basic human rights depend upon it.4 Indeed, the suspicion of uni-
versalizing or essentializing concepts explains a great deal of the resistance
to empirical disciplines (such as psychology) in the humanities and in some
social sciences. “Empathy” becomes yet another example of the Western
imagination’s imposition of its own values on cultures and peoples that it
scarcely knows, but presumes to “feel with,” in a cultural imperialism of the
148 Empathy and the Novel
Hyperempathy
health of the slave (Sower 278). Olamina is exceptional not only because
she can hide her debility (it shows in the others sharers’ cringing behavior),
but also because she can push violent actions further than typical hyper-
empaths. They cannot even engage in self-defense, but Olamina can shoot.
We learn through Olamina’s unusual experiences that “sharing” feelings of
being shot and even dying does not destroy the hyperempath, though it
knocks her out. Olamina can kill those who attack her (142, 215), but she
consequently undergoes their agony. Her empathy has ironically made her
a more effective fighter, for she cannot afford merely to injure her oppo-
nent (256). She shoots (stabs, bludgeons) to kill. This ruthlessness on the
part of Butler’s protagonist makes her survival on the road plausible, but
it would be missing a major part of Butler’s defamiliarizing treatment of
empathy to link it too easily with survival. Olamina survives in spite of her
hyperempathetic feelings for suffering of others, some of whom she kills
with her own hands.
Mitigating Olamina’s violence (always in self-defense) is her persistent
community building. Having perceived the risks of being in a group locked
in behind walls, Olamina does not react by lighting out for the territory on
her own. She judges people well through the fine-tuned skills of the habit-
ual perspective taker, and she compensates for her lack of survival skills
by recruiting companions. Cultivating trust in order to achieve improved
safety through numbers, Olamina gathers a multiracial band of travelers
around her. Deliberate acts of altruism often result in members joining the
group.7 Carrying out altruistic rescues exposes Olamina to hyperempathic
agony, but the moral obligation to help victims and the pragmatic goal of
making the whole group safer override the perils of empathy. The survivors
become the core of the first Earthseed community, whose story Butler tells
in the sequel, Parable of the Talents. Though Butler does not explicitly link
Olamina’s empathy to her success in reforging social bonds, the account of
community arising in negative reaction to a state of anarchy is consistent
with a Humean view of empathy, and Butler has asserted that the novel is
“fundamentally about social power” (Potts, “We Keep Playing” 334).
While some critics of the novel have hastened to assure readers that But-
ler makes Olamina’s hyperempathy the source of her “deep sense of solidar-
ity with others” (Miller, “Octavia Butler’s Vision” 357), in fact, Butler con-
sistently represents it as an obstacle to relationships, an alienating personal
quality that is as likely to result in anger, hatred, distrust, resentment, and
despair, as more positive emotions. The personal distress-suffering hyper-
empath takes to heart the violence done to others, and she learns suspicion
as a first strategy for survival. That the practical ethics of the road lead to
the formation of a protective band emphasizes the dangers posed by others.
There is no solidarity with predatory humans, whom Butler represents as
ruthless individuals or members of barbaric gangs who can only imperil the
weak, the careless, and the isolated. In a public lecture given at MIT, Butler
150 Empathy and the Novel
Michael Ondaatje’s novel Anil’s Ghost (2000) presents in shards and frag-
ments aspects of a postcolonial problem: what (if anything) can a Western
observer of a hybrid transnational identity discover when a human rights
organization sends her into a place like Sri Lanka during its ongoing civil
war? Can she employ her academically authorized empiricism in the task
of truth seeking for the purposes of achieving justice, or is her very mission
a product of a Western fantasy of drop-in intervention, as characters in the
novel suggest? Do the feelings of the individuals involved matter at all?
Michael Ondaatje complicates his task by refusing to create in Anil a heroic
individual who might make an effectual response to crisis and in the pro-
cess buoy the spirits of readers who also look on, through her fictional eyes.
Structurally, Ondaatje’s novel resists the empathetic invitation to character
identification. Early reviewers decried its coolness and its apparently apoliti-
cal stance toward the Sri Lankan situation.11 I argue that Ondaatje rebuffs
readers who seek either an easy bridge character with whom to travel for
a voyeuristic thrill, or a thinly fictionalized work of investigative journal-
ism that can be harnessed for political use. These features participate in
Ondaatje’s skeptical interrogation of empathy and its uses.
Anil’s Ghost, though a recent novel, has already been subjected to search-
ing, intelligent critique by critics of Canadian and postcolonial literature,
but none have zeroed in on the specific criticism that Ondaatje’s novel
makes of empathy and universal human emotions, especially fear, in their
putative relations to justice.12 Some background on a complex text will be
helpful. Anil, the eponymous apparent protagonist, turns out to be one of a
Contesting Empathy 153
wobble into personal responsiveness Anil shows when she comes back to
her country of origin and confronts the corpse of a political murder victim
in a master-class with Sri Lankan medical students suggests that a return
to home turf may restore Anil’s emotions. Which emotions can be shared,
though, in a country that has endured so much grief and routine horror that
a crucifixion (of a truck driver onto a road using builders’ nails) can seem
relatively benign? (130). Indeed, as Sarath points out, Anil cannot help shar-
ing the pervasive fear that everyone else on the island lives with daily—she
whispers as if she can be overheard even when they have gone far from the
capitol (53). This might seem a hopeful development, except that fear so
often leads to paralysis, paranoia, disengagement, and broken trust. Anil her-
self falls victim to her own fear. She effectively betrays herself to the gov-
ernment because she cannot quell her suspicions of her collaborator Sarath.
He responds altruistically, in an act of selfless rescue of both Anil and the
skeletal remains that will provide evidence to pin one murder on the gov-
ernment that swiftly retaliates for his intervention by killing him. Prosocial
action proves a dead end for this good world citizen.
Ondaatje’s novel obliquely presents the concepts, empathy, altruism,
and justice, but shatters the relationships among them. Ondaatje also
arrays fragments of bone, rock, pencil erasers and clay in a celebration of
material objects and artisans’ skill that points toward putting back together.
The novel ends on an up note, with Ananda painting the animating eyes
on the reconstructed statue of a Buddha, but it qualifies aesthetic solutions
to the larger-scale traumas that it depicts. The penultimate scene depicts a
bomber’s assassination of the Sri Lankan president, and one feels that the
destruction and reconstruction could just as well be reversed. Though he
cannot present them simultaneously, Ondaatje’s juxtapositions enjoin the
reader who wishes to emphasize the last words, on human contact with the
artist as, “This sweet touch from the world” (Anil’s Ghost 307), to admit
the limited efficacy of an aesthetic response to carnage. Yet the crafting of
a novel out of the materials of recent Sri Lankan history inevitably replaces
the real irrevocable experiences of the silenced and disappeared with the
creations of fictional representation. The necessary exercise of authorial
empathy (which may accompany the most effective fictional world-mak-
ing) produces a dilemma in a novel that disavows easy connections and
solutions.
Guilty already of having escaped to the west, the author and his alter
ego Anil meditate on the limits of an empirical truth quest. Like her maker
Michael Ondaatje, Anil exits the country as a teenager. She returns in a pro-
fessional capacity as a forensic investigator, sponsored by a human rights
agency based in Geneva. Ondaatje’s return journeys took place for less
politically charged purposes than Anil’s, but he concedes that the project
of the novel still runs the risk of indulging in literary tourism, remarking in
an interview with Maya Jaggi that “it’s a real problem. I’m sure I’m as guilty
Contesting Empathy 155
as anyone. That’s why I didn’t want to make assured judgments about what
should be done—which is often incendiary and facile. . . . I was very careful
to try and avoid the easy solutions” (Writing across Worlds 253). The expa-
triate author indicts himself, as well as his character, when the archaeolo-
gist Sarath chides Anil: “You know, I’d believe your arguments more if you
lived here. . . . You can’t just slip in, make a discovery and leave’” (Anil’s
Ghost 44).
Anil has discovered a modern skeleton, a likely victim of a government-
sponsored murder, among historical remains gathered from an archaeologi-
cal site. The quest to put a name to the victim, to find his village, repre-
sents a larger project. One victim, one village—these stand in for hundreds
of unidentified others (176), according to the logic of Anil’s profession,
which is necessarily synecdochic. If you are to examine only one bone, her
teachers tell her, “the bone of choice would be the femur” (140, emphasis in
original). The soft tissues that hold memories and emotions elude forensic
investigation, so that inferences from the states of bones emphasize nar-
ratives of death. Anil is fortunate to have the entire skeleton, so she dates
“Sailor” and locates him geographically by means of the subtle marks on his
bones, made by larvae after his death, and by his posture at work while still
living. Indeed, by the end of the novel, Anil and her Sri Lankan collabo-
rator, the archaeologist Sarath, find witnesses to his abduction and learn
“Sailor’s” real name.
The discovery is anticlimactic, however. Sarath cautions Anil at the out-
set about the risks of such extrapolation, even when successful: “I want you
to understand the archaeological surround of a fact. Or you’ll be like one
of those journalists who file reports about flies and scabs while staying at
the Galle Face Hotel. That false empathy and blame” (Anil’s Ghost 44).
Ondaatje poses the question of whether narrative fiction, historically kin
to journalism, can make itself more like archaeology, providing the dispas-
sionate surround for the fact, rather than crafting a saleable tale for Western
consumption. Is the novel as an art form too much devoted to the evoca-
tion of feeling and the invitation to character identification to provide such
a rich and contextual understanding? Ondaatje’s formal choices underscore
his suspicion of illusory wholeness. The narration of Anil’s Ghost Ondaatje
breaks up and scatters in multiple centers of consciousness. Anil recedes
from view in whole swaths of the book, though the goal of reassembling
the picture, as in forensic bone gathering and art restoration work, still sug-
gests a grid that may be of use in filling in. The order of events suggests that
the methodology of recovering the past informs the process of repairing
destruction, but Ananda makes the aesthetic decision, as far as the recon-
structed Buddha goes, not to conceal the scars. Ondaatje sets process and
objects in the foreground, with results and discoveries in the background.
Individuals survive or don’t make it, and their outcomes Ondaatje places
in the complicated broader context that repels a sense of satisfaction or
156 Empathy and the Novel
even connection. All of these estranging moves place obstacles in the way of
empathy-seeking novel-readers, who report with puzzlement their experi-
ence of not liking Anil very much.13
I have already suggested that Ondaatje eschews the emotional effects
of a character-centered psychological novel in Anil’s Ghost. Ondaatje also
throws out the usual moves of the character-driven research thriller, with
which Anil’s Ghost has something in common. As Margaret Scanlan observes,
Anil’s Ghost does not participate in the celebration of a recoverable truth
that typifies romances of the archives (“Terrorism’s Time” 310). Specifically,
Ondaatje provides no strong closure to the conclusion of Anil’s research
quest. Anil receives no reward for her efforts, and Sarath pays a severe pen-
alty for his role. The characters abjure pleasurable experiences, including
aesthetic ones, in a novel that idealizes asceticism. The usual research tools
(United Nations and Amnesty reports, atlases, encyclopedias, and newspa-
pers) are revealed as patchy and unreliable. Instead, scientific expertise, local
knowledge, and a knack for improvisation during times of scarcity receive
Ondaatje’s emphasis. Peculiarly, the creation of something approximating
an archaeological surround for a fact in fiction requires jettisoning history
and politics. The novel provides very little detail on the recent strife in Sri
Lanka; though informed readers will recognize Ondaatje’s fictionalized ver-
sions of some events, he leaves much deliberately vague. Ondaatje resists
the generic pressure to provide a researcher hero or to reveal a heroic vic-
tim, a silenced life brought to voice by recovery. I have argued elsewhere
that romances of the archive often place empathy at the center of a research
quester’s work, as a special form of recognition that permits the unlocking
of mysteries.14 Though the novel offers a brief portrait of an epigraphist
(Palipana, Sarath’s mentor) who makes up the evidence that ought to be
there, Ondaatje does not endorse the maker’s trance as a way through to
truth. Similarly, Ananda’s facial reconstruction of “Sailor,” apparently fol-
lowing the Manchester protocol for rebuilding a face up from the skull, fails
in accuracy because it becomes a portrait of the artist’s dead wife, a work of
mourning rather than of recovery. Though she experiences flashes of insight
as she gains knowledge of her surroundings, Anil does not reach the truth
about Sailor through feeling. Dispassionate recognition of the meaning of
evidence replaces empathy, whose leaps to certainty Ondaatje places under
skeptical scrutiny.
False empathy receives explicit condemnation in Anil’s Ghost, as in cri-
tiques such as critical race theorist Richard Delgado’s work. In The Coming
Race War, Delgado creates characters that discover through dialogue how
true empathy is in “shorter and shorter supply” (Race War 8). Whites in par-
ticular are prone to false empathy, a term Delgado relates to Gramsci’s false
consciousness: “False empathy, a sentimental, breast-beating kind, is com-
mon among white liberals, and is the mirror opposite of false consciousness,
Gramsci’s notion” (12). Whether one knows that he or she is faking or not, a
Contesting Empathy 157
name bartered from her brother, strenuously resists attempts to place her
own identity: not the swimmer, not married, not Sri Lankan anymore. Yet
professionally accustomed to placing the dead, Anil routinely turns “bod-
ies into representatives of race and age and place” (55). Being fully alive
embraces particularities of experience, memory, and emotion that elude the
categories that contain the dead. (Hence Ondaatje depicts Leaf’s descent
into early-onset Alzheimer’s disease as embedding the true meaning of
death.) Defying fixed identity entails other distancing gestures, as in Anil’s
characteristic defense against the demand for a personal response to trauma:
“there could never be any logic to the human violence without the distance
of time. For now it could be reported, filed in Geneva, but no one could give
meaning to it. . . . She saw that those who were slammed and stained by vio-
lence lost the power of language and logic” (55). Anil’s expressed solidarity
with the dead, about whom readers learn little, stems from her privilege to
fly away from the scene and to regain her position in Europe or America.
Judgments are to be left to history, conspicuously absent from the text.
Anil’s effort has the virtue of retaining language and logic employed on the
dead’s behalf, but it is disconnected from fellow feeling.
Eventually Anil gets past her fear of emotional responsiveness to arrive
at what Martin Hoffman would call empathic injustice—by which the psy-
chologist means an empathic recognition of injustice suffered by others (see
19 above). Anil finally lays blame on the government, allying herself with
justice. Yet a pallid justice renders its verdicts from the safety of Geneva.
On the ground in Ondaatje’s Sri Lanka a starker reality rules, in which
approaching justice endangers life, perhaps not the best choice in the cir-
cumstances. One victim who might be identified, one monument repaired:
Ondaatje places these works of craft in stark juxtaposition to the healing
arts of the novel’s two doctors, who continue to strive for the wounded
and sick. Ondaatje brings Anil into close proximity with the physicians on
several occasions, as if to chart her cure from dispassion and her induction
into professional caring through actions rather than through narration of
psychological renovation. The conclusion of the novel, in which Ananda
restores sight to the Buddha and receives the companionable gesture of a
child, could not come about without Anil’s swift medical intervention when
Ananda attempts suicide. Gunesena, the man who drives Anil to the air-
port for her last-minute escape to the West, is the crucifixion victim whom
she earlier rescues. If one cares about human rights, Ondaatje suggests, one
could do worse than caring for living persons and human bodies.
Embodied human characters, for both Octavia Butler and Michael
Ondaatje, present fearful dangers to one another. The extreme risk entailed
in empathizing or identifying with others underscores the problems of
empathic inaccuracy and the amorality of empathetic responsiveness to suf-
fering. The victim with whom the empath resonates emotionally may be an
Contesting Empathy 159
Thus the salutary effects of fiction reading fail, in inaction. The worst a false
empathy critic could say can be represented by cultural historian Marcus
Wood’s condemnation of the liberal imagination, as offering onanistic indul-
gence of feeling at the expense of the enslaved (Slavery 36). There, con-
sumption of the pitiable representation as pornography ostensibly makes
something happen, but the wrong thing (certainly not abolition, according
to Wood).
Both false empathy and failed empathy critics dislike the emotions that
empathizers enjoy, but, in a central irony, they confidently predict the
existence and effects of the feelings that they criticize. Their moralizing
depends upon the certainty that pride, disdain, or condescension related to
the empathizer’s position in a social hierarchy truly undergirds any claim
of empathic resonance with another real or fictional being. While the same
critics who express false empathy or failed empathy views may also doubt
the existence of universal human emotions, their conclusions about the del-
eterious effects of empathy endorse a view of human nature (or at least of
white, Western, privileged human nature) as gravitating toward pleasurable
sensations of superiority over others. Some regard this as hardwired, espe-
cially in the male of the species.18 Octavia Butler, for instance, believes that
a genetic tendency toward hierarchical behavior is the species’ most nega-
tive and self-endangering trait (Mehaffey and Keating, “Radio Imagination”
54–55). Not all false empathy or failed empathy critics are biological deter-
minists, however, and they consistently emphasize the significance of rec-
ognizing and responding to cultural differences as a priority over any easy
assumption of understanding based on human universals.
For those whose main object of critique is the notion of universal human
emotion, the failure or falsity of empathy stems from the conviction that
humans do not share basic emotions, neither in the culturally diverse con-
temporary world, nor back in time, nor yet in prehistory on the savannah.
They would regard as risible reductionism a statement such as this, from
two psychologists: “Because humans share similar receptor mechanisms and
brains that are organized in roughly the same way, there is bound to be con-
Contesting Empathy 161
The assumption that there are irreducible features of human life and
experience that exist beyond the constitutive effects of local cultural
conditions. Universalism offers a hegemonic view of existence by
which the experiences, values and expectations of a dominant cul-
ture are held to be true for all humanity. For this reason, it is a crucial
feature of imperial hegemony, because its assumption (or assertion)
of a common humanity—its failure to acknowledge or value cultural
difference—underlies the promulgation of imperial discourse for the
“advancement” or “improvement” of the colonized, goals that thus
mask the extensive and multifaceted exploitation of the colony. (Key
Concepts 235, emphasis in original)
they connect novel reading (or narrative consumption) with the cultivation
of the role-taking imagination? If so, is this association an artifact of post-
Enlightenment liberal humanism, or is it too subject to vigorous reforming
and hybridization, those celebrated qualities of postcolonial literature? In
many parts of the postcolonial world, novel writing is a twentieth-century
phenomenon. Does adoption of the novel as a form of narrative expression
import recent Western expectations about empathy and character identifi-
cation, or can the postcolonial novel accommodate narrative invocation of
preexistent cultural understandings about empathy?
Examining texts from other cultures for signs of empathy or its close
cognates (sympathy, compassion, fellow-feeling) reassures us that they can-
not simply be newfangled notions that come in on the coattails of the
novel. According to Patrick Colm Hogan, Sanskrit literary theorists (third
century) describe rasa, or aesthetic feelings, as entailing empathic versions
of emotions,23 and Arabic Aristotelian theorists name rahmah, compas-
sion or beneficence, as one of the “primary ethical emotions operating in
literature.”24 Hogan rightly calls for attention to the literary theories and
primary imaginative texts of non-Western traditions, and he finds in a vari-
ety of cultures significant evidence of literary universals, including empa-
thy.25 Contributions to this understanding come from many disciplinary
approaches and interdisciplinary conversations. For instance, Richard J.
