Death and Tort
Death and Tort
I. INTRODUCTION
‘T
ort’ covers a variety of claims. They are usually claims for
compensation, brought by someone who has suffered harm,
against someone else who is alleged to have been respon-
sible for that harm. The harm is usually personal injury of some kind,
although other types of harm are recognised (eg, injury to reputation or
to property interests) and the responsibility usually akes the form of a
‘duty of care’, that is, a legal duty to act with reasonable care and skill
to avoid harming the interests of others (also called a duty to avoid
‘negligence’). For current purposes, we can say that most tort cases
concern personal injuries allegedly caused by negligence, although for
completeness we need to mention injury to reputation or ‘defamation’
(ie ‘libel’ or slander’), interference with proprietary interests (‘trespass
to land’, ‘negligent damage to property’ and ‘nuisance’) and other
sorts of economic injury (including, in restricted circumstances, ‘purely
economic loss’).
How does death matter in all of this? There are really two questions, the
first rather easier to answer than the second:
1. What effect does the death of one party to a tort dispute have on that
dispute?
2. Does it make any difference whether the death was caused by the
other party, and/or was a consequence of the injuries the dispute was
about?
The second question really only arises in the context of personal injury
actions—in theory someone might die through indignation on being
libelled, but in practice these things don’t happen—and will be considered
later.
242 Steve Hedley
The modern position, established since 1934, is that tort actions have a life
of their own, and do not die with either of the people involved in them. Put
more formally:
[O]n the death of any person ... all causes of action subsisting against or vested in
him shall survive against, or, as the case may be, for the benefit of, his estate(Law
Reform (Miscellaneous Provisions) Act 1934, section 1(1)).
This reversed the early common law rule that actio personalis moritur cum
persona—‘a personal action dies with the person’. In other words, it termi-
nates automatically on the death of either claimant or defendant. From the
early medieval perspective, of course, the old rule made quite a lot of sense:
common law was then concerned not so much with reaching a fair resolu-
tion of each dispute as with preventing extra-judicial resolution through
feud or vendetta. From that perspective, the death of one of the parties
constituted the end of the dispute.
The modern rule—that rights of action usually don’t die with either of
the people involved, even if they are ‘personal’ rights—is therefore the
opposite of the medieval rule. But the change is not quite as important as it
sounds. What the modern rule does is to ensure survival of rights of action.
If, at the instant before death, there was a right to sue, then that same right
is available after the death. But the right does not expand or grow. By and
large, nothing that occurs after the claimant’s death can be regarded as a
legal wrong to the claimant: nothing that happens to their body can be an
‘injury’; and they no longer have any property or other assets to be taken
from them. This branch of the law therefore pays little heed to dignity or
respect for the deceased, as discussed by Price (chapter twelve this volume;
the criminal law is different, see Herring, chapter thirteen this volume).
Again, dead people aren’t regarded as blameworthy, and so a case that the
defendant was responsible for some harm or other will have to be based
on the defendant’s pre-death behaviour. The effect of death is that all the
rights and liabilities accumulated up to that point are transferred to the
deceased’s estate, to be sorted out by the executors or administrators. It is
really just a more subtle application of the medieval approach, allowing
property disputes to continue (because, after all, someone must own the
property in dispute), but closing down more ‘personal’ disputes—not with
the abruptness of the medieval rule, but nonetheless quite firmly. The old
attitude still applies in very ‘personal’ disputes: actions for injury to reputa-
tion terminate with the death of either party (though this aspect of the 1934
Act has been criticised for failing to include other torts protecting merely
dignitary interests, such as false imprisonment); and claims for ‘exemplary
damages’—meant to call attention to outrageous breaches of duty—do not
survive the death of the claimant.
Death and Tort 243
What is the response of the law of tort where the very complaint being
made is that the defendant’s conduct resulted in the death?
In the early days of the common law, the maxim actio personalis moritur
cum persona applied, regardless of whether the death was the very thing
complained of. This sounds ludicrous to modern ears, but was more under-
standable in the light of the purposes of tort law at that date. If one of the
parties to a dispute was dead, then there was no longer a dispute for the
common law to resolve. If the death didn’t seem fair or just, well, death
rarely was.
The law was not completely helpless, however. If a particular person
could be identified as responsible for the death, then a plea of felony could
be made, resulting in official action against the killer. Sometimes the official
response included an order for reasonable compensation, to prevent the dead
man’s relatives taking more drastic measures (Baker, 1979: 411–13). There
was also the curious doctrine of the deodand, by which a physical object
which had caused a death was forfeit, a process which sometimes meant
that the deceased’s relatives received a share of the thing’s value (Sutton,
1997; and Baker, 1979: 322). But all of these processes were increasingly
exploited for the benefit of the officials involved in them, depriving the vic-
tim’s family of any financial remedy. The procedures in cases of feud quietly
evolved into something resembling modern criminal law, being confined to
cases of murder and manslaughter, and with the killer being punished not
for the injury to others but for breach of fealty owed to the King. All his
assets were forfeit, but they went to the King and not to the victim’s family.
