The Hard Problem of Consciousness & The Progressivism of Scientific Explanation
The Hard Problem of Consciousness & The Progressivism of Scientific Explanation
The Hard Problem of Consciousness & The Progressivism of Scientific Explanation
or why things just are the way they are and not some other way. Sci-
ence may not only instruct us in descriptive matters as to what the
world or the structure of the world is like, but it also provides an
explanation or understanding of why certain phenomena occur. For
example, science may attempt to explain numerous things such as why
it rains, the motions of the planets, why a government failed, why an
individual made one decision rather than another, and why penguins
cannot fly.
When examining the nature and history of scientific explanations, I
would like to introduce and adopt a progressivism view. This view
simply states that just as it is generally conceived that scientific theo-
ries can progress or advance within a field and become closer approxi-
mations to the truth, kinds of scientific explanations within a field also
may progress or advance in their ability to explain even more natural
phenomena with at times even greater precision. Advancements in
types of explanation may increase the explanatory power of the over-
all scientific theory to which the scientific explanation is tied.1 Just as
overall scientific theories that in part provide explanations of phe-
nomena may significantly change and advance, there tend to also be
advancements in kinds of explanations in particular fields.2 Histori-
cally, types of scientific explanations within certain fields tend to
advance and develop. Notice that progressivism does not simply make
the statement that the ability of science to explain phenomena
advances over time. Rather, progressivism makes the deeper point
that the kinds of frameworks that underlie scientific explanations
advances and progresses over time in particular fields which lead to a
greater rather than a lesser or stagnant explanatory power for a given
theory.
Since it may be the case that kinds of explanations within a field
may progress and develop over time, there may be a moderate to
strong relationship between such development and concurrent signifi-
cant and even revolutionary-like progress of scientific theories within
[1] Kinds of explanation are not to be confused with theories of explanation, where theories of
explanation posit the logical structure a correct scientific explanation must take. Our focus
in this paper will only be on kinds of explanations. As understood here, differences in
kinds of explanations are more fine-grained than differences in underlying theories of
explanation. Kinds of explanations are not necessarily individuated by having different
underlying theories of explanation. For example, historical explanations such as what
brought about the first world war and functionalist explanations in the study of the mind
both can be categorized under the umbrella of the causal theory of explanation. However,
historical causal explanations are still a different kind of explanation than functional
explanations.
[2] The phrase ‘in particular fields’ will be explained shortly.
THE HARD PROBLEM AND PROGRESSIVISM 3
a field. As we shall see, this may be the case as it does appear that new
progressive kinds of explanations do take part in the significant
advancement of scientific theories. The development of scientific the-
ories generally allows for the explanation of ever more refined phe-
nomena, and any new and more developed kinds of explanations
being inextricably linked to a scientific theory itself must have neces-
sarily played a role in the advancement of the overall scientific theory.
Here, new kinds of explanations may in part be unfolded through
advancements in the particular scientific field, such as through
advancements in instrumentation, abstract theoretical reasoning,
experimentation, or having increased observational capacities. This
new type of explanation subsequently may play a role in the further
advancement of the overall scientific theory itself as it is applied or
used to explain diverse and previously unexplainable phenomena.
Later we will explore the possibility that advancements in kinds of
explanations for the mind–body problem may advance overall theo-
ries in this subject matter as well. As an additional point, it should not
be wholly surprising if we find that in certain fields there is a progres-
sivism due to the fact that, because overall scientific theories tend to
progress closer to the truth and explanations are intricately related to
overall scientific theories, then it may be the case that new advanced
types of explanations develop as well in being more explanatorily
powerful and precise.
Moreover, progressivism does not deny that previous kinds of
explanations might still play some role in explanation within a field.
Yet, it does say that even if this is the case, the more advanced kinds of
explanations which arise are generally responsible for the greater
explanatory power a scientific theory may have. Furthermore, it may
be the case that there is no progression of kinds of explanations within
a certain field. Therefore, progressivism claims that kinds of explana-
tions relative to a particular field may develop over time. However,
progressivism does contend that there are a number of fields of scien-
tific enquiry in which historical progress in kinds of scientific expla-
nations does take place.