Davidson and Anne Harrington gather the conversations of scientists and
Buddhist monks in their collection, Visions of Compassion: Western Scien-
tists and Tibetan Buddhists Examine Human Nature (2002). The Buddhist
moral virtue karuna combines love and compassion in order to resist greed
and hatred. More important, the practice of karuna models the movement
toward sympathy and altruism, in Nancy Eisenberg’s paraphrase, helping
“a person to overcome indifference” and providing “an understanding of
the suffering of others and a willingness to go out of one’s way to help
those in distress” (“Empathy-Related” 133).26 All major world religions, it is
sometimes claimed, have a version of the Golden Rule at the heart of their
ethical codes. The Hebrew Bible enjoins the faithful to love their neigh-
bors as themselves (Leviticus 19:18), and Jesus’s gloss of Leviticus in the
Sermon on the Mount insists that his followers go further, loving even their
enemies (Matthew 5:44). The Golden Rule, to do unto others as you would
have them do to you (Matthew 7:12; Luke 6:31), emphasizes the principle
of reciprocity, as it comes down from the law and the prophets. The exis-
tence of versions of the Golden Rule (in Buddhist, Brahmin, Confucian,
Sikh, and Hindu religious texts, as well as in ancient Greek philosophi-
cal writing, among others) suggests both the advantages of reciprocity and
the relative weakness of compassion, especially when involving individuals
marked as other.27 In other words, the presence of Golden Rule variants
may show a near universal worry that humans tend not to treat others as
they would themselves.
164 Empathy and the Novel
of feeling more intensely with our family members than with strangers)
lends credence to the charges of failed empathy critics. Indeed, Jesus himself
could be regarded as a failed empathy critic, though he sees a way through
the impasse when he singles out for emulation the unusually “good” Samari-
tan, who acts on his compassionate feeling rather than hurrying by.
Clearly, many cultures value compassion, but their philosophers often
observe the weakness of fellow-feeling in moving people to action on behalf
of others. Religious teaching has sometimes (though by no means always)
addressed this problem by attempting to get people to think of others in
terms of similarities rather than differences, through attribution of universal
traits. Belief in innate qualities, including virtues and vices, often accom-
panies attempts to define the nature of humanity. Though this does not
always result in emphasis on positive qualities such as compassion, it can,
and not only in the West. In the fourth century BCE, the Chinese philoso-
pher Mencius places a concept close to empathy at the heart of his descrip-
tion of humanity. “No man,” Mencius writes, “is devoid of a heart sensitive
to the sufferings of others.” The philosopher illustrates his observation with
an example and an analysis of the authenticity of spontaneous empathetic
responsiveness: “Suppose a man were, all of a sudden, to see a young child
on the verge of falling into a well. He would certainly be moved to compas-
sion, not because he wanted to get in the good graces of the parents, nor
because he wished to win the praise of his fellow villagers or friends, nor
yet because he disliked the cry of the child. From this it can be seen that
whoever is devoid of the heart of compassion is not human” (Mencius 2.6,
82). Further, the “heart of compassion is the germ of benevolence,” or Jen
(sometimes translated as love), one of four fundamental virtues that embed
the potential for good in human beings (83). Indeed, for Mencius, denying
the existence of any one of these virtues in oneself is tantamount to robbing
oneself of one’s humanity.29 The motivation to act upon one’s empathic
responses, in Mencius’s philosophy, then becomes linked to the desire to
remain inside the boundaries of the human group.
Our contemporary celebration of our diversity and our differences may
make the call to recognize our similarities more difficult to heed, though
advocates of virtue ethics and ethics of care hope not.30 We should recall,
however, what the Oliners found when they interviewed holocaust rescuers:
those who had learned to see Jews as human beings like themselves were
more likely to engage in rescuing than those who had been trained to focus
on differences (Altruistic Personality 176). Ihab Hassan, an atypical theo-
rist of postcoloniality and postmodernity, articulates some of the possible
consequences of focusing on otherness to the exclusion of commonalities:
“It can discourage mutual obligation, cripple empathy, defeat transcultural
judgments, leaving only raw power to resolve human conflicts. It can lead
to hostility, exclusiveness, less respect for others than solidarity with our-
selves. . . . Still, the intractable question remains: How and when, pragmati-
166 Empathy and the Novel
Since she writes about a context in which the act of novel reading stood
in opposition to a regime that deprived citizens of basic freedoms, Nafi-
si’s case for empathy through reading may seem more compelling than the
common American and English versions that I have subjected to scrutiny
in this study. This testimony from outside the Anglo-American academy
(though Nafisi is now a professor at Johns Hopkins) suggests that we should
not be quick to discount the symbolic importance of novel reading as a
sign of one’s empathy and one’s commitments to humane principles. When
announcing oneself as a reader of Nabokov and Fitzgerald runs the risk of
censure by agents of a totalitarian state, then siding with imaginative trans-
port looks more like courage than escapism. Nafisi’s testimony also reminds
us that before we discount the universal importance of empathy simply
because it bears the label of a “universal,” that we should attempt to put
ourselves in the shoes of those who see value in the emotional transactions
across time and culture that may be assisted by novel reading.
Nonetheless, the validity of claims about the relationship of empathy to
altruism or good world citizenship should still be tested. These pervasive
beliefs about the efficacy of fiction, advanced in many cases by novelists
themselves, should be investigated in multiple historical contexts, with sen-
sitivity to cultural differences. Striking similarities should also be collected
and questioned. Nafisi’s warning does not differ substantially from the Eng-
lish critic John Carey’s comment, “The imaginative power reading uniquely
demands is clearly linked, psychologically, with a capacity for individual
judgement and with the ability to empathize with other people. Without
reading, these faculties may atrophy” (Pure Pleasure xi). Nafisi and Carey
stand in here for the thousands of similar utterances of teachers, librarians,
and book-lovers all around the world who fear the consequences of an end
to novel reading. This position deserves the respect of critical scrutiny.
The atrophy of faculties of judgment and empathy would certainly
impoverish humans. The replacement of the novel with other forms of nar-
rative may already be underway, and I am sure I am not alone in feeling that
its total abandonment would be a loss. However, I strongly resist the notion
that the decline of a novel-reading population among global citizens would
inevitably result in stultified imaginations and civic lives ruled by antipathy
or apathy. I also doubt that novels alone can cure what ails us: can novel
reading really restore to vitality nearly extinguished civic virtues in a culture
like my own, in which torture and routine violations of international law
and human rights are carried out daily on our behalf? Can novel reading
avert the course of genocide or rouse a torpid public to activism? Of course,
no one goes so far. More modest expressions of hope invest fiction with the
power to reverse the course of apathy and indifference to others. The evi-
dence for such effects, I have argued, is not robust, and we will be bitterly
disappointed if we expect novel reading to accomplish the work of forming
168 Empathy and the Novel
world citizens for us. This is our responsibility as parents, teachers, writers,
and, indeed, as novel readers. We should not fob it off on fiction and risk
spoiling a great source of aesthetic pleasure, refreshing escape, and edifica-
tion with a task it cannot accomplish.
In my judgment, readers themselves, especially those who discuss books
and bring others into conversation about the implications of fiction, pos-
sess the power that they so often attribute to novels. We ought to take care
not to confound the effect of teaching with the effects of reading, when
it has been demonstrated that even a simple perspective-taking game can
inspire altruism where reading alone does not. Readers, which is to say liv-
ing people, bring empathy to the novel, and they alone have the capac-
ity to convert their emotional fusion with the denizens of make-believe
worlds into actions on behalf of real others. That they rarely decide to do so
should not be taken as a sign of fiction’s failings. I have argued throughout
this study that the perception of fictionality releases novel-readers from
the normal state of alert suspicion of others’ motives that often acts as a
barrier to empathy. This means that the contract of fictionality offers a no-
strings-attached opportunity for emotional transactions of great intensity.
A novel-reader may enjoy empathy freely without paying society back in
altruism. Indeed, the appetite for such experiences of imaginative transport
significantly diminishes when they become vehicles for arriving at improv-
ing ends. New ways of analyzing the lives of readers, especially longitudinal
studies that might catch delayed or cumulative effects of novel reading,
ought to be devised.
Further, the fiction that novel-readers actually choose and recommend to
one another ought to command our attention, whether or not it passes criti-
cal tests of significance or literariness. If narrative empathy can be shown
to spill over into prosocial action, then great care ought to be exerted to
identify the full range of novels that make changes in the world. Even there
we should proceed cautiously. A society that insists on receiving immediate
ethical and political yields from the recreational reading of its citizens puts
too great a burden on both empathy and the novel.
APPENDIX
A COLLECTION OF HYPOTHESES
ABOUT NARRATIVE EMPATHY
While several of the hypotheses confute one another (as for instance in
the directionality of empathy and character identification), I include both
formulations to indicate possible directions for research. In its specific-
ity, this collection of possibilities marks a significant advance over earlier
broad assertions about narrative empathy that take the form of un-testable
generalizations.
Preface
ilarity’s relationship to higher empathy scores is Dennis Krebs, “Empathy and Altru-
ism” (1975). On out-groups, see E. P. Sheehan et al., “Reactions to AIDS and Other
Illnesses: Reported Interactions in the Workplace” (1989). On similarity, see the lit-
erature review in Mark H. Davis, Empathy: A Social Psychological Approach (1994),
15, 96–99, 105–6, 109, 116–18.
9. I treat Hume and Smith in detail in chapter 2. On evolutionary bases for empa-
thy for those who are like us, see D. J. Kruger, “Evolution and Altruism: Combining
Psychological Mediators with Naturally Selected Tendencies,” Evolution and Human
Behavior 24 (2003) and Martin Hoffman, Empathy and Moral Development: Implica-
tions for Caring and Justice (2000), 4, 13, 206.
10. See the account of empathy’s potential to replace egocentrism with ethno-
centrism in Nancy Sherman, “Empathy and Imagination” (1998).
11. For this catalog of helps and impediments to empathetic reading of first-per-
son fiction, I draw upon the in-class essays of the students in English 232, The Novel,
composed on 20 February 2006, answering this question: “How does your recent
reading experience in this course square with the notion that first-person narration
is especially productive of empathetic reading? What differences in technique in the
variety of first-person narrative situations might alter readers’ responses?”
12. For starting points in philosophy, see Susan L. Feagin’s Reading with Feeling:
The Aesthetics of Appreciation (1996) and E. M. Dadlez’s, What’s Hecuba to Him?
Fictional Events and Actual Emotions (1997). Psychological critic Norman Holland
deserves attention, not only to his original The Dynamics of Literary Response (1968),
but also to his recent “Where Is a Text? A Neurological View” (2002). Two literary
cognitivists who attend (atypically) to the role of emotion in literary response are
David S. Miall, “Anticipation and Feeling in Literary Response: A Neuropsychologi-
cal Perspective,” Poetics 23 (1995), 275–98 and Keith Oatley, “A Taxonomy of the
Emotions of Literary Response and a Theory of Identification in Fictional Narrative”
(1994). Robyn Warhol’s Having a Good Cry: Effeminate Feelings and Pop-Culture
Forms (2003) models the discussion of embodied emotional responses (other than
the individual critic’s feelings) for narrative theory and literary criticism. Profes-
sional readers will have already discerned the profound influence of Wayne Booth on
this project. His The Company We Keep: An Ethics of Fiction (1988) shows the way.
13. For reception theory and reader-response criticism, see (respectively) Wolf-
gang Iser, The Act of Reading (1978) and Jane Tompkins’s collection, Reader-Response
Criticism: From Formalism to Post-Structuralism (1980).
14. For some of the finest in this burgeoning area, see, variously, Charles Altieri,
The Particulars of Rapture: An Aesthetics of the Affects (2003); Isobel Armstrong, The
Radical Aesthetic (2000); Brian Massumi, Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect,
Sensation (2002); Sianne Ngai, Ugly Feelings (2005); and Rei Terada, Feeling in The-
ory: Emotion after “The Death of the Subject” (2001).
15. See Antonio R. Damasio, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human
Brain (1994) and Joseph LeDoux, The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpin-
nings of Emotional Life (1996).
16. See Tammy Bourg, “The Role of Emotion, Empathy, and Text Structure in
Children’s and Adults’ Narrative Text Comprehension” (1996).
17. See David S. Miall and Don Kuiken, “What Is Literariness?” (1999) and Miall,
“Beyond the Schema Given” (1989).
Notes to Pages xiii–xx 175
18. See Marjorie Taylor et al., “The Illusion of Independent Agency: Do Adult
Fiction Writers Experience Their Characters as Having Minds of Their Own?”
(2002/2003).
19. For the best study of the experience of immersion reading, see Victor Nell,
Lost in a Book: The Psychology of Reading for Pleasure (1988).
20. See both Azar Nafisi’s moving memoir, Reading Lolita in Tehran (2003) and
Elizabeth Long’s superb sociological study, Book Clubs: Women and the Uses of Read-
ing in Everyday Life (2003).
21. David Miall reports that a 1992 pilot survey of adult readers in Canada yields
an 8 percent rate of “regular readers of literary texts,” but the definition of a “literary
text” in the study he cites most likely rules out popular fiction readers. See “Empow-
ering the Reader: Literary Response and Classroom Learning” (1996), 464. On the
Canadian situation, see ABC Canada, http://www.abc-canada.org/literacy_facts/
(accessed 19 November 2004). These recent North American findings are matched
by survey data for the United Kingdom. See the U.K. National Literacy Trust, http://
www.literacytrust.org.uk (accessed 7 September 2004). The sources gathered at this
site suggest that 40 percent of British adults do not read at all, with women reading
more than men. See also Michail Skaliotis’s “Key Figures on Cultural Participation
in the European Union” (October 2002), available online at www.readingeurope.
org/observatory.nsf/ (accessed 7 September 2004).
22. See Robert D. Putnam, Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of Ameri-
can Community (2000). On rates of novel reading contrasted with other genres, see
Reading at Risk (2004), 16–17.
23. Martha C. Nussbaum, Cultivating Humanity: A Classical Defense of Reform in
Liberal Education (1997), 63. See also Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and
Literature (1990) and Poetic Justice: The Literary Imagination and Public Life (1995).
24. See John Sanford, “Human Rights: A Novel Idea?” http://news-service
.stanford.edu/news/2002/april17/hunt-417.html (accessed 10 September 2004),
concerning Lynn Hunt’s presidential lecture, “The Novel and the Origins of Human
Rights: The Intersection of History, Psychology and Literature” (8 April 2004). See
also Lynn Hunt, “The Paradoxical Origins of Human Rights” (2000).
25. Canonically, see Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the
Origin and Spread of Nationalism (1983), 25–36.
26. Physiological measures have the advantage of being unaffected by the sub-
jects’ desire to present themselves favorably, as may occur in surveys, interviews, or
self-reports. See Nancy Eisenberg et al., “Physiological Indices of Empathy” (1987).
On deceleration of heart rate in response to negative experiences of others, see K. D.
Craig, “Physiological Arousal as a Function of Imagined, Vicarious, and Direct Stress
Experiences” (1968). On the measurement of palmar skin conductance and heart
rate in response to images of people in pain, see R. S. Lazarus et al., “A Labora-
tory Study of Psychological Stress Produced by a Motion Picture Film” (1962). This
study relies upon people’s tendency to identify with “characters” in a nonfiction film
(3). For a skin conductance study suggesting that empathetic arousal occurs when
subjects believe a person is receiving a painful shock, see J. H. Geer and L. Jarmecky,
“The Effect of Being Responsible for Reducing Another’s Pain on Subject’s Response
and Arousal” (1973). On facial or gestural responses as indications of empathy, see
the evaluation of Robert F. Marcus, “Somatic Indices of Empathy” (1987). See also
176 Notes to Pages xxi–4
Chapter 1
1. See Davis, Empathy: A Social Psychological Approach (1994), 62–81 for a survey
of this research.
2. See Carolyn Zahn-Waxler et al., “The Development of Empathy in Twins”
(1992).
3. See R. Koestenbaum et al., “Individual Differences in Empathy among Pre-
schoolers: Relation to Attachment History” (1989).
4. See Mark H. Davis et al., “The Heritability of Characteristics Associated with
Dispositional Empathy” (1994).
5. See my treatment of the contextual and paratextual factors that govern read-
ers’ assumptions about the shifting boundary between fiction and nonfiction in
Keen, Narrative Form (2003), 128–39. The literary historical evidence suggests that
cultural assumptions about fictionality and factuality change over time. Thus, the
Notes to Pages 4–5 177
salient point is readers’ belief that a work is fictional, activated as the work of cocre-
ation begins. My contention here is congruent with the claims of Richard J. Gerrig
and David N. Rapp, who argue that “readers must construct disbelief: literature will
have an impact unless readers expend specific effort to forestall that consequence.”
See “Psychological Processes Underlying Literary Impact” (2004), 280. Gerrig and
Rapp observe that “the probability that readers will construct disbelief is affected
by the extent to which they are transported to narrative worlds. . . . the more viv-
idly a work of literature carries its readers off, the more they will be affected by the
journey” (280).
6. Daniel Batson and his group have shown that exposure to the testimony of a
single member of a stigmatized group can improve attitudes toward those groups
through induced empathy. See C. Daniel Batson et al., “Empathy and Attitudes:
Can Feeling for a Member of a Stigmatized Group Improve Feelings Toward the
Group?” (1997). Batson emphasizes the ease with which novels and films induce
empathy and theorizes that the low-cost, low-risk situation may contribute to the
effect: “Rather than the disruption of normal patterns of behavior required to create
direct, equal-status, cooperative personal contact, we can be led to feel empathy for
a stigmatized group member as we sit comfortably in our living room” (106).
7. Social psychologist Mark H. Davis’s Empathy (1994) provides an excellent
and accessible introduction to the subject. For a philosophical account of the role of
empathy in the art of understanding (and the arts generally), see Karl F. Morrison,
“I Am You”: The Hermeneutics of Empathy in Western Literature, Theology, and Art
(1988).
8. See Vittorio Gallese et al., “The Mirror Matching System: A Shared Manifold
for Intersubjectivity” (2002), 35–36.
9. In chapter 2, I trace the fascinating literary careers of the related concepts,
observing the convention of using the terminology actually employed by writers in
the past.
10. See C. Daniel Batson, The Altruism Question: Toward a Social-Psychological
Answer (1991), 56–57 and “Altruism and Prosocial Behavior” (1998), 282–316; see
also Nancy Eisenberg, “Emotion, Regulation, and Moral Development” (2000), 671–
72 and “The Development of Empathy-Related Responding” (2005), 73–117.
11. Students who read under compulsion in order to gain credit for a course may
indeed experience personal distress and still soldier on in their reading. I regard this
situation (and its results) as an extension of teaching, not to be attributed directly
to the novel. Personal distress might contribute to a description of the obstacles to
immersion (including disposition or emotional temperament) for reluctant readers.
12. For instance, the congruent theories of Batson and Eisenberg feature differ-
ent uses of the terms sympathy and empathy and distinct positions on whether pure
empathy precedes other-related sympathy or is defined by its orientation toward the
other. See Eisenberg, “Emotion, Regulation, and Moral Development,” 671–72. For
an excellent recent summary of the different schools of thought about empathy, see
Stephanie D. Preston and Frans B. M. de Waal, “Empathy: Its Ultimate and Proxi-
mate Bases” (2002).
13. Charles Darwin’s treatment of sympathy clearly includes empathy, though
he does not use the term. See The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals
(1872). Paul Ekman, the leading authority on facial expressions as indicators of
178 Notes to Page 5
universal human emotions, does not treat empathy as a core emotion, but as one
of the nine starting points for emotional reactions (when we feel what others feel).
See Ekman, Emotions Revealed: Recognizing Faces and Feelings to Improve Commu-
nication and Emotional Life (2003), 34, 37. Neuroscientist Jaak Panksepp argues
that emotional systems in the brain involve central affective programs composed of
neural anatomy, physiology, and chemicals. Panksepp considers empathy one of the
higher sentiments (mixing lower reflexive affects and higher cognitive processes),
emerging out of the recent evolutionary expansion of the forebrain. See “Emo-
tions as Natural Kinds in the Brain,” (2000), 142–43. For philosopher Martha C.