And the profits of the deodand were quietly appropriated for the officials
involved. So by 1600, the actio personalis maxim governed completely:
death of either party to personal injury litigation terminated it; and causing
the death of another was not a ground for civil action.
Change did not come until the 1840s, when the spread of the railways
across Britain led to an increasing number of injuries and deaths. The fact
that injured railway passengers could sue, but dead ones could not, became
something of a public scandal. Inventive lawyers revived the antique action
for a deodand, which in its 19th-century form no longer permitted for-
feiture of the railway engine involved in the death, but allowed juries to
244 Steve Hedley
A. Death: Liability
You must take reasonable care to avoid acts or omissions which you can reason-
ably foresee would be likely to injure your neighbour. Who then, in law, is my
neighbour? The answer seems to be—persons who are so closely and directly
affected by my act that I ought reasonably to have them in contemplation as
being so affected when I am directing my mind to the acts or omissions which
are called in question (Donoghue v Stevenson1).
Death is therefore one of a range of things which might ‘injure your neigh-
bour’ or ‘affect’ him or her. It is obviously at the higher end of seriousness
in that regard: creating a risk of accidental death, even a quite small one,
makes it ‘likely’ that your ‘neighbour’ will be ‘affected’ by your conduct.
Accordingly, the range of people you ‘ought reasonably to have … in con-
templation as being so affected’ can be quite broad, and can include people
who wouldn’t normally have any hope of a claim against you.
So when the claimants’ lawyers look back on a chain of events that
ultimately led to a death, they are looking for a defendant who ought rea-
sonably to have foreseen the possibility of injury, and who then acted in a
manner which was insufficiently careful in the light of that possibility. Does
it matter that death resulted? It matters in the sense that serious injuries
are taken more seriously: defendants are expected to think further ahead if
serious injuries are possible; more care is expected of them; and defendants
receive less sympathy if they argue that the loss was too ‘remote’, that is,
too unlikely a prospect to contemplate before the event. But there is no
great difference in attitude in death cases and cases of serious injuries.
Indeed, while in practice it is hard to avoid completely, nonetheless the
courts will be adamant that these cases are not to be judged with hindsight.
The question is not how we view the facts now that we know a death has
resulted, but how the defendant should have viewed them before the event,
when injury was a mere possibility. Death is therefore special in this context
because it is an exceptionally severe consequence, with an unfavourable
prognosis. However, the rules on damages then take most of that signifi-
cance away, reducing most claims by dead claimants’ estates to very low
figures indeed.
The last three items are ‘pecuniary’ items, meant to represent as accurately
as possible sums lost or bills incurred as a result of the injury. The first
two ‘non-pecuniary’ items are attempts to capture the injury to feelings
entailed by the accident, and bear no relationship to any other sum of
money involved in the facts. The relative size of the ‘non-pecuniaries’
usually depends on the severity of the case. Where the injury is medically
relatively trivial—so the injury is largely to the claimant’s dignity and sense
of well-being—the ‘non-pecuniary’ sum may constitute the bulk of the
award. At the other end of the scale, say where a high-earning claimant
comes out of the accident as a quadriplegic requiring constant care, then
the figures for loss of earnings and for future expenses will be very large,
and the figure for non-pecuniary loss, while substantial, will be nowhere
near as great.
To get an idea of the value put on life itself, we need to look at the items
one by one:
shall be calculated without reference to any loss or gain to his estate consequent
on his death, except that a sum in respect of funeral expenses may be included
(Law Reform (Miscellaneous Provisions) Act 1934, section 1(2)(c)).
The main claim today remains the one introduced in 1846, though it has
been restated and slightly expanded since. Briefly, if someone dies as the
result of a tort, and if at their death they had one or more dependants,
then those dependants acquire a cause of action against the tortfeasor for
the value of the dependency. Not all dependants can sue in this way—the
statute (the Fatal Accidents Act 1976) has a precise list of which relatives
can sue, although today it’s a pretty extensive list.
The dependency claim is unique as far as I know, and certainly has some
non-standard features. The claim belongs to the dependants, not to the
deceased person, although it is administered through the deceased’s estate.