For example, while Newton allowed for mechanical explanations,
his overall scientific theory did stray from Galileo, Kepler, and Des-
cartes in that it did do away with strict adherence to mechanistic
explanations in that he allowed for non-mechanical interactions and
action at a distance in his view on gravity and gravitational interac-
tion. In fact, in his explanation of gravity he provided no causal mech-
anistic explanation, but rather gave a mathematical relationship. In
part due to such development of this new kind of non-mechanistic
4 J. PARK
properties. One such contention for the hard line position is the
explanatory gap argument, which may also be viewed as being tied to
Chalmers’ notion of the hard problem of consciousness. It claims that
there is a gap between phenomenal psychological properties that we
may grasp subjectively through introspection and neural-biological
properties that may be objectively studied from the third-person point
of view (Levine, 1983; Chalmers, 1996). This epistemic gap questions
whether there can be a reductive explanation of phenomenal proper-
ties to the neural-biological. For instance, if an itch arises from a cer-
tain neural-biological property, what makes it the case that the
sensation of an itch arises from this physical property rather than some
other sensation when this physical property occurs? Why is it the case
that an itch does not arise from a different neural-biological state?
Why do qualia arise from this physical state? These legitimate ques-
tions illustrate that there may be some gap in reductively explaining
qualitative psychological properties to neural-biological ones. To pos-
itively answer the explanatory gap is to provide such a reductive
explanation that closes this supposed gap. Along these lines,
Chalmers labels phenomenal consciousness the hard problem in that
qualia resist functional characterization. While the research pro-
gramme is quite clear for non-phenomenal mental states and pro-
cesses, the lack of a functional definition for the qualitative aspect of
mental states makes the issue of phenomenal consciousness unruly
and difficult. There is an explanatory gap that leads to a corresponding
ontological gap, and the explanatory gap exists because of the absence
of a complete functional account of phenomenal psychological states.
There also are numerous hard line contentions, mostly in the form
of thought experiments, that arguably are ultimately based on or influ-
enced by Descartes’ objections against materialism. Even though they
may have their differences in the type of epistemic gap formed,
hypotheticals such as Chalmers’ zombie conceivability argument
(1996; 2010), inverted qualia (Block, 1990), absent qualia (Block,
1980), and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument (1982) all can be
understood as claiming that there is some kind of epistemic gap
between psychological and neural-biological truths, and thus there is
an ontological gap between such truths, and materialism is false. With
progressivism in hand, we only have the space to directly address
Chalmers’ conceivability argument. The conceivability argument has
been selected because I take this contention to be perhaps the most
intricately defended hard line position. Nevertheless, given the struc-
tural similarity amongst the group of thought experiments that take a
hard line view, it may be understood that my objections to the con-
THE HARD PROBLEM AND PROGRESSIVISM 7
water is XYZ rather than H2O. In this sense, ‘water is not H2O’ is pri-
marily conceivable. However, primary conceivability does not seem
to entail metaphysical possibility because although ‘water is not H2O’
is primarily conceivable, it is not actually metaphysically possible
given that water being H2O is a posteriori necessary.
However, Chalmers clarifies the link between primary conceivab-
ility and metaphysical possibility. He notes that since we can primar-
ily conceive of water not being H2O on Twin Earth, it is metaphysic-
ally possible that water is not H2O, where there is a sense in which we
have access to such a possible world. While this possible world is not
one in which water is not H2O, this world still stands in a strong rela-
tion to the sentence ‘water is not H2O’. In two-dimensional terms,
Twin Earth does not satisfy ‘water is not H2O’ since this sentence is
not true of that world considered as counterfactual. However, Twin
Earth verifies ‘water is not H2O’ given that ‘water is not H2O’ is true of
that world when the world is considered as actual. In other words,
given the difference in the senses of the sentence, the secondary
intension of ‘water is not H2O’ is false for Twin Earth, but its primary
intension is true for this world. Here, Chalmers states that a world w
verifies a sentence S, where the primary intension of S is true at w,
when we should endorse S if we accepted that our own world is quali-
tatively like w.
From here we may conclude that when the primary intension of S is
true at some world w where w verifies S, S is primarily possible. Like-
wise, when the secondary intension of S is true at some w where w sat-
isfies S, then S is secondarily possible. Therefore, sentences like
‘water is not H2O’ are primarily conceivable but not secondarily pos-
sible. Primary conceivability does not entail secondary possibility.
However, secondary conceivability does entail secondary possibility,
and most importantly for Chalmers thus far, primary conceivability
entails primary possibility.
Understanding P to be the conjunction of all microphysical truths
about the universe, including the features of microphysical entities as
well as the fundamental microphysical laws, while Q represents an
arbitrary phenomenal truth such as that everyone is phenomenally
conscious, as a first pass, we now may view Chalmers’ (2010, p. 142)
two-dimensional argument as:
1. P & ~Q is primarily conceivable.
2. If P & ~Q is primarily conceivable, then P & ~Q is primarily
possible.