Nussbaum, empathy comes into play as a part of compassion, which she treats as a
human emotion. See Nussbaum, Upheaveals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions
(2001), 327–35. For John Deigh and those working at the intersection of ethics and
cognitive science, empathy is one of the moral emotions. See Deigh, “Empathy and
Universalizability” (1995), 743–63. Social scientist Jon Elster, by way of contrast,
does not treat empathy in his Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions
(1999). This array of views reflects the current state of empathy studies: experts
have not agreed whether it is primarily emotional, cognitive, or both: their judg-
ments usually reflect their position on the rationality of the emotions or the emo-
tionality of cognition.
14. See, for instance, the working definitions of different vicariously induced
emotional states in Nancy Eisenberg and Richard A. Fabes, “Children’s Disclosure of
Vicariously Induced Emotions” (1995), 111. I follow Nancy Eisenberg in differenti-
ating empathy, aversive personal distress, and sympathy. Empathic response includes
the possibility of personal distress, but personal distress (unlike empathy) is less
likely to lead to sympathy, if it proceeds beyond evanescent shared feeling.
15. Positive forms of empathy are drastically underemphasized in the literature.
As recently as 2002, psychologists George Ainslie and John Monterosso call for
more attention to the full range of emotions involved in empathy. See “Hyperbolic
Discounting Lets Empathy Be a Motivated Process” (2002).
16. Jouissance is a nearly orgasmic pleasure to be experienced through reading,
combining bodily pleasure with intellectual joy in finding meaning. See Roland
Barthes, The Pleasure of the Text (1973, trans. 1975), in which Barthes distinguishes
the relatively easy pleasure of the readerly text from the bliss that comes when the
demanding writerly text helps readers break out of their subject positions. See also
Julia Kristeva, Revolution in Poetic Language (1974, trans. 1984).
17. See, for instance, the treatment of happiness, joy, and love in Elaine Hat-
field, John T. Cacioppo, and Richard L. Rapson, Emotional Contagion (1994). The-
odor Lipps, an important early theorist of empathy, proposed motor mimicry as an
automatic response to another’s expression of emotion. See Lipps, “Das Wissen von
Fremden Ichen” (1906).
18. See Carolyn Zahn-Waxler et al., “Empathy and Prosocial Patterns in Young
MZ and DZ Twins: Development and Genetic and Environmental Influences”
(2001). Zahn-Waxler reports genetic influences on prosocial acts and empathic con-
cern, found across the time points studied.
19. Cultural differences implicate differences in the nature of emotional expe-
rience. Our understanding of what it means to be a person in our cultural con-
text affects the way we experience, for instance, daily emotions of pleasantness
Notes to Pages 5–7 179
“The Mirror Matching System: A Shared Manifold for Intersubjectivity” (2002) and
M. Iacoboni et al., “Cortical Mechanisms of Human Imitation” (1999).
57. See, for instance, Leda Cosmides and John Tooby, “Cognitive Adaptations for
Social Exchange” (1992).
58. D. J. Kruger, “Evolution and Altruism” (2003), 118–25. Cross-cultural research
suggests that Westerners may differ from members of traditional societies in their
emphasis on personal choice that mitigates the obligation to offer a caring response.
See J. G. Miller and D. M. Bersoff, “Cultural Influences on the Moral Status of Reci-
procity and the Discounting of Endogenous Motivation” (1994).
59. See Eisenberg, Fabes, and Spinrad, “Prosocial Development.” 1.
60. See Martin L. Hoffman’s table “Scheme for the development and transforma-
tion of empathic distress” (1987). See also his compressed version of his theory in
the chapter “Toward a Comprehensive Empathy-Based Theory of Prosocial Moral
Development” (2001), 61–86 and his earlier “Empathy, Its Limitations and Its Role
in a Comprehensive Moral Theory” (1984).
61. See C. Daniel Batson, The Altruism Question (1991) and “Altruism and Pro-
social Behavior” (1998); Eisenberg, Fabes, and Spinrad, “Prosocial Development.”
See also Nancy Eisenberg, “Emotion, Regulation, and Moral Development” (2000),
671–72.
62. For his evolutionary argument, see Martin L. Hoffman, “Is Altruism Part of
Human Nature?” (1981). For a full-scale philosophical treatment of evolutionary
altruism, see Elliot Sober and David Sloan Wilson, Unto Others: The Evolution and
Psychology of Unselfish Behavior (1998). Mark Davis provides a concise summary of
the sociobiological and psychological theories in Empathy (1994), 23–45.
63. By connecting caring and justice, Hoffman argues with John Rawls’s influen-
tial Theory of Justice (1971). As Peter Singer notes, even in Rawls’s more recent The
Law of Peoples (1999), Rawls neglects “obligations towards individuals . . . currently
destitute in other countries” (Singer, One World [2002], 176).
64. See Nancy Eisenberg, “Development of Empathy-Related Responding,”
78–83.
65. Psychologists are not the only ones to offer critiques of empathy. Legal the-
orist Richard Posner considers empathy “amoral.” See “Against Ethical Criticism”
(1997), 19. Richard Delgado believes the cultivation of empathy should be rejected
as poor strategy. See his The Coming Race War? And Other Apocalyptic Tales of Amer-
ica after Affirmative Action and Welfare (1996), 4–36. I discuss these and other criti-
cisms of empathy in chapter 6, “Contesting Empathy.”
66. See J. A. Piliavin et al., Emergency Intervention (1981).
67. See the summary of studies involving questionnaires administered to adults,
in Nancy Eisenberg and Paul Miller, “Empathy, Sympathy, and Altruism” (1997).
68. See C. Daniel Batson, The Altruism Question (1991); C. Daniel Batson et
al., “Empathic Joy and the Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis” (1991); “Empathy and
the Collective Good: Caring for One of the Others in a Social Dilemma” (1995);
“Immorality from Empathy-Induced Altruism: When Compassion and Justice Con-
flict” (1995); and “Influence of Self-Reported Distress and Empathy on Egoistic
Versus Altruistic Motivation to Help” (1983). For a response to Batson’s work, see
Steven L. Neuberg et al., “Does Empathy Lead to Anything More Than Superficial
Helping? Comment on Batson et al. (1997)” (1997).
184 Notes to Pages 23–28
69. See Samuel P. and Pearl M. Oliner, The Altruistic Personality: Rescuers of Jews
in Nazi Europe (1988) and their edited collection, Embracing the Other: Philosophi-
cal, Psychological, and Historical Perspectives on Altruism (1992).
70. For the full questionnaire, see Appendix C of The Altruistic Personality (1988),
331–56.
71. See The Altruistic Personality (1988), 189–99, for accounts of several different
empathic rescuers. For a positive view of the correlation of empathy and altruism,
see John F. Dovidio et al., “Specificity of Empathy-Induced Helping: Evidence for
Altruistic Motivation” (1990).
72. See Elizabeth Bowen, The Collected Stories of Elizabeth Bowen (1981),
671–85.
73. See Geoffrey H. Hartman, “Is an Aesthetic Ethos Possible? Night Thoughts
after Auschwitz” (1994), 135–55, 137–38.
74. See Tom W. Smith, “Altruism in Contemporary America: A Report from the
National Altruism Study” (2003).
75. See the variety of views in Altruism, edited by Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D.
Miller, and Jeffrey Paul (1993).
76. For instance, in Unto Others (1998), Sober and Wilson argue that social psy-
chology has not explained away the role of egoism (seeking internal rewards) in
altruism. They advance an evolutionary argument as an alternative.
77. See Patricia Greenspan, Emotions and Reasons: An Inquiry into Emotional Jus-
tification (1988).
78. For a historical survey, see Nico H. Frijda, “The Psychologists’ Point of View”
(2000), 70–71. Philosopher Patricia Greenspan offers a nuanced critique of psycho-
logical arguments in “Emotions, Rationality and Mind/Body” (2003).
79. See, for instance, Antonio Damasio et al., “Somatic Markers and the Guidance
of Behavior: Theory and Preliminary Testing” (1991). Damasio’s works for general
readers have resulted in wide dissemination of his theories. See Descartes’ Error:
Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (1994), The Feeling of What Happens: Body
and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness (1999), and Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sor-
row and the Feeling Brain (2003).
80. See Ronald deSousa, The Rationality of the Emotions (1987) and LeDoux, The
Emotional Brain.
81. See Leda Cosmides and John Tooby, “Evolutionary Psychology and the Emo-
tions” (2000).
82. My informant is neuroscientist Tyler S. Lorig.
83. See, for instance, Stephen K. Reed’s introductory college text, Cognition: The-
ory and Applications, 6th ed. (2004). Emotional states receive fleeting mention on
just three pages of this text.
84. See, for instance, Joseph P. Forgas, ed., Handbook of Affect and Social Cogni-
tion (2001).
85. Hoffman is less concerned with the matching of feelings as an end result of
empathy, and more interested in the empathic process that may lead a person to
feel, for instance, empathic anger on behalf of someone else’s sadness. See Empathy
and Moral Development (2000), 30.
86. See Janet Strayer and Marianne Schroeder, “Children’s Helping Strategies:
Influences of Emotion, Empathy, and Age” (1989), 86.
Notes to Pages 28–35 185
87. Novelist and critic Vernon Lee’s (Violet Paget) 1895 lecture and 1897 essay
“Beauty and Ugliness” contain early mentions of Einfühlung, integrated as empathy
into her book-length aesthetic theory, The Beautiful (1913). The core elements of
the modern concept of empathy can legitimately be traced to Lee, who was also
a novelist. As with several key dates in psychology, rival claimants to earliest usage
appear. Late nineteenth-century German aesthetics makes a claim. Theodor Lipps’s
Einfühlung (1897, in book form Äesthetik [1903]), was translated in 1909 by experi-
mental psychologist E. B. Titchener as empathy. Lee drew on Lipps’ work for The
Beautiful. Freud also had Lipps’s books in his library and adopted the term Einfüh-
lung. See Lauren Wispé, “History of the Concept of Empathy” (1987). For specu-
lations on the role of aesthetics in human evolution, see Leda Cosmides and John
Tooby, “Does Beauty Build Adapted Minds? Toward an Evolutionary Theory of Aes-
thetics, Fiction and the Arts” (2001).
88. Philosopher Lawrence Blum believes that insofar as emotions of sympa-
thy and empathy promote perspective taking, they may result in better prosocial
responses than rationality alone. See Blum, Friendship, Altruism and Morality (1980),
122–39.
89. Alexander McCall Smith, Morality for Beautiful Girls (2001).
90. Received from “USMAM BELLO” usmanbello20004@telstra.com on 24 Feb-
ruary 2004.
91. On the 419 advance fee fraud, see the London Metropolitan Police Web site,
http://www.met.police.uk/fraudalert/419.htm (accessed 16 September 2004).
92. Personal collection of the author. Letter from Noor Nazziwa to Suzanne
Keen, no date (received in February 2004).
93. Washington and Lee University students’ responses were gathered by Suzanne
Keen in a postcolonial literature course in 2003. Students were asked of each docu-
ment, “What does it make you feel?” and “What would you do?” Everyone quoted in
the subsequent discussion gave me permission to reproduce his or her words.
94. http://www.soschildrensvillages.org.uk/ (accessed 7 October 2004). Alter-
natively, contact the SOS Children’s Village Association in Botswana at P.O. Box
30396, Gaborone, Botswana, tel. +267-395 32 20; fax +267-395 32 20. Ordi-
narily, the notion of intervention on behalf of a fictional character is considered
“absurd,” as Susan L. Feagin has it (“Imagining Emotions and Appreciating Fiction”
[1997], 54).
95. David S. Miall argues that literary reading characteristically “provides a forum
within which the concerns of the self are mediated” and results in strong differences
among readers (as opposed to nonliterary reading, in which a consensus about mean-
ing tends to emerge). I note that only two students made the move of self-applica-
tion. See David S. Miall, “Anticipation and Feeling in Literary Response: A Neuro-
psychological Perspective” (1995), 294.
96. For a useful interrogation of the uses to which moral philosophy puts the
novel, see Peter Johnson, Moral Philosophers and the Novel: A Study of Winch, Nuss-
baum and Rorty (2004).
97. See Ellen J. Esrock, The Reader’s Eye: Visual Imaging as Reader Response
(1994).
98. See Davis, Empathy (1994) and Stotland, ed., Empathy, Fantasy, and Helping
(1978).
186 Notes to Pages 37–42
Chapter 2
1. For a collection of responses from the early days of the form, see Novel and
Romance 1700–1800: A Documentary Record, edited by Ioan Williams (1970).
2. Stowe’s novel was not the only American narrative of the nineteenth century
to make an impact on reform movements. Richard Henry Dana’s autobiographical
Two Years before the Mast: A Personal Narrative of Life at Sea (1840) brought the
abuse of sailors to public attention and may have influenced congressional debate
over the following decade. Some celebrated cases of fiction related to reform, such as
Herman Melville’s White Jacket (1850), which also condemned flogging, accompany
rather than directly influence legislation. T. S. Arthur’s temperance novel Ten Nights
in a Bar-Room and What I Saw There (1854) rivaled even Uncle Tom’s Cabin for pop-
ularity in its time and may have assisted in the spread of temperance sentiment.
3. In 1909, the experimental psychologist E. B. Titchener translated as “empathy”
aesthetician Theodor Lipps’s term Einfühlung (which meant the process of “feeling
one’s way into” an art object or another person). See Experimental Psychology of the
Thought Processes (1909), 181–85. Notably, Titchener’s 1915 elaboration of the con-
cept in Beginner’s Psychology exemplifies empathy through a description of a reading
experience: “We have a natural tendency to feel ourselves into what we perceive or
imagine. As we read about the forest, we may, as it were, become the explorer; we
feel for ourselves the gloom, the silence, the humidity, the oppression, the sense of
lurking danger; everything is strange, but it is to us that strange experience has come”
(198). For Einfühlung, see Theodor Lipps, Ästhetik (1903, 1906).
4. On film, see Alex Neill, “Empathy and (Film) Fiction” (1996). A negative view
of empathetic effects in film occurs in film theory employing the Lacanian psycho-
analytic term suture to describe impositions of identifications on film viewers. See
Jean-Pierre Oudart, “Suture (elements of the logic of the signifier)” (1969). See Kaja
Silverman’s assessment of suture (1983), excerpted in Narrative, Apparatus, Ideol-
ogy: A Film Theory Reader (1986). For a critique of suture theory, see Noel Carroll,
Mystifying Movies: Fads and Fallacies in Contemporary Film Theory (1988), 196–97.
5. Edmund Burke, for example, writes of sympathy’s paradoxical role in aesthetic
response: “It is by this principle that poetry, painting, and other affecting arts, trans-
fuse their passions from one breast to another, and are often capable of grafting a
delight on wretchedness, misery, and death itself.” See A Philosophical Enquiry into
the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful (1757), 41.
6. See Aristotle’s Rhetoric, Book 3, 2. On Rhetoric: A Theory of Civic Discourse
(1991), 38, 152–53. Aristotle treats emotions as an aspect of the art of persuasion,
mentioning the arousal of the audience’s emotion (by inviting role taking) and the
refutation of the audience’s sympathy for an opponent’s view. Elements of empathy
appear in his brief accounts of pity and pathos.
7. For instance, Henry Home, Lord Kames’s treatment of the topics “Grandeur
and Sublimity” (in the chapter so named) includes aspects of motor mimicry, as
when a tall object inspires stretching in the beholder, or when a broad prospect of
land or sea causes a feeling of expansiveness that Kames links to an enlargement of
mind. See Henry Home, Lord Kames, Elements of Criticism (1762), 150–78.
8. For a contemporary psychological update of Hume’s insight, see Leslie Broth-
ers, Friday’s Footprint: How Society Shapes the Human Mind (2001), in which social
Notes to Pages 43–48 187
neuroscientist Brothers argues that the human brain has evolved a specialized capac-
ity for exchanging signals with other brains. In common with primate brains, our
brains have evolved to be social, as their sensitive attunement to facial expressions
and physical gestures (the basis for emotional contagion) and their way of assigning
mental life to animate and inanimate others demonstrate.
9. See also Adela Pinch’s subtle reading of Hume’s sympathy, Strange Fits of Pas-
sion (1996), 24–44.
10. They do differ: Hume accentuates the automatic nature of sympathy; in
Smith, the harmonious connection between feeling spectator and the object of his
gaze receives emphasis.
11. See Ann Jessie Van Sant, Eighteenth-century Sensibility and the Novel: The
Senses in Social Context (1993) and the discussion of sympathy in Catherine Galla-
gher, Nobody’s Story: The Vanishing Acts of Women Writers in the Marketplace 1670–
1820 (1994), 162–75.
12. Of course, this phenomenon was not confined to the British Isles, as the
responses to Goethe’s Sorrows of Young Werther (1774) and Rousseau’s La Nouvelle
Héloïse (1761) demonstrate. For a cultural reading of the latter case, see Robert
Darnton, The Great Cat Massacre and Other Episodes of French Cultural History
(1984), 215–56.
13. Henry Home, Lord Kames, “Emotions Caused by Fiction,” Elements of Criti-
cism (1762), 66–77.
14. For one of the few recent treatments of sensibility to entertain a version of the
positive, activist view represented here by Kames, see Markman Ellis, The Politics of
Sensibility: Race, Gender, and Commerce in the Sentimental Novel (1996).
15. Henry Mackenzie, paper from The Lounger 20 (18 June 1785), reprinted in
The Works of Henry Mackenzie (1996), 176–87.
16. For an important version of this critique, see Raymond Williams’s criticism of
the structure of feeling of industrial fiction, in Culture and Society, 1780–1950 (rpt.
1983), 88–109.
17. See William Godwin, An Enquiry Concerning Political Justice (1798 edition),
vol. 2. 499–500. For suspicion of sympathy as instigating contagious panic, see Shaft-
esbury, Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times, etc. (1711), 10. A magis-
trate’s sympathy, in contrast, can absorb and calm the people’s panic.
18. See Audrey Jaffe, Scenes of Sympathy: Identity and Representation in Victo-
rian Fiction (2000). For Jaffe, modern sympathy is inseparable from representations.
She usefully comments on the dynamics of projection, displacement, and imagined
exchange that characterize sympathy: “Thus the distinction between sympathy for
fictional characters and sympathy for actual people dissolves into . . . the difference
between the pleasurable sympathetic feelings fiction invites and the potential threat
of an encounter with an actual person. Pleasure, here, coincides with an absence
of reciprocity: a fictional character cannot look back” (7). Contrast this view with
Catherine Gallagher, Nobody’s Story, which emphasizes the difference between fic-
tional characters (“nobodies”) and real people (171).
19. For a classic statement of this legacy, see Walter Jackson Bate, “The Sympa-
thetic Imagination in Eighteenth-Century Criticism” (1945), 144, 159.
20. On the sentimental novel as political, see Markman Ellis’s excellent The Poli-
tics of Sensibility (1996).
188 Notes to Pages 48–53
21. For a view emphasizing the disconcerting effects of sympathy, especially loss
of self, indulgence in voyeurism, and the dangers of mistaking the feelings of others,
see David Marshall, The Surprising Effects of Sympathy (1988).
22. When in the early twentieth century the concepts of Einfühlung and empa-
thy became semantically separate from sympathy, the Romantic poets (and Shake-
speare) seemed obvious places to turn to detect representational empathy at work.
Richard Harter Fogle describes poetic empathy as the “presence of motor, kines-
thetic, or organic imagery, so powerful in effect as to evoke kindred impulses in
the reader” (“Empathetic Imagery” 149). For Fogle, poetic empathy begins with
physiological response and culminates in a psychological effect, the sensory fusion
of body and spirit: “If this fusion is perfect the total effect is not merely of physical
and emotional self-projection, but of imaginative projection balanced and tem-
pered by an objective self-possession born of intense contemplation” (Imagery 151).
The best examples of empathic poetic imagery Fogle locates in the work of Keats.