It arises only where the deceased would have been able to sue if he or she
had survived, and is defeated by any defence that would have been good
against the deceased. In particular, if the deceased was r per cent respon-
sible for the accident, the dependency claim is reduced by r per cent (Fatal
Accidents Act 1976, section 5, see Appendix). In principle each dependant
has an individual claim for their lost part of the dependency, although the
statute says that all of the claims are to be handled together by the executor
(Fatal Accidents Act 1976, section 2). It takes a purely factual criterion—
the amount of income which would have been paid but for the defendant’s
misconduct—and substitutes a legal right to its continuance. This ‘depen-
dency’ bears no necessary resemblance either to any right of maintenance
the dependant could legally have demanded from the deceased, or to the
amount they can demand when the deceased’s estate is divided up. The
build-up of case law reveals a gradual expansion of the concept of the
‘dependency’. The courts have been prepared to include and to estimate a
dependency which they imagine would have come into an existence later if
the death had not occurred (Taff Vale Railway Co v Jenkins15). Moreover,
the courts have since the 1970s begun to hold that the ‘dependency’ need
not consist of money—so the death of a family member not in employ-
ment leads the court to assess the value of their services at home, which
sum is then the basis of a dependency (eg Hay v Hughes16; accidents in the
home are rarely the subject of tort actions, so these claims are relatively
infrequent).
The statutory list of dependants of course mirrors the legislators’ con-
cepts of what a family looks like. The original 1846 list included only the
deceased’s spouse, parents, grandparents, step-parents, children, grand-
children and step-children. The 1976 list, now in force, seeks to be more
inclusive, including all descendants and ascendants of the deceased, as well
as brothers, sisters, uncles and aunts, and their children (Fatal Accidents
Act 1976, section 1). Children treated by the deceased as part of the family
are also included. Marriage is still of some significance under the detailed
rules, but no longer has commanding status: illegitimate children have the
same entitlement as legitimate, and anyone cohabiting ‘as the husband or
wife of the deceased’ receives the same rights as a spouse, provided that the
cohabitation had lasted at least two years (Fatal Accidents Act 1976, section
1(3); for some of the difficulties involved in the cohabitation provision, see
Kotke v Saffarini17). The recent introduction of civil partnerships included
modifications to the 1976 Act, so that civil partners have the same rights as
spouses, and relationships can be established through civil partnership as
well as by blood or by marriage (Civil Partnership Act 2004, section 83).
The live question today is whether the list continues to serve a purpose, or
whether it could simply be abolished. The Law Commission wants to bring
in a general clause which would allow any person actually or potentially
dependent on the deceased to bring a claim (Law Commission for England
and Wales, 1999: paragraph 3.46).
Traditionally, the claim was strictly for money lost: the ‘dependency’
was financial only, usually calculated on a multiplier-multiplicand basis. It
included the anomalous claim for reasonable funeral expenses. But not a
penny more was allowed for emotional pain. However, the narrow traditional
conception of the claim has not proved satisfactory to all, and various rather
ad hoc compromises have been introduced. If the widow of a deceased man
remarries and her new husband is a wealthier or more generous provider,
then on this narrow conception the dependency will be very low or even
non-existent: the death has not caused the widow a significant financial loss.
Therefore, a common tactic by defence counsel in the early 20th century was
to parade the more attractive claimant widows before the court, to support
an argument that a future profitable re-marriage was very likely (the ‘cattle
market’ approach, as it was known). Outrage at this manoeuvre eventually
led to a change in the law in 1971, so that the actual or potential re-marriage
of a claimant widow is ignored (Law Reform (Miscellaneous Provision) Act
1971, section 1, now consolidated into the Fatal Accidents Act 1976, section
3(3)). The absence of any provision for non-financial loss was addressed in
1982, when legislation allowed for the claim to include a sum for ‘bereave-
ment’, not corresponding to any financial loss. This is currently set at
£10,000 (Damages for Bereavement (Variation of Sum) (England and Wales)
Order, 2002). If the deceased was married, the sum belongs to their spouse;
if he or she was an unmarried legitimate minor, it belongs to both his or her
parents; if an unmarried illegitimate minor, then to her mother; otherwise,
the sum is not claimable (Fatal Accidents Act, 1976, section 1A, inserted by
the Administration of Justice Act 1982, section 3). This is obviously a little
arbitrary, but then so would be any suggested replacement formula.
So, in summary, the injury done to those left behind by the death is seen
as interference with their ‘dependency’, an unusual sort of a right to say the
least. While, as I have shown, the tendency has been to expand the rights
available here, nonetheless the rate of expansion has been slow. Are there
any other avenues open to those who had been close to the deceased, before
he or she was deceased?
something wholly distinct from the rest of negligence law. The results are
not, however, altogether satisfactory, and the law is in constant develop-
ment as the judges flit from one awkward compromise to another.