THE HARD PROBLEM AND PROGRESSIVISM 9
ondary intensions may not be the same for P. Even though we as of yet
have not stated anything in particular about the primary and secondary
intensions of Q and their relationship to one another (Chalmers does
understand Q’s intensions to be the same for Kripkean reasons
although he does not believe that this sameness is required for his
argument to work), since the primary and secondary intensions may
not be the same for P, the third premise requirement that the conjunc-
tion P and Q must have primary and secondary intensions that coin-
cide may not be met.
However, Chalmers attempts to resolve this problem by first noting
that for the third premise to be false it must be the case that the struc-
tural profile of physics in the actual world does not necessitate Q but
that the structural and intrinsic profiles of physics in the actual world
do necessitate Q. Yet, if this is the case, this leads to the view of
Russellian monism. For Russellian monism, Bertrand Russell in The
Analysis of Matter (1927) claimed that the intrinsic properties that are
the bases of microphysical entities may themselves be phenomenal
properties, where the nature of such properties are not revealed to us
by science or by perception. As physics is silent about the intrinsic
nature of microphysical entities and there is the question of how phe-
nomenal consciousness can be integrated in the physical world,
Russell attempted to kill two birds with one stone by stating that phe-
nomenal consciousness is constituted by the intrinsic properties of
microphysical dispositions. While this view has ties to materialism in
that phenomenal properties may be considered to be physical proper-
ties that are the intrinsic properties to microphysical entities,
Russellian monism is a property dualism in that phenomenal proper-
ties are ontologically fundamental, and they are ontologically dispa-
rate from the structural-dispositional properties characterized in
physical theory. Given Russellian monism, with the third premise, if P
& ~Q is primarily possible, then Chalmers believes the only options
are that it is the case that P & ~Q is either secondarily possible or
Russellian monism is true. Either end of the disjunction embedded in
premise three inevitably will lead to an ontological gap that Chalmers
desires. The above is how Chalmers defends a revised version of the
third premise. With Chalmers’ defence in mind, we may now restate
the two-dimensional argument as:
1. P & ~Q is primarily conceivable.
2. If P & ~Q is primarily conceivable, then P & ~Q is primarily
possible.
THE HARD PROBLEM AND PROGRESSIVISM 11
dynamics, one can deduce only further truths about structure and dyna-
mics. Third, truths about consciousness are not truths about structure
and dynamics. (Chalmers, 2010, p. 120)
Chalmers’ first premise is that microphysics only provides descrip-
tions of things that have physical spatio-temporal structure. More-
over, such things may have dynamical properties in which certain
laws may govern their change over time. Second, as we work our way
up levels from physics to chemistry to biology, etc. the low-level
microphysical structural and dynamic descriptions only entail more
structural and dynamic descriptions at the higher levels, such as in
chemistry and biology. The third premise is that phenomenal con-
sciousness does not have spatio-temporal structure. While Chalmers
admits that qualia may have some kind of phenomenal structure, this
structure is not in-and-of-itself physical structure. From these pre-
mises he concludes that even if there may be some vaguely stated
notion of a conceptual revolution in science, science will still never be
able to reductively explain qualia because science only reductively
explains things with structural and dynamical properties, but qualia
do not have physical structure.
The problem with the structural argument is with the second prem-
ise. Once we get to the higher levels of the social sciences, such as
with psychology and economics, it does appear that structural descrip-
tions do entail non-structural descriptions. For example, consider easy
problems of the mind–body problem such as with non-phenomenal
psychological states and processes that are multiply realized at the
neural-biological level. Here, certain structural neural-biological
states entail certain non-phenomenal psychological states, where such
psychological states are non-structural, distinct, and higher-order
states as compared to the physical structural neural-biological states
in question. Likewise, in economics, there are higher-order properties
such as the economies of scale3 that are non-reductively and multiply
realized at the bio-sociological levels. Spatio-temporally structured
biological human beings and certain complex stories of their social
interactions explain the economies of scale at the lower bio-sociologi-
cal levels. As the economies of scale is a distinct and higher-level
property from the bio-sociological levels, the economies of scale does
not have spatio-temporal structure even though what reductively
explains and entails it does.
Thus, I take it that the structural argument alone is false, and it alone
cannot be used against, for example, the above philosophers who
[3] Economies of scale are the cost advantages one may receive from business expansion.