Projecting himself into the inanimate realm, while preserving the sense of embod-
ied perception results, Keats exercises empathy as the “best and most complete
means of contemplation” (151). Fogle sees poetic empathy as exercised by Keats
and Keats’s attuned reader as “a kind of sensuous imagination, which bases percep-
tion firmly upon our muscular, nervous, and organic processes” (151). Fogle’s views
of the physical and affective functions of romantic imagery took issue with the
then-dominant school of thought known as the New Criticism and perhaps for this
reason they were never widely accepted. A very different attitude toward empathy
and sympathy prevailed in the modern period, and the New Critics derived many
of their attitudes toward affect from the modern rather than the Romantic writers.
Taking the long view afforded by twenty-first-century interests in the embodied
mind and metaphor, Fogle can perhaps now be appreciated as a perceptive stu-
dent of metaphor and empathy. On metaphor as a product of embodied minds,
see canonically George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Metaphors We Live By (1980);
George Lakoff, Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about
the Mind (1987); and George Lakoff and Mark Turner, More Than Cool Reason: A
Field Guide to Poetic Metaphor (1989).
23. For an exhaustive treatment of this topic, see Thomas J. McCarthy, Relation-
ships of Sympathy: The Writer and the Reader in British Romanticism (1997), which
trawls through the poetry, prose, and the voluminous correspondence of writers of
the period.
24. For a brilliant and exhaustive account of the topicality of Victorian fiction,
see Richard D. Altick’s The Presence of the Present: Topics of the Day in the Victorian
Novel (1991).
25. See both the account and extensive bibliography of the periodical literature
in Richard Stang’s useful The Theory of the Novel in England, 1850–1870 (1959),
67–72, 228–41.
26. For details of these events, see Peter Ackroyd’s Dickens (1990), 255–57.
27. Sensation fiction records changing attitudes about domestic violence as the
marriage laws undergo reform. See Marlene Tromp, The Private Rod: Marital Vio-
lence, Sensation, and the Law in Victorian Britain (2000).
28. For an extended treatment of the narrative strategies employed by Victo-
rian novelists as they tackled ostensibly forbidden or impossible topics, see Suzanne
Notes to Pages 55–60 189
Keen, Victorian Renovations of the Novel: Narrative Annexes and the Boundaries of
Representation (1998).
29. See, for instance, Wilkie Collins’s depiction of the moral agriculturalist Cap-
tain Wragge in No Name (1862). This con man cultivates sympathy in order to
harvest cash.
30. Dickens’s great favorite type for satirizing, the moral hypocrite, invariably
attempts to cultivate sympathy, though he doesn’t deserve it.
31. For a lucid account of the philosophical differences between German aes-
thetics and British associationism, as they effect the development of the notion of
empathy, see Charles Edward Gauss, “Empathy” (1973–74), vol. 2, 86–9.
32. For the original essays, see Vernon Lee and C. Anstruther-Thomson, “Beauty
and Ugliness,” Contemporary Review 72 (October 1897): 544–69 and (November
1897): 669–88. Lee subjects this material to revision in her later book, The Beauti-
ful (1913).
33. See Suzanne Clark’s account of the reversal of values in modernism, stressing
disruption and experiment over sentiment, in Sentimental Modernism: Women Writ-
ers and the Revolution of the Word (1991).
34. Brecht’s statements about the V-effekt appear in many different interviews
and essays. See, for instance, “Alienation Effects in Chinese Acting” (1964), 91–99.
35. Brecht’s word for empathy was of course the German Einfühlung. V-effekt is
sometimes rendered A-effect in translation. As I discuss in the next chapter, defamil-
iarization and estrangement have not been demonstrated to cause alienation. Indeed,
some theorists of reading response suggest that defamiliarization, or foregrounding,
can slow the reader’s pace and invite empathetic identification. See, for instance,
David S. Miall and Donald Kuiken, “The Form of Reading: Empirical Studies of Lit-
erariness” (1998).
36. See, for instance, Ezra Pound’s brief manifesto, “A Few Don’ts by an Imagiste”
(1913), 5.
37. For an account of how empathy fell out of favor as a consequence of the shift
from romantic theories of the imagination to modern theories of form, see Ellen
Dissanayake, Homo Aestheticus (1992), 142–47.
38. Exceptions among modernists: some of Hemingway’s stories and virtually all
of Ivy Compton-Burnett’s novels focus on an externalized view of characters, relying
on the readers’ ability to infer psychological states from plain reports of dialogue.
Wyndham Lewis notoriously created abstract characters whose traits would work
against readers’ efforts to recuperate believable fictional worlds and confute what he
regarded as a noxious tradition of English individualism.
39. See Percy Lubbock, The Craft of Fiction (1926) for an early and influen-
tial elaboration of the implications of James’s narrative technique. Henry James’s
brother, the psychologist William James, contributed the term stream of conscious-
ness to his discipline in his Principles of Psychology (1890, 1892). See Dorrit Cohn’s
account in Transparent Minds: Narrative Modes for Presenting Consciousness in Fiction
(1978), 87.
40. For a good historical treatment of this trend, see Nicola Humble, The Femi-
nine Middlebrow Novel, 1920s to 1950s (2001), 7–56.
41. For demographics and details about selections, see Elizabeth Long, Book
Clubs (2003).
190 Notes to Pages 61–70
42. For my treatment of the changing reputation of one of those subgenres and
the relationship of the gender of a subgenre’s readership to its status, see Suzanne
Keen, “The Historical Turn” (2006).
43. My account is indebted to Janice A. Radway, A Feeling for Books (1997). See
also Joan Shelley Rubin, The Making of Middle/brow Culture (1992).
44. Martha Nussbaum, “Exactly and Responsibly: A Defense of Ethical Criticism”
(1998), 350. Not all empathy results in compassion, she concedes in this essay. For
Nussbaum, empathy is “thinner” than compassion (351).
45. For a summary of critical responses to Oprah Winfrey’s Book Club, see Kath-
leen Rooney, Reading with Oprah: The Book Club That Changed America (2005).
Chapter 3
“‘Mr. Popular Sentiment’: Dickens and the Gender Politics of Sentimentalism and
Social Reform Literature” (1998).
27. Sara L. Maurer, “empathetic reading experiences of c19 novels,” VICTORIA-L
(Monday, 15 November 2004).
28. Ellen Moody, “empathetic reading experiences of c19 novels,” VICTORIA-L
(Friday, 19 November 2004).
29. Kerryn Goldsworthy, “empathy for literary characters,” VICTORIA-L (Satur-
day, 20 November 2004).
30. Private correspondence (14 November 2004).
31. Kathleen O’Neill Sims, “empathy (and sympathy) for literary characters,”
VICTORIA-L (Saturday, 20 November 2004).
32. Michel Faber, “empathy (and sympathy) for literary characters,” VICTORIA-L
(Friday, 19 November 2004).
33. Els Andringa, “The Interface between Fiction and Life: Patterns of Identifica-
tion in Reading Autobiographies” (2004).
34. Sheldon Goldfarb, “empathetic reading experiences of c19 novels,” VICTO-
RIA-L (Monday, 15 November 2004).
35. Deborah D. Morse, “empathy, again,” VICTORIA-L (Monday, 15 November
2004).
36. For an excellent recent work historicizing emotions relevant to the history of
empathy, see Julie Ellison, Cato’s Tears and the Making of Anglo-American Emotion
(1999).
37. Cross-cultural studies of this kind are uncommon. See W. F. Brewer and K.
Ohtsuka, “Story Structure, Characterization, Just World Organization, and Reader
Affect in American and Hungarian Short Stories” (1988).
38. See Peter J. Rabinowitz, Before Reading: Narrative Conventions and the Politics
of Interpretation (1987). Rabinowitz offers a nuanced account of the different kinds
of narrative audiences to which an individual reader may belong.
39. Both Michael Steig and David Bleich emphasize the meaning making of read-
ers over authoritative, professional critical interpretation. That feature of reader-
response criticism provoked concern in the 1970s and 1980s, as literary theorists
worried about what would happen to interpretation. Today, interpretation is more
threatened by aliteracy than by empowered meaning-making readers.
40. Margot K. Louis, “empathetic reading experiences of c19 novels,” VICTO-
RIA-L (Sunday, 14 November 2004).
41. See Bonnie Brennan, “Bridging the Backlash: A Cultural Material Reading of
The Bridges of Madison County” (1996). Most of the critical commentary concerns
the film, dignified by association with Clint Eastwood and Meryl Streep.
42. Diana Ostrander, “empathetic reading experience of c19 novels,” VICTORIA-L
(Monday, 15 November, 2004).
43. June Siegel, “empathetic reading experiences of c19 novels,” VICTORIA-L
(Monday, 15 November 2004).
44. Michel Faber, “empathy (and sympathy) for literary characters,” VICTORIA-L
(Saturday, 20 November 2004).
45. See Don Kuiken et al., “Forms of Self-Implication in Literary Reading” (2004).
Though empathy is important for the theories of Kuiken and Miall, they concede
Notes to Pages 84–86 193
here, “the effects of empathy, identification, and their associated narrative feelings
have not been systematically examined in empirical studies” (175 n).
46. Victor Nell studied larger numbers of readers; Norman Holland drew conclu-
sions from study of just five readers. David S. Miall and Don Kuiken break stories
into segments.
47. By no means all reader-response criticism involves experiments with actual
readers. The methods of introspection and philosophical speculation about reading
often feature an abstract single “reader,” bearing closest resemblance to the author.
See, for instance, Stanley Fish’s early intervention in this area, “Literature in the
Reader: Affective Stylistics” (1970).
48. See, for example, C. D. Brisbin’s unpublished dissertation, “An Experimental
Application of the Galvanic Skin Response to the Measurement of Effects of Litera-
ture on Attitudes of Fifth Grade Students towards Blacks” (1971).
49. Understandably, medical research is the dominant application of neuroimag-
ing. The subfields of psycholinguistics, cognition, and developmental psychology and
the related field of education feature a great deal of work on reading.
50. See the recent article by W. D. Gaillard et al., “fMRI Identifies Regional Spe-
cialization of Neural Networks for Reading in Young Children” (2003). This group
ascertains that the neural networks processing reading are strongly lateralized (in
most subjects, in the left brain, associated with language) and are similar in early
readers and in adults.
51. I treat Patrick Colm Hogan’s cognitive theory of aesthetic empathy in chap-
ter 6. His interesting theories draw on wide reading of world literature, including
Arab and Indian aesthetic treatises, and support a general argument about literary
universals. He does not conduct empirical research on reading. Similarly, philoso-
pher Susan L. Feagin’s Reading with Feeling: The Aesthetics of Appreciation (1996)
theorizes a role for emotion in reading but does not study actual readers empirically.
Several literary critics treat empathy as a thematic element of fiction. These include
J. Brooks Bouson, whose book, The Empathic Reader: A Study of the Narcissistic Char-
acter and the Drama of the Self (1989), draws reader-response theory into dialogue
with psychoanalytic theory of Heinz Kohut. As a result, the study focuses on narcis-
sistic characters and contributes little to the understanding of readers’ empathy. An
influence on the concerns of the present study, Judith Kegan Gardiner’s Rhys, Stead,
Lessing, and the Politics of Empathy (1989) traces thematics of empathy in three
postcolonial women writers. Gardiner gestures toward the impact of empathic rep-
resentations or intentions on readers.
52. Despite its subtitle, János László’s Cognition and Representation in Literature:
The Psychology of Literary Narratives (1999) proves an exception to the general
trend. László treats the notion of distinctive literariness with more skepticism than
his colleagues in the field.
53. Few go as far as David S. Miall in openly advocating moving “beyond inter-
pretation,” as in his lecture “Beyond Interpretation: The Cognitive Significance of
Reading” (2004).
54. Perhaps the possibility of observing beneficial results from reading mass-mar-
ket junk fiction deters professionals from designing experiments that might suggest
the redundancy of postsecondary literary education. Miall, however, is an exact-
194 Notes to Pages 87–91
ing critic of literary education as it is carried out in the United States and Canada.
He sees it as interfering with or even destroying the pleasure of reading. See his
“Empowering the Reader: Literary Response and Classroom Learning” (1996).
55. See, for instance, David S. Miall, “On the Necessity of Empirical Studies of
Literary Reading” (2000); David S. Miall and Don Kuiken, “What Is Literariness?
Three Components of Literary Reading” (1999); and David S. Miall, “Beyond the
Schema Given: Affective Comprehension of Literary Narratives” (1989).
56. See Tammy Bourg, “The Role of Emotion, Empathy, and Text Structure in
Children’s and Adults’ Narrative Text Comprehension” (1996). See also Tammy
Bourg et al., “The Effects of an Empathy-Building Strategy on 6th-graders’ Causal
Inferencing in Narrative Text Comprehension” (1993), 117–33.
57. See Norma D. Feshbach and Seymour Feshbach, “Affective Processes and
Academic Achievement” (1987).
58. Paul Ekman, Emotions Revealed (2003), 35. For David S. Miall’s speculative
treatment of the neurophysiology of literary response, see “Anticipation and Feeling
in Literary Response” (1995).
59. For experimental support of this claim, see Rolf A. Zwaan, “The Immersed
Experiencer: Toward an Embodied Theory of Language Comprehension” (2004).
60. A common view coming out of the Artificial Intelligence area of cognitive
science holds that literature enables humans to run simulations that may provoke
revisions of our models of self. See Keith Oatley, Best Laid Schemes: The Psychology of
Emotions (1992), 225–61. For experimental results substantiating aspects of Oatley’s
theories, see G. C. Chupchik, Keith Oatley, and L. Vorderer, “Emotional Effects of
Reading Excerpts from Short Stories by James Joyce” (1998).
61. David S. Miall and Don Kuiken, “Aspects of Literary Response: A New Ques-
tionnaire” (1995). Subsequently cited as LRQ.
62. On this topic, see Jonathan Rose’s magisterial The Intellectual Life of the British
Working Classes (2001). Rose details the reading habits, attitudes, and preferences
of ordinary British readers.
63. Jèmeljan Hakemulder, The Moral Laboratory: Experiments Examining the
Effects of Reading Literature on Social Perception and Moral Self-Concept (2000). See
also Jèmeljan Hakemulder, “Foregrounding and Its Effect on Readers’ Perception”
(2004), 193–96. Here Hakemulder efficiently surveys the assumptions and existing
research, conceding that few studies showing positive effects for reading literature
establish the particularity of those effects to literature or a positive correlation to
literariness.
64. Hakemulder’s own research after The Moral Laboratory contributes to the
literature on foregrounding, but his focus is on the relationship between textual
features and literary reading experiences. See his “Foregrounding and Its Effect on
Readers’ Perception” (2004).
65. The four studies examined by Hakemulder include three dissertations, two of
which focus on preschool children, a drawback he de-emphasizes.
66. See C. Daniel Batson et al. “Empathy, Attitudes, and Action” (2002), 1658–61.
While Batson regards fiction reading as the equivalent of the high empathy condi-
tion (in which subjects are instructed to engage in perspective taking), he finds that
empathic feelings are lower among those who believe the experiment’s interviewee
Jared, a heroin addict and dealer, is a fictional character (1661).
Notes to Pages 91–93 195
67. For a fantasy empathy measure that could be used to study such questions,
see Mark H. Davis, Empathy (1994), 55–58 and “Measuring Individual Differences
in Empathy: Evidence for a Multidimensional Approach” (1983), 113–26.
68. Very little empirical research has been attempted to verify the theoretical
speculations about aspects of characterization that operate in readers’ character
identification. Marisa Bortolussi and Peter Dixon’s pioneering study Psychonarratol-
ogy (2003) report their findings that character actions contribute to readers’ assess-
ments of character traits, while self-evaluations provided by the narrator (descrip-
tion) do not. However, the test stories employed first-person narrators, so narrators’
evaluations of characters in third-person fiction cannot be included in this prelimi-
nary conclusion. See Psychonarratology, 160–65.
69. For John Dewey, “esthetic emotion is native emotion transformed through
the objective material to which it has committed its development and consum-
mation.” See Art as Experience (1985), 85. E. M. Dadlez surveys the controversy
about the status of aesthetic emotions in What’s Hecuba to Him? Fictional Events and
Actual Emotions (1997), a lively area of debate. In addition to the works of Martha
Nussbaum, most recently Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (2001),
see the following: Charles Altieri, The Particulars of Rapture: An Aesthetics of the
Affects (2003); Susan L. Feagin, Reading with Feeling (1996); Patrick Colm Hogan,
“From Mind to Matter: Art, Empathy, and the Brain,” in his Cognitive Science, Litera-
ture, and the Arts (2003), 166–90; Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugum Olsen, Truth,
Fiction, and Literature: A Philosophical Perspective (1994); Alex Neill, “Fiction and the
Emotions” (1993); Keith Oatley, Best Laid Schemes (1992); Robert C. Solomon, ed.,
Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions (2004); Rei Terada,
Feeling in Theory: Emotion after “The Death of the Subject” (2001); Kendall Walton,
Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts (1990); and
L. S. Vygotsky, The Psychology of Art (1925). The recent revival of Silvan Tomkins has
enlivened the literary study of negative affects such as shame and disgust: see Shame
and Its Sisters: A Silvan Tomkins Reader (1995).
70. For a summary of major ideas about and theorists of narrative situation, see
Keen, Narrative Form (2003), 30–50. Ralf Schneider represents narrative situation
as a factor in eliciting readers’ empathy and lack of representation of inner life as
a likely inhibitor of it, in “Toward a Cognitive Theory of Literary Character: The
Dynamics of Mental-Model Construction” (2001).
71. See Robyn R. Warhol on affective responses to serial fiction in Having a Good
Cry (2003), 71–72. See also Hakemulder, The Moral Laboratory ([2000], 93, 143),
drawing on N. D. Feshbach’s observations of the effects of repetitive role taking in
“Studies of Empathic Behavior in Children” (1978).
72. Martha Nussbaum’s empathy-inducing novels are invariably long, though not
always the longest works by the authors she mentions. Writing about the reading
habits of the character David Copperfield in Dickens’s novel of that name (1849–
50), Nussbaum comments, “he remains with [books] for hours in an intense, inti-
mate, and loving relationship. As he imagines, dreams, and desires in their com-
pany, he becomes a certain sort of person.” Nussbaum believes that novels, as David
Copperfield highlights, have the effect of making readers perceive “the social world
around them with a new freshness and sympathy.” For Nussbaum, the length of the
immersion (in what Victor Nell describes as ludic reading) is a vital component of
196 Notes to Page 93
the process, permitting intensity, dreaming, and desiring that develops the reader’s
loving heart. See Martha C. Nussbaum, Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and
Literature (1990), 230–31.
73. Canonically, see Fredric Jameson, The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a
Socially Symbolic Act (1981). See also Rolf Zwaan, “Effect of Genre Expectations
on Text Comprehension” (1994), which compares readers’ behavior when pro-
cessing texts labeled as “news stories” or “narratives.” In Psychonarratology (2003),
Bortolussi and Dixon caution that research in discourse processing has focused on
broad generic distinctions rather than on narrative fiction’s subgenres (253–54).
However, a body of work on emotional responses to fictional subgenres in televi-
sion exists in the field of mass communications, as in the essays collected in Jen-
nings Bryant and Dolf Zillmann’s Responding to the Screen: Reception and Reaction
Processes (1991). Literary genre critics have been reluctant to adopt findings from
mass communications research, perhaps because audiovisual (iconic) representa-
tions are assumed to be more emotionally stimulating than the verbal representa-
tions of prose narrative fiction. This assumption, however, has not been investi-
gated systematically.
74. Feminist criticism often celebrates the power of women’s writing’s viv-
idly represented spaces and places, in tandem with identity themes, to work out
boundary-crossing potentials for connection, communication, and change. See, for
instance, Susan Stanford Friedman’s Mappings: Feminism and the Cultural Geogra-
phies of Encounter (1998).
75. See Monika Fludernik’s account of Ansgar Nünning’s remarks on empathy-
inducing functions of metanarration in “Metanarrative and Metafictional Commen-
tary: From Metadiscursivity to Metanarration and Metafiction” (2003), 39.