As to injury, the current approach is that injury is sufficiently established
if there is a recognised psychiatric condition. Quite apart from any changes
in legal attitude (and the courts tend to make major innovations here
on a regular basis) the definition of ‘injury’ will fluctuate with whatever
psychiatric knowledge can be brought to bear on the particular case—the
law shows a deference to medical knowledge which it shows only patchily
in other contexts (see Jackson, chapter three this volume; and Chau and
Herring, chapter two this volume). PTSD is now a sufficiently well-estab-
lished condition to count as an ‘injury’ for this purpose and most nervous
shock cases are variants on this. But borderline cases are not uncommon. In
the case of Vernon v Bosley (No 1),19 for example, the Court of Appeal had
the unedifying task of deciding whether a father’s reaction to the loss of his
daughters by drowning constituted ‘pathological grief disorder’ (an injury
for which he could be compensated) or was ‘merely’ a severe grief reaction
(not an injury, and so not compensatable). The objections to this approach
are obvious: the knowledge that a sum in the order of half a million pounds
hung on the precise label the courts placed on his mental state cannot have
assisted his recovery. Further, it posed substantial temptations, which the
father did not resist to the courts’ satisfaction: success in his personal injury
action depended on showing that his condition was severe and long-last-
ing, whereas success in his family proceedings depended on showing the
reverse—and a comparison of the evidence in those two separate actions
made sorry reading indeed (see Vernon v Bosley (No 2)20). The line drawn
is plainly not satisfactory, but the courts currently see no other possibility
short of holding that ‘mere’ grief is actionable, which for them would be a
step too far.
As to directness, the criteria are reasonably well established: how direct
was the claimant’s perception of the death? What was it that they actually
perceived? Did they know the victim before the accident, and if so, did
they care very much about what happened to him or her? These tests are
easy enough to apply and the law seems relatively stable. The worry is, of
course, that it is all nonsense, that it takes psychiatric commonplaces about
who is likely to suffer shock, and turns them into moral injunctions. No
doubt someone who suffers PTSD over a death they did not see, and/or
whose victim they did not know, is unusual, but it is not clear how they
can be stigmatised as a person of ‘insufficient psychological firmness’ and
therefore undeserving of compensation (the requirement that the claimant
demonstrate ‘the customary phlegm’ or come up to ‘a normal standard of
susceptibility’ derives from Bourhill v Young21). This is only one step away
from saying that they should buck their ideas up and stop whingeing, which
would not usually be seen as an appropriate response to a sufferer from a
recognised disorder. For this reason, there is almost universal agreement
amongst academics that the ‘directness of perception’ criterion should be
abolished, though the ‘directness of relation’ criterion has rather more
defenders.
In these ‘nervous shock’ cases, courts here are uncomfortably caught
between two realities, one psychological and the other political. The psy-
chological reality is that the injury caused by the death of a loved one is as
real as any of the injuries the courts are more used to dealing with, and no
legally valid reason for treating it less generously has been discovered. The
contrary belief held by the legal system in the past represents not ancient
wisdom but pre-scientific ignorance, deriving largely from an exaggerated
fear of ‘compensation neurosis’. The competing political reality is that giv-
ing full weight to the seriousness of such psychological injuries would cause
a major storm, in the course of which the judges would be trenchantly criti-
cised for encouraging a ‘culture of compensation’. But the uneasy middle
course the judges have followed is not really satisfactory from any point
of view. The continual resort to psychiatric concepts is a particularly glar-
ing example of buck-passing—no doubt there are arguments both for and
against psychiatric recognition of ‘pathological grief disorder’, but none of
them have to do with whether compensation should be paid to the sufferer.
No doubt the line will continue to be blurred for quite a while yet.
IV. CONCLUSION
the accident, plus a reasonable sum for funeral expenses. Viewed in terms
of the defendant’s moral culpability, this makes little sense. But then it is a
very long time since the law of personal injury was an exercise in morality,
if indeed it ever was.
APPENDIX
Sections 1 and 1A are reproduced here. These texts were inserted by the
Administration of Justice Act 1982, section 3. [Square brackets] indicate
amendments currently in force.
1A. Bereavement
(1) An action under this Act may consist of or include a claim for dam-
ages for bereavement.
(2) A claim for damages for bereavement shall only be for the benefit—
(a) of the wife or husband [or civil partner] of the deceased; and
(b) where the deceased was a minor who was never married [or a
civil partner]—
(i) of his parents, if he was legitimate; and
(ii) of his mother, if he was illegitimate.
(3) Subject to subsection (5) below, the sum to be awarded as damages
under this section shall be [£10,000].
(4) Where there is a claim for damages under this section for the benefit
of both the parents of the deceased, the sum awarded shall be divided
equally between them (subject to any deduction falling to be made in
respect of costs not recovered from the defendant).
(5) The Lord Chancellor may by order made by statutory instrument,
subject to annulment in pursuance of a resolution of either House of
Parliament, amend this section by varying the sum for the time being
specified in subsection (3) above.
Death and Tort 259
REFERENCES
Publications
Legislation