14 J. PARK
think that a future conceptual revolution may show that there is not an
epistemic gap. Requiring the explanandum be something that has
physical structure and dynamics has, by itself, got nothing to do with
shaping the limits of scientific explanation. The structural argument
by itself is debunked. Now, Chalmers may be read as having anticip-
ated this move in that he acknowledges that non-structural psycholog-
ical beliefs are entailed by a structural-dynamic system. He writes:
[T]here are some truths that are not themselves structural-dynamic but
are nevertheless implied by a structural-dynamic description. It might
be argued, perhaps, that truths about representation or belief have this
character. As we saw earlier, however, it seems clear that any sense in
which these truths are implied by a structural-dynamic description
involves a tacitly functional sense of representation or belief.
(Chalmers, 2010, p. 121)4
Here, Chalmers may be read as now hinging his objection to those
who believe in a future conceptual revolution on the fact that phenom-
enal consciousness lacks a complete functional description. In sci-
ence, only functionalism can provide a reductive explanation of
non-structural states to structural ones. Assuming that a behaviourist
explanation is misguided, and a type identity explanation is also false,
although we will discuss the general idea of an identity reduction and
its plausibility given progressivism in further detail in the next sec-
tion, the only remotely tenable hope to explain non-structural qualia is
with functionalism, but functionalism still leaves an explanatory gap
for qualia. Chalmers writes:
The basic problem… is that epistemic implication from A to B requires
some sort of conceptual hook by virtue of which the condition described
in A can satisfy the conceptual requirements for the truth of B. When a
physical account implies truths about life, for example, it does so in vir-
tue of implying information about the macroscopic functioning of
physical systems of the sort required for life. Here, broadly functional
notions provide the conceptual hook. In the case of consciousness, by
contrast, no such conceptual hook is available… (Ibid., p. 123)
[4] Chalmers immediately continues this quote with: ‘This is what we would expect: if claims
involving these can be seen (on conceptual grounds) to be true in virtue of structural-
dynamic description[s] holding, then the notions involved must themselves be structural-
dynamic at some level’ (ibid., pp. 121–2). Here, he seems to be saying that since represen-
tational truths are truths due to functionalism and lower-level structural-dynamic descrip-
tions, then representational truths are structural and dynamic at a lower level. Notice that
representations are still non-structural at the psychological level. Hence, Chalmers’ state-
ment is all well and good, but the second premise of the structural argument still is false
because from truths about structure we may deduce truths about things that do not have
physical structure at the psychological level.
THE HARD PROBLEM AND PROGRESSIVISM 15
study of the nature of the mind and very well may occur in the future.
Notice the inherent and sheer power of progressivism as the utiliza-
tion of it does not even require or demand painting even a remotely
nebulous picture of what the new kind of explanation may look like.
The history of science demonstrates that the progression of kinds of
explanations in certain fields can provide or underwrite new types of
explanations within that field that can overcome previous explanatory
obstacles and augment a theory’s explanatory power; types of expla-
nations some of which were not even previously imagined before
within the field.
Chalmers claims that despite future progress in science, there can
be no conceptual hook to explain phenomenal consciousness due to
the failure of functionalism and other previous conceptual explana-
tory hooks. Thus, science and its numerous potential types of explana-
tions cannot reductively explain non-structural qualia in terms of
structural neural-biological properties. Recalling his two-dimensional
argument, he boldly concludes that materialism is false or Russellian
monism is true. However, Chalmers does not specifically account for
the thesis of progressivism. Chalmers’ problem is that he understands
science’s explanatory methods and frameworks to be stagnant. How-
ever, given progressivism, it does not immediately follow that there
absolutely cannot be a conceptual hook. Remember how we have pre-
viously discussed how the study of fields such as physics and the
nature of the mind have produced new types of explanations within
their respective fields that allowed for overcoming previous explana-
tory hurdles and also allowed for a greater explanatory power and suc-
cess. Therefore, given the wisdom of progressivism, Chalmers’ first
premise that ‘P & ~Q is primarily conceivable’ is not warranted since
there is a reasonable and legitimate likelihood that P & ~Q is not ide-
ally conceivable due to potential future ideal reflection and theoretical
rationalization that is influenced by the discovery of a new kind of
explanation. Although the premise ‘P & ~Q is primarily conceivable’
has not absolutely been ruled out, we are not justified in making the
strong claim that this premise is true. Just as we would not be justified
in believing that a five-year-old boy will never grow up to be a good
soccer player given the poor way in which he currently plays, we like-
wise would not be justified in wholly believing Chalmers’ first prem-
ise either.5 Here is a legitimate warranted possibility that it is not the
case that P & ~Q is primarily conceivable.