76. On slower pace as potentially fostering empathy, see Dolf Zillmann, “Empa-
thy: Affect from Bearing Witness to the Emotions of Others” (1991), 160–61. Zill-
mann hypothesizes that the fast pace of television news stories and dramas may
impede empathetic response. David S. Miall’s previously mentioned work on fore-
grounding and empathy in literary texts correlates a slower reading pace with
enhanced empathy.
77. See, for instance, Willie van Peer’s judgment that the notion of perspective
influencing empathy is due for a shake-up in his “Justice in Perspective” (2001).
78. Character identification is thus an example of what Marisa Bortolussi and
Peter Dixon identify as readers’ mental constructions, as opposed to textual fea-
tures (Psychonarratology 28). They systematically measure how particular readers
process specific textual features in narratives, but the experimental results bridging
disciplines of discourse processing and narrative theory are still quite scanty, and the
accuracy of Bortolussi and Dixon’s narratology has been questioned. See Nilli Dien-
gott, “Some Problems with the Concept of the Narrator in Bortolussi and Dixon’s
Psychonarratology” (2004).
79. See Peter Dixon, et al., “Literary Processing and Interpretation: Towards
Empirical Foundations” (1993).
80. See Dolf Zillman, “Mechanisms of Emotional Involvement with Drama”
(1994). Writing about identification with dramatic characters rather than narra-
tive personae, Zillman argues that the audience members’ disposition precipitates
empathic and counterempathic reactions and suggests that audiences must be made
Notes to Pages 94–95 197
to care about characters one way or another. He believes that enactment of good
or evil deeds by protagonists and antagonists, in circumstances that prompt moral
appraisal of their actions, promotes strong emotional reactions.
81. See Keith Oatley, “A Taxonomy of the Emotions of Literary Response and a
Theory of Identification in Fictional Narrative” (1994).
82. In this respect, Miall and Kuiken are in accord with earlier work that demon-
strates a relationship between a subject’s prior similar experiences and empathy felt
for another in the same situation. See Ezra Stotland, Empathy, Fantasy and Helping
(1978), 52.
83. See Miall and Kuiken, “What Is Literariness?” (1999) and Miall, “Beyond the
Schema Given” (1989).
84. See Don Kuiken et al., “Locating Self-Modifying Feelings within Literary
Reading” (2004).
85. Max Louwerse and Don Kuiken, “The Effects of Personal Involvement in
Narrative Discourse” (2004), 170. This research confirms some of what Wolfgang
Iser proposes about active reading as gap filling, in The Act of Reading: A Theory of
Aesthetic Response (1978), 168–69.
86. For good critiques of this assumption from different disciplinary bases, see
Elly A. Konijn and Johan F. Hoorn, “Reality-based Genre Preferences Do Not Direct
Personal Involvement” (2004) and Richard Walsh, “Why We Wept for Little Nell:
Character and Emotional Involvement” (1997).
87. See Edith Klemenz-Belgardt, “American Research of Response to Literature”
(1981), 368 and P. E. Jose and W. F. Brewer, “Development of Story Liking: Charac-
ter Identification, Suspense, and Outcome Resolution” (1984). In The Moral Labora-
tory, Hakemulder reports on recent studies confirming the importance of personal
relevance for intensity of reader response (71).
88. M. Wünsch (1981), cited in Hakemulder (Moral Laboratory 73).
89. G. C. Chupchik and János László, “The Landscape of Time in Literary Recep-
tion: Character Experience and Narrative Action” (1994).
90. Research into the empathy evoked by various genres of television adver-
tisements suggests that discontinuous, nonlinear “vignette” ads discourage empathy,
whereas classical, character-centered dramatic form in ads evokes viewers’ empathy.
See Barbara B. Stern, “Classical and Vignette Television Advertising Dramas: Struc-
tural Models, Formal Analysis, and Consumer Effects” (1994).
91. For a good application of cognitive theory on levels of embedding to readers’
capacity to comprehend embedded accounts of characters’ mental states, see Lisa
Zunshine, “Theory of Mind and Experimental Representations of Fictional Con-
sciousness” (2003).
92. For a subtle treatment of the variety of techniques by which sympathy for
characters may be cultivated, see Wayne C. Booth, The Rhetoric of Fiction, 2nd. ed.
(1983), 129–33, 243–66, 274–82, and 379–91. Ultimately Booth prefers the use
of an “inside view” for invoking sympathy, but he describes the full range of strate-
gies that authors from the classical period to the modernists actually employ. For
an excellent recent look at how cognitive science can revise narratological views of
representation of consciousness, see Alan Palmer, Fictional Minds (2004).
93. See David S. Miall, “Affect and Narrative: A Model of Responses to Stories”
(1988).
198 Notes to Pages 95–97
94. For the best description of how readers imaginatively construct characters,
see Steven Cohan, “Figures Beyond the Text: A Theory of Readable Character in the
Novel” (1983).
95. See Richard J. Gerrig, “The Construction of Literary Character: A View from
Cognitive Psychology” (1990). See also his account of participatory responses to
fiction in his book Experiencing Narrative Worlds: On the Psychological Activities of
Reading (1993).
96. See Patrick Colm Hogan, “The Epilogue of Suffering: Heroism, Empathy,
Ethics” (2001). Though this article suggests a preference for the cognitive role taking
Hogan associates with situational empathy, his later, very brief treatment of read-
ers’ empathy in Cognitive Science, Literature, and the Arts improves on his theory by
describing how emotion triggers invoke quick-and-dirty responses, as well as imag-
inative role taking, neither of which need be denigrated as egocentric (186–87).
Work confirming the role of lived experience in spontaneous situational empathy
with characters on film has been carried out by Barry Sapolsky and Dolf Zillmann,
“Experience and Empathy: Affective Reactions to Witnessing Childbirth” (1978).
Women who had given birth who responded to a medical film of actual childbirth
showed more intense physiological reactions; otherwise, gender and related experi-
ences had a negligible effect on empathy. Note that the film was not fictional.
97. See Hans Robert Jauss, Aesthetic Experience and Literary Hermeneutics (1982),
152–88, especially his summary figure, “Interaction Patterns of Identification with
the Hero,” 159. See also Patrick Colm Hogan on emotions and prototypes in narra-
tive, in The Mind and Its Stories: Narrative Universals and Human Emotion (2003).
98. This insight has received preliminary confirmation from studies of the effect
of point of view and voice-over in film. See Els Andringa, Q et al., “Point of View and
Viewer Empathy in Film” (2001), 154–55.
99. See the definitions of narrated monologue, psycho-narration, and quoted
monologue in Dorrit Cohn, Transparent Minds (1978), 14. Parallel terminology
exists for the representation of consciousness in first-person narration.
100. See Sylvia Adamson, “The Rise and Fall of Empathetic Narrative: A Histori-
cal Perspective on Perspective” (2001).
101. See Wayne Booth’s discussing of traditional literature’s use of “telling” in
The Rhetoric of Fiction, 3–16 and Dorrit Cohn on psycho-narration in Transparent
Minds, 46–57.
102. For a subtle exploration of the intersection between cognitive science and
narratology on this point, see Alan Palmer, Fictional Minds (2004), 49, 170–204.
103. Three good starting points for recent work on the representation of con-
sciousness include: Monika Fludernik’s magisterial The Fictions of Language and the
Languages of Fiction (1993); the essays of Lisa Zunshine, “Theory of Mind” (2003)
and “Richardson’s Clarissa and a Theory of Mind” (2004); and the phenomenological
theory of George Butte, I Know That You Know That I Know (2004).
104. See F. K. Stanzel, Narrative Situation in the Novel (1971) and A Theory of
Narrative (1984).
105. See Willie van Peer and H. Pander Maat, “Perspectivation and Sympathy:
Effects of Narrative Point of View” (1996). They designed experiments using five
versions of stories, rewritten to allow them to test the relationship between positive
internal focalization and readers’ allocation of sympathy (145).
Notes to Pages 98–103 199
106. For a thorough investigation of the issues raised here, see Monika Fludernik,
Towards a “Natural” Narratology (1996).
107. See Keen, Narrative Form, 45–47, 171.
108. Bertolussi and Dixon have done the best work on this subject, though
they phrase the question differently (Psychonarratology 166–99). They are inter-
ested in the degree to which readers fuse narrators and characters as a result of
perceptual access to a particular character’s perspective, and thus develop a root-
ing interest in that character and making assumptions about the narrator’s and
author’s gender.
Chapter 4
ing with” against charges of egoism and bolsters the case for the effects of reading
without explaining how readers actually transpose the experience of empathy for
fictional characters from a fictive context to empathy for real people in the actual
world. Philosopher Frank Palmer writes, “to be moved in the way that great art can
move us is to be put in touch with something that in a way dwarfs our own little
concerns, which is a step nearer to being sensitive to the ‘reality’ of other people. . . .
But to appreciate the ‘reality’ of another person involves not just an act of identifica-
tion with him, but a sense of his ‘otherness.’” Note how Palmer slides from respon-
siveness to art to understanding of real people (Literature and Moral Understanding
(1992), 240).
17. Lindsay Pace, survey (10 March 2004).
18. Meredith Walker, survey (10 March 2004).
19. Courtney Fitzgerald, survey (10 March 2004).
20. Paige Halter, survey (10 March 2004).
21. See Krystina A. Finlay and Walter G. Stephan, “Improving Intergroup Rela-
tions: The Effects of Empathy on Racial Attitudes” (2000). Of the students in this
experiment who read, some received realistic “scenarios” that were presented to
them as nonfictional first-person accounts of African Americans, and some read the
same accounts framed as American students’ reports about their experiences study-
ing abroad in Hong Kong. Neither manipulation changed rates of reactive empathy
associated with helping.
22. Psychologist C. Daniel Batson and his collaborators argue that empathy may
indeed spur prosocial action, but they also show that empathy can hinder justice.
See “Immorality from Empathy-Induced Altruism: When Compassion and Justice
Conflict” (1995), 1042–54.
23. Hakemulder believes that the novel excerpts’ ironic tone may have cued
literature students to the intention of the study (“Foregrounding” [2004], 206).
It is also possible that the use of short extracts, while essential for fine-grained
analysis of discourse processing, interferes with the study of the effects of read-
ing long works that ordinarily invite hours and hours of involved reading. Since
the grandest claims for fictions’ beneficial role in society inevitably refer to long
novels, it would make sense to devise ways of studying them as they are actual-
ly read.
24. Research on television-viewing habits shows that empathy with characters of
comedies and dramas increases the likelihood of watching reruns. See P. H. Tannen-
baum, “Entertainment as Vicarious Emotional Experience” (1980).
25. See Skaliotis (2002), cited in Wim Knulst and Andries van den Broek, “The
Readership of Books in Times of De-Reading” (2003), 233. Exceptionally, Knulst
and van den Broek examine the relative popularity of different genres of reading,
using data on Dutch readers. As I have already shown, most of the theorizing and
empirical research on effects of reading has focused on literary fiction and has set
aside the effects of a diet of subliterary kinds of mass-market fiction.
26. This has not always been the case. In the past, middlebrow reading marked
individuals as aspirant middle-class professionals. See Janice Radway, A Feeling for
Books (1997), 221–60.
27. For the most up-to-date statistics, see Book Retailing—US (2004). In the U.K.,
the percentage of books bought by women is slightly lower than in the U.S. but
202 Notes to Pages 110–21
still accounts for 65 percent or more of consumer book purchases. See Bookselling
(2004), tables 18, 19, 20. For summary European data, see Publishing Market Watch.
Sectoral Report 2: Book Publishing (2004), 9.
28. Online excerpted transcript, “A Fine Balance Discussion,” Oprah’s Book Club
(accessed 15 February 2002). Currently accessible at http://www.oprah.com/obc/
pastbooks/rohinton_mistry/obc_20020124_discussion.jhtml.
29. Seventy-three percent of Oprah’s books were written by women. She selected
books by ten men between 1996 and 2002. Her new book club reverses this trend,
with Steinbeck, Paton, Garcia Marquez, and Tolstoy outnumbering McCullers and
Pearl S. Buck.
30. Winfrey recently included Alan Paton’s Cry the Beloved Country in her new
club’s selections.
31. See the discussion of the vogue for “Commonwealth” authors in Elizabeth
Long, Book Clubs (2003).
32. Salil, SASIALIST listserv discussion group (accessed 2 April 1998).
33. Chandra, SASIALIST listserv discussion group (accessed 3 April 1998).
34. This is neither a callow nor an abnormal response. See Kuiken et al., “Forms
of Self-Implication,” in which the authors argue that the “search for concepts that
potentially subsume narrative particulars will sometimes involve self-relevant con-
cepts, especially those that represent personal strivings” (177).
35. Rooney sees this pattern of response as debasing and oversimplifying the
literary texts, but she also admires Winfrey for establishing “practical protocols”
for reading that have contributed to the enlargement of the audience for fiction
(Oprah xii).
36. On Winfrey’s emphasis on empathetic reading practices, juxtaposed to “more
reflective” habits, see Farr, Reading Oprah, 61. Farr embraces the social function of
the novel as a genre and admires Winfrey’s way of integrating fiction into readers’
“talking life,” a phrase borrowed from Toni Morrison (Reading Oprah 45–51, 60).
37. Though it would be interesting to study changes in attitude toward bullying
or rule breaking, in groups of Harry Potter readers.
38. See B. Latane and J. M. Darley, The Unresponsive Bystander—Why Doesn’t
He Help? (1970). This famous research was spurred by the 1964 murder of Kitty
Genovese, in which dozens of people within earshot of the victim’s cries failed to
intervene. See Darley’s recent summary of three decades’ worth of work in this field,
in “Bystander Phenomena” (2000), 493–95.
39. These numbers add up to 118 percent because I tallied emotion, understand-
ing, and moralizing separately. Eighteen percent of responses mentioned both emo-
tional intensity and improved understanding.
Chapter 5
1. What novelists hope to do in writing fiction has not, of course, remained con-
sistent over the centuries, nor do writers of a single tradition or generation agree
in their aims. Though subjected to criticism for decades since they put it forth in
1946 in the Sewanee Review, Wimsatt and Beardsley’s “intentional fallacy” (which
sought to move the literary critic’s role toward evaluation and away from subjec-
Notes to Pages 122–32 203
tive response) has never been completely dislodged. While I concur that scrutiny of
texts must be literary critics’ first task, that much of an author’s intentions cannot
be recovered, and also that authors often do more in texts than they can explain or
understand, my perspective as a narrative theorist leads me to believe that writers
craft narratives using tools in order to accomplish ends that they can, and often do,
articulate.
2. Though once again I draw upon my experience as a teacher of fiction in making
this generalization, see for documented cases the Amazon.com’s readers’ reviews of
The Handmaid’s Tale.
3. See “Envisioning the Past,” in Keen, Romances of the Archive in Contemporary
British Fiction (2001), for the romance of the archive’s cultivation of the sympa-
thetic historical imagination (181–207).
4. Smiley defines empathy cognitively, as “perceiving with” or “seeing through” a
character (13 Ways [2005], 76, 118), but despite her disavowal of the affective com-
ponent of empathy, she argues that “the novel has made a world in which people are
fairly adept at both feeling and thinking, and at thinking about feeling” (176).
5. “High fantasizers,” or individuals who score high on a Fantasy-Empathy scale,
tend to assume that people in general are more altruistic than low scorers assume.
See Ezra Stotland et al., Empathy, Fantasy and Helping (1978), 88–9, 107. If novelists
are likely to score as high fantasizers, then they may also be prone to believe in the
power of empathy because they positively estimate the altruism of others.
6. See, for example, Caro Clarke, ed., “Writing Advice,” http://www.caroclarke.
com/ (accessed 10 February 2005).
7. Anti-Defamation League press release, “Q and A on the Turner Diaries” (16
May 1996) http://www.adl.org/PresRele/Militi_71/2737_71.asp (accessed 22 Feb-
ruary 2005).
8. Nancy Eisenberg argues that “it is more often cognitively-based processes like
perspective taking, and, to a lesser degree, empathy, that can be devoted to socially
undesirable ends.” These readers might share the perspective or feel with Pierce’s
protagonist. However, according to Eisenberg, “one would seldom expect sympathy
to be related to undesirable ends.” Personal correspondence with the author.
9. F. R. Conway, Amazon.com review of The Turner Diaries (posted 6 March
2002).
10. The twenty-eight-item Bernstein and Putnam’s Dissociative Experiences
Scale (DES) asks subjects to rate the percentage of time they spend having fantasies
and daydreams (absorption) and the frequency of their gaps in episodic memory
(amnesia) and experiences of derealization and depersonalization.
11. Leslie Marmon Silko, interviewed on In Search of the Novel, http://www
.learner.org/channel/workshops/isonovel/Pages/subpage7.html (accessed 14 Febru-
ary 2005).
12. Arthur Golden, interviewed on In Search of the Novel, http://www.learner.org/
channel/workshops/isonovel/Pages/subpage7.html (accessed 14 February 2005).
13. J. K. Rowling, interviewed on In Search of the Novel, http://www.learner.org/
channel/workshops/isonovel/Pages/subpage7.html (accessed 15 February 2005).
14. The first edition of this novel (Spiral, 1983) is so scarce that I provide instead
page number references to the most widely disseminated version, the 1986 Penguin
paperback.
204 Notes to Pages 132–39
15. See, for instance, Mary Ann Hughes, “Transgressing Boundaries” (1994).
Hughes argues that Hulme “chooses to upset our idea of corporeal boundaries in her
ambivalent attitude to violence with The Bone People. While the assaults upon Simon
are deplored and regretted, they are also glorified as the transgression of the bound-
ary between internal and external, spiritual and material, one human and another”
(“Transgressing” 57).
16. Stead faults the prize more than the winner. See C. K. Stead, “Keri Hulme’s
The Bone People and the Pegasus Award for Maori Literature” (1985). See also Mar-
gery Fee’s rejoinder, “Why C. K. Stead Didn’t Like Keri Hulme’s the bone people:
Who Can Write as Other?” (1989).
17. Ato Quayson notices the novel’s discursive nervousness but attributes that
to Hulme’s unresolved feelings about disabilities. Though Quayson describes the
scene of beating, he misses Kerewin’s clear judgment of Joe, or perhaps he forgets
it, because it is not the negative judgment his argument would predict. This critical
aversion from the novel’s statements bespeaks the exquisite difficulty of facing the
implications of Hulme’s representation. See Ato Quayson, “Looking Awry: Tropes of
Disability in Post-colonial Writing” (1999).
18. See, for instance, Philip Armstrong’s nuanced article, “Good Eating: Ethics and
Biculturalism in Reading “The Bone People” (2001) and Gay Wilentz, “Instruments of
Change: Healing Cultural Dis-ease in Keri Hulme’s the bone people” (1995).
19. On empathic accuracy, see the research reported in William Ickes, ed.,
Empathic Accuracy (1997).
20. See Suzette A. Spencer, “Shall We Gather at the River? Ritual, Benign Forms
of Injury, and the Wounds of Displaced Women in Opal Palmer Adisa’s It Begins with
Tears” (2001).
21. Opal Palmer Adisa, interviewed by Suzette A. Spencer (quoted in Spencer’s
“Shall We Gather at the River?” 108). See also Opal Palmer Adisa, “A Writer/Healer:
Literature, a Blueprint for Healing” (2001).
22. The most neutral term currently in favor, Female Genital Cutting (FGC),
describes a range of practices from reduction of the clitoris to the removal of parts
of the labia (infibulation). Amnesty International sticks with Female Genital Muti-
lation (FGM) in order to emphasize its decision to treat these practices as torture
and as human rights violations. Terms used by those who wish to indicate respect
for cultural practices include female circumcision and excision. Nwapa’s term “bath”
emphasizes FGC’s role in a purification ritual.
23. Nwapa does not specify which form of circumcision is performed, but it
seems likely from the geographical and cultural locations, as well as from the later
narration of childbirth, that Efuru has undergone excision of her clitoris rather than
the more radical infibulation. See U. Megafu, “Female Ritual Circumcision in Africa:
An Investigation of the Presumed Benefits among Ibos of Nigeria” (1983).
24. A later novelist, Buchi Emecheta, takes up Nwapa’s phrase, “the joys of moth-
erhood,” and gives it a darkly ironic reworking in her novel of that name.
25. See the summary, “Female Genital Cutting,” at http://www.4woman.gov/
faq/fgc.htm#11 (accessed 8 March 2005). The U.K., several European nations, and
indeed some African countries have similar laws. Whether they can be enforced is
another matter.
Notes to Pages 139–48 205
26. For an exploration of insider and outsider views of the practice, see Ellen
Gruenbaum, The Female Circumcision Controversy: An Anthropological Perspective
(2001).
27. See Isabelle R. Gunning, “Uneasy Alliances and Solid Sisterhood: A Response
to Professor Obiora’s Bridges and Barricades” (1997). Gunning reports that “it is not
an accident that it is [Walker’s] work that has been frequently identified as having
elevated the surgeries in the popular consciousness of Western feminists; African
activists whose concern and activity preceded Walker’s were not heard” (452–53).
See also Elisabeth Bekers, “Daughters of Africa W/Riting Change: Female Genital
Excision in Two African Short-Stories and in Alice Walker’s Possessing the Secret of
Joy” (1999), in which Bekers argues that Walker creates “the impression that African
women are not able to fight their battles completely by themselves” (267).
28. Micere Githae Mugo, “Elitist Ant-Circumcision Discourse as Mutilating and
Anti-Feminist” (1997). Mugo criticizes Walker for her depiction of Africa as “con-
descending and touristic,” arguing that Walker’s “philosophical outlook is informed
by colonial and missionary conceptions of Africa” and that Walker’s denunciation of
female genital cutting silences and vilifies the victims of the practice (464).
29. On the external messiah syndrome exemplified by Alice Walker, see L. Amede
Obiora, “The Issue of Female Circumcision: Bridges and Barricades, Rethinking
Polemics and Intransigence in the Campaign against Female Circumcision” (1997).
Chapter 6
1. See, for instance, the teaching anthology edited by Peter and Renata Singer, The
Moral of the Story: An Anthology of Ethics Through Literature (2005).
2. See Jonathan Rose, The Intellectual Life of the British Working Classes (2001),
76. Solitary reading and private study were distrusted, Rose discovers, as “selfish and
unneighborly” (86).
3. See Philip Gourevitch, who not only writes of the hard-hearted responses to
the pleas of Rwandan victims, but also offers an explanation: “Genocide, after all, is
an exercise in community building.” We Wish to Inform You That Tomorrow We Will
Be Killed with Our Families (1998), 95. See also Batson, “Empathy-Induced Altru-
ism” (2004) on the limitations of empathy in dealing with large-scale problems of
long duration (372–73).
4. Indeed, human rights are not exempted from criticism. Some regard “the
whole idea of ‘universal’ human rights” as a “gigantic fraud, where Western imperial-
ist or excolonial powers try to pass off their own, very specific and localized idea of
what ‘rights’ should be as universal, trampling roughly over everyone elses’s beliefs
and traditions.” See Stephen Howe, Empire: A Very Short Introduction (2002), 3. For
a good starting point on this debate, see Mary Williams’s collection, Human Rights:
Opposing Viewpoints (1998).
5. See 3–4 above for the distinction between personal distress, a nonmoral emo-
tional reaction that is not likely to lead to prosocial behavior, and empathy (or
sympathy). See Nancy Eisenberg, “Emotion, Regulation, and Moral Development”
(2000) for a review of the current research on the role of emotion in morality.
206 Notes to Pages 148–59
6. On this point, see also Patricia Melzer, “‘All that you touch you change’”
(2002), 45.
7. See also Peter G. Stillman, “Dystopian Critiques, Utopian Possibilities, and
Human Purposes in Octavia Butler’s Parables” (2003), 23.
8. On Parable of the Sower as slave narrative, see Raffaela Baccollini, “Gender and
Genre in the Feminist Critical Dystopias of Katharine Burdekin, Margaret Atwood,
and Octavia Butler” (2000); on race, see Jerry Phillips, “The Intuition of the Future:
Utopia and Catastrophe in Octavia Butler’s Parable of the Sower” (2002).
9. See Samuel and Pearl Oliner, The Altruistic Personality (1988), 188 and Goure-
vitch’s account of failed appeals from genocide victims in We Wish to Inform You
(1998), 42–43, 135, 141–42. Butler would probably concur with Richard Delgado’s
character Roderigo’s assessment that empathy for racial minorities is on the decline
(Coming Race War? 8). She depicts mixed race and minority characters as especially
vulnerable to persecution, robbery, rape, and murder.
10. For extrapolation of these views, see Charles Rowell’s interview with Butler,
“An Interview with Octavia E. Butler” (1997), 47–66.
11. See, for examples, Tom Le Clair, “The Sri Lankan Patients” (2000), 31 and the
unsigned review “Brrr!” (2000), 14.
12. Among the finest articles are those by Teresa Derrickson, on the narratives of
justice that global human rights discourse produces and Ondaatje’s oblique inter-
vention in the debate about globalization; and Antoinette Burton, on the evidence
of bones in the archives of twentieth-century violence. See Teresa Derrickson, “Will
the ‘Un-Truth’ Set You Free? A Critical Look at Global Human Rights Discourse in
Michael Ondaatje’s Anil’s Ghost” (2004) and Antoinette Burton, “Archive of Bones:
Anil’s Ghost and the Ends of History” (2004).
13. Novel readers in this case include my college-aged students and a group of
mature readers with whom I discussed Anil’s Ghost at the Rockbridge Regional
Library, Lexington, Virginia, in 2001. See also the reviews posted by readers at Ama-
zon.com.
14. For a list of the qualities that define the subgenre of archival research quests,
see Keen, Romances of the Archive (2001), 35. For the role of empathy in realistic
narratives of archival research, see 183–207.
15. Surveying the recent studies, Nancy Eisenberg concludes that a “real, albeit
sometimes modest” relation between situational sympathetic concern and proso-
cial responses exists in children. The leap between the original empathetic response
and sympathy does not invariably occur if, for instance, personal distress provokes
an aversive emotional state rather than an other-oriented emotion. See Eisenberg,
“Emotion, Regulation, and Moral Development,” 671–73.
16. In social psychology, this problem is investigated under the term moral dis-
engagement, by which people take restraints and self-judgments offline. Deficient
empathy explains inhumanity more widespread than can be explained by the exis-
tence of sociopaths. See Albert Bandura, “Moral Disengagement in the Perpetuation
of Inhumanities” (1999) and “Reflexive Empathy: On Predicting More Than Has
Ever Been Observed” (2002).
17. These critics assume that empathy will be inaccurate and that misunder-
standing and harm will result from the misunderstanding. Psychologists who work
on empathic accuracy agree that incorrect empathetic assessments can have bad
Notes to Pages 160–65 207
results in human relations and communication, but they emphasize the relative rar-
ity of failures of empathy. For my discussion of what I term empathic inaccuracy, see
136–41 above.
18. The reverse statement of this gender determinism praises females for their
empathy while noticing the dominating habits of males.
19. See, for instance, Lila Abu-Lughod and Catherine A. Lutz, “Introduction:
Emotion, Discourse, and the Politics of Everyday Life” (1990). For a survey of recent
cross-cultural work on the emotions, see David Matsumoto, “Culture and Emotion”
(2001).
20. See, for instance, the text of the United Nations’ Universal Declaration of
Human Rights (1948) at the UN’s Web site, http://www.un.org/Overview/rights
.html (accessed 5 May 2005); on human capabilities, see Amartya Sen, Inequality
Reexamined (1992).
21. Developmental psychologists, as we have earlier seen, regard empathy as a
faculty that develops in individuals over time, from simple emotional contagion
to mature sympathy. Some thus criticize as mechanistic the overemphasis on neu-
roanatomical explanations of empathy. See, for example, Phillipe Rochat, “Various
Kinds of Empathy as Revealed by the Developing Child, Not the Monkey’s Brain”
(2002).
22. One recent study of advertising shows that “other-focused” appeals lead to
more favorable attitudes in members of individualist cultures, while “ego-focused”
appeals garner better responses from members of collectivist cultures (based on
a comparison of the responses of American and Chinese students). See Jennifer
L. Aaker and Patti Williams, “Empathy Versus Pride: The Influence of Emotional
Appeals across Cultures” (1998).
23. See Patrick Colm Hogan, The Mind and Its Stories (2003), 46, 66, 74–75, 81.
24. See Patrick Colm Hogan, “Stories and Morals: Emotion, Cognitive Exempla,
and the Arabic Aristotelians” (2004), 43.
25. Absolute universals need not recur in all works, but in all traditions; statistical
universals occur across traditions with greater frequency than chance alone predicts
(Hogan, Mind and Its Stories 19).
26. On mahakaruna, or great compassion, see Hammalawa Saddhatissa, Buddhist
Ethics (1997) 27–29, 136–37.
27. For an array of views and subtle interrogations of compassion, see Laren Ber-
lant, ed., Compassion: The Culture and Politics of an Emotion (2004).
28. Often, in recent years, disapprovingly. A typical strong case against what
Hogan calls categorical identity and empathy appears in Audrey Jaffe, Scenes of Sym-
pathy (2000), 22.
29. See I. A. Richards’s gloss in Mencius on the Mind: Experiments in Multiple Defi-
nition (1932), 20.
30. On the imperatives of warm, agent-based virtue ethics regarding the treat-
ments of others, including sentient nonhumans such as dolphins and chimpanzees,
see Slote, Morals from Motives (2001), 37. Slote writes, “If we assume that human
beings have a basic capacity for empathy and sympathy with others (an assumption
the moral sentimentalists tended to make . . . ), then making someone vividly aware
of the effects of certain kinds of actions (or attitudes) on people’s welfare can change
the way that person feels about those actions (or attitudes) and make a difference, for
208 Notes to Page 166
good, to her act-effecting motives.” On caring, see in addition to Slote, Nel Noddings,
Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education (1984).
31. On the limitations of reading alone, see Darcia Narvaez, “Does Reading Moral
Stories Build Moral Character” (2002). Narvaez finds that children do not predict-
ably understand the themes of moral stories as intended by the author (or by the
adult presenting them).
WORKS CITED
Aaker, Jennifer L., and Patti Williams. “Empathy Versus Pride: The Influence of Emo-
tional Appeals across Cultures.” Journal of Consumer Research 25, 3 (December
1998): 241–61.
Abu-Lughod, Lila, and Catherine A. Lutz. “Introduction: Emotion, Discourse, and
the Politics of Everyday Life.” Language and the Politics of Emotion. Ed. Cath-
erine A. Lutz and Lila Abu-Lughod. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1990. 1–23.
Achebe, Chinua. Morning Yet on Creation Day. London: Heinemann, 1975.
Ackroyd, Peter. Dickens. London: Sinclair Stevenson, 1990.
Adamson, Sylvia. “The Rise and Fall of Empathetic Narrative: A Historical Perspec-
tive on Perspective.” New Perspectives on Narrative Perspective. Ed. Willie van
Peer and Seymour Chatman. Albany: SUNY Press, 2001. 83–99.
Adisa, Opal Palmer. It Begins with Tears. London: Heinemann, 1997.
———. “She Scrape She Knee.” Caribbean Women Writers: Essays from the First
International Conference. Ed. Selwyn R. Cudjoe. Wellesley, MA: Calaloux, 1990.
145–50.
———. “A Writer/Healer: Literature, a Blueprint for Healing.” Healing Cultures:
Art and Religion as Curative Practices in the Caribbean and Its Diaspora. Ed.
Margarite Fernández Olmos and Lizabeth Paravisini-Gebert. London: Palgrave,
2001. 179–93.
Aiken, Anna Laetitia. “An Enquiry into Those Kinds of Distress Which Excite Agree-
able Sensations.” 1773. Rpt. Novel and Romance 1700–1800: A Documentary
Record. Ed. Ioan Williams. New York: Barnes and Noble 1970. 289.
Ainslie, George, and John Monterosso. “Hyperbolic Discounting Lets Empathy Be
a Motivated Process.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25, 1 (February 2002):
20–21.
Ainsworth, William Harrison. Jack Sheppard. London, 1839.
Altick, Richard D. The Presence of the Present: Topics of the Day in the Victorian Novel.
Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1991.
Altieri, Charles. The Particulars of Rapture: An Aesthetics of the Affects. Ithaca and
London: Cornell University Press, 2003.
Anand, Mulk Raj. Untouchable. 1935. London and New York: Penguin, 1986.
Anderson, Benedict. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of
Nationalism. London: Verso, 1983.
210 Works Cited
Andringa, Els. “The Interface between Fiction and Life: Patterns of Identification in
Reading Autobiographies.” Poetics Today 25, 2 (Summer 2004): 205–40.
Andringa, Els, et al. “Point of View and Viewer Empathy in Film.” New Perspectives
on Narrative Perspective. Ed. Willie van Peer and Seymour Chatman. Albany:
SUNY Press, 2001. 133–57.
Anti-Defamation League. “Q and A on the Turner Diaries.” (16 May 1996) http://
www.adl.org/PresRele/Militi_71/2737_71.asp. Accessed 22 February 2005.
Aristotle. Rhetoric. Trans. George A. Kennedy. Oxford and New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1991.
Armstrong, Isobel. The Radical Aesthetic. Oxford: Blackwell, 2000.
Armstrong, Paul B. Play and the Politics of Reading: The Social Uses of Modernist Form.
Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2005.
Armstrong, Philip. “Good Eating: Ethics and Biculturalism in Reading ‘The Bone Peo-
ple.’” Ariel 32, 2 (April 2001): 7–27.
Ashcroft, Bill, Gareth Griffiths, and Helen Tiffin. Key Concepts in Post-Colonial Stud-
ies. London and New York: Routledge, 1998.
Attwood, Tony. Asperger’s Syndrome: A Guide for Parents and Professionals. London
and New York: Jessica Kingsley, 1998.
Atwood, Margaret. The Handmaid’s Tale. Toronto: McClelland and Stewart, 1985.
Baccollini, Raffaela. “Gender and Genre in the Feminist Critical Dystopias of Katha-
rine Burdekin, Margaret Atwood, and Octavia Butler.” Future Females, the Next
Generation: New Voices and Velocities in Feminist Science Fiction Criticism. Ed.
Marleen S. Barr. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2000. 13–34.
Bandura, Albert. “Moral Disengagement in the Perpetuation of Inhumanities.” Per-
sonality and Social Psychology Review 3 (1999): 193–209.
———. “Reflexive Empathy: On Predicting More Than Has Ever Been Observed.”
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25, 1 (February 2002): 24–25.
Baron-Cohen, Simon. The Essential Difference: The Truth about the Male and Female
Brains. New York: Basic Books, 2003.
Barthes, Roland. “Introduction to the Structural Analysis of Narratives.” Trans. Ste-
phen Heath. Image-Music-Text. New York: Hill and Wang, 1977. 79–124.
———. The Pleasure of the Text. 1973. Trans. Richard Miller. New York: Hill and
Wang, 1975.
Bate, Walter Jackson. “The Sympathetic Imagination in Eighteenth-Century Criti-
cism.” Journal of English Literary History 12 (1945): 144–64.
The Altruism Question: Toward a Social-Psychological Answer. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum,
1991.
Batson, C. Daniel. “Altruism and Prosocial Behavior.” The Handbook of Social Psychol-
ogy. Ed. D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, and G. Lindzey. v. 2. New York: McGraw-Hill,
1998. 282–316.
———. The Altruism Question: Toward a Social-Psychological Answer. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum, 1991.
Batson, C. Daniel, et al. “Benefits and Liabilities of Empathy-Induced Altruism.” The
Social Psychology of Good and Evil. Ed. Arthur G. Miller. New York and London:
Guilford Press, 2004. 359–85.
———. “Empathic Joy and the Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis” Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology 61, 3 (September 1991): 413–26.
Works Cited 211
———. The Rhetoric of Fiction, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983.
Bortolussi, Marisa, and Peter Dixon. Psychonarratology: Foundations for the Empirical
Study of Literary Response. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2003.
Bourg, Tammy. “The Role of Emotion, Empathy, and Text Structure in Children’s
and Adults’ Narrative Text Comprehension.” Empirical Approaches to Litera-
ture and Aesthetics. Ed. Roger J. Kreuz and Mary Sue MacNealy. Norwood, NJ:
Ablex, 1996. 241–60.
Bourg, Tammy, et al. “The Effects of an Empathy-Building Strategy on 6th-grad-
ers’ Causal Inferencing in Narrative Text Comprehension.” Poetics 22 (1993):
117–33.
Bouson, J. Brooks. The Empathic Reader: A Study of the Narcissistic Character and the
Drama of the Self. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1989.
Bowen, Elizabeth. The Collected Stories of Elizabeth Bowen. New York: Ecco Press,
1981.
Brecht, Bertolt. “Alienation Effects in Chinese Acting.” Brecht on Theatre: The Develop-
ment of an Aesthetic. Ed. John Willett. New York: Hill and Wang, 1964. 91–99.
———. “Conversation with Bert Brecht.” Brecht on Theatre: The Development of an
Aesthetic. Ed. John Willett. New York: Hill and Wang, 1964. 14–17.
———. “Short Description of a New Technique of Acting.” Brecht on Theatre: The
Development of an Aesthetic. Ed. John Willett. New York: Hill and Wang, 1964.
141–47.
———. “A Short Organum for the Theatre.” Brecht on Theatre: The Development of an
Aesthetic. Ed. John Willett. New York: Hill and Wang, 1964. 179–205.
Brennan, Bonnie. “Bridging the Backlash: A Cultural Material Reading of The Bridges
of Madison County.” Studies in Popular Culture 19, 1 (1996): 59–78.
Brewer, W. F., and K. Ohtsuka. “Story Structure, Characterization, Just World Orga-
nization, and Reader Affect in American and Hungarian Short Stories.” Poetics
17 (1988): 395–415.
Brisbin, C. D. “An Experimental Application of the Galvanic Skin Response to the
Measurement of Effects of Literature on Attitudes of Fifth Grade Students
towards Blacks.” Dissertation. Wayne State University Press, 1971.
Brontë, Charlotte. Jane Eyre. London, 1847.
Brothers, Leslie. “A Biological Perspective on Empathy.” American Journal of Psychia-
try 146, 1 (1989): 10–19.
———. Friday’s Footprint: How Society Shapes the Human Mind. Oxford and New
York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
“Brrrr!” Review of Michael Ondaatje’s Anil’s Ghost. The Economist (17 June
2000), 14.
Bryant, Jennings, and Dolf Zillmann. Responding to the Screen: Reception and Reaction
Processes. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1991.
Burke, Edmund. A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime
and Beautiful. 1757. Ed. Adam Phillips. Oxford and New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1990.
Burnett, Frances Hodgson. The Secret Garden. London: Heinemann, 1911.
Burton, Antoinette. “Archive of Bones: Anil’s Ghost and the Ends of History.” The
Journal of Commonwealth Literature 39, 1 (March 2004): 39–56.
Works Cited 213
Cohan, Steven. “Figures beyond the Text: A Theory of Readable Character in the
Novel.” Novel: A Forum on Fiction 17, 1 (1983): 5–27.
Cohn, Dorrit. Transparent Minds: Narrative Modes for Presenting Consciousness in
Fiction. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978.
Coleridge, Samuel Taylor. Biographia Literaria. Vol. 7, Collected Works of Samuel Tay-
lor Coleridge. Ed. James Engell and Walter Jackson Bate. Routledge and Princ-
eton: Princeton University Press, 1983.