future. Similar to the fact that water is H2O, such a reasonable possi-
bility may lead to an a posteriori necessity claim that phenomenal
consciousness is x (although for qualia it need not be a type identity
reduction to the physical). P & ~Q may not be secondarily conceiv-
able, although it may be primarily conceivable. Thus, even though P &
~Q is primarily conceivable and thus, primarily possible, it may be
that it is not the case that P & ~Q is secondarily possible, where
Russellian monism also is not true. If there is a physicalist a posteriori
necessity, a warranted possibility that progressivism legitimately
allows for, then the consequent of Chalmers’ third premise must allow
for this possibility of physicalism, and this renders the third premise
as false or incomplete. Here, I do not claim that a materialist a posteri-
ori necessity will in fact be discovered, but as I have previously
argued, I do believe that there is a reasonably strong probability that
this may occur. Hence, this leads to an altered conclusion for the two-
dimensional conceivability argument that allows for the possibility of
a materialist picture. No strong conclusion for dualism may be drawn.
On this objection, Chalmers’ argument now appears as:
1. P & ~Q is primarily conceivable.
2. If P & ~Q is primarily conceivable, then P & ~Q is primarily
possible.
3. If P & ~Q is primarily possible, then P & ~Q is secondarily
possible, or Russellian monism is true, or it is not the case
that P & ~Q is secondarily possible where Russellian mon-
ism is also false.
4. If P & ~Q is secondarily possible, then materialism is false.
5. If it is not the case that P& ~Q is secondarily possible where
Russellian monism is also false, then materialism is true.
———————
6. Materialism is false, or Russellian monism is true, or materi-
alism is true.
Chalmers may respond that, based on his argument, materialism can-
not be true because if it is not the case that P & ~Q is secondarily pos-
sible, then the only option is for Russellian monism. Recall that
Chalmers states that if the structural and intrinsic properties of physics
do necessitate the existence of phenomenal consciousness, then the
intrinsic properties of microphysical entities must be phenomenal
properties. This is Russellian monism. However, the issue with this is
that the problem of phenomenal consciousness asks for a reductive
explanation of the psychological to the neural-biological, not to the
microphysical. It is the structural and intrinsic profiles of the neu-
ral-biological level that is important here. As a legitimate possibility,
THE HARD PROBLEM AND PROGRESSIVISM 19
References
Bealer, G. (1994) Mental properties, Journal of Philosophy, 91, pp. 185–208.
[6] Chalmers will also object that an a posteriori necessity in relation to phenomenal con-
sciousness is unlike cases such as water = H2O because the former involves necessities
that are epistemically primitive whereas the latter do not. In other words, cases like water =
H2O can be deduced from a complete physical description of the world given structural
and/or functional properties, but the connection between the neural-biological and the
phenomenal cannot given the lack of structure and a complete functional description of
the phenomenal. Without a complete functional description of the phenomenal, we cannot
simply find the physical realizers of the functional role in order to find the a posteriori
necessity. Chalmers states that this makes epistemically primitive necessities mysterious
and ad hoc. Rather, we should posit the connection as being a fundamental law of nature in
which there are the two distinct properties of the neural-biological and the phenomenal.
However, the lack of a functional description of qualia which leads to the supposed corre-
sponding epistemically primitive necessities is not sufficient to stop progressivism. For
progressivism allows for the legitimate warranted possibility that the a posteriori neces-
sity in relation to phenomenal consciousness may be shown to not be epistemically primi-
tive given future advancements in explanation. The a posteriori necessity may be able to
be deduced from a complete physical description of the world. In other words, the new
conceptual explanatory hook will allow us to deduce the a posteriori necessity relation-
ship by examining the physical world without there being any kind of gaps. In continua-
tion of this point, progressivism does not necessarily claim that the a posteriori necessity
will be made in terms of the mental to the physical. All I have said is that phenomenal con-
sciousness may be x. For example, x may be something that allows for a previously
unimagined conceptual hook; a hook that in some way also allows for multiple realiz-
ability. This identity of phenomenal consciousness to x may allow the a posteriori relation
to not be epistemically primitive in that it may be deduced from a complete physical
description of the world regardless of the lack of a complete functional description for
qualia.
THE HARD PROBLEM AND PROGRESSIVISM 21