———. Lectures 1795 on Politics and Religion. Vol. 1, Collected Works of Samuel Tay-
lor Coleridge. Ed. Lewis Patton and Peter Mann. London: Routledge; Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1971.
———. The Watchman. Vol. 2,. Collected Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge. Ed. Lewis
Patton. London: Routledge; Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970.
Collins, Wilkie. No Name. 1862. Ed. Virginia Blain. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press, 1998.
Conrad, Joseph. A Personal Record and the Shadow Line: A Confession. Malay Edi-
tion. New York: Doubleday, 1928.
Cooke, David J., et al. Psychopathy: Theory, Research and Implications for Society. Dor-
drecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic, 1998.
Cosmides, Leda, and John Tooby. “Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange.” The
Adapted Mind. Ed. J. Barkow, Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby. Oxford and New
York: Oxford University Press, 1992. 163–228.
———. “Does Beauty Build Adapted Minds? Toward an Evolutionary Theory of
Aesthetics, Fiction and the Arts.” SubStance 30, 1–2 (2001): 6–27.
———. “Evolutionary Psychology and the Emotions.” Handbook of Emotions. 2nd
ed. Ed. Michael Lewis and Jeanette M. Haviland-Jones. New York and London:
Guilford Press, 2000. 91–115.
Covey, Stephen R. The 7 Habits of Highly Effective People: Powerful Lessons in Personal
Change. New York: Free Press, 1990.
Craig, K. D. “Physiological Arousal as a Function of Imagined, Vicarious, and Direct
Stress Experiences.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 73 (1968): 513–20.
Cunningham, Michael. The Hours. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1998.
Dadlez, E. M. What’s Hecuba to Him? Fictional Events and Actual Emotions. Univer-
sity Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997.
Damasio, Antonio R. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New
York: Putnam, 1994.
———. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Conscious-
ness. San Diego and London: Harcourt, 1999.
———. Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow and the Feeling Brain. Orlando and London:
Harcourt, 2003.
Damasio, Antonio R., et al. “Somatic Markers and the Guidance of Behavior: Theory
and Preliminary Testing.” Frontal Lobe Function and Dysfunction. Ed. H. S. Levin,
H. M. Eisenberg, and A. L. Benton. Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press, 1991. 217–29.
Dangarembga, Tsitsi. Nervous Conditions. 1988. Rpt. Seattle: Seal Press, 1989.
Darley, J. M. “Bystander Phenomena.” Encyclopedia of Psychology. Vol. 1 Ed. Alan
Kazden. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 2000. 493–
495.
Works Cited 215
Darnton, Robert. The Great Cat Massacre and Other Episodes of French Cultural His-
tory. New York: Basic Books, 1984. 215–56.
Darwin, Charles. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. 1872. Ed. Paul
Ekman. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Davies, Stevie. Impassioned Clay. London: Women’s Press, 1999.
Davis, Mark H. Empathy: A Social Psychological Approach. Boulder: Westview, 1994.
———. “Measuring Individual Differences in Empathy: Evidence for a Multidi-
mensional Approach.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 44 (1983):
113–26.
———. “A Multidimensional Approach to Individual Differences in Empathy.” JSAS
Catalog of Selected Documents in Psychology, 10 (1980): 85.
Davis, Mark H., et al. “The Heritability of Characteristics Associated with Disposi-
tional Empathy.” Journal of Personality 62 (September 1994): 369–91.
Deigh, John. “Empathy and Universalizability.” Ethics 105, 4 (July 1995): 743–63.
Deitz, S., et al. “Measurement of Empathy toward Rape Victims and Rapists.” Jour-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology 43 (1982): 372–84.
Defoe, Daniel. Robinson Crusoe. London: 1719.
Delgado, Richard. The Coming Race War? And Other Apocalyptic Tales of America
after Affirmative Action and Welfare. New York: New York University Press,
1996.
DeLillo, Don. Libra. New York: Viking, 1988.
Derrickson, Teresa. “Will the ‘Un-Truth’ Set You Free? A Critical Look at Global
Human Rights Discourse in Michael Ondaatje’s Anil’s Ghost.” Literature Inter-
pretation Theory 15 (2004): 131–52.
Desai, Anita. Fire on the Mountain. London: Heinemann, 1977.
de Sousa, Ronald. The Rationality of the Emotions. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987.
Dewey, John. Art as Experience. The Later Works. Vol. 10. Ed. Jo Ann Boydston. Car-
bondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1985.
Dick, Philip K. Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep? New York: Doubleday, 1968.
Dickens, Charles. Dombey and Son. London: 1848.
———. Nicholas Nickelby. London: 1839.
———. Oliver Twist. London: 1837–38.
Diengott, Nilli. “Some Problems with the Concept of the Narrator in Bortolussi and
Dixon’s Psychonarratology.” Narrative (October 2004): 306–16.
Disraeli, Benjamin. Coningsby. London: 1844.
——. Sybil. London: 1845.
Dissanayake, Ellen. Homo Aestheticus: Where Art Comes From and Why. New York:
Free Press, 1992.
Dixon, Peter, et al. “Literary Processing and Interpretation: Towards Empirical Foun-
dations.” Poetics 22 (1993): 5–33.
Donnelly, Daria. “Studies Abroad.” Commonweal (23 April 2004): 22–24.
Dovidio, John F., et al, “Specificity of Empathy-Induced Helping: Evidence for
Altruistic Motivation.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59, 2 (August
1990): 249–60.
Duan, Changming, and Clara E. Hill. “The Current State of Empathy Research.”
Journal of Counseling Psychology 43, 3 (July 1996): 261–74.
Duane, Diane. A Wizard Alone. New York: Harcourt, 2002.
216 Works Cited
Ellis, Markman. The Politics of Sensibility: Race, Gender, and Commerce in the Senti-
mental Novel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Ellison, Julie. Cato’s Tears and the Making of Anglo-American Emotion. Chicago: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, 1999.
Elster, Jon. Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions. Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1999.
Esrock, Ellen J. The Reader’s Eye: Visual Imaging as Reader Response. Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1994.
Evans, Dylan. Emotions: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press, 2001.
Eysenck, H. J., and S. B. G. Eysenck. “Impulsiveness-Venturesomeness-Empathy
Scale.” Manual of the Eysenck Personality Scales (EPS adult). Rev. ed. Hodder
and Stoughton, 1996.
Farr, Cecilia Konchar. Reading Oprah: How Oprah’s Book Club Changed the Way
America Reads. Albany: SUNY Press, 2005.
Feagin, Susan L. “Imagining Emotions and Appreciating Fiction.” Emotion and the
Arts. Ed. Mette Hjort and Sue Laver. New York and Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1997. 50–62.
———. Reading with Feeling: The Aesthetics of Appreciation. Ithaca and London: Cor-
nell University Press, 1996.
Fee, Margery.“Why C. K. Stead Didn’t Like Keri Hulme’s the bone people: Who Can
Write as Other?” Australian and New Zealand Studies in Canada 1 (1989):
11–32.
“Female Genital Cutting.” Department of Health and Human Services’ National
Women’s Health Information Center. http://www.4woman.gov/faq/fgc.htm#11.
Accessed 8 March 2005.
Feshbach, Norma D. “Studies of Empathic Behavior in Children.” Progress in Experi-
mental Personality Research. Vol. 8. Ed. Brendan A. Maher. New York: Academic
Press, 1978. 1–47.
Feshbach, Norma D., and Seymour Feshbach. “Affective Processes and Academic
Achievement.” Child Development 58, 5 (1987): 1335–47.
Finlay, Krystina A., and Walter G. Stephan. “Improving Intergroup Relations: The
Effects of Empathy on Racial Attitudes.” Journal of Applied Social Psychology 30,
8 (2000): 1720–37.
Fish, Stanley. “Literature in the Reader: Affective Stylistics.” New Literary History 2,
1 (1970), 123–62.
Fludernik, Monika. The Fictions of Language and the Languages of Fiction. London and
New York: Routledge, 1993.
———. “Metanarrative and Metafictional Commentary: From Metadiscursivity to
Metanarration and Metafiction.” Poetica 35 (2003): 1–39.
———. Towards a “Natural” Narratology. London and New York: Routledge,
1996.
Fogle, Richard Harter. “Empathetic Imagery.” The Imagery of Keats and Shelley: A
Comparative Study. North Carolina, 1949. 139–83.
Forgas, Joseph P., ed. Handbook of Affect and Social Cognition. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum,
2001.
Forster, E. M. Aspects of the Novel. New York: Harcourt, 1927.
218 Works Cited
Fox, Stephen D. “Keri Hulme’s The Bone People: The Problem of Beneficial Child
Abuse.” Journal of Evolutionary Psychology (March 2003): 40–55.
Franzen, Jonathan. The Corrections. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2001.
Freud, Sigmund. “Creative Writers and Day-Dreaming.” 1907. Standard Edition of
the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Vol. 9. Ed. James Strachey.
London: Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-Analysis, 1959. 141–54.
Friedman, Susan Stanford. Mappings: Feminism and the Cultural Geographies of
Encounter. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998.
Frijda, Nico H. “The Psychologists’ Point of View.” Handbook of Emotions. 2nd ed. Ed.
Michael Lewis and Jeanette M. Haviland-Jones. New York and London: Guil-
ford Press, 2000. 59–74.
Gaillard, W. D., et al. “fMRI Identifies Regional Specialization of Neural Networks
for Reading in Young Children.” Neurology 60, 1 (2003): 94–100.
Gallagher, Catherine. Nobody’s Story: The Vanishing Acts of Women Writers in the
Marketplace, 1670–1820. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995.
Gallese, Vittorio. “ ‘Being Like Me’: Self-Other Identity, Mirror Neurons, and Empa-
thy.” Perspectives on Imitation: From Neuroscience to Social science, vol. 1. Mecha-
nisms of Imitation and Imitation in Animals. Ed. Susan Hurley and Nick Chater.
Cambridge: MIT Press, 2005. 101–18.
———. “The Roots of Empathy: The Shared Manifold Hypothesis and the Neural
Basis of Intersubjectivity.” Psychopathology 36, 4 (July–August 2003): 171–80.
———. “A Unifying View of the Basis of Social Cognition.” Trends in Cognitive Sci-
ence 8, 9 (September 2004): 396–403.
Gallese, Vittorio, et al. “The Mirror Matching System: A Shared Manifold for Inter-
subjectivity.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25, 1 (February 2002): 35–36.
Gallup, Gordon G., Jr., and Steven M. Platek. “Cognitive Empathy Presupposed Self-
awareness: Evidence from Phylogeny, Ontogeny, Neuropsychology, and Mental
Illness.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25, 1 (February 2002): 36.
Gardiner, Judith Kegan. Rhys, Stead, Lessing, and the Politics of Empathy. Blooming-
ton: Indiana University Press, 1989.
Gaskell, Elizabeth. Mary Barton. London: 1848.
———. Ruth. London: 1853.
———. Sylvia’s Lovers. London: 1863.
Gault, Barbara A., and John Sabini. “The Roles of Empathy, Anger, and Gender in
Predicting Attitudes toward Punitive, Reparative, and Preventative Public Poli-
cies.” Cognition and Emotion 14, 4 (2000): 495–520.
Gauss, Charles Edward. “Empathy.” Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Studies of Selected
Pivotal Ideas, 2 vols. Ed. Philip P. Wiener. New York: Scribner, 1973–74. v. 2, 86–9.
Geberth, Vernon J., and Ronald N. Turco. “Antisocial Personality Disorder, Sexual
Sadism, Malignant Narcissism, and Serial Murder.” Journal of Forensic Science
42, 1 (1997): 49–60.
Geer, J. H., and L. Jarmecky. “The Effect of Being Responsible for Reducing Anoth-
er’s Pain on Subject’s Response and Arousal.” Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology (1973): 232–37.
Gerrig, Richard J. “The Construction of Literary Character: A View from Cognitive
Psychology.” Style 24, 3 (Fall 1990): 380–92.
Works Cited 219
———. The Moral Laboratory: Experiments Examining the Effects of Reading Literature
on Social Perception and Moral Self-Concept. Utrecht Publications in General and
Comparative Literature 34. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2000.
Hall, Judith. “The PONS Test and the Psychometric Approach to Measuring Inter-
personal Sensitivity.” Interpersonal Sensitivity: Theory and Measurement. Ed.
Judith Hall and Frank Bernieri. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum, 2001. 143–60.
Hall, Judith, et al. “Profile of Nonverbal Sensitivity.” Advances in Psychological Assess-
ment. Vol. 4. Ed. P. McReynolds. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1977. 179–211.
Hardwick, Elizabeth. “Reading.” Reading in the 1980s. Ed. Stephen Graubard. New
York: Bowker, 1983. 13–18.
Härting, Heike. “Diasporic Cross-Currents in Michael Ondaatje’s Anil’s Ghost and
Anita Rau Badami’s The Hero’s Walk.” Studies in Canadian Literature 28, 1
(2003): 43–70.
Hartman, Geoffrey H. “Is an Aesthetic Ethos Possible? Night Thoughts after Aus-
chwitz.” Cardozo Studies in Law and Literature 6 (1994).
Harvey, W. J. Character and the Novel. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press,
1965.
Hassan, Ihab. “Queries for Postcolonial Studies.” Philosophy and Literature 22, 2
(1998): 328–42.
Hatfield, Elaine, John T. Cacioppo, and Richard L. Rapson. Emotional Contagion.
Studies in Emotion and Social Interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1994.
Hazlitt, William. “A Essay on the Principles of Human Action, Being an Argument
in Favour of the Natural Disinterestedness of the Human Mind.” 1805. The
Selected Writings of William Hazlitt. Vol. 1. Ed. Duncan Wu. London: Pickering
& Chatto, 1998. 1–82.
Highsmith, Patricia. The Talented Mr. Ripley. New York: Coward McCann, 1955.
Hjort, Mette, and Sue Laver eds. Emotion and the Arts. New York and Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1997.
Hochman, Baruch. Character in Literature. Ithaca and London: Cornell University
Press, 1985.
Hoffman, Martin. “Empathy, Its Limitations and Its Role in a Comprehensive Moral
Theory.” Morality, Moral Behavior and Moral Development. Ed. William Kurtines
and Jacob Gewirtz. New York: John Wiley, 1984.
———. Empathy and Moral Development: Implications for Caring and Justice. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
———. “Is Altruism Part of Human Nature?” Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology 40 (1981): 121–37.
———. “The Measurement of Empathy.” Measuring Emotions in Infants and Chil-
dren. Ed. C. E. Izard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982. 279–96.
———. “Scheme for the Development and Transformation of Empathic Distress.”
Empathy and Its Development. Ed. Nancy Eisenberg and Janet Strayer. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987. 50.
———. “Toward a Comprehensive Empathy-Based Theory of Prosocial Moral
Development.” Constructive and Destructive Behavior: Implications for Family,
School, and Society. Ed. Arthur C. Bohart and Deborah J. Stipek. Washington,
DC: American Psychological Association, 2001. 61–86.
Works Cited 221
Hogan, Patrick Colm. Cognitive Science, Literature, and the Arts: A Guide for Human-
ists. London and New York: Routledge, 2003.
———. “The Epilogue of Suffering: Heroism, Empathy, Ethics.” SubStance 30, 1–2
(2001): 119–43.
———. The Mind and Its Stories: Narrative Universals and Human Emotion. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.
———. “Stories and Morals: Emotion, Cognitive Exempla, and the Arabic Aristote-
lians.” The Work of Fiction: Cognition, Culture, and Complexity. Ed. Alan Rich-
ardson and Ellen Spolsky. Aldershot, Hampshire, and Burlington, VT: Ashgate,
2004. 31–50,
Holland, Norman. The Dynamics of Literary Response. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press, 1968.
———. Five Readers Reading. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1975.
———. “Where Is a Text? A Neurological View.” New Literary History 33, 1 (2002):
21–38.
Home, Henry. Lord Kames. Elements of Criticism. 1762. 2 vols. Ed. Peter Jones. India-
napolis: Liberty Fund, 2005.
Howe, Stephen. Empire: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press, 2002.
Howitt, Simon, ed. Bookselling: 2000 Market Report. Hampton, Middlesex: Key
Note, 2000.
Hughes, Mary Ann. “Transgressing Boundaries.” SPAN 39 (October 1994): 56–68.
Hugo, Victor. Les Miserables. Paris: 1862.
Hulme, Keri. the bone people. 1983. Rpt. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986.
Hulme, Keri, and Antonella Sarti. “Keri Hulme, March 1995.” Interview. Spiritcarv-
ers: Interviews with Eighteen Writers from New Zealand. Amsterdam: Rodopi,
1998. 57–69.
Hulme, Keri, and Gerry Turcotte. “Reconsidering the bone people.” Australian and
New Zealand Studies in Canada 12 (December 1994): 135–54.
Humble, Nicola. The Feminine Middlebrow Novel, 1920s to 1950s. Oxford and New
York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Hume, David. 1739. A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1978.
Hunt, Lynn. Lecture. “The Novel and the Origins of Human Rights: The Intersection
of History, Psychology and Literature.” Presidential Lecture in the Humanities
and Arts at Stanford University (8 April 2004).
———. “The Paradoxical Origins of Human Rights.” Human Rights and Revolutions.
Ed. Jeffrey N. Wasserstrom, Lynn Hunt, and Marilyn B. Young. Lanham, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield, 2000. 3–17.
Iacoboni, M., et al. “Cortical Mechanisms of Human Imitation.” Science 286 (1999):
2526–28.
Ickes, William, ed. Empathic Accuracy. New York and London: Guilford Press, 1997.
Ingmansan, Ellen J. “Empathy in a Bonobo.” Pretending and Imagination in Animals
and Children. Ed. Robert W. Mitchell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2002. 280–84.
Iser, Wolfgang. The Act of Reading: A Theory of Aesthetic Response. Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1978.
222 Works Cited
Knulst, Wim, and Andries van den Broek. “The Readership of Books in Times of De-
Reading.” Poetics 31 (2003): 213–33.
Koestenbaum, R., et al. “Individual Differences in Empathy among Preschoolers:
Relation to Attachment History.” New Directions for Child Development 44
(1989): 51–64.
Kohut, Hans. “Introspection, Empathy, and Psychoanalysis.” Journal of the American
Psychoanalytic Association 7 (1959): 459–83.
Konijn, Elly A., and Johan F. Hoorn. “Reality-based Genre Preferences Do Not Direct
Personal Involvement.” Discourse Processes 38, 2 (2004): 219–46.
Krebs, Dennis. “Empathy and Altruism.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
32, 6 (1975): 1134–46.
Kristeva, Julia. Revolution in Poetic Language. 1974. Trans. Margaret Waller. New
York: Columbia University Press, 1984.
Kruger, D. J. “Evolution and Altruism: Combining Psychological Mediators with Natu-
rally Selected Tendencies.” Evolution and Human Behavior 24 (2003): 118–25.
Kuiken, Don, et al. “Locating Self-Modifying Feelings within Literary Reading.” Dis-
course Processes 38, 2 (2004): 267–86.
Kuiken, Don, et al. “Forms of Self-Implication in Literary Reading.” Poetics Today 25,
2 (Summer 2004):171–203.
Lahiri, Jhumpa. Interpreter of Maladies. New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1997.
Lakoff, George. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about the
Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987.
Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1980.
Lakoff, George and Mark Turner. More Than Cool Reason: A Field Guide to Poetic
Metaphor. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989.
Lamarque, Peter, and Stein Haugum Olsen. Truth, Fiction, and Literature: A Philo-
sophical Perspective. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994.
Lang, Andrew. “Introduction.” The Pleasures of Literature and the Solace of Books. Ed.
Joseph Shaler. Wilbur B. Ketcham, no date. 9–10.
Latane, B., and J. M. Darley. The Unresponsive Bystander—Why Doesn’t He Help?
New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1970.
László, János. Cognition and Representation in Literature: The Psychology of Literary
Narratives. Budapest: Akadémiai Kiadó, 1999.
Lazarus, R. S., et al. “A Laboratory Study of Psychological Stress Produced by a
Motion Picture Film.” Psychological Monographs 76 (1962): 1–35.
Leavis, F. R. The Great Tradition: George Eliot, Henry James, Joseph Conrad. London:
Chatto and Windus, 1948.
Le Clair, Tom. “The Sri Lankan Patients.” The Nation (19 June 2000): 31.
LeDoux, Joseph. The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional
Life. New York and London: Simon and Schuster, 1996.
Lee, Harper. To Kill a Mockingbird. Philadelphia: Lippincott, 1960.
Lee, Vernon. [Violet Paget]. The Beautiful. An Introduction to Psychological Aesthetics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1913.
Lee, Vernon, and C. Anstruther-Thomson. “Beauty and Ugliness.” Contemporary
Review 72 (October 1897): 544–69; (November 1897): 669–88.
224 Works Cited
Lenard, Mary. “‘Mr. Popular Sentiment’: Dickens and the Gender Politics of Senti-
mentalism and Social Reform Literature.” Dickens Studies Annual 27 (1998):
45–68.
———. Preaching Pity: Dickens, Gaskell, and Sentimentalism in Victorian Culture.
New York: Peter Lang, 1999.
Lennon, Randy, and Nancy Eisenberg. “Gender/Age Differences in Empathy/Sym-
pathy.” Empathy and Its Development. Ed. Nancy Eisenberg and Janet Strayer.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987. 195–217.
Levenson, Robert, and Anna Ruef. “Physiological Aspects of Emotional Knowledge
and Rapport.” Empathic Accuracy. Ed. William Ickes. New York and London:
Guilford Press, 1997. 44–72.
Levinson, Jerrold. “Emotion in Response to Art: A Survey of the Terrain.” Emotion
and the Arts. Ed. Mette Hjort and Sue Laver. New York and Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1997. 20–34.
Linz, Daniel G., et al. “Effects of Long-Term Exposure to Violent and Sexually
Degrading Depictions of Women.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
55, 5 (November 1988): 758–68.
Lipps, Theodor. Äesthetik: Psycholgie des Schönen und der Kunst, 2 vols. Hamburg and
Leipzig: Voss, 1903, 1906.
———. “Das Wissen von Fremden Ichen.” Psychologische Untersuchungen 1 (1906):
694–722.
———. Zur Einfühlung. Leipzig: Engleman, 1913.
Lodge, David. Consciousness and the Novel: Connected Essays. Cambridge, MA: Har-
vard University Press, 2002.
Long, Elizabeth. Book Clubs: Women and the Uses of Reading in Everyday Life. Chi-
cago: University of Chicago Press, 2003.
Louwerse, Max, and Don Kuiken. “The Effects of Personal Involvement in Narrative
Discourse.” Discourse Processes 38, 2 (2004): 169–72.
Lowry, Lois. The Giver. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1993.
Lubbock, Percy. The Craft of Fiction. 1926. Rpt. New York: Viking, 1957.
Mackenzie, Henry. The Man of Feeling. 1771.
———. The Works of Henry Mackenzie. Vol. 5. 1808. Facsimile. London: Routledge/
Thoemmes, 1996.
Marcus, Robert F. “Somatic Indices of Empathy.” Empathy and Its Development. Ed.
Nancy Eisenberg and Janet Strayer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1987. 374–79.
Marlyn, John. Under the Ribs of Death. Toronto: McClelland and Stewart, 1957.
Marshall, David. The Surprising Effects of Sympathy: Marivaux, Diderot, Rousseau,
and Mary Shelley. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988.
Maryles, Daisy, and Laurele Riippa. “Bestsellers of 2003: Hardcover Bestsellers; The
Stakes Rise for Chart Toppers.” The Bowker Annual: Library and Book Trade Annual,
2004. 49th ed. Ed. Dave Bogart. New York: Information Today, 2004. 576.
Massumi, Brian. Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation. Durham: Duke
University Press, 2002.
Matsumoto, David. “Culture and Emotion.” The Handbook of Culture and Psychology.
Ed. David Matsumoto. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
171–94.
Works Cited 225
McCarthy, Thomas J. Relationships of Sympathy: The Writer and the Reader in British
Romanticism. Aldershot: Scolar Press; Brookfield, VT: Ashgate Press, 1997.
McEvoy, Dermot, and Daisy Maryles. “Paperback Bestsellers: Numbers Up; Fiction
Dominates.” The Bowker Annual: Library and Book Trade Annual, 2004. 49th
ed. Ed. Dave Bogart. New York: Information Today, 2004. 584–85.
McLemee, Scott. “Literary Reading Is Declining.” The Chronicle of Higher Education
(9 July 2004): A1, A16.
Megafu, U. “Female Ritual Circumcision in Africa: An Investigation of the Presumed
Benefits Among Ibos of Nigeria.” East African Medical Journal (November
1983): 793–800.
Mehaffy, Marilyn, and AnaLouise Keating. “‘Radio Imagination’: Octavia Butler
on the Poetics of Narrative Embodiment.” MELUS 26, 1 (Spring 2001): 45–
76.
Mehrabian, Albert. Manual for the Balanced Emotional Empathy Scale (BEES),
1996.
———. “Relations among Personality Scales of Aggression, Violence, and Empathy:
Validational Evidence Bearing on the Risk of Violence Scale.” Aggressive Behav-
ior 23 (1997): 433–45.
Melzer, Patricia. “‘All that you touch you change’: Utopian Desire and the Concept
of Change in Octavia Butler’s Parable of the Sower and Parable of the Talents.”
Femspec 3, 2 (2002): 31–52.
Mencius. Trans. D. C. Lau. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1970.
Mesquita, Betja, and Mayumi Karasawa. “Different Emotional Lives.” Cognition and
Emotion 16, 1 (2004): 127–41.
Miall, David S. “Affect and Narrative: A Model of Responses to Stories.” Poetics 17
(1988): 259–72.
———. “Anticipation and Feeling in Literary Response: A Neuropsychological Per-
spective.” Poetics 23 (1995): 275–98.
———. “Beyond Interpretation: The Cognitive Significance of Reading.” Lecture
delivered at the conference Cognition and Literary Interpretation in Practice.
(29 August 2004) University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland.
———. “Beyond the Schema Given: Affective Comprehension of Literary Narra-
tives.” Cognition and Emotion 3, 1 (1989): 55–78.
———. “Empowering the Reader: Literary Response and Classroom Learning.”
Empirical Approaches to Literature and Asethetics. Ed. Roger J. Kreuz and Mary
Sue MacNealy. Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1996. 463–78.
———. “On the Necessity of Empirical Studies of Literary Reading.” Frame 14, 2–3
(2000): 43–59.
Miall, David S., and Donald Kuiken. “Aspects of Literary Response: A New Ques-
tionnaire,” Research in the Teaching of English 29, 1 (February 1995): 37–58.
———. “The Form of Reading: Empirical Studies of Literariness.” Poetics 25 (1998):
327–31.
———. “What Is Literariness? Three Components of Literary Reading.” Discourse
Processes 28, 2 (1999): 121–38.
Miller, J. G., and D. M. Bersoff. “Cultural Influences on the Moral Status of Reci-
procity and the Discounting of Endogenous Motivation.” Personality and Social
Psychology Bulletin 20 (1994): 592–602.
226 Works Cited
Pope, Alexander. An Essay on Man. 1733–34. Ed. Maynard Mack. The Twickenham
Edition of the Poems of Alexander Pope. Vol. 3, part 1. New Haven and London:
Yale University Press, 1950. 163–64.
Posner, Richard. “Against Ethical Criticism.” Philosophy and Literature 21, 1 (1997):
1–27.
Potts, Stephen W. “‘We Are Playing the Same Record’: A Conversation with Octavia
E. Butler.” Science-Fiction Studies 23 (1996): 331–38
Pound, Ezra. “A Few Don’ts by an Imagiste.” Poetry 1 (Feb. 1913): 5.
Powers, Samantha. “A Problem from Hell”: America and the Age of Genocide. New
York: Basic Books, 2002.
Preston, Stephanie D., and Frans B. M. de Waal. “The Communication of Emo-
tions and the Possibility of Empathy in Animals.” Altruism and Altruistic
Love: Science, Philosophy, and Religion in Dialogue. Ed. Stephen G. Post and
Lynn G. Underwood. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2002.
284–308.
———. “Empathy: Its Ultimate and Proximate Bases.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences
25, 1 (February 2002): 1–20, 49–71.
Price, Leah. The Anthology and the Rise of the Novel: From Richardson to George Eliot.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Price, Martin. Forms of Life: Character and Moral Imagination in the Novel. New
Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1983.
Publishing Market Watch. Sectoral Report 2: Book Publishing. n.p.: European Com-
mission, 2004.
Putnam, Robert D. Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community.
New York and London: Simon and Schuster, 2000.
Quayson, Ato. “Looking Awry: Tropes of Disability in Post-colonial Writing.” An
Introduction to Contemporary Fiction. Ed. Rod Mengham. Cambridge: Polity
Press, 1999. 53–68.
Rabinowitz, Peter J. Before Reading: Narrative Conventions and the Politics of Interpre-
tation. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1987.
Radway, Janice. A Feeling for Books: The Book-of-the-Month Club, Literary Taste, and
Middle-class Desire. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1997.
Rawls, John. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999.
———. Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971.
Reading at Risk: A Survey of Literary Reading in America. Research Division Report
#46. Washington, DC: The National Endowment for the Arts, June 2004.
Reed, Stephen K. Cognition: Theory and Applications. 6th ed. Belmont, CA: Wad-
sworth, 2004.
Richards, I. A. Mencius on the Mind: Experiments in Multiple Definition. London and
New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1932.
Richardson, Alan. “Studies in Literature and Cognition: A Field Map.” The Work of
Fiction: Cognition, Culture, and Complexity. Ed. Alan Richardson and Ellen Spol-
sky. Aldershot, Hampshire and Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2004. 1–30.
Richardson, Samuel. Pamela. London: 1740.
Rochat, Phillipe. “Various Kinds of Empathy as Revealed by the Developing Child,
Not the Monkey’s Brain.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25, 1 (February 2002):
45–46.
Works Cited 229
Sheehan, E. P., et al. “Reactions to AIDS and Other Illnesses: Reported Interactions
in the Workplace.” The Journal of Psychology 123 (1989): 525–36.
Shelley, Percy Bysshe. A Defence of Poetry. 1821. Shelley’s Poetry and Prose. Ed. Don-
ald H. Reiman. New York: Norton, 1977. 480–508.
———. “A Treatise on Morals.” 1840. Shelley’s Prose. Ed. David Lee Clark. Albuquer-
que: University of New Mexico Press, 1954.
Sherman, Nancy. “Empathy and Imagination.” Philosophy of Emotions. (Midwest
Studies in Philosophy, XXII). Ed. Peter French and Howard K. Wettstein. Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998. 82–119.
Shields, Stephanie A. Speaking from the Heart: Gender and the Social Meaning of Emo-
tion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
Showalter, Elaine. Teaching Literature. Oxford: Blackwell, 2003.
Shute, Nevil. The Pied Piper. New York: William Morrow, 1942.
Silko, Leslie Marmon. “Workshop 7—WHO AM I IN THIS STORY?” In Search of
the Novel. http://www.learner.org/channel/workshops/isonovel/Pages/subpage7
.html. Accessed 14 February 2005.
Silverman, Kaja. “Suture [Excerpts].” 1983. Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology: A Film Theory
Reader. Ed. Philip Rosen. New York: Columbia University Press, 1986. 219–35.
Singer, Peter. One World. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2002.
Singer, Peter, and Renata Singer. The Moral of the Story: An Anthology of Ethics Through
Literature. Oxford: Blackwell, 2005.
Singer, Tania, et al. “Empathy for Pain Involves the Affective but Not Sensory Com-
ponents of Pain.” Science 303 (20 February 2004): 1157–62.
Slote, Michael. Morals from Motives. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press,
2001.
Smiley, Jane. 13 Ways of Looking at the Novel. New York: Knopf, 2005.
Smith, Adam. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. 1759. Ed. D. D. Raphael and A. L.
Macfie. Vol. 1. Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith.
Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1976.
Smith, Alexander McCall. Morality for Beautiful Girls. New York: Polygon, 2001.
Smith, Tom W. “Altruism in Contemporary America: A Report from the National
Altruism Study.” GSS Topical Report No. 34. NORC, 2003.
Sober, Elliot, and David Sloan Wilson. Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of
Unselfish Behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998.
Solomon, Robert C. Ed. Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emo-
tions. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2004.
Sontag, Susan. Regarding the Pain of Others. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux,
2003.
Spencer, Herbert. Principles of Psychology. London: Longmans, 1855.
Spencer, Suzette A. “Shall We Gather at the River? Ritual, Benign Forms of Injury,
and the Wounds of Displaced Women in Opal Palmer Adisa’s It Begins with
Tears.” MaComère 4 (2001): 108–18.
Spryi, Joanna. Heidi. 1885. Trans. Boston: 1885.
Stang, Richard. The Theory of the Novel in England, 1850–1870. New York: Columbia
University Press; London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1959.
Stanzel, F. K. Narrative Situation in the Novel. Trans. James P. Pusack. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1971.
Works Cited 231
Todd, Janet. Sensibility: An Introduction. London and New York: Methuen, 1986.
Tolstoi, Leo. Anna Karenina. 1878. Trans. London: Dent, 1912.
Tompkins, Jane, ed. Reader-Response Criticism: From Formalism to Post-Structuralism.
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1980.
Treece, Henry. The Horned Helmet. London: Brockhampton, 1963.
Tromp, Marlene. The Private Rod: Marital Violence, Sensation, and the Law in Victo-
rian Britain. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 2000.
Turvey, Brent E. “Psychopathy and Sadism.” Criminal Profiling: An Introduction to
Behavioral Evidence Analysis. New York: Academic Press, 1999. 193–207.
United Nations, Universal Declaration of Human Rights. General Assembly reso-
lution 217 A (III) (10 December 1948). http://www.un.org/Overview/rights
.html. Accessed 5 May 2005.
U. S. Census Bureau, Statistical Abstract of the United States (2003). No. 1125.
Media Usage and Consumer Spending: 1998 to 2006, Information and
Communications.
van Peer, Willie. “Justice in Perspective.” New Perspectives on Narrative Perspective.
Ed. Willie van Peer and Seymour Chatman. Albany: SUNY Press, 2001. 325–
38.
van Peer, Willie, and H. Pander Maat. “Perspectivation and Sympathy: Effects of
Narrative Point of View.” Empirical Approaches to Literature and Aesthetics.
Ed. Roger J. Kreuz and Mary Sue MacNealy. Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1996.
143–54.
Van Sant, Ann Jessie. Eighteenth-century Sensibility and the Novel: The Senses in Social
Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
VICTORIA-L archives. https://listserv.Bloomington: Indiana UP,.edu/archives/vic-
toria.html 12 November–3 December 2004.
Vygotsky, L. S. The Psychology of Art. 1925. Trans. Scripta Technica. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1971.
Wagner, M., et al. “The AIDS Empathy Scale: Construction and Correlates.” New
Directions in the Psychology of Human Sexuality: Research and Theory. Ed. W. E.
Snell, Jr. Cape Girardeau, MO: Snell, 2001.
Walker, Alice. Possessing the Secret of Joy. New York: Harcourt, 1992.
Waller, Robert James. The Bridges of Madison County. New York: Time Warner,
1992.
Walsh, Richard. “Why We Wept for Little Nell: Character and Emotional Involve-
ment.” Narrative 5, 3 (October 1997): 306–21.
Walton, Kendall. Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational
Arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.
Warhol, Robyn. Having a Good Cry: Effeminate Feelings and Pop-Culture Forms.
Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 2003.
Weber, Bruce. “Poet Brokers Truce in Culture Wars.” Washington Post (7 September
2004): B1, B5.
Weldon, Fay. The Bulgari Connection. London: Flamingo, 2001.
Wilentz, Gay. “Instruments of Change: Healing Cultural Dis-ease in Keri Hulme’s
the bone people.” Literature and Medicine 14, 1 (1995): 127–45.
Williams, Ioan, ed. Novel and Romance 1700–1800: A Documentary Record. New
York: Barnes and Noble, 1970.
Works Cited 233
Williams, Mark. “Keri Hulme and Negative Capability.” Leaving the Highway: Six
Contemporary New Zealand Novelists. Auckland: Auckland University Press,
1990. 84–109.
Williams, Mary. Ed. Human Rights: Opposing Viewpoints. San Diego: Greenhaven
Press, 1998.
Williams, Preston N. “A Personal Perspective on the Elimination of Female Circum-
cision.” Colloquium: Bridging Society, Culture, and Law. Case Western Reserve
Law Review 47 (Winter 1997): 491–500.
Williams, Raymond. Culture and Society, 1780–1950. 1958. Rpt. with a new intro-
duction. New York: Columbia University Press, 1983.
———. Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society. Rev. Ed. Oxford and New
York: Oxford University Press, 1983.
Wimsatt, W. K., and Monroe Beardsley. “The Affective Fallacy.” The Verbal Icon: Stud-
ies in the Meaning of Poetry. Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1954.
21–39.
Wing, Lorna. “Asperger’s Syndrome: A Clinical Account.” Psychological Medicine 11
(1981): 115–30.
Winnicott, D. W. Playing and Reality. London: Tavistock, 1971.
Wispé, Lauren. “History of the Concept of Empathy.” Empathy and Its Development.
Ed. Nancy Eisenberg and Janet Strayer. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1987. 17–37.
Wood, Marcus. Slavery, Empathy and Pornography. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press, 2002.
Woolf, Virginia. “Middlebrow.” The Death of the Moth and Other Essays. London:
Hogarth Press, 1942. 176–86.
———. “Modern Fiction.” 1919. Rpt. The Common Reader. New York: Harcourt,
1925. 207–18.
———. Mrs. Dalloway. London: Hogarth Press, 1925.
Zahn-Waxler, Carolyn. “Caregiving, Emotion, and Concern for Others.” Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 25, 1 (February 2002): 48–49.
Zahn-Waxler, Carolyn, et al. “Development of Concern for Others.” Developmental
Psychology 28 (1992): 126–36.
———. “The Development of Empathy in Twins.” Developmental Psychology 28
(1992): 1038–47.
———. “Empathy and Prosocial Patterns in Young MZ and DZ Twins: Development
and Genetic and Environmental Influences.” Infancy to Early Childhood: Genetic
and Environmental Influences on Developmental Change. Ed. Robert M. Emde
and John K. Hewitt. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
141–62.
Zepetnek, S. Tötösy de, and I. Sywenky, eds. The Systematic and Empirical Approach
to Literature and Culture as Theory and Application. Edmonton: University of
Alberta Press, 1997.
Zillmann, Dolf. “Empathy: Affect from Bearing Witness to the Emotions of Others.”
Responding to the Screen: Reception and Reaction Processes. Ed. Dolf Zillmann
and Jennings Bryant. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1991. 135–67.
———. “Mechanisms of Emotional Involvement with Drama.” Poetics 23 (1994):
33–51.
234 Works Cited
Zunshine, Lisa. “Richardson’s Clarissa and a Theory of Mind.” The Work of Fiction:
Cognition, Culture, and Complexity. Ed. Alan Richardson and Ellen Spolsky.
Aldershot, Hampshire, and Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2004. 127–46.
———. “Theory of Mind and Experimental Representations of Fictional Conscious-
ness.” Narrative 11, 3 (October 2003): 270–91.
Zwaan, Rolf A. “Effect of Genre Expectations on Text Comprehension.” Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition 20 (1994): 920–33.
———. “The Immersed Experiencer: Toward an Embodied Theory of Language
Comprehension.” The Psychology of Learning and Motivation 44 (2004): 35–62.
INDEX